💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › david-graeber-consumption.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 09:05:06. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Consumption
Author: David Graeber
Date: August 2011
Language: en
Topics: consumption, Consumerism, anthropology
Source: Retrieved on 28th November 2021 from https://davidgraeber.org/papers/consumption/
Notes: Published in Current Anthropology, Vol. 52, No. 4 (August 2011), pp. 489–511.

David Graeber

Consumption

Beginning in the 1980s, anthropologists began to be bombarded with

endless—and often strangely moralistic—exhortations to acknowledge the

importance of something referred to as “consumption.” The exhortations

were effective; for the past 2 decades, the term has become a staple of

theoretical discourse. Rarely, however, do anthropologists examine it:

asking themselves why it is that almost all forms of human

self-expression or enjoyment are now being seen as analogous to eating

food. This essay seeks to investigate how this came about, beginning

with medieval European theories of desire and culminating in the

argument that the notion of consumption ultimately resolves certain

conceptual problems in possessive individualism.

I do not want to offer yet another critique of consumption or of

consumer practices. I want to ask instead why it is that we assume such

things exist. Why is it that when we see someone buying refrigerator

magnets and someone else putting on eyeliner or cooking dinner or

singing at a karaoke bar or just sitting around watching television, we

assume that they are on some level doing the same thing, that it can be

described as “consumption” or “consumer behavior,” and that these are

all in some way analogous to eating food?[1] I want to ask where this

term came from, why we ever started using it, and what it says about our

assumptions about property, desire, and social relations that we

continue to use it. Finally, I want to suggest that maybe this is not

the best way to think about such phenomena and that we might do well to

come up with better ones.

To do so necessarily means taking on a whole intellectual industry that

has developed over the past few decades around the study of consumption.

For most scholars, not only is the category of “consumption”

self-evident in its importance[2] but also one of the greatest sins of

past social theorists was their failure to acknowledge it. Since the

mid-1980s, theoretical discussions of the topic in anthropology,

sociology, history, or cultural studies almost invariably begin by

denouncing past scholars for having refused to give consumption

sufficient due. The most frequent villains are the Frankfurt School. One

widely used cultural studies textbook begins by explaining that

theorists such as Adorno and Horkheimer

argued that the expansion of mass production in the twentieth century

had led to the commodification of culture, with the rise of culture

industries. Consumption served the interests of manufacturers seeking

greater profits, and citizens became the passive victims of advertisers.

Processes of standardization, they argued, were accompanied by the

development of a materialistic culture, in which commodities came to

lack authenticity and instead merely met “false” needs. These needs were

generated by marketing and advertising strategies and, it is argued,

increased the capacity for ideological control or domination. (MacKay

1997:3)[3]

The author goes on to observe that this view was first shaken when

ethnographers such as Dick Hebdige (1979) began examining the actual

behavior of those involved in youth subcultures and discovered that

rather than being passive and easily manipulated ... young consumers

were active, creative and critical in their appropriation and

transformation of material artifacts. In a process of bricolage, they

appropriated, reaccented, rearticulated or transcoded the material of

mass culture to their own ends, through a range of everyday creative and

symbolic practices. Through such processes of appropriation, identities

are constructed. (MacKay 1997:3)

Of course, Hebdige was dealing not just with subcultures but mainly with

self-conscious countercultures. Still, this became the model. Before

long, what was taken to be true of rebellious youth came to be seen as

true, if perhaps in a less flamboyant fashion, of all consumers. Rather

than being passive victims of media manipulation, they were active

agents. In anthropology, a number of scholars soon began making similar

arguments and telling similar stories from the mid1980s to the early

1990s: Arjun Appadurai (1986) in The Social Life of Things, Jonathan

Friedman (1994) in Consumption and Identity, and above all, Daniel

Miller (1987, 1995, 1997, 1998, 2001) in a series of books beginning

with Material Culture and Mass Consumption. Each of these authors had

his own version of the story, and each developed his own idiosyncratic

theories of what consumption was all about, but what was ultimately more

important than any particular author’s version was what might be

described as the standard narrative that began to take shape in classes,

seminars, and informal graduate school conversations at the time. This

was a surprisingly uniform little morality tale that runs something like

this. Once upon a time, it begins, we all used to subscribe to a Marxist

view of political economy that saw production as the driving force of

history and the only truly legitimate field of social struggle. Insofar

as we even thought about consumer demand, it was largely written off as

an artificial creation, the results of manipulative techniques by

advertisers and marketers meant to unload products that nobody really

needed. But eventually we began to realize that this view was not only

mistaken but also profoundly elitist and puritanical. Real working

people find most of their life’s pleasures in consumption. What is more,

they do not simply swallow whatever marketers throw at them like so many

mindless automatons; they create their own meanings out of the products

with which they chose to surround themselves. In fact, insofar as they

fashion identities for themselves, those identities are largely based on

the cars they drive, clothes they wear, music they listen to, and videos

they watch. In denouncing consumption, we are denouncing what gives

meaning to the lives of the very people we claim we wish to liberate.[4]

The obvious question is, Who is this “we”? After all, it is not as if

cultural anthropology had ever produced any Frankfurt School–style

analysis of consumption to begin with. This seems all the more

significant because the story was not simply told at one historical

juncture. By now it has effectively become a regular instrument of

academic socialization whereby graduate students—many themselves coming

from countercultural backgrounds or at least still struggling with their

own adolescent revulsion against consumer culture—adjust themselves to

more settled, consumer-oriented lives. Still, the real (and rather

perverse) effect of this narrative has been to import the categories of

political economy—the picture of a world divided into two broad spheres,

one of industrial production, another of consumption—into a field that

had never seen the world that way before. It is no coincidence that this

is a view of the world equally dear to Marxist theorists who once wished

to challenge the world capitalist system and to the neoliberal

economists currently managing it.

Perhaps this is not entirely surprising. I have argued elsewhere

(Graeber 2010) that as an ideology, at least, neoliberalism consists

largely of such systematic inversions: taking concepts and ideas that

originated in subversive, even revolutionary rhetoric and transforming

it into ways of presenting capitalism itself as subversive and

revolutionary. And the story looks rather different if one looks at the

broader social context, particularly what was happening within

capitalism itself. Until the mid-1970s, economists and marketers, when

they sought outside expertise to help understand consumer behavior,

tended to consult psychologists. Starting in the late 1970s, essays in

the Journal of Consumer Behavior and other marketing journals began to

argue for the importance of social context—the foundational essay here

is often considered to be by Belk (1975)—and look to anthropology, in

particular, for models and assistance. At first there was a great deal

of resistance to this line of approach within marketing studies itself,

but as advertisers themselves began to speak of accelerated “market

segmentation” and increasingly move to defining consumers as,

essentially, a diverse collection of subcultures, it became more and

more obviously relevant.

The first major attempt at an alliance between anthropologists and

economists in the study of consumption was soon to follow—Mary Douglas’s

(1979) work with Baron Isherwood, The World of Goods: Towards an

Anthropology of Consumption. Their work, however, had little real

traction in the discipline largely because it came from a fairly

explicitly conservative political position—it was framed in part as a

rejoinder to 1960s countercultural types who criticized materialist

values. In fact, with the exception of a few mavericks such as Steve

Barnett, who (also in 1979) left academia to set up his own marketing

consultancy firm, anthropology as a discipline remained largely

reluctant to answer the business world’s call.[5] The real breakthrough

occurred in the late 1980s with the populist turn described above, that

is, when anthropologists began to take the opposite approach to Douglas,

and rather than condemn countercultures, they effectively began treating

all cultures as subcultures and all subcultures as countercultures.

The following quote is from a recently published encyclopedia of

anthropology, in the section, “Anthropology and Business”:

The British anthropologist Daniel Miller argues that this “turn”

represented a metamorphosis of anthropology, from a less mature state in

which mass consumption goods were viewed as threatening (i.e.,

signifying both the loss of culture and a threat to the survival of

anthropology), to a more enlightened outlook that frankly acknowledges

consumption as the local idiom through which cultural forms express

their creativity and diversity. This rather amazing about-face has

permitted a confluence of interest between anthropology and the field of

marketing. (Baba 2006:43)

The author goes on to observe that

the literature in consumer behavior and marketing produced by

anthropologists has been well received by marketing departments and

corporations, with the result that anthropologists now hold positions in

the marketing departments of several major business schools (e.g.,

University of Pennsylvania, Northwestern University, University of

Nebraska, University of Utah). It would appear that anthropology is now

a permanent addition to the disciplines that comprise the academic

marketing field. (Baba 2006:47)

A synthetic discipline, called “consumer culture theory” (see Arnould

and Thomson 2005) has emerged as increasing numbers of anthropologists

follow the path blazed by Barnett and work directly with advertising

firms on specific campaigns.

I certainly do not mean to suggest that pressures from the corporate

world created this discourse; as I say, all this was part of a much

broader infiltration of neoliberal categories into anthropology that was

happening at the time. Neither do I mean to suggest that the resultant

field of “consumption studies” has been driven by business interests or

for that matter that it has not produced any number of interesting and

worthwhile analyses. What I do want to argue is that this choice of

initial terms has made a difference.

This is what I really want to investigate. How did “consumption” become

a field of anthropology, and what does it mean that we now call certain

kinds of behavior “consumption” rather than something else? It is a

curious fact, for example, that those who write about consumption almost

never define the term.[6] I suspect this is in part because the tacit

definition they are using is so extraordinarily broad. In common

academic usage (and to an only slightly less degree popular usage),

“consumption” has come to mean “any activity that involves the purchase,

use or enjoyment of any manufactured or agricultural product for any

purpose other than the production or exchange of new commodities.” For

most wage laborers, this means nearly anything one does when not working

for wages. Imagine, for example, four teenagers who decide to form a

band. They scare up some instruments, teach themselves to play, write

songs, come up with an act, and practice long hours in the garage. Now

it seems reasonable to see such behavior as production of some sort or

another, but if one takes the common de facto definition to its logical

conclusion, it would be much more likely to be placed in the sphere of

consumption simply because they did not themselves manufacture the

guitars.[7] Granted, this is something of a reductio ad absurdum. But it

is precisely by defining “consumption” so broadly that anthropologists

can then turn around and claim that consumption has been falsely

portrayed as passive acquiescence when in fact it is more often an

important form of creative self-expression. Perhaps the real question

should be, Why does the fact that manufactured goods are involved in an

activity automatically come to define its very nature?

It seems to me that this theoretical choice—the assumption that the main

thing people do when they are not working is “consuming” things—carries

within it a tacit cosmology, a theory of human desire and fulfillment

whose implications we would do well to think about.[8] This is what I

want to investigate in the rest of this paper. Let me begin by looking

at the history of the word “consumption” itself.

Etymologies and Antecedents

The English “to consume” derives from the Latin verb consumere, meaning

“to seize or take over completely” and, hence, by extension, to “eat up,

devour, waste, destroy, or spend.” To be consumed by fire, or for that

matter consumed with rage, still holds the same implications: it implies

something not just being thoroughly taken over but being overwhelmed in

a way that dissolves away the autonomy of the object or even that

destroys the object itself.

“Consumption” first appears in English in the fourteenth century. In

early French and English usages, the connotations were almost always

negative. To consume something meant to destroy it, to make it burn up,

evaporate, or waste away. Hence, wasting diseases “consumed” their

victims, a usage that according to the Oxford English Dictionary is

already documented by 1395. This is why tuberculosis came to be known as

“consumption.” At first the now-familiar sense of consumption as eating

or drinking was very much a secondary meaning. Rather, when applied to

material goods, “consumption” was almost always synonymous with waste:

it meant destroying something that did not have to be (at least quite so

thoroughly) destroyed.[9]

The contemporary usage, then, is relatively recent. If we were still

talking the language of the fourteenth or even seventeenth centuries, a

“consumer society” would have meant a society of wastrels and

destroyers.

Consumption in the contemporary sense really appears in the political

economy literature only in the late eighteenth century, when authors

such as Adam Smith and David Ricardo began to use it as the opposite of

“production.”[10] One of the crucial features of the industrial

capitalism emerging at the time was a growing separation between the

places in which people—or men, at least—worked and the places where they

lived. This in turn made it possible to imagine that the “economy”

(itself a very new concept) was divided into two completely separate

spheres: the workplace, in which goods were “produced,” and the

household, in which they were “consumed.” That which was created in one

sphere is used— ultimately, used up, destroyed—in the other. Vintners

produce wine, and consumers take it home and drink it; chemical plants

produce ink, and consumers take it home, put it in pens, and write with

it, and so on. Of course, even from the start, it was more difficult to

see in what sense consumers were “consuming” silverware or books because

these are not destroyed by use; however, because just about anything

does eventually wear out or have to be replaced, the usage was not

entirely implausible.

All this did, certainly, bring home one of the defining features of

capitalism: that it is a motor of endless production, one that can

maintain its equilibrium, in fact, only by continual growth. Endless

cycles of destruction do seem to be, necessarily, the other side of

this. To make way for new products, all that old stuff must somehow be

cleared away, destroyed, or at least cast aside as outmoded or

irrelevant. And this is indeed the defining feature of “consumer

society” as usually described (especially by its critics): one that

casts aside any lasting values in the name of an endless cycling of

ephemera. It is a society of sacrifice and destruction. And often what

seems to most fascinate Western scholars—and the Western public—about

people living in radically different economic circumstances are

phenomena that seem to mirror this in one way or another. George

Bataille (1985[1937]) saw here a clue to the nature of culture itself,

whose essence he saw as lying in apparently irrational acts of wild

sacrificial destruction, for which he drew on examples such as Aztec

human sacrifice or the Kwakiutl potlatch.[11] Or consider the

fascination with the potlatch itself. It is hard not to think about

Northwest Coast potlatch without immediately evoking images of chiefs

setting fire to vast piles of wealth—such images play a central role not

only in Bataille’s but in just about every popular essay on “gift

economies” since. If one examines the sources, though, it turns out most

Kwakiutl potlatches were stately redistributive affairs, and our image

is really based on a handful of extremely unusual ones held around 1900

at a time when the Kwakiutl population was simultaneously devastated by

disease and was undergoing an enormous economic boom (e.g., Masco 1995).

Clearly, the spectacle of chiefs vying for titles by setting fire to

piles of blankets or other valuables strikes our imagination not so much

because it reveals some fundamental truth about human nature largely

suppressed in our own society as because it reflects a barely hidden

truth about the nature of our own consumer society: that it is largely

organized around the ceremonial destruction of commodities.

“Consumption,” then, refers to an image of human existence that first

appears in the North Atlantic world around the time of the industrial

revolution, one that sees what humans do outside the workplace largely

as a matter of destroying things or using them up. It is especially easy

to perceive the impoverishment this introduces into accustomed ways of

talking about the basic sources of human desire and gratification by

comparing it to the ways earlier Western thinkers had talked about such

matters. St. Augustine and Hobbes (1968), for example, both saw human

beings as creatures of unlimited desire, and they therefore concluded

that if left to their own devices, they would always end up locked in

competition. As Marshall Sahlins (1996) has pointed out, in this they

almost exactly anticipated the assumptions of later economic theory. But

when they listed what humans desired, neither emphasized anything like

the modern notion of consumption. In fact, both came up with more or

less the same list: humans, they said, desire (1) sensual pleasures, (2)

the accumulation of riches (a pursuit assumed to be largely aimed at

winning the praise and esteem of others), and (3) power.[12] None were

primarily about using anything up.[13] Even Adam Smith (1976[1776]), who

first introduced the term “consumption” in its modern sense in The

Wealth of Nations, turned to an entirely different framework when he

developed a theory of desire in his Theory of Moral Sentiments (Smith

2002[1761]), one that assumed that what most humans want above all is to

be the object of others’ sympathetic attention.[14] It was only with the

growth of economic theory and its gradual colonization of other

disciplines that desire itself began to be imagined as the desire to

consume.

The notion of consumption, then, that assumes that human fulfillment is

largely about acts of (more or less ceremonial) material destruction

represents something of a break in the Western tradition. It is hard to

find anything written before the eighteenth century that precisely

anticipates it. It seems to appears abruptly, mainly in countries such

as England and France, at exactly the moment when historians of those

places begin to talk about the rise of something they call “consumer

society” or simply “consumerism” (Berg and Clifford 1999; McKendrick,

Brewer, and Plum 1982; Smith 2002; Stearns 2001), that is, the moment

when a significant portion of the population could be said to be

organizing their lives around the pursuit of something called “consumer

goods,” defined as goods they did not see as necessities but as in some

sense objects of desire, chosen from a range of products, subject to the

whims of fashion (ephemera again), and so on.

Theories of Desire

All this makes it sound as if the story should really begin around 1750

or even 1776. But could such basic assumptions about what people thought

life is about really have changed that abruptly? It seems to me there

are other ways to tell the story that suggest much greater continuities.

One would be to examine the concept of “desire” itself as it emerged in

the Western philosophical tradition, to understand how it is that

“consumption” could become our key idiom for talking about material

desire. Here I think there is a great deal of continuity, and

investigating it should make it much easier to understand why in fact

European thought provided fertile ground for the emergence of such a

concept—one that, I suspect, would have seemed quite odd almost anywhere

else.

This approach might seem surprising because it is not as if one can

immediately identify a single “Western” theory of desire. In fact,

thinking on the matter in what we have come to think of as the Western

philosophical tradition contains a number of apparently contradictory

strands. Since Plato, the most common approach has been to see desire as

rooted in a feeling of absence or lack. This does make a certain obvious

intuitive sense. One desires what one does not have. One feels an

absence and imagines how one might like to fill it; this very action of

the mind is what we think of as “desire.” But there is also an

alternative tradition that goes back at least to Spinoza (2000) that

starts off not from the yearning for some absent object but from

something even more fundamental: self-preservation, the desire to

continue to exist (Nietzsche’s “life which desires itself”). Here desire

becomes the fundamental energetic glue that makes individuals what they

are over time. Both strands continue to do battle in contemporary social

theory as well. Desire as lack is especially developed in the work of

Jacques Lacan (1977). The key notion here is of the “mirror stage,”

where an infant, who is at first really a bundle of drives and

sensations unaware of its own existence as a discrete bounded entity,

manages to construct a sense of self around some external image, for

example, an encounter with his or her own reflection in the mirror. One

can generalize from here a much broader theory of desire (or perhaps

merely desire in its more tawdry narcissistic forms) where the object of

desire is always some image of perfection, an imaginary completion for

one’s own ruptured sense of self (Graeber 2001:257–258). But then there

is also the approach adopted by authors such as Deleuze and Guattari

(1983), who wrote Anti-Oedipus, their famous critique of psychoanalysis,

largely as an attack on this kind of thinking. Appealing to the

Spinozist/Nietzschean tradition, they deny that desire should be found

in any sense of lack at all. Rather, it is something that “flows”

between everyone and everything; much like Foucault’s power, it becomes

the energy knitting everything together. As such, desire is everything

and nothing; there is very little one can actually say about it.

One might be tempted to conclude at this point that “desire” is not a

very useful theoretical concept[15] —that is, one that can be

meaningfully distinguished from needs, or urges, or intentions—because

even authors working within the same philosophical tradition cannot make

up their minds what it is supposed to mean. But if one goes back to the

origins of the alternative tradition of Spinoza (2000), one soon

discovers that the two strands are not nearly as different as they

appear. When Spinoza refers to the universal driving force of all beings

to persist in their being and expand their powers of action, he is

referring not to desire (cupiditas) but to what he calls conatus,

usually translated “will.” On a bodily level, conatus takes the form of

a host of appetites: attractions, dispositions, and so forth. Desire is

“the idea of an appetite,” the imaginative construction one puts on some

such attraction or disposition.[16] In other words, the one constant

element in all these definitions is that desire (unlike needs, urges, or

intentions) necessarily involves the imagination. Objects of desire are

always imaginary objects and usually imaginary totalities of some sort

because, as I have argued before, most totalities are themselves

imaginary objects (Graeber 2001).

The other way one might say desire differs from needs, urges, or

intentions is that as Tzvetan Todorov (2001) puts it, it always implies

the desire for some kind of social relation. There must necessarily be

some kind of quest for recognition involved. The problem is that owing

to the extreme individualism typical of the Western philosophical

tradition, this tends to be occluded; even where it is not, the desire

for recognition is assumed to be the basis for some kind of profound

existential conflict. The classic text here is Hegel’s (1998) “On

Lordship and Bondage,” the famous “master/slave dialectic” in

Phenomenology of Spirit that has made it difficult for future theorists

to think of this kind of desire without also thinking of violence and

domination.

If I may be allowed a very abbreviated summary of Hegel’s argument,[17]

human beings are not animals because they have the capacity for

self-consciousness. To be self-conscious means to be able to look at

ourselves from an outside perspective— that must necessarily be that of

another human being. All these were familiar arguments at the time;

Hegel’s great innovation was to bring in desire, to point out that to

look at ourselves this way, one has to have some reason to want to do

it. This sort of desire is also inherent in the nature of humanity,

according to Hegel, because unlike animals, humans desire recognition.

Animals experience desire simply as the absence of something: they are

hungry; therefore, they wish to “negate that negation” by obtaining

food; they have sexual urges; therefore, they seek a mate.[18] Humans go

further. They not only wish to have sex—at least, if they are being

truly human about the matter—but also wish to be recognized by their

partner as someone worthy of having sex with. That is, they wish to be

loved. We desire to be the object of another’s desire. So far this seems

straightforward enough: human desire implies mutual recognition. The

problem is that for Hegel, the quest for mutual recognition inevitably

leads to violent conflict, to “life-and-death struggles” for supremacy.

He provides a little parable: two men confront each other at the

beginning of history (as in all such stories, they appear to be

40-year-old males who simply rose out of the earth fully formed). Each

wishes to be recognized by the other as a free, autonomous, fully human

being. But in order for the other’s recognition to be meaningful, he

must prove to himself that the other is fully human and worthy of

recognizing him; the only way to do this is to see whether he values his

freedom and autonomy so much that he is willing to risk his life for it.

A battle ensures. But a battle for recognition is inherently unwinnable,

because if you kill your opponent, there is no one to recognize you; on

the other hand, if your opponent surrenders, he proves by that very act

that he was not willing to sacrifice his life for recognition after all

and therefore that his recognition is meaningless. One can of course

reduce a defeated opponent to slavery, but even that is self-defeating,

because once one reduces the Other to slavery, one becomes dependent on

one’s slave for one’s very material survival while the slave at least

produces his own life and is in fact able to realize himself to some

degree through his work.

This is a myth, a parable. Clearly, there is something profoundly true

in it. Still, it is one thing to say that quest for mutual recognition

is necessarily going to be tricky, full of pitfalls, with a constant

danger of descending into attempts to dominate or even obliterate the

Other. It is another thing to assume from the start that mutual

recognition is impossible. As Majeed Yar (2001) has pointed out, this

assumption has come to dominate almost all subsequent Western thinking

on the subject, especially since Sartre refigured recognition as “the

gaze” that, he argued, necessarily pins down, squashes, and objectifies

the Other.[19] As in so much Western theory, when social relations are

not simply ignored, they are assumed to be inherently competitive.

Todorov (2001:66–67) notes that much of this is the result of starting

one’s examples with a collection of adult males: psychologically, he

argues, it is quite possible to argue that the first moment in which we

act as fully human beings is when we seek recognition from others, but

that is because the first thing a human baby does that an animal baby

does not do is try to catch her mother’s eye, an act with rather

different implications.

At this point, I think we have the elements for a preliminary synthesis.

Insofar as it is useful to distinguish something called “desire” from

needs, urges, or intentions, then, it is because desire (a) is always

rooted in imagination and (b) tends to direct itself toward some kind of

social relation, real or imaginary, and that social relation generally

entails a desire for some kind of recognition and hence an imaginative

reconstruction of the self, a process fraught with dangers of destroying

that social relation or turning it into some kind of terrible conflict.

Now, all this is more arranging the elements of a possible theory than

proposing one; it leaves open the actual mechanics of how these elements

interact. But if nothing else, it helps explain why the word “desire”

has become so popular with authors who write about modern consumerism,

which is, we are told, all about imaginary pleasures and the

construction of identities. Even here, though, the historical

connections between ideas are not what one might imagine.

In the next section, I will look at theories of consumerism as desire

and see how they tie into this broader philosophical tradition—one

rooted, I believe, in some very fundamental underlying assumptions about

the nature of human beings.

On Lovers and Consumers

Let me begin with Colin Campbell’s (1987) Romantic Ethic and the Spirit

of Modern Consumerism, certainly one of the more creative essays on the

subject. Campbell’s book aims to provide a corrective to the usual

critique of consumer culture, which is that it throws up all sorts of

wonderful fantasies about what you will get when you purchase some

product and inevitably disappoints you once you get the product. It is

this constant lack of satisfaction, the argument goes, that then drives

consumption and thus allows the endless expansion of production. If the

system delivered on its promises, the whole thing would not work.

Campbell is not denying this happens so much as he is questioning

whether the process itself is really so frustrating or unpleasant as

most accounts imply. Really, he says, is not all this a form of pleasure

in itself? In fact, he argues that it is the unique accomplishment of

modern consumerism that it has assisted in the creation of a genuinely

new form of hedonism.

“Traditional hedonism,” Campbell argues, was based on the direct

experience of pleasure: wine, women, and song; sex, drugs, and rock and

roll; whatever the local equivalent. The problem from a capitalist

perspective is that there are inherent limits to all this. People become

sated and bored. There are logistical problems. “Modern self-illusory

hedonism,” as he calls it, solves this dilemma because here what one is

really consuming are fantasies and daydreams about what having a certain

product would be like. The rise of this new kind of hedonism, he argues,

can be traced back to certain sensational forms of Puritan religious

life but primarily to the new interest in pleasure through the vicarious

experience of extreme emotions and states that one sees emerge in the

popularity of Gothic novels and the like in the eighteenth century and

that peaks with romanticism itself. The result is a social order that

has become, in large measure, a vast apparatus for the fashioning of

daydreams. These reveries attach themselves to the promise of pleasure

afforded by some particular consumer good or set of them; they produce

the endless desires that drive consumption, but in the end, the real

enjoyment is not in the consumption of the physical objects but in the

reveries themselves (see also Wagner 1995).

The problem with this argument—or one of them (one could find all

sorts)—is the claim that all of this was something new. It is not just

the obvious point that pleasure through vicarious participation in

extreme experience did not become a significant social phenomenon only

in the seventeenth century. It was accepted wisdom as early the eleventh

century that desire was largely about taking pleasure in fantasies.

Here I turn to the work of the Italian philosopher Giorgio Agamben

(1993a, 1993b) and the Romanian historian of religions Ioan Couliano

(1987) on medieval and Renaissance theories of love. These theories all

turned on the notion of what was called the “pneumatic system.” One of

the greatest problems in medieval metaphysics was to explain how it was

possible for the rational soul to perceive objects in the material world

because the two were assumed to be of absolutely alien natures. The

solution was to posit an intermediate astral substance called “pneuma,”

or spirit, that translated sense impressions into phantasmic images.

These images then circulated through the body’s pneumatic system (which

centered on the heart) before they could be comprehended by the

intellectual faculties of the soul. Because this was essentially the

zone of imagination, all sensations, or even abstract ideas, had to

proceed through the imagination—becoming emotionally charged in the

process—before they could reach the mind. Hence, erotic theory held that

when a man fell in love with a woman, he was really in love not with the

woman herself but with her image, one that, once lodged in his pneumatic

system, gradually came to hijack it, vampirizing his imagination and

ultimately drawing off all his physical and spiritual energies. Medical

writers tended to represent this as a disease that needed to be cured;

poets and lovers represented it as a heroic state that combined

pleasures (in fantasy but also, somewhat perversely, in the very

experience of frustration and denial) with an intrinsic spiritual or

mystical value in itself. The one thing all agreed on, though, is that

anyone who got the idea that one could resolve the matter by “embracing”

the object of his or her fantasy was missing the point. The very idea

was considered a symptom of a profound mental disorder, a species of

“melancholia.”

Here Agamben discusses Ficino:

In the same passage, the specific character of melancholic Eros was

identified by Ficino as disjunction and excess. “This tends to occur,”

he wrote, “to those who, misusing love, transform what rightly belongs

to contemplation into the desire of the embrace.” The erotic intention

that unleashes the melancholic disorder presents itself as that which

would possess and touch what ought merely to be the object of

contemplation, and the tragic insanity of the saturnine temperament thus

finds its root in the intimate contradiction of a gesture that would

embrace the unobtainable. (Agamben 1993b:17–18)

Agamben goes on to quote the French scholastic Henry of Ghent to the

effect that melancholics “cannot conceive the incorporeal” as such

because they do not know “how to extend their intelligence beyond space

and size.” For such depressive characters, lonely brooding is punctuated

by frustrated urges to seize what cannot really be seized.[20]

Now, one might quibble over whether anyone was ever quite so

consistently pure in his or her affections as all this might imply. A

fair amount of “embracing” certainly did go on in medieval Europe, as

elsewhere. Still, this was the ideal, and critically it became the model

not just for sexual desire but for desire in general—that is, at least

among the literate elites. This leads to the interesting suggestion that

from the perspective of this particular form of medieval psychological

theory, our entire civilization—as Campbell (1987) describes it—is

really a form of clinical depression, which in some ways does actually

make a lot of sense.[21]

Couliano (1987) is more interested in how erotic theory was appropriated

by Renaissance magicians such as Giordano Bruno, for whom the mechanics

of sexual attraction became the paradigm for all forms of attraction or

desire and, hence, the key to social power. If human beings tend to

become dominated by powerful, emotionally charged images, then anyone

who developed a comprehensive scientific understanding of the mechanics

by which such images work could become a master manipulator. It should

be possible to develop techniques for “binding” and influencing others’

minds, for instance, by fixing certain emotionally charged images in

their heads or even little bits of music (jingles, basically) that could

be designed in such a way as to keep coming back into people’s minds

despite themselves and pull them in one direction or another.[22] In all

of this, Couliano sees, not unreasonably, the first self-conscious form

of the modern arts of propaganda and advertising. Bruno felt his

services should be of great interest to princes and politicians.

It apparently never occurred to Bruno or anyone else in this early

period to apply such protoadvertising techniques to economic rather than

political purposes. Politics, after all, is about relations between

people. Manipulating others was, by definition, a political business,

which I think brings out the most fundamental difference between the

medieval conception of desire and the sort of thing Campbell (1987)

describes. If one starts with a model of desire where the object of

desire is assumed to be a human being, then it only makes sense that one

cannot completely possess the object. (“Embrace” is a nice metaphor,

actually, because it is so inherently fleeting.) And one is presumably

not intentionally in the business of destroying it, either.

One might say, then, as a starting point, that the shift from the kind

of model of desire that predominated in the Middle Ages and Renaissance

to the kind of consumerist model described by Campbell is a shift from

one whose paradigm is erotic to one in which the primary metaphor is

eating food.

Complications 1: Individualism

Still, even if one examines the original medieval version, the basic

conception is already surprisingly individualistic. This is because it

is so passive. Desire is the result of an individual receiving sense

impressions from outside. Now it is certainly true that this is one very

common experience of desire, as something that seems to seize us from

outside our conscious control, let alone better judgment, and often

causes us to do things for which we would really rather not hold

ourselves entirely responsible. But it also allows us to overlook the

fact that desire emerges in relations between people.

Granted, the relationship between lover and beloved, even an imaginary

one, is a relationship of a sort. Still, it is easier to see how much

this opens the way to a purely individualistic conception if one

compares this particular model of desire as developed explicitly in

medieval and Renaissance theory and tacitly through the sort of consumer

practice Campbell (1987) describes with, say, the kind of value-based

approach I have tried to develop elsewhere (Graeber 2001). Money, for

example, can be considered in Marxian terms as a representation of the

value (importance) of productive labor (human creative action) as well

as the means by which it is socially measured and coordinated, but it is

also a representation that brings into being the very thing it

represents, because after all, in a market economy, people work in order

to get money. Arguably, something analogous happens everywhere. Value

then could be said to be the way the importance of one’s own actions

register in the imagination—always by translation into some larger

social language or system of meaning, by being integrated into some

greater social whole. It also always happens through some kind of

concrete medium—which can be almost anything (wampum, oratorical

performances, sumptuous tableware, kula artifacts, Egyptian

pyramids)—and these objects in turn (unless they are utterly generic

substances, such as money, that represent sheer potentiality) tend to

incorporate in their own structure a kind of schematic model of the

forms of creative action that bring them into being but that also become

objects of desire that end up motivating actors to carry out those very

actions. Just as the desire for money inspires one to labor, the desire

for tokens of honor inspires forms of honorable behavior, the desire for

tokens of love inspires romantic behavior, and so on.[23]

By contrast, pneumatic theory begins not from actions but from what

might once have been called “passions.” Godfrey Lienhardt (1961) long

ago pointed out that while actions and passions form a logical

set—either you act on the world or the world acts on you—we have become

so uncomfortable with the idea of seeing ourselves as passive recipients

that the latter term has almost completely disappeared from the way we

talk about experience. Medieval and Renaissance authors did not yet have

such qualms. In pneumatic theory, “passions” are not what one does but

what is done to one (where one is not agent but “patient”); at the same

time, they referred, as they do now, to strong emotions that seem to

seize us against our will. The two were linked: emotions such as love

were in fact seen as being caused by just such impressions on the

pneumatic system. Far from being models of action, in fact, passivity

came to be seen as a virtue in itself: it was those who tried to act on

their passions, to seize the object rather than contemplate it, who

really missed the point.

Framing things in such passive terms then opened the way for that

extreme individualism that appears to be the other side of the

peculiarly Western theory of desire. A schema of action is almost of

necessity a collective product; the impression of a beautiful image is

something that one can imagine involves a relation between only two

people or even (insofar as love became a mystical phenomenon) between

the desirer and God. Even with romantic love, the ideal was that it

should not really be translated into an ongoing social relation but

remain a matter of contemplation and fantasy.

Complications 2: Shifting Lines of Class and Gender

All this makes it easier to understand how it might be possible to shift

from erotic fantasies to something more like the modern idea of

“consumption.” Still, the transition, I would argue, also required a

number of other conceptual shifts and displacements in terms of both

class and gender.

Compare, for example, how images of paradise in medieval and early

modern Europe varied by social milieu. When peasants, craftspeople, and

the urban poor tried to imagine a land in which all desires would be

fulfilled, they tended to focus on the abundance of food. Hence, the

land of Cockaigne, where bloated people loll about as geese fly fully

cooked into their mouths, rivers run with beer, and so forth. Carnival,

as Mikhail Bakhtin (1984) so richly illustrated, expands on all the same

themes, jumbling together every sort of bodily indulgence and enormity,

pleasures sexual as well as gastronomic and every other kind. Still, the

predominant imagery always centers on sausages, hogsheads, legs of

mutton, lard and tripes, and tubs of wine. The emphasis on food is in

striking contrast with visions of earthly paradise in other parts of the

world at that time (such as those prevalent in the Islamic world), which

were mostly about sex. Erotic fantasies are usually strikingly absent

from the literature on the Land of Cockaigne; if they are present, they

seem thrown in rather by way of an afterthought.

As Herman Pleij (2001:421) has pointed out, the medieval high-culture

version of paradise was in many ways conceived in direct opposition to

the popular one—not that it emphasized erotic pleasures, either.

Instead, it tended to fix on what we would now call elite consumables,

the exotic commodities of the day that were primarily essences: spices

above all but also incense, perfumes, and similar delicate scents and

flavors. Instead of the Land of Cockaigne, one finds a hankering after

the lost Garden of Eden, thought to exist somewhere in the East, near

the fabled kingdom of Prester John (Delumeau 2000)—anyway, from

somewhere near those fragrant lands whence cardamom, mace, peppers, and

cumin (not to mention frankincense and myrrh) were harvested. Rather

than a land of complete fatty indulgence in every sort of food, these

were often conceived as lands whose ethereal inhabitants did not have to

eat at all but simply subsisted on beautiful smells (Friedman 1981;

Schivelbusch 1992). This emphasis on refined flavors and fragrances in

turn opens onto a whole different realm of experience: of “taste,”

ephemerality, fleeting essences, and, ultimately, the familiar elite

consumption worlds of fashion, style, and the pursuit of ungraspable

novelty. Once again, then, the elite—who in reality, of course, tended

to grasp and embrace all sorts of things—constructed their ideal of

desire around that which somehow seemed to escape their hold. One might

argue that the modern consumer ethos is built on a kind of fusion

between these two class ideals. The shift from a conception of desire

modeled on erotic love to one based on the desire for food

(“consumption”) was clearly a shift in the direction of popular

discourse; at the same time, though, one might say the innovative aspect

of modern consumeristic theories of desire is to combine the popular

materialist emphasis on consumption with the notion of the ephemeral

ungraspable image as the driving force of maximization of production.

This might at least suggest a solution to what has always struck me as a

profound paradox in Western social theory. As I have already noted, the

idea of human beings as creatures tainted by original sin and therefore

cursed with infinite wants, as beings living in a finite universe who

were inevitably in a state of generalized competition, was already fully

developed by authors such as St. Augustine and therefore formed an

accepted part of Christian doctrine throughout the Middle Ages. At the

same time, very few people actually seemed to behave like this.

Economically, the Middle Ages were still the time of “target incomes,”

in which the typical reaction to economic good times, even among urban

craftspeople and most of the protobourgeoisie, was to take more days

off. It is as if the notion of the maximizing individual existed in

theory long before it emerged in practice. One explanation might be that

until the early modern period, at least, high culture (whether in its

most Christian or most courtly versions) tended to devalue any open

display of greed, appetite, or acquisitiveness, while popular

culture—which could sometimes heartily embrace such impulses—did so in

forms that were inherently collective. When the Land of Cockaigne was

translated into reality, it was in the form of popular festivals such as

Carnival; almost any increase in popular wealth was immediately diverted

into communal feasts, parades, and collective indulgences. One of the

processes that made capitalism possible, then, was what might be termed

the “privatization of desire.” The highly individualistic perspectives

of the elite had to be combined with the materialistic indulgences of

what Bakhtin liked to call the “material lower stratum.”

Getting from there to anything like the capitalist notion of consumption

required, I think, one further shift, this time along lines not of class

but of gender. The courtly love literature and related theories of

desire represent a purely male perspective,[24] and this no doubt was

true of fantasies about the Land of Cockaigne and similar idealized

worlds of gastronomic fulfillment, too. Although here it was

complicated, the fact is that in the folk psychology of the day, women

were widely considered more lustful, greedy, and generally desirous than

men. Insofar as anyone was represented as insatiable, then, it was

women: the image of woman as a ravenous belly, demanding ever more sex

and food, and men as haplessly laboring in an endless but ultimately

impossible effort to satisfy them is a standard misogynist topos going

back at least to Hesiod. Christian doctrine only reinforced it by

saddling women with the primary blame for original sin and thus

insisting that they bore the brunt of the punishment. It was only around

the time of the industrial revolution and the full split between

workplace and household that this sort of rhetoric was largely set aside

and women—proper bourgeois women, anyway—were redefined as innocent,

largely sexless creatures, guardians of homes that were no longer seen

as places of production but as “havens in a heartless world.”

Significantly, it was at just the moment that consumption came to be

defined as an essentially feminine business (Davis 1975:125–151; Graeber

1997; Thomas 1971:568–569; cf. Federici 2004).

The legacy of this shift is still with us. As feminist theorists

emphasize (e.g., Bordo 1993), women in contemporary consumer culture

remain caught in a perpetual suspension between embodying the extremes

of both spirit and matter, transcendent image and material reality, that

seems to play itself out in impossible dilemmas about food.

On Having Your Cake and Eating It, Too, and Certain Problems

Incumbent Therein

What I am suggesting, then, is that while medieval moralists accepted in

the abstract that humans were cursed with limitless desires—that, as

Augustine put it, their natures rebelled against them just as they had

rebelled against God—they did not think this was an existential dilemma

that affected them; rather, people tended to attribute such sinful

predilections mainly to people they saw as social and therefore moral

inferiors. Men saw women as insatiable; the prosperous saw the poor as

grasping and materialistic. It was really in the early modern period

that all this began to change.

Agamben (1993a) has a theory as to why this happened. He suggests that

the idea that all humans are driven by infinite unquenchable desires is

possible only when one severs imagination from experience. In the world

posited by medieval psychology, desires could be satisfied for the very

reason that they were really directed at phantasms: imagination was the

zone in which subject and object, lover and beloved, could genuinely

meet and partake of one another. With Descartes, he argues, this began

to change. Imagination was redefined as something inherently separate

from experience—as, in fact, a compendium of all those things (dreams,

flights of fancy, pictures in the mind) that one feels one has

experienced but really has not. It was at this point, once we were

expected to try to satisfy one’s desires in what we have come to think

of as “the real world,” that the ephemeral nature of experience, and

therefore of any “embrace,” becomes an impossible dilemma (Agamben

1993b:25–28). One is already seeing such dilemmas worked out in De Sade,

he argues, again around the same time as the dawn of consumer culture.

This is pretty much the argument one would have to make if one were to

confine oneself, as Agamben does, entirely to literary and philosophical

texts. In the past couple sections I have been trying to develop a more

socially nuanced approach that argues, among other things, that the

modern concept of “consumption,” which carries with it the tacit

assumption that there is no end to what anyone might want, could really

only take form once certain elite concepts of desire—as the pursuit of

ephemera and phantasms—fused, effectively, with the popular emphasis on

food. Still, I do not think this is quite a complete or adequate

explanation. There is, I believe, another element that made all this

possible, perhaps inevitable. This was the expansion of the market in

the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries and the redefinition of the

world according to an essentially market logic that came to accompany

it. MacPherson (1962) first referred to it as an ideology of “possessive

individualism”—but in this case, an ideology that extended far beyond

the disputations of the learned and effected the perceptions of artisans

and rabble-rousing politicians—one by which people increasingly came to

see themselves as isolated beings who defined their relation with the

world not in terms of social relations but in terms of property rights.

It was only then that the problem of how one could “have” things, or for

that matter experiences (“we’ll always have Paris”), could really become

a crisis.[25]

There is a great deal of debate about when the ideal of private property

in the modern sense first developed and how early it could be said to

have become common sense even among the popular classes. Some (e.g.,

MacFarlane 1998) insist that it was well under way in the High Middle

Ages, at least in England. It was certainly so by the time of

Cromwell.[26] The notion of “consumption,” I would suggest, eventually

came to resolve a certain contradiction inherent within this ideal.

From an analytical perspective, of course, property is simply a social

relation: an arrangement between persons and collectivities concerning

the disposition of valuable goods. Private property is one particular

that entails one individual’s right to exclude all others—“all the

world”—from access to a certain house or shirt or piece of land, and so

on. A relation so broad is difficult to imagine, however, so people tend

to treat it as if it were a relation between a person and an object. But

what could a relation between a person and an object actually consist

of?

In English law, such relations are still described according to the

logic of sovereignty—that is, in terms of dominium. The power a citizen

has over his or her own possessions is exactly the same power once held

by kings and princes and that is still retained by states in the form of

“eminent domain.” This is why private property rights took so long to

enshrine in law: even in England, which led the way in such matters, it

was almost the eighteenth century before jurists were willing to

recognize a dominium belonging to anyone other than the king (Aylmer

1980).What would it mean, then, to establish “sovereignty” over an

object? In legal terms, a king’s dominium extended to his land, his

subjects, and their possessions; the subjects were “included in” the

person of the king, who represented them in dealing with other kingdoms,

in a similar fashion to that by which the father of a family represented

his wife, children, and servants before the law. The wife, children, and

servants of a head of household were likewise “included in” his legal

personality in much the same way as his possessions. And in fact the

power of kings was always being likened to that of fathers; the only

real difference (aside from the fact that in any conflict, the king was

seen to have a higher claim) was that unlike fathers, kings wielded the

power of life and death over their subjects. These were the ultimate

stakes of sovereignty; certainly, it was the one power kings were least

willing to delegate or share.[27] The ultimate proof that one has

sovereign power over another human being is one’s ability to have the

other executed. In a similar fashion, one might argue, the ultimate

proof of possession, of one’s personal dominium over a thing, is one’s

ability to destroy it—and indeed this remains one of the key legal ways

of defining dominium, as a property right, to this day. But there is an

obvious problem here. If one does destroy the object, one may have

definitively proved that one owned it, but, as a result, one does not

have it any more.

We end up, then, with what might seem a particularly perverse variation

on Hegel’s master/slave dialectic in which the actor, seeking some sort

of impossible recognition of absolute mastery of an inanimate object,

can achieve this recognition only by destroying it. Still, I do not

really think this is a variation on the master/slave dilemma. I think a

better case could probably be made that the dilemma described by Hegel

actually derives from this. After all, the one thing least explained in

Hegel’s account is where the necessity of conflict comes from (after

all, there are ways to risk one’s life to impress another person that do

not involve trying to murder that person).[28] Hegel’s quest for

recognition does not lead to the destruction of property, but it does

lead to a choice of either destroying the Other or reducing the Other to

property. Relations that are not based on property—or, more precisely,

on that very ambiguous synthesis between the two types of

sovereignty—suddenly become impossible to imagine, and I think this is

true because Hegel is starting from a model of possessive individualism.

At any rate, the paradox exists, and it is precisely here where the

metaphor of “consumption” gains its appeal because it is the perfect

resolution of this paradox[29] —or, at least, about as perfect a

resolution as one is ever going to get. When you eat something, you do

indeed destroy it (as an autonomous entity), but at the same time, it

remains “included in” you in the most material of senses.[30] Eating

food, then, became the perfect idiom for talking about desire and

gratification in a world in which everything, all human relations, were

being reimagined as questions of property.

Hence we return to Hegel. But I want to emphasize here that Hegel is not

the starting point of this journey. He’s the end. An account that

focused on the actual emergence of the term “consumption” in the late

eighteenth century and early nineteenth century would, no doubt, have to

contend with the broader sociopolitical context of Hegel’s day. As Susan

Buck-Morss (2000; see also Fischer 2004) has recently made clear, Hegel

composed his master/slave dialectic with questions of real colonial

slavery—particularly, the revolution in Haiti—very much at the forefront

of his mind. The reappearance of actual chattel slavery in Europe and

its colonies was of course another direct result of the emergence of

possessive individualism and caused endless dilemmas for its

ideologists. The connections here are infinitely complicated: I have

argued that capitalism is really a transformation of slavery and cannot

be understood outside it (Graeber 2005). But in this essay, in this

argument, by taking things back to the eleventh century, before Western

Europeans had a colonial empire and when chattel slavery was at its low

ebb, I am trying to cast the net even broader to ask, What, in fact, are

the origins of that attitude toward the material world that allowed

people in certain corners of Atlantic Europe to create these colonial

empires to begin with? If we do not ask such questions, we are left with

the tacit assumption that there is nothing to be explained here, that

anyone in a position to massacre and enslave millions of people in the

name of personal profit would naturally wish to do so. I would hardly

suggest I have offered a full explanation for this, but I think the

material assembled here is quite suggestive in this regard.

Conclusions: What about Consumerism?

What does all this imply about the current use of the term

“consumption”? For one thing, I think it suggests we should think about

how far we want to extend the metaphor—as Wilk (2004) has justly

emphasized, a metaphor is all this really is. It makes perfect sense to

talk about the “consumption” of fossil fuels. It is quite another thing

to talk about the “consumption” of television programming—much though

this has been the topic of endless books and essays. Why, exactly, are

we calling this “consumption”? About the only reason I can see is that

television programming is created by people paid wages and salaries

somewhere other than where viewers are watching it. Otherwise, there

appears to be no reason at all. Programming is not even a commodity,

because viewers often do not pay for it (and in the past they almost

never did); it is not in any direct sense “consumed” by its viewers.[31]

It is hardly something one fantasizes about acquiring, and one cannot,

in fact, acquire it. It is in no sense destroyed by use. Rather, we are

dealing with a continual stream of potential fantasy material, some

intended to market particular commodities, some not. Cultural studies

scholars and anthropologists writing in the same vein will of course

insist that these images are not simply passively absorbed by

“consumers” but actively interpreted and appropriated in ways the

producers would probably never have suspected and employed as ways of

fashioning identities—the “creative consumption” model again. It is the

undoubted truth that there are people who design their identities around

certain TV shows. In fact, there are people who organize much of their

imaginative life around one particular show—Trekkies, for instance, who

participate in a subculture of fans who write stories or comic zines

around their favorite characters, attend conventions, design costumes,

and the like. But when a 16year-old girl writes a short story about

forbidden love between Kirk and Spock, this is hardly consumption any

more; we are talking about people engaging in a complex community

organized around forms of (relatively unalienated) production. One can

imagine here a kind of continuum with this representing one extreme. At

the other, we have a considerable slice of television viewing by people

who work 40 or 50 hours a week at jobs they find mind-numbingly boring,

extremely stressful, or both; who commute; who come home far too

exhausted and emotionally drained to be able to engage in any of the

activities they would consider truly rewarding, pleasurable, or

meaningful; and who just plop down in front the of the tube because it

is the easiest thing to do.[32] In other words, when “creative

consumption” is at its most creative, it is not really consumption at

all; when it most resembles something we would call “consumption,” it is

at its least creative. And there is no particular reason to define

television watching as “consumption” at all.[33]

Does it really matter that we use the word “consumption” when speaking

of television programming as opposed to some other term? Actually, I

think it matters a great deal. Because, ultimately, doing so represents

a political choice: it means that we align ourselves with one body of

writing and research— in this case, the one most closely aligned with

the language and interests of the corporate world and not with others—

in this instance, that activist literature explicitly critical of the

role of television in contemporary life. Around the same time as Steve

Barnett was dropping out of academia to become an advertising

consultant, an advertising executive named Jerry Mander (1978) abandoned

the business world to publish a book called Four Arguments for the

Elimination of Television using his own technical knowledge of the

industry to make a case that the common popular discourse that sees

television as a mind-numbing drug and advertisers as cynical

manipulators is entirely accurate. Unlike the works of exponents of the

“creative consumption” paradigm, which remain largely confined to the

desks of graduate students and marketing executives, this volume found a

ready popular audience and continues to sell well to the present day.

The same can be said of more recent additions to the literature, such as

Kalle Lasn’s (1999) Culture Jam, and of the flagship journal of the

antimarketing activists, Adbusters, largely composed by current or

former employees in the industry, which (unlike, say, the Journal of

Consumer Research) can occasionally even be found for sale in

supermarket checkout lines (even if, admittedly, mostly cooperative

supermarkets). Some of this literature—which incidentally tends to take

a neo-Situationist rather than a Frankfurt School approach[34] —may be

anthropologically naive, but this is largely because anthropologists

have played almost no role in helping shape it. This literature in turn

overlaps with the truly voluminous critical literature on TV journalism,

corporate public relations, and the mediatization of political life,

from which again anthropologists have largely excluded themselves even

if they may often be personally sympathetic. Pierre Bourdieu’s (1999) On

Television, for instance, which emerges from this tradition and which

was a surprise best seller in France, has gone largely unnoticed as a

result. What I am really trying to draw attention to here is the

profound irony of the situation. While academics that espouse such

opinions risk being instantly denounced as elitists with contempt for

“ordinary people,” these opinions seem to resonate with many “ordinary

people” in a way that the creative consumption literature never has.

Oddly, those writing in venues such as the Journal of Consumer Research

itself often seem more open to this critical literature than most

anthropologists,[35] perhaps because they are aware that one cannot very

well represent consumers as subversive unless there is something out

there, some dominant ideology, for them to subvert. After all, if all

that existed was a collection of subcultures, there could not also be

countercultures, as there would be no hegemony for them to resist. The

shadow of the Frankfurt School’s “mass society” must therefore be

preserved if only to be eternally transcended. This is perhaps also why

the story with which I began, that “we used to be naive Marxists,” has

effectively become a permanent element in academic socialization. We all

come to graduate school already aware of the anticonsumerist discourse

precisely because it is a popular discourse (if obviously not the only

one). Part of our initiation into that peculiar elite that is academia

is our learning to denounce that discourse as elitist.

What methodological conclusions am I suggesting, then? Above all, I

think we should be suspicious about importing the political economy

habit of seeing society as divided into two spheres, one of production

and one of consumption,[36] into cultural analysis in the first place.

Doing so almost inevitably forces us to push almost all forms of

nonalienated production into the category of consumption or even

“consumer behavior.” Consider the following passage, found (in fact) in

a critique of the culture of consumption:

Cooking, playing sports, gardening, DIY (Do-It-Yourself), home

decoration, dancing and music-making are all examples of consumer

activities which involve some participation, but they cannot of

themselves transform the major invasion by commercial interest groups

into consumption which has occurred since the 1950s. (Bocock 1993:51)

According to the logic of the quote above, if I bought some vegetables

and prepared a gazpacho to share with some friends, that is actually

consumerism. In fact, it would be even if I grew the vegetables myself

(presumably because I bought the seeds). We are back to my earlier

parable of the garage band. Any production not for the market is treated

as a form of consumption, which has the incredibly reactionary political

effect of treating almost every form of unalienated experience we do

engage in as somehow a gift granted us by the captains of industry.

How to think our way out of this box? No doubt there are many ways. This

paper is meant more to explain why it is important to do so than to

propose an actual solution. Still, one or two suggestions might be in

order. The first and most obvious is that we might begin treating

consumption not as an analytical term but as an ideology to be

investigated. Clearly, there are people in the world who do base key

aspects of their identity around what they see as the destructive

encompassment of manufactured products. Let us find out who these people

really are, when they think of themselves this way and when they do not,

and how they relate to others who conceive their relations to the

material world differently. If we wish to continue applying terms

borrowed from political economy—as I have myself certainly done

elsewhere (e.g., Graeber 2001, 2005)—it might be more enlightening to

start looking at what we have been calling the “consumption” sphere

rather as the sphere of the production of human beings, not just as

labor power but as persons, internalized nexes of meaningful social

relations, because after all, this is what social life is actually

about, the production of people (of which the production of things is

simply a subordinate moment), and it is only the very unusual

organization of capitalism that makes it even possible for us to imagine

otherwise.[37]

This is not to say that everything has to be considered a form of either

production or consumption (consider a softball game—it is clearly

neither), but it at least allows us to open up some neglected questions,

such as that of alienated and nonalienated forms of labor, terms that

have somewhat fallen into abeyance and therefore remain radically

undertheorized. What exactly does engaging in nonalienated production

actually mean? Such questions become all the more important when we

start thinking about capitalist globalization and resistance. Rather

than looking at people in Zambia or Brazil and saying “Look! They are

using consumption to construct identities!” and thus implying they are

willingly or perhaps unknowingly submitting to the logic of neoliberal

capitalism, perhaps we should consider that in many of the societies we

study, the production of material products has always been subordinate

to the mutual construction of human beings and what they are doing, at

least in part, is simply insisting on continuing to act as if this were

the case even when using objects manufactured elsewhere. In some cases,

this can turn into self-conscious resistance to—or, for that matter, an

equally self-conscious enthusiastic embrace of—consumer capitalism. But

in many cases, at least, I suspect that our issues and categories are

simply irrelevant.

One thing I think we can certainly assert. Insofar as social life is and

always has been mainly about the mutual creation of human beings, the

ideology of consumption has been endlessly effective in helping us

forget this. Most of all it does so by suggesting that (a) human desire

is essentially a matter not of relations between people but of relations

between individuals and phantasms; (b) our primary relation with other

individuals is an endless struggle to establish our sovereignty, or

autonomy, by incorporating and destroying aspects of the world around

them; (c) for the reason in c, any genuine relation with other people is

problematic (the problem of “the Other”); and (d) society can thus be

seen as a gigantic engine of production and destruction in which the

only significant human activity is either manufacturing things or

engaging in acts of ceremonial destruction so as to make way for more, a

vision that in fact sidelines most things that real people actually do

and insofar as it is translated into actual economic behavior is

obviously unsustainable. Even as anthropologists and other social

theorists directly challenge this view of the world, the unreflective

use—and indeed self-righteous propagation—of terms such as “consumption”

end up undercutting our efforts and reproducing the very tacit

ideological logic we are trying to call into question.

Comments

Robert Cluley and David Harvie

School of Management, University of Leicester, University Road,

Leicester LE1 7RH, United Kingdom (david.harvie@ gmail.com). 29 XI 10

We like this piece a lot. Our only real criticism is perhaps the journal

in which it is being published. It should be required reading for all

theorists of consumption, but alas, it seems few of them “consume”

Current Anthropology. A search on the Business Source Premier database

reveals that the journal has never been cited in any of the five

marketing journals ranked highest by the United Kingdom–based

Association of Business Schools or in “top” economics journals.

As Graeber stresses in his article, it is not that these disciplines do

not care about anthropology but that they largely care only about what

anthropology can do for them. (See Basbøll 2010 for an exemplary exposé

of the way organization studies scholars use and abuse anthropological

research.) Indeed, one of the most informative aspects of the essay is

the way it describes a performative power of “consumption” as an

imperialistic concept taking over the academic galaxy one discipline at

a time. Graeber shows us that many anthropologists have been willing to

add to the marketing and economics literature, but in so doing they have

accepted a readymeal understanding of consumption prepackaged by the

disciplinary demands of marketing and economics such that their research

serves to valorize the very category they should analyze.

Part of the appeal of consumption, then, is that it simultaneously

pleases the two handmaidens of the modern university: business and

intellectuals. It bridges the practical and the useless, the scholarly

and the mundane. But these material factors do not fully explain the

power of consumption-asconcept. All too often an analysis that focuses

on political economy does not take account of the libidinal economy.

Here Graeber shows us how the concept of consumption has changed over

time, from being a reference to waste and destruction to a mirror for

production in monopoly capitalism and now, finally, in the “consumer

society” to being a mirror to itself. It is not the things we consume

that are important to us anymore but that we consume. We no longer

produce things in a sphere of production that we consume elsewhere.

Rather, we consume everywhere. Or so say the scholars.

For many academics, consumption is a concept whose ingredients are milk

and honey. And it is true that for many of us in paradise, we plan to do

a lot of consuming. But there is a hell of a lot of consumption going on

in hell, too. Here, though, it is the individual who is being

consumed—by fire, hate, and frustration, by one’s inability to be

consumed. It is through prolonging desire, as desire for destruction,

that hell is imagined to be so, well, hellish. In hell, your appetites

are turned against you. The separation of appetite or desires and

consumption, we might conclude, is tantamount to hell. In short,

capitalism, for most people for most of the time, is a lot like hell.

And it is capitalism that produces this separation (or “scarcity” in the

language of economics) just as it consumes we who labor within it.

So for us, the power of Graeber’s piece is that it encourages us to ask

what the world might look like if we, like early political economists,

could draw a line around “consumption”—thus defining it and containing

it. (Indeed, it is notable that within marketing studies there is much

talk of a “nexus” between consumption and production, a blurring of the

categories, without ever specifying the contours of this nexus.)

Researchers would have to look at consumption rather than through

consumption. Traditionally, we have done this in terms of production,

but that has now melted into air or at least migrated to the global

South. But what if we had a concept other than production, consumption,

or some stupid combination of the two that would allow us to look into

the mirror of consumption rather than hold up another mirror to it?

If marketing scholars do not want to limit their studies, economists

rarely care, and anthropologists have been distracted by the very

concept they should be critiquing, what is to be done? One solution is

to look outside of academia. Those outside the academy are happy to

critique consumption. This work is being done. Graeber’s challenge to

us, though, is to force ourselves to regurgitate the concept, to stick

our scholarly fingers down our academic throats until we vomit up the

idea of consumption. The question is, once it has been exposed to the

disinfectants of sunlight, will we, like dogs, return to the concept and

swallow it down once more?

Dimitra Doukas

Independent Scholar, 408 West College Street, Fredericksburg, Texas

78624, U.S.A. (dimitra.doukas@gmail.com). 29 X 10

This is a very persuasive analysis. Consumption, Graeber argues, no

matter how creatively it is used by the people we study, is an ideology

that tricks us into shouldering the modernist assumption of an economy

with two spheres, production and consumption. Whatever is not production

for markets becomes, by default, consumption, a symbolic eating that

both destroys and incorporates its object. Relegated to the sphere of

consumption, social life appears as the pursuit of products, its

life-giving creativity all but forgotten. In this ideological regime,

social life itself, the “mutual creation of human beings,” can appear as

“a gift granted us by the captains of industry.”

What Graeber is doing here is one of anthropologists’ most important

tasks: owning up to the cultural bias in our analytical vocabulary and

pruning it out. In support of this necessarily social effort—the mutual

creation of anthropologists—I would like to draw out a couple of

Graeber’s points, add a pinch of four-fields perspective, and suggest

further hidden entanglements of consumerist ideology.

Consumption, Graeber argues, embeds an “impoverished” theory of “human

desire and fulfillment” that breaks decisively with all previous Western

tradition. Centuries of Western philosophy viewed desire not as directed

toward objects for consumption but toward social objectives:

recognition, “sympathetic attention,” sexual pleasure, wealth (for the

praise and esteem of others), and power.

By the early modern period, however, the achievement of these social

objectives had become a vexing problem in Western thought. Graeber

illustrates with a parable of Hegel’s: two men desire mutual recognition

as free, autonomous, fully human beings but only if the other is

worthy—the recognition of an inferior does not count. But determining

whether the other is equally free and autonomous brings these men to an

impossible dilemma. How could they know for sure? A fight would only end

in revealing the inferiority of the loser. (It is rather like the other

Marx’s not being interested in joining any club that would have him as a

member.)

Consumption, Graeber suggests, resolves the dilemma of such “passions”

by redirecting the imagination from relations with persons to relations

with things. This resonates with Albert O. Hirschman’s (1977) study of

writings from the early Modern period, in which the winning argument for

the removal of legal limits on European capitalists was the substitution

of “interests” for “passions.” Rather than destroying each other, the

ideology of consumption, in Graeber’s words, has individual consumers

relating to each other in “an endless struggle to establish ...

sovereignty, or autonomy, by incorporating and destroying aspects of the

world around them.”

The problem here is that a truly autonomous being would have no desire

for recognition from another nor any other kind of social relationship.

Hegel and those who followed this line of thinking were not so much

“starting from a model of possessive individualism,” as Graeber

proposes, but rather from one of innate competition, a model that would

soon surface as “survival of the fittest.” Human beings are in no way

autonomous. (Hegel’s two men meet “at the beginning of history,” having

never encountered another consciousness, i.e., in the impossible

condition of having survived infancy without caregivers.) To the

contrary, we are, as the late Walter Goldschmidt (2006) put it, innately

“affect hungry,” such sluts for recognition that we are likely to see

worthiness in anyone who offers us encouraging words, as flatterers and

cons the world over have always known.

Consumption in everyday practice is a way to satisfy our affect hunger,

and that is exactly what advertisers promise. Get love with cosmetics.

Get respect with a Lexus. Be the envy of your friends with the latest

electronic gizmo. But not everybody can play this game, and here is

where the question of worthiness breaks out on ever larger scales. Take

“keeping up with the Joneses,” a competitive consumption that is at the

same time a mutual creation of human beings—neighbors become worthy of

recognition by exhibiting the material signs of having engaged this

torturous labor-money system and having been able to claim some of its

prizes (tokens, as Graeber says, of the actions they represent). Who

cannot play? The unemployed and the so-called underclass—constructed as

unworthy in consumerist ideology, they suffer the fate of political

scapegoats.

Take the same dynamic global and we find “backward” multitudes who have

not “evolved” to the heights of modern consumption. As enslavement and

colonization were once justified by enlightening the benighted native,

so the unworthiness of the “backward” justifies a so-called

international development that covertly pursues the same goals: cheap

labor, cheap resources, mass markets. Hidden in the ideology of

consumption, no matter how creatively people use it, is the

world-shaking contempt of the West for “the rest” that our discipline

has long been at pains to deconstruct. Graeber is right. Let it go.

Felix Girke

Zentrum für Interdisziplinäre Regionalstudien, MartinLuther-Universität

Halle-Wittenberg, ReichardtstraĂźe 6, 06114 Halle/Saale, Germany

(felix.girke@zirs.uni-halle.de). 26 I 11

This commentary provides a welcome return to a familiar text, which has

gained only a few hundred words since its last and considerably less

centrally placed appearance (Graeber 2007b), and I do believe it has

earned its republication and discussion in this much more visible

format. David Graeber’s anamnesis of the current hypertrophic attention

to consumption is to me plausibly argued. My commentary, then, is not

intensely critical of the argument itself: there is currently a broad

public tendency to see citizens as consumers or as “customers” of their

own governments even. This does entail a number of disconcerting notions

about who we are, what we want, and how we go about getting what we

believe we need or, rather, what we ephemerally think we desire. Some

anthropologists, instead of deconstructing public discourse, are

consumed by the very idea of consumption, having accepted it as our own

analytical term instead of treating it as an epistemological arena, as a

concept that sits in fact rather uneasily between phenomenon and

category. But even in fields such as tourism, where “consumption of

people” has long been augmented to “cannibalism,” the metaphor needs to

be understood as just that: even if people feel as if they are being

eaten alive, they are, in fact, not. By calling this “consumption,” we

actively impoverish our tool kit. Graeber’s text does us the

considerable service of treating the ongoing consumption conversation as

data, as an empirical phenomenon just like others we study, and tracing

its emergence as well as some of its ramifications with great clarity.

In the end, he returns us to the anthropological commonplace that social

life is really about “the production of people,” a statement echoing

Stephen Gudeman’s (2009) consistent calls for attention to what he has

termed the base, “the incommensurable collection of goods and services

mediating relationships between people, and connecting them to things

and intangibles,” providing “conditions for sustaining locally

constituted life” (64). Not every object-oriented segment of individual

behavior is an equally meaningful actualization of the self.

Still, has the argument not overstayed its welcome? Complaints about the

turn to consumption and its particulars are not a particularly new

phenomenon within anthropology; by now 15 years old, there are the

gently cautioning words by Jim Carrier (1996), “whether consumption is

the new master narrative we ought to construct about the world and, if

so, how we ought to construct it” (422), and Carrier and Heyman’s (1997)

only slightly later explicitly stated “intellectual and political

dissatisfaction with the anthropology of consumption” (356). Strikingly,

in these earlier texts, the hypertrophic overextension of the term was

not a critical issue; in fact, the authors themselves might be targets

for Graeber’s criticism because they include items from housing to

television in the category of consumption. Their thrust, then, was

instead turned against one-dimensional semiological analyses of the

“meaning” of objects rather than their actual consequences and practical

applications and the larger contextual constraints of class and race,

that is, inequality. Additionally, Carrier and Heyman (1997) emphasize

how much of consumption is in fact about reproduction of the household,

about necessity and practical uses more than about fantastic desires, a

turn that also allows them to divert the focus away from “the individual

actors who populate much of the conventional consumption literature”

(362). This is where they again converge with Graeber’s stance against

the commonly involved emancipatory narratives, which while seemingly

liberating the constrained agents and turning them into selfactualizing

individuals (or members of self-actualizing sub/ countercultures; e.g.,

Habeck/Ventsel 2009) also cast them out of their supportive dependences.

Of course, this eviction locks such agents with quite a bit of

interpretive violence into the everyday battle for “recognition,” which

in its antagonistic sense is usefully shown here as a social

unobtainium.

This leads me to the intriguing methodological (as well as ideological)

alternative of acknowledging “passion(s)” along with actions/agency.

Burkhard Schnepel (2009), not coincidentally a student of Godfrey

Lienhardt’s, has recently suggested a return of this dialectic to its

proper place: it could serve both to balance the overly individualistic

and infuriatingly vague postmodern propagation of human agency and to

better understand certain emic positions in which, classically, one does

not catch a cold but is caught by a cold. Just because it is more

difficult to talk about passions does not mean we should not try to do

it. Thinking through this dialectic, then, we soon reach the field of

the middle voice, where desire (to have, to absorb) might be reconceived

as “something that befalls the subject without subjugating him or her”

(Eberhard 2004:63), with untold effects on the idea of consumption. Such

an understanding might be critical for the research program suggested by

Graeber, to work out what it is that actually drives people to

destructive encompassment. In this theoretical tangent, I find this

valorously quixotic paper most stimulating.

Alf Hornborg

Human Ecology Division, Lund University, Sölvegatan 12, 223 62 Lund,

Sweden (alf.hornborg@hek.lu.se). 26 XI 10

Although at times more convoluted than necessary, Graeber’s argument is

a welcome antidote to the currently fashionable neoliberal discourse on

consumption as creative self-expression. He is supremely justified in

asking how anthropologists became engaged in marketing and is to be

congratulated for reorienting anthropology toward a critical analysis of

the cultural foundations of capitalism. His paper raises several

worthwhile questions that deserve lucid and coherent treatment. The

least problematic is how consumption became a field of anthropology. For

many, it was Marshall Sahlins’s (1976) useful elaboration of Baudrillard

that taught us to view commodities as elements of semiotic systems that

shoppers sought to incorporate into their selves, as the consummation of

culturally constituted desires. Such an understanding of consumption, of

course, is not in itself a reason to turn to marketing.

Graeber provides several persuasive historical hypotheses for why the

metaphor of eating is now applied to whatever people do when they are

not working, including the fusion of medieval elite desires for ephemera

and plebeian desires for food, the expansion of market principles and

individual property rights, and the urge to destroy things in order to

gain recognition of one’s sovereignty over them. Eating is indeed the

perfect idiom for destroying something while literally incorporating it.

But Graeber argues that many activities conventionally classified as

consumption, such as watching television, do not involve goods that are

destroyed by use. Nor, for the same reason, does he think that a teenage

band practicing in a garage should be called consumption. Yet even these

activities must submit to the twin constraints of capitalism and the law

of entropy (Georgescu-Roegen 1971) that correctly identify consumption

as destruction: any activity that, for want of other resources, must

involve manufactured goods—or even using electricity—implies destroying

purchased physical resources in the process of creating meaning. The

concept of consumption thus deserves to be retained, paradoxically, for

its critical potential: because it highlights how that which capitalism

would have us maximize is ultimately destroying the planet. While there

is no exemption from entropy whatever the mode of production, the

specificity of capitalism lies in its relentless pursuit of ever higher

rates of resource destruction.

It thus seems that Graeber’s call for an abandonment of the discourse on

consumption, although highly understandable when directed at its

neoliberal version, would be at odds with those activists for whom the

concept remains integral to their criticism of the treadmill logic of

capitalism. His paper, conceived in the early 1990s and published some

years ago (Graeber 2007a), criticizes the concept of consumption from

two opposite angles, that is, for being perceived as creativity and

destruction. As much as I share his skepticism regarding the ideological

uses of the former perception, I am unable to abandon the latter (even

when applied to television programming). In fact, it is only by

acknowledging the material biophysical dimension of the global economy

that we can resist the seductive neoliberal glorification of consumption

as the right to creative self-expression.

Graeber traces the historical recognition that consumer desires are

potentially infinite and quite possible to manipulate. Clearly, it is

this latter dilemma that raises the most incisive doubts about

capitalism rather than the extent of resource destruction itself. For if

profits are proportional to our “creative” destruction of resources, it

means that marketing will be geared to fabricating increasingly

arbitrary incentives for us to maximize such destruction. To continue to

expose this fundamental logic seems a more trenchant criticism of

neoliberalism than to debate whether this or that activity is really

destructive of resources.

The most significant point in Graeber’s paper is his observation that

consumption is really about the production of people, echoing Marx’s

insight that in capitalism, relations between people masquerade as

relations between things. The human appropriation (and incorporation) of

things has always been about the production of persons, but as Graeber

reminds us, commodity fetishism encourages us to imagine otherwise.

Although the idea of private property is a thoroughly social relation,

that is, a person’s right to exclude others from access to a thing, it

presents itself to us as a relation between that person and that thing.

Nor do we generally see that the commodity is an embodiment of other

people’s labor and landscapes. If the consumer’s sovereignty over his or

her commodified objects is modeled on the monarch’s sovereignty over his

or her subjects, as Graeber suggests, the affinity between the two

relations thus boils down to a transformation of social power. Viewed in

this light, it is indeed revealing to see capitalism as a transformation

of slavery or even cannibalism. Graeber’s (2001, 2004, 2007a)

stimulating and entertaining contributions to economic anthropology

continue to generate insights about how human relations to objects are

ultimately about their relations to other humans, whether objects are

treated as humans or humans are treated as objects.

Peter N. Stearns

Office of the Provost, George Mason University, 4400 University Drive,

MS 3A2, Fairfax, Virginia 22030, U.S.A. (pstearns@gmu.edu). 5 X 10.

The challenge to open a new discussion on the meaning of consumerism is

both welcome and stimulating. I am accurately cited in David Graeber’s

article as among the several historians who have worked to identify the

emergence of new forms of consumer behavior in the Western world in the

eighteenth century, and it is useful to be reminded of how new

conceptualizations began to emerge at this point, if initially among the

dreaded economists, as well as new behaviors.

Even with a commitment toward identifying significant historical change

and using new intensities of consumer activities as one measure, the

need to explore continuities, which the Graeber essay emphasizes under

the broader category of desire, unquestionably deserves more scrutiny

than it has received from historians and others. Even those of us who

think that something new and important was emerging in early modern

Europe have faced the question of whether the essential novelty resulted

simply from greater prosperity and new shopkeeper lures, not from new

motivations at all. Is the consumer potential rather uniformly present

in human makeup, or at least Western cultural makeup, so that its

awakening requires little explanation once new levels of mass affluence

set in? The invitation to think more about continuities in desire—even

though framed in this essay largely in terms of intellectual constructs

rather than popular motivations— advances the issue constructively while

partly redefining it.

There are, I think, a few additional angles to explore under this

general heading, not in frontal opposition to the Graeber formulation

but by way of extension and complication. First, a historian looking at

pre-eighteenth-century illustrations of premodern desire would not focus

solely or even primarily on the Western context. (I always worry about

Western statements that lack any real comparative ballast.) Those of us

interested in the emergence of consumerism but with a disproportionately

European or U.S. history background need to pay a great deal more

attention to the earlier emergence of consumer commitments in prosperous

urban settings such as Song China, where, among other things, tastes and

possibly motivations emerged that would directly influence European

interests later on. To the extent that we accept the Graeber focus on

desire as a human or at least clearly premodern category, we may need to

explore Asian (and probably other) manifestations as well. (It is also

relevant to note that Chinese consumerism, if that is what it should be

called, emerged in a cultural context officially hostile to undue

emphasis on romantic or erotic attachments.) Of course, premodern

Chinese consumerism, like its European outcropping until recently,

frequently encountered societal disapproval, with arrests and even

executions responding to some of the most vigorous consumer behaviors,

but this does not contradict the existence and significance of relevant

desire. Modern consumerism is gaining some excellent comparative

attention from several disciplines including both history and

anthropology, but we may well need more premodern work as well.

Even for the Western context, particularly before the eighteenth century

but to an extent even since, I wonder also about a possible overemphasis

on individualism. Another avenue to explore—and it may also encompass

identifiable categories of desire—involves group consumerism. Premodern

cities in the West but also elsewhere burst with group consumer projects

(and I know by now I am referencing consumerism a lot despite the

admonitions in the Graeber article). Religious projects were front and

center, with consumer decisions about church and clergy styles and

decorations, but guild presentations count as well. One of the

constraints on individual consumerism was the pervasive emphasis on

using costume and other objects to denote group identity and conformity,

though in terms of a basic definition of acquisitive efforts beyond the

needs of any reasonable subsistence, they fit a consumerism umbrella.

And this element, though by now far less organized, has hardly

disappeared from consumer behavior. The frequency of individual

decisions to acquire items or entertainments that in fact help blend

with a recognizable group—the peer cluster in school, the office

assemblage—is another complexity in consumerism that needs attention.

Here, too, links with as well as changes from more traditional patterns

factor in substantially.

All this said, let me return to my admiration for the Graeber hypothesis

about a transition, at least in Western culture, between desire for a

person to a desire for things (whether the food consumption focus is

entirely apt requires discussion, but it is beside the main point). I am

not sure I agree that this is what happened; certainly, it is not what

many new consumers thought was happening when they hoped to use objects

to express not only personal identity but also sexual or affectionate

relationships with loved ones. But perhaps it did happen, playing a role

in the misfiring of relationships in the modern Western world, and it

certainly is worth further exploration and analysis.

David Sutton

Department of Anthropology, Southern Illinois University, Mailcode 4502,

Carbondale, Illinois 62901, U.S.A. (dsutton@ siu.edu). 8 XI 10

In the 1940s a Swedish sociologist traveled through the villages of

northern Sweden asking people about their “hobbies.” A farmer confronted

with this newfangled word hesitated, then answered “chopping wood.” (Ehn

and Lofgren 2010:111)

David Graeber’s article is a trenchant reminder of how problematic the

categories of political economy are for anthropological analysis.[38]

They were problematic in the 1970s, when it was all about modes of

production, and they are problematic now that the focus has turned to

consumption. The first step in thinking beyond these categories is to

excavate them, which Graeber does with his fascinating genealogy of the

concept of desire in the Western philosophical tradition. To the extent

that consumption studies have become ubiquitous and many of them fail to

define or even think through what is meant by the term “consumption,”

Graeber’s critique is all the more cogent. I think many of us are

familiar with the kind of studies he is referring to: ones that claim,

for example, that McDonald’s in Japan is really not so bad because they

serve squid, too (thus short-circuiting or deflecting attention from any

serious critique of their sourcing, labor, waste disposal, and other

practices). These types of analysis are so ubiquitous that one of my

students, Leo Vournelis, dubbed them the “It’s OK, they’ve appropriated

it” school of thought.

One of the key contributions of Graeber’s approach, then, is to get us

to consider the possibility of different models to analyze activities we

have been lumping under the consumption rubric. Surely, he is right that

it is dubious at best to think of television watching as an act of

“consumption,” and it would be more interesting to look at the

categories that people bring to the activity of television watching in

different contexts and communities. But I would like to briefly focus on

one object that Graeber has suggested is the epitome of consumption:

food. Indeed, food could be seen as “consumed” in the act of eating, and

Melanesian anthropologists— for example, Weiner (1992)—have claimed that

this is what makes food of limited social value: unlike shells, it is

used up in its transacting and thus cannot carry enduring meaning.

Indeed, Graeber suggests in his history of Western desire that food

plays a particular role: he sees it as key to the transition from

medieval and Renaissance to modern notions of consumption, from erotics

to gastronomics. The model of modern consumption, Graeber suggests,

highlights food because eating was “the perfect idiom for talking about

desire ... in a world in which everything, all human relations, were

being reimagined as questions of property.” Perhaps. But as Graeber

points out with regard to most of these philosophical musings, we are

probably talking about 40-year-old upper-class white men eating food, or

at least their ideas about their eating. Anthropologists have shown

repeatedly in many cultural contexts, including the United States, how

food is one of the key ways that humans imagine their

interconnectedness—how food is almost always about sharing and creating

social relations as well as for tying past, present, and future

together— not, primarily, their Marxian alienation and commodity

fetishism. Food, pace Weiner, does carry enduring social meaning through

its powerful role in imagining and in remembering social relatedness in

everyday and ritual contexts. This is merely to suggest that the fitness

of the metaphor of eating as a model for modern consumption is not

inherently obvious; many other factors were clearly at play.

Indeed, Graeber’s argument that we move beyond the categories of

consumption and production fits very well with an interest in food

preparation or cooking. Cooking clearly is not illuminated by a model of

identity, creative consumption, and resistance as much as it might be by

a model that focuses on cooking as part of a project of value

transformation (Weiss 1996), as the creation of flavors that influence

others (Adapon 2008), or as an embodied memory and skill that can be

studied just as many anthropologists study apprenticeship (Sutton 2010).

A reexamination of the usefulness of consumption as a theoretical

category opens up all kinds of new possibilities, and in this Graeber is

right on target.

Reply

I must confess I am a bit startled by the uniformly positive response;

when one writes an intentionally provocative piece, one expects that at

least someone will be provoked. Take it as a sign, perhaps, that as a

discipline we have turned a corner. At any rate, I must offer my sincere

thanks to the commentators for their grace and generosity and for giving

me so much to think about.

The lack of any need for elaborate self-defense also allows me an

opportunity to use the space to fill readers in on the background of

this small collection. The real mastermind behind it is Lauren Leve, and

the vision grew from a series of collective conversations between fellow

anthropologists in New York as far back as 2002 around a “new keywords”

project. Leve’s idea was not just to make a list of buzzwords and

explore—à la Raymond Williams (1983)—why at certain points in history,

certain terms (“culture” was his famous example) suddenly seem to jump

to the center of intellectual and social debate. Even more, she proposed

to study those theoretical terms that were not, really, being debated—or

often, really, defined—and why. Starting in the 1990s, anthropology has

moved away from grand questions of theory; indeed, it largely stopped

generating theory of any sort. Instead, we were greeted with a flood of

new topics of research and attendant technical terms (“identity,”

“consumption,” “agency,” and “flow” but also “the body,”

“governmentality,” etc.) whose meaning was largely assumed to be

self-evident. The approach instantly made sense to the rest of us, who,

as scholars trained to believe that it is, in fact, impossible to look

at the world without applying some base assumptions about what humans

are and how they interact and convey meaning to one another and that

those who do not consciously work out their theoretical assumptions are

generally condemned to simply reproduce the dominant ideology of the day

(usually some form of economistic individualism) without realizing it,

could not help but be suspicious. We soon reached the collective

conclusion that together, these terms did in fact begin to constitute a

kind of neoliberal orthodoxy that had crept over anthropology without

our being willing to admit it. It was neoliberal in the classic sense:

naturalizing market ideology in the form of a mushy but often

self-righteous populism even as anthropology itself (and now I am

speaking for myself here) abandoned its onetime political autonomy and

became, increasingly, a handmaiden to bureaucrats, marketers, and NGOs.

The project first led to a session called “The New Keywords: Unmasking

the Terms of an Emerging Orthodoxy” at the 104^(th) Annual Meetings of

the American Anthropological Association (AAA) in Chicago in November

2003. It has taken some years to come together as a volume, but the key

points of the essays continue to be all too relevant.

My own contribution was based on an idea that I had been working at on

and off since graduate school inspired by puzzlement over the peculiar

moral fervor with which, starting in the 1980s, anthropologists and

others critical of consumerism had been denounced as enemies of the

people by highly paid members of the academic elite. Why had this

particular assault happened at that particular time?

It would seem that moment of moral fervor has passed— though there were

some signs of outrage in the original peer reviews; the published

responses are quite remarkable. Most are concerned mainly to extend the

argument even further, and all of them offer something I would never

have thought of myself. Let us take them one by one.

Robert Cluley and David Harvie manage to be both funny and poetic at the

same time. Writing from a school of management, they suggest in their

relation to the business world, anthropologists have failed in their

primary duty, which is to challenge economists’ received categories

rather than reproducing them. This is perhaps not entirely fair (when I

say it either), because there are anthropologists who are critical; it

is just that marketers ignore them. But I would like to strongly second

their point that the main voices criticizing consumption now come from

outside the academy entirely. Here let me repeat an autobiographical

note relegated to a footnote in the essay itself. I actually come from a

working-class family—not only that, from a onetime Nielsen family that

during my early childhood represented the entirety of southern Manhattan

for ratings purposes until we gave an anonymous interview to TV Guide. I

know a little about ordinary Americans’ attitudes. This is why I find it

so bizarre to be lectured by a bunch of high-bourgeois-born academics

that critiquing consumption makes me out of touch. Maybe they should

stop designing so many surveys and talk to people for a change.

Dimitra Doukas suggests that perhaps possessive individualism is not so

much the culprit behind the rise of the ideology of consumption as the

principle of universal competition. She may be right. I think the appeal

of her notion of “affect hunger” is compelling. I guess I would only

ask, Is affect hunger and the resultant perverse competitive dynamics

the necessary result when you imagine your relation with the world

primarily by analogy with things?

I much appreciate Felix Girke’s suggestions that many have long been

reminding us that “consumption” is largely about the creation and

maintenance of households; one of the pitfalls of employing the term

“production,” even when referring to the production of people and social

relations (a usage that goes back at least to the German Ideology), is

that much of the most important labor—and particularly caring labor,

which should probably be considered the primary form of labor—is not

about “producing” so much as preserving, maintaining, and sustaining

things. So, too, with the point about passions. It dovetails both with

Gershon’s critique of agency (Gershon 2011) and in a complex way, I

think, with Doukas’s invocation of Herschfeld. We used to feel

“consumed” by passions. Now we have a passion to consume. Yet to what

degree is all this based not in an active desire to make, do, or

construct but a (sometimes secret) desire not to have to do so for a

change. In earlier drafts, one of the comments that most enraged

marketing theorists seemed to be the idea that some of the desire to

throw oneself in front of the television was grounded on the desire not

to have to do—or think—anything at all.

Alf Hornborg might be right that I let my old teacher Marshall Sahlins

off the hook in my genealogy of the modern notion of consumption, but if

so, it is a genuine irony, because if there is one theme that runs

through his entire intellectual history, it is a challenge to any

assumption that humans are cursed with infinite needs. (It is also worth

mention that as the commentator on the AAA version, he agreed strongly

with the argument.) More challenging is his proposal that we retain the

word “consumption” to remind us that everything we do has an ecological

impact. I am of two minds about this. Certainly, everything we do

(including production) expends resources and is subject to the law of

entropy, and Hornborg deserves much credit for being one of the few

anthropologists willing to consistently remind us of this fact. Still,

why does this mean we have to continue to embrace consumption as an

analytical category rather than as a native category that is having

almost unimaginably destructive ecological effects?

Peter Stearns’s generous comments raise a number of critical questions,

only some of which I can fully answer—though I take some comfort in the

suspicion that no one else can, either. I agree that the phenomenon of

collective consumption, in Europe and elsewhere, and the shift from

collective to individual (or family or interpersonal) forms and ideals

of enjoyment and fulfillment is absolutely crucial and is not adequately

addressed in the text. Here Puritanism played a crucial role. The

question of Song China is also a perennial challenge, along with the

broader “why didn’t China conquer the world instead of Europe?” question

(though this focuses more on the early Ming), which, to be honest, was

in the back of my mind when writing this piece, even though it is not

explicitly addressed. This is why I resisted calls from earlier peer

reviewers to focus more on colonialism: I was much more interested in

trying to get at the roots of that peculiarly European (or perhaps

“Western,” if that term is allowed to include Islam?) incorrigibility

that made colonial expansion possible. But, surely, what I offer are

just suggestions, and much comparative work is required.

Finally, I genuinely appreciate David Sutton’s comments about

food—appropriate indeed for a project that began in a restaurant in

lower Manhattan with just the sort of conversation he describes. I would

just reemphasize the second half of the clause “40-year-old upper-class

white men eating food, or at least their ideas about their eating.”

Indeed. Conviviality has always been, for most humans everywhere, the

definition of shared experience, a kind of communism of the senses that

puts the lie to the entire ideology of consumption. (And even when rich

white guys eat in expensive French restaurants—how often do you see one

eating by himself?) It is not even most eating that is the model; it is

the midnight snack, the piece of pie snarfed from the fridge when no one

else is looking, the sandwich you have at the train station, the morning

coffee, possibly the candy bar you buy when you are depressed. In a way,

that last one tells you everything.

—David Graeber

References Cited

Adapon, Joy. 2008. Culinary art and anthropology. Oxford: Berg. [DS]

Agamben, Giorgio. 1993a. Infancy and history: essays on the destruction

of experience. Liz Heron, trans. London: Verso.

———. 1993b. Stanzas: word and phantasm in Western culture. Minneapolis:

University of Minnesota Press.

Appadurai, Arjun. 1986. Introduction: commodities and the politics of

value. In The social life of things: commodities in cultural

perspective. Arjun Appadurai, ed. Pp. 3–63. Cambridge: Cambridge

University Press.

Appleby, Joyce. 1999. Consumption in early modern social thought. In The

consumer society in American history: a reader. Lawrence B. Glickman,

ed. Pp. 130–144. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

Arnould, Eric J., and Craig J. Thompson. 2005. Consumer culture theory

(CCT): twenty years of research. Journal of Consumer Research

31:868–882.

Aylmer, G. E. 1980. The meaning of property in seventeenth-century

England. Past and Present 86:87–97.

Baba, Marietta. 2006. Anthropology and business. In The encyclopedia of

anthropology. H. James Birx, ed. Pp. 83–117. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.

Bakhtin, Mikhail. 1984. Rabelais and his world. Bloomington: Indiana

University Press.

Basbøll, Thomas. 2010. Softly constrained imagination: plagiarism and

misprision in the theory of organizational sensemaking. Culture and

Organization 16(2):163–167. [RC/DH]

Bataille, Georges. 1985 (1937). The notion of expenditure. In Visions of

excess, selected writings, 1927–1939. Allan Stoekl, ed. and trans. Pp.

116–129. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

Belk, Russell W. 1975. Situational variables and consumer behavior.

Journal of Consumer Research 2(3):157–164.

Berg, Maxine, and Helen Clifford, eds. 1999. Consumers and luxury:

consumer culture in Europe, 1650–1850. Manchester, UK: Manchester

University Press.

Boase, Roger. 1977. The origin and meaning of courtly love. Manchester,

UK: Manchester University Press.

Bocock, Robert. 1993. Consumption. London: Routledge.

Bordo, Susan. 1993. Unbearable weight: feminism, Western culture, and

the body. Berkeley: University of California Press.

Bourdieu, Pierre. 1999. On television. New York: New Press. Buck-Morss,

Susan. 2000. Hegel and Haiti. Critical Inquiry 26(4): 821–865.

Campbell, Colin. 1987. The romantic ethic and the spirit of modern

consumerism. Oxford: Blackwell.

Carrier, James G. 1996. Review of Acknowledging consumption: a review of

new studies. American Ethnologist 23(2):421–422. [FG]

Carrier, James G., and Josiah M. Heyman. 1997. Consumption and political

economy. Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute 3(2):355–373.

[FG]

Casey, Edward S., and J. Melvin Woody. 1983. Hegel and Lacan: the

dialectic of desire. In Interpreting Lacan. Joseph Smith and William

Kerrigan, eds. Pp. 77–88. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

Couliano, Iouan. 1987. Eros and magic in the Renaissance. Margaret Cook,

trans. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Davis, Natalie Zemon. 1975. Society and culture in early modern France.

Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

Debord, Guy. 1994. Society of the spectacle. New York: Zone.

Deleuze, Gilles, and Felix Guattari. 1983. Anti-Oedipus: capitalism and

schizophrenia. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

Delumeau, Jean. 2000. History of paradise: the Garden of Eden in myth

and tradition. Matthew O’Connell, trans. Chicago: University of Illinois

Press.

Douglas, Mary, and Baron Isherwood. 1979. The world of goods: towards an

anthropology of consumption. New York: Basic.

Eberhard, Philippe. 2004. The middle voice in Gadamer’s hermeneutics.

TĂĽbingen, Germany: Mohr Siebeck. [FG]

Ehn, Billy, and Orvar Lofgren. 2010. The secret world of doing nothing.

Berkeley: University of California Press. [DS]

Federici, Silvia. 2004. Caliban and the witch: women, the body, and

primitive accumulation. New York: Autonomedia.

Fischer, Sibylle. 2004. Modernity disavowed: Haiti and the cultures of

slavery in the age of revolution. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.

Friedman, John Block. 1981. The monstrous races in medieval art and

thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Friedman, Jonathan. 1994. Introduction. In Consumption and identity.

Jonathan Friedman, ed. Amsterdam: Harwood Academic.

Gates, Moira, and Genevieve Lloyd. 1999. Collective imaginings: Spinoza,

past and present. London: Routledge.

Georgescu-Roegen, Nicholas. 1971. The entropy law and the economic

process. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. [AH]

Gershon, Ilana. 2011. “Neoliberal agency.” Current Anthropology

52(4):537–555.

Goldschmidt, Walter. 2006. The bridge to humanity: how affect hunger

trumps the selfish gene. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [DD]

Graeber, David. 1997. Manners, deference and private property: the

generalization of avoidance in early modern Europe. Comparative Studies

in Society and History 39(4):694–728.

———. 1998. Rebel without a god: a review of Buffy the vampire slayer. In

These Times 23(2):28–30.

———. 2001. </em>Towards an anthropological theory of value: the false

coin of our own dreams.</em> New York: Palgrave.

———. 2004. Fragments of an anarchist anthropology. Chicago: Prickly

Paradigm. [AH]

———. 2005. Turning modes of production inside out; or, why capitalism is

a transformation of slavery (short version). Critique of Anthropology

26(1):61–81.

———. 2007a. Possibilities: essays on hierarchy, rebellion, and desire.

Oakland, CA: AK. [AH]

———. 2007b. The very idea of consumption: desire, phantasms, and the

aesthetics of destruction from medieval times to the present. In

Possibilities: essays on hierarchy, rebellion, and desire. Pp. 57–85.

Oakland, CA: AK. [FG]

———. 2008. The sadness of post-Workerism. Commoner. http://

www.commoner.org.uk/?pp33.

———. 2010. Neoliberalism; or, the bureaucratization of the world. In The

insecure American.

Hugh Gusterson and Catherine Besteman, eds. Berkeley: University of

California Press. Gudeman, Stephen. 2009. The persuasions of economics.

In Economic persuasions: studies in rhetoric and culture, vol. 3.

Stephen Gudeman, ed. Pp. 62–80. Oxford: Berghahn. [FG]

Habeck, Joachim Otto, and Aimar Ventsel. 2009. Consumption and popular

culture among youth in Siberia. Zeitschrift für Ethnologie 134(1):1–22.

[FG]

Hebdige, Dick. 1979. Subculture: the meaning of style. London:

Routledge.

Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. 1998. Phenomenology of spirit. A. V.

Miller, trans. Oxford: Clarendon.

Hirschman, Albert O. 1977. The passions and the interests: political

arguments for capitalism before its triumph. Princeton, NJ: Princeton

University Press. [DD]

Hobbes, Thomas. 1968. Leviathan. Harmondsworth, UK: Penguin.

Kojéve, Alexandre. 1969. Introduction to the reading of Hegel. New York:

Basic.

Lacan, Jacques. 1977. Écrits: a selection. Alan Sheridan, trans. New

York: Norton.

Lasn, Kalle. 1999. Culture jam: how to reverse America’s suicidal

consumer binge—and why we must. New York: Harper Collins.

Lazzarato, Maurizio. 1996. Immaterial labor. In Radical thought in

Italy: a potential politics. Paolo Virno and Michael Hardt, eds. Pp.

133–147. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

Levinas, E. 1998. Otherwise than being; or, beyond essence. Pittsburgh,

PA: Duquesne University Press.

Lienhardt, Godfrey. 1961. Divinity and experience. Oxford: Oxford

University Press.

Lodziak, Conrad. 2002. The myth of consumerism. London: Pluto.

MacFarlane, Alan. 1998. The mystery of property: inheritance and

industrialization in England and Japan. In Property relations: renewing

the anthropological tradition. C. M. Hann, ed. Pp. 104–123. Cambridge:

Cambridge University Press.

MacKay, Hugh. 1997. Consumption and everyday life. London: Sage.

MacPherson, Crawford Brough. 1962. The political theory of possessive

individualism: Hobbes to Locke. Oxford: Clarendon.

Mander, Jerry. 1978. Four arguments for the elimination of television.

New York: Harper Perennial.

Masco, Joseph. 1995. “It is a strict law that bids us dance”:

cosmologies, colonialism, death, and ritual authority in the

Kwakwaka’wakw potlatch, 1849 to 1922. Comparative Studies in Society and

History 37:41–75.

Massignon, Louis. 1982. The life of al-Hallaj, vol. 1 of The passion of

al-Hallaj: mystic and martyr of Islam. Princeton, NJ: Princeton

University Press.

McKendrick, Neil, John Brewer, and J. H. Plumb. 1982. Birth of a

consumer society: the commercialization of eighteenth-century England.

London: Europa.

Miller, Daniel. 1987. Material culture and mass consumption. London:

Blackwell.

———, ed. 1995. Acknowledging consumption: a review of new studies.

London: Routledge.

———. 1997. Capitalism: an ethnographic approach. Oxford: Berg

———. 1998. A theory of shopping. Cambridge: Polity/Cornell University.

———. 2001. Introduction. In Consumption: critical concepts in the social

sciences. Daniel Miller, ed. Pp. 1–6. London: Taylor & Francis.

Negri, Antonio. 1991. The savage anomaly: the power of Spinoza’s

metaphysics and politics. Michael Hardt, trans. Minneapolis: University

of Minnesota Press.

Pagden, Anthony. 1987. The fall of natural man: the American Indian and

the origins of comparative ethnography. Cambridge: Cambridge University

Press.

Pleij, Herman. 2001. Dreaming of Cockaigne: medieval fantasies of the

perfect life. Diane Webb, trans. New York: Columbia University Press.

Sahlin, H., and J. P. Robinson. 1980. Beyond the realm of necessity:

television and the colonization of leisure. Media, Culture and Society

3:85–95.

Sahlins, Marshall. 1996. The sadness of sweetness; or, the native

anthropology of Western cosmology? Current Anthropology 37(3): 395–428.

Sahlins, Marshall D. 1976. Culture and practical reason. Chicago:

University of Chicago Press. [AH]

Schivelbusch, Wolfgang. 1992. Tastes of paradise: a social history of

spices, stimulants and intoxicants. New York: Vintage.

Schnepel, Burkhard. 2009. Zur Dialektik von Agency and Patiency.

Paragrana 18(2):15–22. [FG]

Schor, Juliet B., and Douglas B. Holt, eds. 2000. The consumer society

reader. New York: New Press.

Silverman, Hugh. 2000. Twentieth-century desire and the histories of

philosophy. In Philosophy and desire. Pp. 1–13. New York: Routledge.

Smith, Adam. 1976 (1776). An inquiry into the nature and causes of the

wealth of nations. Oxford: Clarendon.

———. 2002 (1761). Theory of moral sentiments. Cambridge: Cambridge

University Press.

Smith, Woodruff D. 2002. Consumption and the making of respectability:

1600–1800. London: Routledge.

Spinoza, Baruch. 2000. Ethics. G. H. R. Parkinson, ed. and trans.

Oxford: Oxford University Press. Stearns, Peter. 2001. Consumerism in

world history: the global transformation of desire. London: Routledge.

Sutton, David. 2010. The mindful kitchen, the embodied cook: tools,

technology and knowledge transmission on a Greek island. Canadian

Material Culture Review 70:63–68. [DS]

Thomas, Keith. 1971. Religion and the decline of magic. New York:

Scribner.

Todorov, Tzvetan. 2001. Life in common: an essay in general

anthropology. Katherine Golsan and Lucy Golsan, trans. Lincoln:

University of Nebraska Press.

Wagner, Roy. 1995. If you have the advertisement you don’t need the

product. In Rhetorics of self-making. D. Battaglia, ed. Pp. 60–77.

Berkeley: University of California Press.

Weiner, Annette. 1992. Inalienable possessions: the paradox of keeping

while-giving. Berkeley: University of California Press. [DS]

Weiss, Bradd. 1996. The making and unmaking of the Haya lived world:

consumption, commoditization and everyday practice. Durham, NC: Duke

University Press. [DS]

Wilk, Richard. 2004. Morals and metaphors: the meaning of consumption.

In Elusive consumption. Karin Ekstrom and Helene Brembeck, eds. Pp.

11–26. London: Berg.

Williams, Raymond. 1983. Keywords: a vocabulary of culture and society.

Rev. edition. New York: Oxford University Press.

Yar, Majeed. 2001. Recognition and the politics of human(e) desire.

Theory, Culture and Society 18(2–3):57–76.

Yates, Frances. 1964. Giordano Bruno and the hermetic tradition.

Chicago: University of Chicago Press. ———. 1966. The art of memory.

Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Yovel, Yirmiyahu, ed. 1999. Desire and affect: Spinoza as psychologist.

New York: Little Room.

[1] As Richard Wilk (2004) has shown in endless and elegant detail, the

term “consumption” is basically a metaphor of eating.

[2] To take one example, a while ago a book came out called The Consumer

Society Reader (Schor and Holt 2000), which contains essays by 28

authors, ranging from Thorsten Veblen to Tom Frank, about consumption

and consumerism. Not a single essay offers a definition of either term

or asks why these terms are being used rather than others.

[3] As Conrad Lodziak (2002), who also cites this passage, makes clear,

this standard version does not really reflect the actual arguments of

anyone involved in the Frankfurt School. It is all something of a myth.

[4] I note that such demotic wisdom is rarely precisely reflected in the

works of any particular author, though Miller often comes very close to

saying this. Yet they have tremendous power. Another example of the

phenomenon is the phrase “How can I know The Other?” and the debate

surrounding the question, which raged around the same time, in the late

1980s and early 1990s. As far as I know, the phrase never actually

appeared in print at all, even in the works of those authors (e.g.,

Marcus and Clifford) with whom it was broadly identified.

[5] In fact there was equal resistance in the early 1980s on either

side. Richard Wilk (personal communication) informs me that he and Eric

Arnould, a professor of marketing, wrote a paper called “Why Do the

Indians Want Adidas?” in 1981; no anthropological journal would accept

it, and American Anthropologist returned it unreviewed with the comment

“This is not an anthropological topic.”

[6] Of the few exceptions of which I am aware, one is Miller (1987), who

first defined “consumption” as an action that “translates the object

from an alienable to an inalienable condition; that is from being a

symbol of estrangement and price value to being an artifact invested

with particular inseparable connotations” (190), a rather idiosyncratic

and arcane definition related to his own Hegelian notion of

self-creation that, however, I do not believe is shared by any other

consumption theorist, and later (Miller 2001:1) as “the consequences of

objects for the people that use them,” a definition that is so broad it

is presumably not really meant as a definition at all. The other is

Appleby (1999:130): “the desiring, acquiring and enjoying of goods and

services which one has purchased,” though elsewhere in the same piece

she also defines consumption as “the active seeking of personal

gratification through material goods” (164).

[7] Especially if the band had not yet received a record contract or

many professional gigs; if they were able to market some kind of

product, it might be considered production again.

[8] Here I also want to answer some of the questions rather left

dangling at the end of my book on value theory (Graeber 2001).

[9] In French the word consummation, which is from a different root,

eventually displaced consumption. But the idea of taking possession of

an object seems to remain, and any number of authors have remarked on

the implied parallel between sexual appropriation and eating food.

[10] “Produce” is derived from a Latin word meaning to “bring out” (a

usage still preserved in phrases such as “the defense produced a

witness” or “he produced a flashlight from under his cloak”) or “to put

out” (as from a factory).

[11] Bataille’s argument was that production, which Marx saw as

quintessentially human, is also the domain of activity most constrained

by practical considerations—consumption the least so. To discover what

is really important to a culture, therefore, one should look not at how

things are made but at how they are destroyed.

[12] Similar lists appear throughout the Western tradition. Kant also

had three—wealth, power, and prestige—interestingly skipping pleasure.

[13] The sensual pleasures they had in mind seem to have centered as

much on having sex as on eating food, on lounging on silk pillows, and

on burning incense or hashish, and by “wealth,” both seemed to have in

mind, first and foremost, permanent things such as mansions, landed

estates, and magnificent jewelry rather than consumables.

[14] One could even argue that Smith’s approach to questions of desire

and fulfillment is so one sided, centering almost entirely on social

recognition and immaterial rewards (wealth, in his system, was only

really desirable insofar as wealthy people were more likely to be the

object of others’ attention and spontaneous sympathetic concern), that

it is meant to head off the very possibility of the consumption model

that was to develop from his economic work.

[15] Working here on the assumption that if one examines any

intellectual tradition carefully enough, one could find the materials

for a genuinely insightful analysis of such “big questions” (i.e.,

sufficient perusal of the Buddhist would also have yielded useful

results had I been competent to do it, which I am not).

[16] For the best collection of essays on Spinoza’s theory of desire,

see Yovel (1999). On his theory of imagination, see Gates and Lloyd

(1999) and Negri (1991).

[17] I am especially drawing on the famous “strong reading” of this

passage by Alexander Kojéve (1969) that had such an influence on

Bataille, Lacan, Sartre, de Beauvoir, Fanon, and so on. Levinas (1998)

has recently challenged this reading, but it has certainly dominated

social theory, and particularly French social theory, for at least half

a century.

[18] In Hegel’s language, they construct themselves as a negation;

therefore, they seek to negate that negation by negating something else,

that is, by eating it.

[19] Lacan’s “mirror phase” itself actually draws directly on Hegel

(Casey and Woody 1983; Silverman 2000). I might note, too, that it is

the Hegel-Kojéve-Sartre connection that is responsible for the habit of

writing about “the Other” with a capital O, as an inherently unknowable

creature.

[20] “That is the incapacity of conceiving the incorporeal and the

desire to make of it the object of an embrace are two faces of the same

coin, of the process in whose course the traditional contemplative

vocation of the melancholic reveals itself vulnerable to the violent

disturbance of desire menacing it from within” (Agamben 1993b:18).

[21] There is a lot of evidence that suggests that levels of clinical

depression do in fact rise sharply in consumer-oriented societies; they

have certainly been rising steadily in the United States for most of the

century. I should emphasize, by the way, that while Agamben (1993b) and

Couliano (1987) draw exclusively on European sources, these ideas were

very likely developed earlier and more extensively in the Islamic world.

Certainly, it is well established that the courtly love tradition in

medieval France harkened back to Sufi poetic traditions of love as the

chaste and spiritually fulfilling contemplation of an idealized object

(e.g., Boase 1977; Massignon 1982:348–349). Unfortunately, I lack the

language skills to pursue the question of medieval Islamic theories of

the imagination, but I would underline that this is yet another way in

which when one refers to the “Western tradition,” one should think of

oneself, especially in this period, referring equally or even primarily

to Islam.

[22] Along lines already developed by the Art of Memory (see Yates 1964,

1966).

[23] Almost always this also ends up involving a certain degree of

fetishization, where the objects end up appearing, from the actor’s

perspective, to be the source of the very powers by which they are in

fact created—because from the actor’s position, this might as well be

true. Often, too, these objects become imaginary micrototalities that

play a similar role to Lacan’s mirror objects or similar critiques of

the commodity as capturing an illusory sense of wholeness in a society

fragmented by capitalism itself (Debord 1994; Graeber 2001).

[24] Even women, when they wrote love poems, tended to adopt a male

point of view.

[25] In other words, rather than asking how is it possible to truly

“have” or possess some object or experience, perhaps we should be asking

why anyone should develop a desire to do so to begin with.

[26] To the extent that, as MacPherson (1962) shows, populist

politicians such as the Levellers framed their arguments in such terms.

[27] Supposedly, in early Roman law, the paterfamilias did have the

power to execute his children as well as his slaves; both rights, if

they really did exist in practice, were stripped away quite quickly.

[28] “Similarly, just as each stakes his own life, so each must seek the

other’s death, for it values the other no more than itself; its

essential being is present” (Hegel 1998:114).

[29] Or, more technically, I suppose, synecdoche.

[30] And it has the additional attraction of being almost the only power

that kings do not have over their subjects: as one sixteenth-century

Spanish jurist wrote, in arguing that American cannibalism violated

natural law, “no man may possess another so absolutely that he may make

use of him as a foodstuff” (Pagden 1987:86).

[31] Obviously, with cable, PPV, TiVo, and so on, it is more a commodity

than it once was. But still it is so in a very minor sense: most

television is still a medium for advertising.

[32] The passage above is partly inspired by Conrad Lodziak’s (2002:

106–107) discussion of television viewing in his book The Myth of

Consumerism. Such thoughts are, of course, anathema to the mainstream of

media studies and will no doubt provoke the withering ire of many

readers, but as Lodziak cogently remarks, empirical studies and

questionnaires tend to ask what viewers find meaningful or important

about television programming, not how meaningful or important they take

the experience to be. Those few studies that do ask consumers how

important television viewing is to them find it “the most expendable or

least important of daily activities” (Sahlin and Robinson 1980). It is

hard to square such stated preferences with the statistical facts—for

instance, that in the average American household, the television is on

roughly 4.5 hours per day—in any other way.

[33] Lest I be instantly accused of affiliation—or at least

affinity—with the dreaded Frankfurt School, allow me to provide some

personal qualifications. I grew up in a Nielsen family and know all

about collective working-class family viewing but also have myself had

many horrific jobs from which I often returned to stare blankly at the

television. I also have a certain experience of fandom, being, in fact,

the first academic ever to publish an essay on the topic of Buffy the

Vampire Slayer (Graeber 1998), surely one of the greatest shows of all

time. I think my personal attitude is typical of most Americans:

television is a wasteland, except for those shows I like.

[34] The ritual vilification of the Frankfurt School is so relentless

that I cannot resist one small word in their defense. It is certainly

true that Adorno and Horkheimer could be remarkably puritanical and

elitist. But it is also important to bear in mind these were German Jews

who witnessed the rise of the Nazis to power in Germany and were keenly

aware that fascism was one of the first political movements to make full

use of modern marketing techniques. Starting from that fact makes it

much harder to deny that sometimes people really are intentionally

manipulated with political ends in mind. Would anyone seriously suggest

that most of those who “consumed,” for example, Goebbels’s anti-Semitic

effusions, were really creatively and subversively reappropriating his

messages—or that if they did, this made the slightest bit of difference?

No doubt Adorno and Horkheimer overstated their case in making fascism

the model for all subsequent political-economic forms, but one could

equally argue that others have overstated its uniqueness.

[35] For example, Arnould and Thomson (2005), in their summary of 20

years of “Consumer Culture Theory” in the Journal of Consumer Research,

are careful to acknowledge the importance of this critical literature

and sometimes sound very much like ideology critics themselves.

“Consumer culture theorists read popular texts (advertisements,

television programs, films) as lifestyle and identity instructions that

convey unadulterated marketplace ideologies”; thus, they aim to “reveal

the ways in which capitalist cultural production systems invite

consumers to covet certain identity and lifestyle ideals” (875).

However, they add, in such theory, “consumers are conceptualized as

interpretive agents rather than as passive dupes. Thus, various forms of

consumer resistance inevitably greet the dominant normative ideological

influence of commercial media and marketing. Consumers seek to form

lifestyles that defy dominant consumerist norms or that directly

challenge corporate power” (875). Lest this sound surprisingly radical

for a marketing journal, I note that the authors immediately go on to

argue that this by no means should be meant to suggest that there is any

natural alliance between such subversive consumers and anticorporate

“consumer activists.” The latter, in their “evangelical” zeal to reform

society as a whole, really see consumers themselves as “part of the

problem.” Corporate power is apparently to be challenged—but not

unreservedly.

[36] Or, at best, three: production, consumption, and exchange.

[37] Another approach that treats consumption largely as a form of

production—in this case, value production—is the “immaterial labor”

argument that has emerged from Italian post-Workerism, particularly in

the works of Maurizio Lazzarato (1996). I have critiqued this position

elsewhere (Graeber 2008).

[38] Thanks to my colleagues and students who shared their thoughts with

me on this article over dinner. Animal and vegetable products were

bought, cooked, and eaten and a fair amount of fermented beverages

imbibed. Properly sated, we discussed and debated a lot of ideas. Only a

bureaucrat would try to label this as either “production” or

“consumption.”