đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș alfredo-m-bonanno-considerations-on-illegality.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 07:16:02. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Considerations on illegality Author: Alfredo M. Bonanno Date: 1981 Language: en Topics: insurrectionary, illegalism, anarchist movement, control, action, privacy, technology Source: Retrieved on 11th June 2022 from https://pantagruel-provocazione.blogspot.com/search/label/Considerations%20on%20illegality
Simply spreading information that has been distorted or kept quiet by
the institutions and the media is âillegalâ. It does not go against any
precise law (except in cases of information protected by âState
secretâ), but is contrary to the Stateâs management of social control,
of enforcing the law.
So a wide range of activity exists that attracts the attention of the
Stateâs repressive organisms to the same extent (if not more) as
behaviour that actually breaks a precise law.
At certain moments the circulation of information can be very damaging
to projects of State control, at least (if not more) as much as action
considered by the law as crime.
It derives from this that the difference between the âformalâ line of
illegality and the ârealâ one fluctuates according to the repressive
projects of power.
So State and capital both nationally and internationally determine
levels of illegalityâor if you prefer a limit of âlegalityââfixed not so
much through recourse to precise laws (the law acts in given cases), but
with an intricate practice of control and dissuasion that only at
certain moments becomes actual repression as such.
Basically, all political critique is within the terms of legality. In
fact, it strengthens the institutional fabric by allowing it to overcome
defects and delays determined by the contradictions of capital and some
excessively rigid aspects of the State.
But no political critique can go as far as to reach the absolute
negation of the State and capital. If it were to do soâas happens with
anarchist critiqueâit would be a question of social critique, so would
not be considered a constructive contribution to the institutional
fabric and consequently becomeâin factââillegalâ.
Social and political situations can arise in which greater equilibrium
between the political and economic forces make it easy for a social
critique, even a radical, anarchist one, to be recuperated. But that
does not alter the substantially âillegalâ content of this critique.
On the other hand, even behaviour that falls quite outside the law can
be considered differently in the light of determined political
situations. For example, the armed struggle of a combatant party is
undoubtedly illegal behaviour, but at a given moment it can turn out to
be functional to the project of recuperation and restructuring of the
State and capital, an eventual agreement between combatant party and the
State is not impossible (the latter in its guise of guarantor of the
privileges of capitalism).
This is not as absurd as it seems in that the combatant party places
itself in the logic of destablising the ruling power in order to
construct a power structure that is different in form but identical in
substance. In this kind of project, as soon as it is realised that the
military confrontation cannot proceed because there is no outlet in the
medium term they come to some agreement. The amnesty being discussed in
the [Italian 1970s] movement is one of these possible agreements. Other
forms can be imagined in the light of the recuperation by social
democracy. A cohabitation as a result of the military defeat that seems
the only possible solution to those who yesterday were convinced they
could take over the old power structure and manage it completely.
As you can see, whereas simple anarchist critiqueâradical and
absoluteâis always âillegalâ, even the armed struggle of the combatant
parties can sometimes enter the domain of âlegalityâ. That proves once
again the âfluctuatingâ concept of legality and the Stateâs intention to
adapt this to the conditions of control.
The instruments of repression are only in minimal part related directly
to repression as such. Most of them function as preventive instruments
of control.
This consequently has an effect on all potential forms of
illegalityâthrough a series of measuresâand on all forms of different
behaviour. Potential illegality is within the law today, allowing the
far-seeing eye of the censor to calculate a possible outlet. The same
goes for âdifferentâ âdeviantâ behaviour (a move away from that imposed
by the producers of consensus), today a possible object of study or
wonder, but real danger points of social subversion in the future.
Now, the exercise of control is based on the accumulation of data:
behaviour, deviance, taste, ideology, actions, etc. The greatest amount
of data possible and its relative elaboration is at the root of any
extensive project of control. Without these elements the latter would
not be possible, it would be circumscribed and not very dependable in
the wider, participatory perspective of control.
Contrary to the opinion of someâwho maintain it is pointlessâI consider
secrecy to be one of the essential elements of revolutionary action.
But this concept must be gone into.
In the first place the idea that one can only think of secrecy in the
eventuality of clandestine action.
Secrecy is also indispensable in the activity of counter-information,
activity aimed at intermediate struggle. In fact an intermediate
struggle, for example, a factory occupation, is not the ârealâ aim of
anarchists, this comes afterwards in the consequences that might
develop. These consequences cannot be foreseen during the work of
counter-information and, in the narrow sense, are not part of the
intermediate action, but belong to a successive phase which can only
with difficulty be grasped by those who participate in the struggle
simply to satisfy a primary, immediate need.
Secondly, even if we take it for granted that the repressive forces will
come to know every aspect of our struggleâfrom the phase of
counter-information to the successive oneâthat is no reason for not
adopting the method of giving as little information as possible to the
enemy. Doing things in the light of day does not mean that we supply
explanations of everything for use by the police. Think, for example, of
a situation where many actions take place in different places
simultaneously. By taking care of the communication aspect (leaflets,
posters, papers, etc.) one can make it more difficult for the police to
discover the relationship that exists between these actions. This is a
question of simple caution in order to delay repressive action.
Educating oneself to care and prudence is therefore fundamental for
every revolutionary no matter what action they intend to carry out. If
we stop to think about this for a moment, even when simply drawing up a
leafletwe can easily work out safeguarding techniques that should be
used so as to avoid aspects of repression . On the other hand, knowledge
of these techniques allows us to use instruments of denunciation or
contempt at opportune moments when we consider it important in such a
way that the risk involved becomes a calculated risk not a simple error
of the pen or ideas, to be regretted immediately afterwards.
As we can see, the space for secrecy is wide and goes far beyond the
realm of clandestinity.
The anarchist movement and the problem of secrecy
To say that the anarchist movement is by nature not a clandestine
movement is meaningless. A revolutionary movement as complex and rich in
elements for the radical transformation of society cannot fail to be
thought of as anything other than an intervention that is realised in
the light of day so that everyone has the chance take its ideas into
consideration.
The fact that the anarchist movement has at times been reduced to
clandestinity depended exclusively on altered historical and political
conditions in a given country.
But that does not prevent the anarchist movement from developing its
political and revolutionary activity with the caution mentioned earlier.
It also develops more specific activity that is not aimed at propaganda
and participation in social struggles, but has different objectives that
areâobviouslyânot in contrast with the first. In the first place, the
problem of finding the means necessary for the struggle. In the second,
attacks against objectives and individuals actively involved in
exploitation, and so on.
This kind of activity cannot be considered as something âdifferentâ or
âseparateâ from the rest. The need for secrecy, which seems out of the
question as far as these aspects are concerned, leads those who believe
secrecy is impossible to conclude that all such activity must be
abandoned, thus sacrificing a potential that continues to reduce
everything to simple declarations of principle and a sad inadequacy of
means.
But do the potent technological means the adversary is doted with really
make secrecy impossible?
This question enters the field of perplexities that have been generated
over the past few years due to a lack of knowledge of technology and a
fantastic and hyperbolic view of its possible use.
Like everything else one does not know, or that one knows little about,
the technology of the past few years with its computers, automatic
listening centres, lasers, radar, etc. has fascinated many comrades who
were once nearly all passionate readers of science-fiction. The
pleasures they once found in such reading is now found in reading, often
without a necessary basic preparation, more or less specialised
newspaper accounts (more often simply âscandalisticâ), of the great
possibilities of technology today.
We are not trying to underestimate the repressive potential that the
technical findings of today are putting at the disposition of power. We
just want to say that certain things should be said with caution. If for
no other reason than not to undo peopleâs subversive energy and
contribute to hammering nails into our own coffin.
Total control is a dream that power has been passing on since the era of
the great Leviathan. In actual fact this is impossible. The main
obstacle is not so much lack of technical efficiency concerning the
mechanisms of control and not even the limitations of those who have the
task of making it work. The limitation of control is that, in order to
extend, it must penetrate the mind of whoever is being controlled. So
the real controller is not so muchâor at least not onlyâthe policeman,
the judge or the prison guard, but the person that is being controlled
him or her self.
Whoever realises control plans to enter the culture of the person they
are controlling, building within them a resistance to freedom, obstacles
to the subversive struggle, impediments to free thought. Once that is
done it will be the controlled person to censure their own actions and
thoughts. Finally, in a third phase the controlled person will see to
extending control, to perfecting it by participating in the elaboration
of technological centres for storing data and the elaboration of
information. This participation, which constitutes the maximum level of
control imaginable, will only become possible when the first two levels
have been interiorised (control seen as the enemy and control
penetrating us as a way of thinking). The third level should not be seen
as participation in the functioning of âmachineryâ so much as an ongoing
contribution to enriching the information available to capital and which
constitutes the base of capitalist accumulation of the future.
In such a perspective clearly any sector that is removed from the
reaches of control or protected from the spreading process of cultural
integration must be defended with every means, even by having recourse
to the techniques of depistage that are based on secrecy.
Anyone who denies such techniques a priori does so because they
short-sightedly see them as plots and romantic nonsense of days gone by.
This is not so.
Of course, it would be absurd to entrust messages to a ciphered code,
not only of the kind used by Bakunin and Malatesta but any kind at all,
for the simple reason that any communication that is more than a couple
of lines long can easily be decoded by any computer. But even the code
of Bakunin and Malatesta (for messages of a few words) still holds and
cannot be decoded by computers because they lack the necessary frequency
to establish the various characters.
I am not discussing the question of coded messages here, I am just
saying that no one can exclude that at a given moment a revolutionary
might be forced to make a communication that they do not want to make
known to the enemy. It is as well to know that such a thing is
possibleâif the message is very briefâand that no technology in the
world that can break even the most simple codes.
Why open the way to repression?
Those who consider secrecy to be impossible maintain that all anarchist
and revolutionary action should be publicised to a maximum degree. For
example, for them there would be nothing strange about publicising lists
of those belonging to all the anarchist organisations (beginning with
the FAI, [Italian Anarchist Federation]: precisely these comrades
publish the names of the members of that organisation).
On a purely abstract level there would be nothing strange about this.
But in practice many objections to such an idea arise. First, why open
the way to the repression? Second, if anarchists are tolerated today
within a certain repressive perspective, tomorrow this could change for
the worse, and the police would already find themselves with well
drawn-up lists to facilitate their task. Why should we help them in
their job of policing? Of course, many comradesâ names are already
known, but many others are not and the police go to great lengths to
find them out. Some innocent soul might ask themselves why they bother,
given that the work of the movement âin the main partâtakes place in the
light of day. But that would be a stupid question. Accumulating data
today could be useful to the repression of tomorrow.
When we see that control is not just a repressive fact but is also, and
often essentially, participatory, it is possible to evaluate the problem
of secrecy differently.
Basically it is we ourselves who by âparticipatingâ could end up
sanctioning definitive real control. If we refuse to collaborate, if we
obstruct the creation of a ghetto culture with all possible means, a
language for the exclusive use of those who are and will be excluded
from the technological management of production, therefore of power,
then real control will not be possible.
It is not so much the problem of considering today what margins the
State conserves from so-called ânot applied controlâ, i.e. of the
capacity it could employâalso preventivelyâbut doesnât, so as to give
the impression that at least there is an area that is devoid of control.
In substance, this area might exist, it might not. It is social control
as a whole that is not yet total. Even that which looms up before
usâprisons for exampleâare still incomplete control. It follows that it
is not a question of the extent of control, but of the quality of the
control itself.
The function of secrecy in subversive behaviour could therefore be that
of denying this participation, avoiding interiorising the values and
language that the State is transmitting with the aim of perfecting
control.