💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › karl-korsch-revolutionary-commune.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 11:52:44. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Revolutionary Commune
Author: Karl Korsch
Date: 1929
Language: en
Topics: Council Communism, Paris Commune, German Revolution, Germany, commune
Source: https://www.marxists.org/archive/korsch/1929/commune.htm
Notes: First Published: in Die Aktion #19, 1929  Translated by Andrew Giles-Peters and Karl-Heinz Otto  Source: Class Against Class;  Transcribed: by Zdravko Saveski, for marxists.org 2009;

Karl Korsch

Revolutionary Commune

I

What should every class-conscious worker know about the revolutionary

commune in the present historical epoch which has on its agenda the

revolutionary self-liberation of the working class from the capitalist

yoke? And what is known about it today by even the politically

enlightened and therefore self-conscious segment of the proletariat?

There are a few historical facts, together with a few appropriate

remarks by Marx, Engels, and Lenin, which now after half a century of

Social Democratic propaganda prior to the Great War and after the

powerful new experiences of the last fifteen years, have already become

part and parcel of proletarian consciousness. However, this piece of

world history is today mostly dealt with as little in the schools of the

“democratic” (Weimar) republic as it was earlier in the schools of the

Kaiser’s imperial monarchy. I am referring to the history and

significance of the glorious Paris Commune, which hoisted the red flag

of proletarian revolution on March 18, 1871, and kept it flying for

seventy-two days in fierce battles against an onslaught of a well-armed

hostile world. This is the revolutionary commune of the Paris workers in

1871 of which Karl Marx said in his address to the General Council of

the International Workers Association on May 30, 1871, on the civil war

in France, that its “true secret” lay in the fact that it was

essentially a government of the working classes, “the result of the

struggle by the producing class against the propertied class, the

finally discovered political form under which the economic liberation of

labor could develop.” And it was in this sense that twenty years later,

when on the occasion of the founding of the Second International and the

creation of proletarian May Day celebrations as the first form of direct

international mass action, the propertied classes once again were

overcome with holy terror whenever the alarming words “dictatorship of

the proletariat” were sounded. Friedrich Engels flung the proud

sentences into the faces of the startled philistines: “Well then,

gentlemen, would you like to know what this dictatorship looks like?

Look at the Paris Commune. That was the dictatorship of the

proletariat.” And then again, more than two decades later, the greatest

revolutionary politician of our time, Lenin, analyzed in exact detail

the experiences of the Paris Commune and the struggle against the

opportunist decline and confusion in regard to the theories of Marx and

Engels in the main part of his most important political work State and

Revolution. And when a few weeks later the Russian Revolution of 1917,

which had begun in February as a national and bourgeois revolution,

broke through its national and bourgeois barriers and expanded and

deepened into the first proletarian world revolution, the masses of West

European workers (and the progressive sections of the working class of

the whole world), together with Lenin and Trotsky, welcomed this new

form of government of the revolutionary “council system” as the direct

continuation of the “revolutionary commune” created half a century

earlier by the Paris workers.

So far, so good. As unclear as the ideas may have been that bound

together the revolutionary workers under the formula “all power to the

councils,” following that revolutionary period of storm and stress which

spread far and wide over Europe after the economic and political

upheavals of the four war years; however deep already then the rift may

have been between these ideas and that reality which in the new Russia

had come to the fore under the name of “Socialist Councils Republic”

nonetheless, in that period the call for councils war a positive form of

development of a revolutionary proletarian class will surging toward

realization. Only morose philistines could bewail the vagueness of the

councils concept at that time, like every incompletely realized idea,

and only lifeless pedants could attempt to alleviate this defect by

artificially contrived “systems” like the infamous “little boxes-system”

of Daumig and Richard Muller. Wherever in those days the proletariat

established its revolutionary class-dictatorship, as happened in Hungary

and Bavaria temporarily in 1919, it named and formed its “government of

the working class”-which was a result of the struggle by the producing

class against the propertied class and whose determined purpose was to

accomplish the “economic liberation of labor” — as a revolutionary

council government. And if in those days the proletariat had been

victorious in anyone of the bigger industrial countries, perhaps in

Germany during the big commercial strikes of spring, 1919, or in the

counteraction of the Kapp putsch in 1920, or in the course of the

so-called Cunow strike during the Ruhr-occupation and the inflation year

of 1923, or in Italy at the time of the occupation of factories in

October, 1920-then it would have established its power in the form of a

Council Republic and it would have united together with the already

existing “Federation of Russian Socialist Soviet Republics” within a

world-federation of revolutionary council republics.

Under today’s conditions, however, the council concept has quite another

significance, as does the existence of a so-called socialist and

“revolutionary” council government. Now after the overcoming of the

world economic crisis of 1921 and the related defeat of the German,

Polish, and Italian workers-and the following chain of further

proletarian defeats including the British general strike and miners’

strike of 1926 — European capitalism has commenced a new cycle of its

dictatorship on the backs of the defeated working class. Under these

changed objective conditions we, the revolutionary proletarian

class-fighters of the whole world, cannot any more hold subjectively

onto our old belief, quite unchanged and unexamined, in the

revolutionary significance of the council concept and the revolutionary

character of council government as a direct development of that

political form of the proletarian dictatorship “discovered” half a

century ago by the Paris communardes.

It would be superficial and false, when looking at the flagrant

contradictions existing today between the name and the real condition of

the Russian “Union of Socialist Soviet Republics,” to satisfy ourselves

with the statement that the men in power in present-day Russia

“betrayed” that original “revolutionary” council principle, just as in

Germany Scheidemann, Muller, and Leipart have “betrayed” their

“revolutionary” socialist principles of the dap before the war. Both

claims are true without doubt. The Scheidemanns, Mullers, and Leiparts

were traitors to their socialist principles. And in Russia the

“dictatorship” exercised today from the highest pinnacle of an extremely

exclusive government-party apparatus by means of a million-headed

bureaucracy over the proletariat and the whole of Soviet Russia-that

only in name is still reminiscent of the “Communist” and “Bolshevik”

party-has as little in common with the revolutionary council concept of

1917 and 1918 as the Fascist party dictatorship of the former

revolutionary Social Democrat Mussolini in Italy. However, so little is

explained in both cases in regard to “betrayal” that rather the fact of

betrayal itself requires explanation.

The real task that the contradictory development from the once

revolutionary slogan “All Power to the Councils” to the now

capitalist-fascist regime in the so-called socialist soviet-state has

put on the agenda for us class-conscious revolutionary proletarians is

rather a task of revolutionary self-critique. We must recognize that not

only does that revolutionary dialectic apply to the ideas and

institutions of the feudal and bourgeois past, but likewise to all

thoughts and organizational forms which the working class itself has

already brought forward during the hitherto prevailing stages of its

historical struggle for liberation. It is this dialectic which causes

the good deed of yesterday to become the misery of today as Goethe said

in his Faust — as it is more clearly and definitely expressed by Karl

Marx: every historical form turns at a certain point of its development

from a developing form of revolutionary forces of production,

revolutionary action, and developing consciousness into the shackles of

that developing form. And as this dialectical antithesis of

revolutionary development applies to all other historical ideas and

formations, it equally applies also to those philosophical and

organizational results of a certain historical phase of revolutionary

class struggle, which is exemplified by the Paris communards of almost

60 years ago in the “finally discovered” political form of government of

the working class in the shape of a revolutionary commune. The same is

applicable to the following new historical phase of struggle in the

revolutionary movement of the Russian workers and peasants, and the

international working class, which brought forth the new form of the

“revolutionary councils power.”

Instead of bewailing the “betrayal” of the council concept and the

“degeneration” of the council power we must gather by illusion-free,

sober, and historically objective observation the beginning, middle, and

end of this whole development within a total historical panorama and we

must pose this critical question: What is — after this total historical

experience -the real historical and class-oriented significance of this

new political form of government, which brought about in the first place

the revolutionary Commune of 1871, although its development was

forcefully interrupted after 72 days duration, and then the Russian

Revolution of 1917 in concrete, more final, shape?

It is all the more necessary to once again basically orient ourselves

concerning the historical and class-oriented character of the

revolutionary commune and its further development, the revolutionary

councils system, for even the barest of historical critique shows how

completely unfounded the widely spread conception is today among

revolutionaries who theoretically reject and want to “destroy” in

practice the parliament, conceived as a bourgeois institution with

regard to its origin and purpose, and yet at the same. time see the

so-called council system, and also its predecessor the revolutionary

commune;” as the essential form of proletarian government which stands

with its whole essence in irreconcilable opposition to the essence of

the bourgeois state, in reality it is the “commune,” in its almost

thousand years of historical development, which represents an older,

bourgeois form of government than parliament. The commune forms from the

beginnings in the eleventh century up to that highest culmination which

the revolutionary movement of the bourgeoisie found in the French

Revolution of 1789/93 the almost pure class-oriented manifestation of

that struggle which in this whole historical epoch the then

revolutionary bourgeois class has waged in various forms for the

revolutionary change of the whole hitherto existing feudal order of

society and the founding of the new bourgeois social order.

When Marx — as we saw in the previously quoted sentence of his “Civil

War in France” — celebrated the revolutionary Commune of the Paris

workers of 1871 as the “finally discovered political form under which

the economic liberation of labor could be consummated,” he was aware at

the same time that the “commune” could only take on this new character —

its traditional form having been passed on over hundreds of years of

bourgeois struggle for freedom — if it radically changed its entire

previous nature. He expressly concerns himself with the

misinterpretations of those who at that time wanted to regard this “new

commune which shatters the modern state power” as a “revival of the

medieval communes which preceded that state power and thence formed

their foundation.” And he was far removed from expecting any wondrous

effects for the proletarian class struggle from the political form of

the communal constitution per se- detached from the definite proletarian

class-oriented content, with which the Paris workers, according to his

concept, had for one historical moment filled this political form,

achieved through struggle and put into the service of their economic

self-liberation. To him the decisive reason enabling the Paris workers

to make the traditional form of the “commune” the instrument of a

purpose which was so completely opposed to their original historically

determined goal lies, rather, on the contrary, in its being relatively

undeveloped and indeterminate. In the fully formed bourgeois state, as

it developed in its classical shape especially in France (i.e., in the

centralized modern representative-state), the supreme power of the state

is, according to the well known words of the “Communist Manifesto,”

nothing more than “an executive committee which administers the common

affairs of the bourgeois class as a whole”; thus its bourgeois class

character is readily apparent. However, in those underdeveloped early

historical forms of bourgeois state constitutions, that also include the

medieval “free commune,” this bourgeois class character, which

essentially adheres to every state, comes to light in a quite different

form. As opposed to the later ever more clearly appearing and ever more

purely developed character of the bourgeois state power as a “supreme

public power for the suppression of the working class, a machine of

class rule” (Marx), we see that in this earlier phase of development the

originally determined goal of the bourgeois class organization still

prevails as an organ of the revolutionary struggle of liberation of the

suppressed bourgeois class against the medieval feudal rule. However

little this struggle of the medieval bourgeoisie has in common with the

proletarian struggle for emancipation of the present historical epoch it

yet remains as a historical class struggle. And those instruments

created then by the bourgeoisie for the requirements of their

revolutionary struggle contain to a certain extent-but only to a certain

extent--certain formal connecting links with the formation of today’s

revolutionary struggle of emancipation which is being continued by the

proletarian class on another basis, under other conditions, and for

other purposes.

Karl Marx had already at an earlier date pointed out the special

significance which these earlier experiences and achievements of the

bourgeois class struggle-which found their most important expression in

the various phases of development of the revolutionary bourgeois commune

of the middle ages — had in regard to the forming of modern proletarian

class consciousness and class struggle; in fact, he pointed this out

very much earlier than the great historical event of the Paris Commune

insurrection of 1871 permitted him to praise this new revolutionary

commune of the Parisian workers as the finally discovered political form

of economic liberation of labor. He had demonstrated the historical

analogy existing between the political development of the bourgeoisie as

the suppressed class struggling for liberation within the medieval

feudal state and the development of the proletariat in modern capitalist

society. It is from this perspective that he was able to win his main

theoretical support for his special dialectical revolutionary theory of

the significance of trade unions and the trade union struggle — a theory

which until this day is still not completely and correctly understood by

many Marxists from both the left and right wing. And he arrived at it by

comparing the modern coalitions of workers with the communes of the

medieval bourgeoisie, stressing the historical fact that the bourgeois

class likewise began their struggle against the feudal social order by

forming coalitions. Already in the polemical treatise against Proudhon

we find in regard to this point the following illustration, classical to

this day:

In the bourgeoisie we have two phases to distinguish: that in which it

constituted itself as a class under the regime of feudalism and absolute

monarchy, and that in which, already constituted as a class, it

overthrew feudalism and monarchy to make society into a bourgeois

society. The first of these phases was the longer and necessitated the

greater efforts. This too began by partial combinations against the

feudal lords.

Much research has been carried out to trace the different historical

phases that the bourgeoisie has passed through, from the commune up to

its constitution as a class.

But when it is a question of making a precise study of strikes,

combinations and other forms in which the proletarians carry out before

our eyes their organization as a class, some are seized with real fear

and others display a transcendental disdain. (Marx, The Poverty of

Philosophy, chapter 2, # 5)

What is theoretically articulated here, by the young Marx in the 1840’s,

who only recently crossed over to proletarian socialism, and what he

repeats in a similar form a few years later in the Communist Manifesto

by illustrating the diverse phases of development of the bourgeoisie and

the proletariat, he also articulates once again 20 years later in the

well known resolution of the Geneva Congress of the International

Association of Workers with regard to trade unions, He argues that the

trade unions have already during their hitherto prevailing development

become “the focal points of organization of the working class ... Just

as the medieval municipalities and villages had become focal points of

the bourgeoisie.” This is so although the trade unions are not aware of

their focal significance beyond the immediate daily tasks of defending

the wages and working hours of the workers against the continuous

excessive demands of capital. Hence in the future the trade unions must

act consciously as such focal points of the organization of the whole

working class.

II

If one wants to understand Marx’s later position regarding the

revolutionary commune of the Parisian workers in its real significance,

one must take his original concept on the historical relationship

between the organizational forms of the modern proletarian and the

earlier bourgeois class struggle as a starting point. The commune arose

from the struggle of the producing class against the exploiting class

and broke up in a revolutionary act the prevailing bourgeois state

machinery. When Marx celebrates this new commune as the finally

discovered form for the liberation of labor, it was not at all his

desire — as some of his followers later claimed and still do so to this

day — to designate or brand a definite form of political organization,

whether it is called a revolutionary commune or a revolutionary council

system, as a singularly appropriate and potential form of the

revolutionary proletarian class dictatorship. In the immediately

preceding sentence, he expressly points to “the multifariousness of

interpretations which supported the commune and the multiplicity of

interests expressed in the commune,” and he explained the already

established character of this new form of government as a “political

form thoroughly capable of development.” It is just this unlimited

capability of development of new forms of political power, created by

the Paris communardes in the fire of battle, which distinguished it from

the “classic development of bourgeois government,” the centralized state

power of the modern parliamentary republic. Marx’s essential

presupposition is that in the energetic pursuit of the real interests of

the working class this form can in the end even be used as that lever

which will overthrow the economic bases forming the existence of

classes, class rule, and the state. The revolutionary communal

constitution thus becomes under certain historical conditions the

political form of a process of development, or to put it more clearly,

of a revolutionary action where the basic essential goal is no longer to

preserve any one form of state rule, or even to create a newer “higher

state-type,” but rather to create at last the material conditions for

the “withering away of every state altogether.” Without this last

condition, the communal constitution was all impossibility and all

illusion,” Marx says in this context with all desired distinctness.

Nonetheless, there remains still an unbalanced contradiction between on

one hand Marx’s characterization of the Paris Commune as the finally

discovered “political form” for accomplishing the economic and social

self-liberation of the working class and, on the other hand, his

emphasis at the same time that the suitability of the commune for this

purpose rests mainly on its formlessness; that is, on its

indeterminateness and openness to multiple interpretations. It appears

there is only one point at which Marx’s position is perfectly clear and

to which he professed at this time under the influence of certain

political theories he had in the meantime come up against and which were

incorporated in this original political concept-and not least under the

practical impression of the enormous experience of the Paris Commune

itself. While in the Communist Manifesto of 1847–48 and likewise in the

Inaugural Address to the International Workers’ Association in 1864, he

still had only spoken of the necessity “for the proletariat to conquer

political power” now the experiences of the Paris Commune provided him

with the proof that “the working class can not simply appropriate the

ready-made state machinery and put it into motion for its own purposes,

but it must smash the existing bourgeois state machinery in a

revolutionary way.” This sentence has since been regarded as an

essential main proposition and core of the whole political theory of

Marxism, especially since in 1917 Lenin at once theoretically restored

the unadulterated Marxian theory of the state in his work “State and

Revolution” and practically realized it through carrying through the

October Revolution as its executor.

But obviously nothing positive is at all yet said about the formal

character of the new revolutionary supreme state power of the

proletariat with the merely negative determination that the state power

cannot simply “appropriate the state machinery” of the previous

bourgeois state “for the working class and set it in motion for their

own purposes.” So we must ask: for which reasons does the “Commune” in

its particular, determinate form represent the finally discovered

political form of government for the working class, as Marx puts it in

his Civil War, and as Engels characterizes it once more at great length

in his introduction to the third edition of the Civil War twenty years

later? Whatever gave Marx and Engels, those fiery admirers of the

centralized system of revolutionary bourgeois dictatorship realized by

the great French Revolution, the idea to regard precisely the “Commune”

as the “political form” of the revolutionary dictatorship of the

proletariat, when it appeared to be the complete opposite to that

system?

In fact, if we analyze more exactly the political program and goals to

be attained as proposed by the two founders of scientific socialism,

Marx and Engels, not only in the time before the Paris Commune

insurrection, but also afterwards, the assertion cannot be maintained

that the form of proletarian dictatorship realized by the Paris Commune

of 1871 would in any particular sense be in unison with those political

theories. Indeed, Marx’s great opponent in the First International,

Michael Bakunin, had on this point the historical truth on his side when

he sarcastically commented on Marx’s having annexed the Paris Commune

retrospectively:

“The impact of the Communist insurrection was so powerful that even the

Marxists, who had all their ideas thrown to the wind by it, were forced

to doff their hats to it. They did more than that: in contradiction to

all logic and their innermost feelings, they adopted the program of the

Commune and its aim as their own. It was a comic, but enforced travesty.

They had to do it, otherwise they would have been rejected and abandoned

by all- so mighty was the passion which this revolution had brought

about in the whole world.” (Cf. [Fritz] Brupbacher: Marx and Bakunin,

pp. 114–115.)

The revolutionary ideas of the Paris communardes of 1871 are partly

derived from the federalistic program of Bakunin and Proudhon, partly

from the circle of ideas of the revolutionary Jacobins surviving in

Blanquism, and only to a very small degree in Marxism. Twenty years

later, Friedrich Engels claimed that the Blanquists who formed the

majority of the Paris Commune had been forced by the sheer weight of the

facts to proclaim instead of their own program of a “strict dictatorial

centralization of all power in the hands of the new revolutionary

government” the exact opposite, namely the free federation of all French

communes with the Paris Commune. On this issue the same contradiction

arises between Marx and Engels’ political theory upheld so far and their

now prevailing unconditional acknowledgment of the commune as the

“finally discovered political form” of the government of the working

class. It is erroneous when Lenin in his 1917 work “State and

Revolution” describes the evolution of the Marxian theory of state, as

if Marx had in the transition period up to 1852 already concertized the

abstract formulation of the political task of the revolutionary

proletariat (as proposed in his “Communist Manifesto” of 1847–48) to the

effect that the victorious proletariat must “destroy” and “smash”, the

existing bourgeois supreme state power. Against this thesis of Lenin

speaks Marx and Engels’ own testimony, who both declared repeatedly that

just the experience of the Paris Commune of 1871 provided for the first

time the effective proof that “the working class cannot simply

appropriate the ready made state machinery and set it in motion for its

own purposes.” It was Lenin himself who provided the logical gap

appearing in his presentation of the development of revolutionary

Marxist state theory at this point by simply jumping over a time span of

20 years in his otherwise so historically correct and philologically

exact reproduction of Marx and Engels’ remarks on the state, He proceeds

from the 18^(th) Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte (1852) straight on to the

Civil War in France (1871) and in so doing overlooks among other things

the fact that Marx summarized the whole “political program” of the

working class in this one lapidary sentence of his Inaugural Address of

the First International: “It is therefore the great task of the working

class now to seize political power.”

Yet even in the time after 1871, when Marx, on account of the experience

of the Paris Commune, advocated in a far more certain and unequivocal

way that ever before the indispensable necessity of crushing the

bourgeois state machinery and building the proletarian class

dictatorship, he was far removed from propagating a form of government

modelled on the revolutionary Paris Commune as the political form of

proletarian dictatorship, Just for that one historical moment-in which

he unconditionally and without reservations came forward on behalf of

the heroic fighters and victims of the commune vis-Ă -vis the triumphant

reaction did he, or so it appears, uphold this standpoint-and I am

referring to the Address to the General Council of the International

Workers’ Association on the “Civil War in France,” written in blood and

fire on behalf of this first international organization of the

revolutionary proletariat. For the sake of the revolutionary essence of

the Paris Commune, he repressed the critique which from his standpoint

he should have exercised on the special form of its historical

manifestation. If beyond that he even went a step further and celebrated

the political form of the revolutionary communal-constitution directly

as the “finally discovered form” of the proletarian dictatorship, then

the explanation does not lie any more merely with his natural solidarity

with the revolutionary workers of Paris, but also in a special,

subsidiary purpose. Having written the Address to the General Council of

the I.W.A, directly after the glorious battle and defeat of the Paris

communardes, Marx not only wanted to annex the Marxism of the Commune

but also at the same time the Commune to Marxism. It is in this sense

that one must understand this remarkable document, if one wishes to

correctly grasp its meaning and range of significance not only as a

classic historical document looked at as a hero’s epic or as a death

lament. Rather beyond all that, it should be seen as a fractional

polemical treatise of Marx against his most intimate opponents in the

bitter struggles which had already broken out and would soon thereafter

lead to the collapse of the First International. This fractional

subsidiary purpose hindered Marx from appraising in a historically

correct and complete way that interconnecting revolutionary movement of

the French proletariat which began with the insurrections of the Commune

in Lyon and Marseilles in 1870 and had its climax in the Paris Commune

insurrection of 1871. It also forced him to explain the revolutionary

communal constitution, welcomed as the “finally discovered political

form” of proletarian class dictatorship, as a centralist government as

well — although this was in contrast to its actual essential being.

Already Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels themselves, and more so Lenin,

deny the charge that the Paris Commune had an essentially federalist

character. If Marx cannot help but explain in his short account of the

sketch of the All-French Communal Constitution produced by the Paris

Commune the unambiguous federalist aspects of this constitution, then in

so doing he still emphasizes purposively the fact (naturally not denied

by such federalists as Proudhon and Bakunin) that “the unity of the

nation was not to be broken but on the contrary was to be organized”

through this communal constitution. He underlines “the few but important

functions” which are still remaining to be dealt with by a “central

government” within this communal constitution. He remarks that according

to the plan of the Commune these functions “were not — as some

intentionally falsified-to be abolished, but were to be transferred to

communal (and strictly responsible) civil servants.” On this basis,

Lenin later declared that “not a trace of federalism is to be found” in

Marx’s writings on the example of the Commune. “Marx is a centralist and

in his explanations cited here there is no deviation from centralism”

(“State and Revolution”). Quite correctly so, but Lenin omits to mention

at this point that Marx’s exposition of the Paris Commune is also

everything else but a historically correct characterization of the

revolutionary commune constitution aspired to by the Paris communardes

and realized in the first beginnings.

In order to deflect from the federative and anti-centralist character of

the Paris Commune as much as possible, Marx and Engels; and likewise

Lenin, have emphasized above all else the negative aspect, that it

represents as such the destruction of the prevailing bourgeois state

power. On this point there is no quarrel among revolutionaries. Marx,

Engels, and Lenin have justly emphasized that the decisive foundation

for the proletarian revolutionary character of the form of political

supreme power as stated by the Commune is to be sought in its societal

being as a realization of proletarian class dictatorship. They pointed

out to their “federalist” adversaries with great severity that the

decentralized, federative sidle form as such is quite as bourgeois as

the centralist form of government of the modern bourgeois state. They

nevertheless committed the same error which they so strongly opposed in

their opponents, not by concentrating on the “federalist” character of

the communal constitution, but rather by emphasizing too much the other

formal differences which distinguished the Paris Commune from

parliamentarism and other surpassed forms of the bourgeois state

constitution (for example, on the replacement of the standing army

through the militia, on the unification of executive and legislative

power, and on the responsibility and right of dismissal of “communal”

functionaries). They thereby created a considerable confusion of

concepts out of which emerged not only harmful effects with regard to

the position of Marxism vis-Ă -vis the Paris commune, but also likewise

for the later positing of the revolutionary Marxist direction vis-Ă -vis

the new historical phenomenon of the revolutionary council system.

As incorrect as it may be to see with Proudhon and Bakunin an overcoming

of the bourgeois state in the “federative” form, it is just as incorrect

when today some Marxist followers of the revolutionary commune on the

revolutionary council system believe on the basis of such misunderstood

explanations by Marx, Engels, and Lenin that a parliamentary

representative with a short-term, binding mandate revocable at any time,

or a government functionary employed by private treaty for ordinary

“wages,” would be a less bourgeois arrangement than an elected

parliamentarian. It is completely erroneous when they believe that there

are any “communal” or “council-like” forms of constitution whose

introduction may cause the state governed by the revolutionary

proletarian party in the end to relinquish completely that character of

an instrument of class suppression which adheres to every state. The

whole theory of the final “withering away of the state in Communist

society,” taken over by Marx and Engels out of the tradition of utopian

socialism and further developed on the basis of practical experiences of

the proletarian class struggle in their time, loses its revolutionary

meaning when one declares with Lenin that there is a state where the

minority does not suppress anymore the majority, but rather “the

majority of the people themselves suppress their own suppressors”; and

such a state of proletarian dictatorship then in its capacity as

“fulfiller” of true or proletarian democracy “is already a withering

away of the state” (“State and Revolution”).

It is high time again to posit with full clarity the two basic theories

of the real revolutionary proletarian theory which by temporary adapting

to practical requirements of such certain phases of struggle as the

Paris Commune insurrection of 1871 and the Russian October Revolution of

1917 in the end ran into danger of being abrogated. The essential final

goal of proletarian class struggle is not anyone state, however

“democratic,” “communal,” or even “council-like,” but is rather the

classless and stateless Communist society whose comprehensive form is

not any longer some kind of political power but is “that association in

which the free development of every person is the condition for the free

development of all” (“Communist Manifesto”).

Irrespective of whether the proletarian class can “conquer” more or less

unchanged the surpassed state apparatus following the illusion of the

Marxist reformists, or whether it can only really appropriate it

according to revolutionary Marxist theory by radically “smashing” its

surpassed form and “replacing” it through a new voluntary created form —

until then, in either case this state will differ from the bourgeois

state in the period of revolutionary transformation of capitalist into

Communist society only through its class nature and its social function,

but not through its political form. “The true secret of the

revolutionary commune, the revolutionary council system, and every other

historical manifestation of government of the working class exists in

this social content and not in anyone artificially devised political

form or in such special institutions as may once have been realized

under some particular historical circumstances.