💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › gilles-dauve-getting-rid-of-work.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 10:30:11. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Getting Rid Of Work
Author: Gilles Dauvé
Date: March 2018
Language: en
Topics: communization, anti-work
Source: Retrieved on March 12, 2018 from https://ediciones-ineditos.com/2018/03/08/getting-rid-of-work/
Notes: Here you will find a lightly modified chapter 3 from the book “From Crisis to Communization” published in 2017 by Editions Entremonde. Translated by EDICIONES INÉDITOS

Gilles Dauvé

Getting Rid Of Work

What follows is a long essay by the French communization theorist,

Gilles Dauvé. It is a long read, a read which varies in content and tone

but a text which masterfully summarizes the communist critique of work.

The original can be found here at Troploin. He also dutifully notes that

without the abolition of work there can be no communist revolution or

communism. We hope you enjoy reading this as much as we enjoyed

translating it. ¡A la chingada con el trabajo! </example>

False construction sites

In 1997, in the French department of Sarthe, some 20 workers were

constructing a section of highway under the direction of an engineer

employed by a large company, BTP. After two months the engineer was

arrested: no one had ordered the work that was partially done, which

with an initial financing, the false construction site manager had

successfully hoodwinked both banks and public organizations. Between

1983 and 1996, Philippe Berre had been convicted 14 times for ordering

false construction sites. In 2009, “The Beginning,” a film inspired by

this whole adventure was released, displaying a population struck by

unemployment which briefly found work and hope. Phillippe Berre was not

motivated by personal gain, but rather by the need to do, to be of use,

to reanimate a group of workers. In 2010, once again, he took on this

role while helping those affected by Cyclone Xynthia.

We all know “rogue bosses.” Philippe Berre is a fictitious boss, an

anti-hero for our times; at once a “manipulator of symbols,” an agile

manager of human resources, at a crossroads between the automobile and

the BTP (presented as the two principal employers within modern

countries), wandering as a nomad on the highways, as mobile as the

activities which he preyed upon, living on the ephemeral dreams that his

dynamism created around him, an illustration of a fluidity without

markers or attachments, where money flows but is not wasted, where

success has no future, where one builds worthless things, where all

appears as communication and virtuality. But is not a sense of reality

which Philippe Berre is lacking, rather he lacks respect.

When a crook brings work, revenue, and thus some “meaning” to a

community in perdition, even if it is a provisional and false meaning,

this raises the question – what does production and work mean? The

unemployed at Sarthe trusted Philippe Berre because he brought them some

socializing, a role, a status, a sense of being recognized. What is

useful? Useless? Fictitious? Real? What is profitable or not? Was this

piece of highway more or less absurd than any “real” highway? What work

is worthy of being qualified as “a waste”? Beyond the hard reality of

work (it creates objects, creates profit and is generally onerous), what

is the truth?

1. Rereading Marx: from Marx to Marxism

Marx has left us the most powerful synthesis of communism, one with the

deepest theoretical breakthroughs and also the most acute

contradictions. Capital and the The Critique of the Gotha Program

notably, along with the Grundrisse, manuscripts from 1857-58, which have

since renewed our approach towards capitalism and communism, and whose

first publication in French almost coincided with May 1968. Though we

have personally cited these pages more than a few times, we now find

reason to bear a critique.[1]

Marx is particularly necessary to return to since his analysis of work

places front and center the question of time.

1.1 The commodity and work

Capital does not begin with a definition of capitalism, but rather the

way in which it “presents itself”: “an immense accumulation of

commodities.” This point of departure relays a certain choice of

perspective. If work is at the heart of the problem, why not begin with

the the division of labor? While not writing a history book, why would

Marx start with the encounter between private producers exchanging on

the market and not with the meeting of the wage laborer and the

capitalist? The first chapter of Capital considers work (not waged

labor, but work, whatever kind it may be) as being both abstract and

concrete: in other words, use-value and exchange-value are presented as

arising with the dawn of humanity and within almost every society.

To naturalize work is to eternalize it.

Section 1.4 will return to Marx and his definitions of work. That which

Capital affirms, at any rate, is that work, in the past, before value

(or value-less, as it would be under communism), work without a labor

market, is both positive and necessary. Capital considers productive

activity and work as one in the same.

Here Marx announces an essential trait which Marxism would embody: the

worker ceases to be proletarian (= a wage laborer exploited by a boss)

when everyone becomes a proletarian, since bosses would have been

replaced by a community of laborers. The solution to this social problem

would be to generalize labor. But which kind? Waged labor? Marx reasons

as though the answer were self-evident: as soon as we all join in on a

community working without capitalists, the question of the wage-laborer

will be resolved. The overcoming of capitalism will not consist of the

abolishment of the Capital-labor relation but rather to rescue work from

Capital.

1.2 Working in a world without money

For Marx it is the arrival of use-value on the market (a “natural”

product of labor) which gives use-value its character as an

exchange-value. When Marx talks about labor time, it is squarely about

production, but at that point value only has a potential existence,

before finding its reality on the market. It would be as though value is

not born of production, but, after the productive moment, it comes to

impose itself on labor as a constraint, which would thus need to be

liberated from the worker. In reading Marx, as long as there is no

sale/purchase, labor time acts as a neutral given, which capitalism in

its own way takes advantage of, and which communism would also use but

in a totally different way.

The filigree-legible communism in Capital looks like a world without

money based on communitarian labor. However, work is more than the

meeting of cooperative humans within a workshop making objects. To work

is to count the time, to economize, which implies that we quantify the

socially-necessary labor time to produce this or that: exactly what Marx

rightly calls value.

Marx’s distrust of any utopian description for a post-revolutionary

future is well-known. Thus it is even more meaningful that one of the

rare appearances on this subject seems to propose labor vouchers for the

“lower phase” of communism (Critique of the Gotha Program, 1875),

because, such as he makes them out to be, what are these labor vouchers

but value without money?

1.3 The Map

“Let us now picture to ourselves, by way of change, a community of free

individuals, carrying on their work with the means of production in

common, in which the labour power of all the different individuals is

consciously applied as the combined labour power of the community (…)

The total product of our community is a social product. One portion

serves as fresh means of production and remains social. But another

portion is consumed by the members as means of subsistence (…) We will

assume, but merely for the sake of a parallel with the production of

commodities, that the share of each individual producer in the means of

subsistence is determined by his labour time. Labour time would, in that

case, play a double part. Its apportionment in accordance with a

definite social plan maintains the proper proportion between the

different kinds of work to be done and the various wants of the

community. On the other hand, it also serves as a measure of the portion

of the common labour borne by each individual, and of his share in the

part of the total product destined for individual consumption. The

social relations of the individual producers, with regard both to their

labour and to its products, are in this case perfectly simple and

intelligible,with regard not only to production but also to

distribution.” (Capital, Vol. 1, Chp. 1, iv)

If Marx assumes a regulation of production by labor time “to put this

state of affairs in parallel with commodity production,” it is because

the opposite supposition for him is almost unthinkable. His perspective

lies in replacing the separation between producers, great and small,

with a production-commune, and replacing capitalist disorder with

planification done by all.

Further, politically the State will no longer be a State when everyone

will take on its functions: shared by everyone, political power will

lose its oppressive character; so writes Engels: “Insofar as the anarchy

of social production disappears, the political authority of the State

goes to sleep. Men, finally masters of their own way of life in society,

thereby become masters of nature, masters of themselves, and thus are

free.”[2]

Such as Marx sketches it out, communism is marked by transparency and

self-understanding: men become at last conscious of whom they are.

Associated producers are naturally assumed to be the best people to know

the socially-necessary labor time of what they produce.

1.4 Which definition of work?

In 1845, Marx defined it as such:

“ ‘Labor’ is the living base of private property, as it is the only

source of private property. Private property is nothing more than

materialized labor. If you would want to deal it a lethal blow, we would

need to attack private property not only as an objective state; we must

also attack it as an activity, as labor. To speak of free, human, social

labor, of labor without private property, is one of the greatest

misunderstandings that exist. ‘Labor’ is by nature an enslaved activity,

inhumane, antisocial, determined by private property and created by

private property. Consequently, the abolition of private property only

becomes a reality if we conceive of it as the abolition of ‘labor’; an

abolition which naturally is only possible when done by labor itself,

which is a way of saying the by the material activity of society and not

just the substitution of one category for another.”[3]

In 1846, in The German Ideology speaks of “the division of labor” : This

is what is impossible without a community. (…) Up until now, all

revolutions have left intact this mode of activity; what changed was

only the distribution of this activity, a new apportionment of labor

between persons. On the other hand, communist revolution, standing up

against this traditional mode of activity, gets rid of labor and

abolishes the domination of all classes by abolishing classes

themselves; this revolution being the work of the class who, within

society, no longer has any ranking as a class and is no longer

recognized as such: from then on out, communist revolution marks the

dissolution of all classes, of all nationalities, etc. at the very heart

of present society.”[4]

Communist theory does not equate man with homo faber, nor as a “maker of

tools,” as Benjamin Franklin thought of man.

On the other hand, in 1867, work is defined as “the existential and

indispensable condition of man, the mediator of organic exchanges

between nature and man.”[5]

From a radical position that was unacceptable at the time (and remains

so to this day), Marx was moving toward a definition of work that is

practically applicable to any society.

Let’s quote then The Critique of the Gotha Program (1875): “At a higher

phase of communist society, when enslaved subordination of individuals

to the division of labor would have been disappeared, and with it, the

opposition between the intellectual and the manual labor; when work will

not only be a means to live, but will become the primary vital need;

when along with the manifold development of individuals, the productive

forces will have been so developed and when all sources of collective

wealth abundantly overflow – and only then (…) society will be able to

write on its banners: From each according to their ability, to each

according to their needs!.”[6]

1.5 Measuring by time (re-reading the Grundrisse )

According to Capital, “In all social states, the time necessary to

produce the means of consumption have interested mankind, albeit

unequally, in accordance with their diverse degrees of civilization.”[7]

The 1857-58 manuscripts (Grundrisse) have an exceptionally visionary

force. What they express does not however contradict Capital as much on

labor as on labor time, two themes which complement each other.

“The real economy, savings, consists of economizing labor time (as well

as reducing the costs of production). But, inseparable from the

development of the productive forces, this economy is in no way a

renunciation of joy. Growth in strength and in the means of production

condition the faculties which render the individual apt to enjoy their

existence, an aptitude which goes hand in hand with productive power.

The economy of labor time means the augmentation of free time for the

full blossoming of the individual (…)” (For the Grundrisse we use the

edition by Maximilien Rubel, Œuvres, Gallimard, II, 1968. p. 310)

“(…) it is clear that immediate labor time cannot always be abstractly

opposed to free time, as is the case in the bourgeois economic system.

Work cannot become a game, as Fourier wants, whom had the great merit of

having proclaimed the ultimate goal of transcendence, in a superior

form, not of distribution but of production.” (p. 311)

That life, particularly a productive one, “demands practical

manipulation and free movement,” (p. 311) and implies effort, is

self-evident and it is useful to recall that against the myth of a

liberating automation; but it does not follow that we must then reason

with the opposition of work/play, categories which themselves are

historical and open to critique. Across the same pages, Marx prolongs

his critique of political economy.

Of course not everything is play. But just because one has to exert

effort does not mean that what you are doing must be work. And it is not

necessarily less enjoyable to cook as it is to eat. And what about the

dishes? It only becomes a chore through the routine of household chores

(which are still 80% done by housewives) performed under the dual

constraint of time saving and the pressure of family life. The

reappropriation of our living conditions, and along with it its

upheaval, involves other relations such as man/woman, parents/children,

adults/children, which implies another kind of living situation, another

kind of education, etc.

The perspective set forth in the Grundrisse is as profound as it is

ambiguous:

“Adopting labor time as the standard for wealth, is to found this wealth

on poverty; it is reduction of all time to labor time and to degrade the

individual to the exclusive role of being a worker, an instrument of

work.” (p. 308)

“Capital is contradiction in action: it tends to reduce to a minimum

labor time, all the while making it the sole source and measure of

wealth.” (p. 306)

“The reduction of socially-necessary labor time, and not solely

diminished in favor of surplus labor, will allow us to free up the

blossoming of the individual. In fact, thanks to free time and the means

opened up to all, the reduction of labor time to the minimum

socially-necessary will favor the artistic, scientific, etc. development

of everyone.” (p. 306)

“True wealth being the full productive power of all individuals, the

yardstick employed will not be labor time, but rather the time

available.” (p. 308)

By definition, available time being not employed (or at least not yet ),

and thus representing but a potentiality, is then impossible to measure:

there thus seems to be a rupture with value and capitalism. But does

this available time become the totality of time, or is it added to an

ever-present labor time, which is essential albeit reduced to a few

hours a day?

Marx posed the question of the accounting of time (crucial in

understanding labor), but could not resolve this problem because he

treated time as a given, not as a category also open to critique.

1.6 Communism and labor time (the councilist project)

In 1930, Dutch council communists of the GIC [Group of International

Communists] had the enormous merit of having concretely posed the

question of communism based on the question of value, but had done so,

in our opinion, based on a bad premise.[8]

In 1966, the principal editor of the project, Jan Appel (1890-1985)

summed up this premise: workers’ councils will make of “the hourly unit

of average labor time [the] measure of production time and of all the

needs and services at once found within production and distribution.”[9]

The error here is in wanting to place Marxian theory of value at the

service of the management of communism. The notion of socially-average

labor time, and further its whole calculus, are not useful instruments

at the same level as a wheelbarrow or a milling machine: they are the

substance of capitalism and their use is inseparable from their function

which they demand. A society cannot be organized on the direct calculus

of average labor time without sooner or later a general equivalence

materializing, giving birth to some variant of money. Everyone knows

that despite some of its friendly aspects, barter is based on an

implicit accounting, an exchange of invisible money (nobody swaps a

motorcycle in running condition for some random swimsuit). For as long

as a product has a double existence, one as a determined object and

another as an exchange value serving as a base for comparison and

exchange, we will have not left behind the world of the

commodity-society and capitalism. A direct accounting of labor time will

create an invisible general equivalency: it will bring about measured

products just like commodities, though they will not circulate like

commodities, and there will be workers that will consume based on their

work without receiving a wage. One would soon see the re-emergence of

the classic forms of capitalism whose foundations never disappeared,

since only a market where businesses clash is able to sanction this

calculus of production time.

It is obvious that there is nothing intrinsically in common between a

head of lettuce and a skirt, except the quantity of primary materials

and energy necessary to obtain one or the other. But is within commodity

exchange, and further within capitalism, which find the need to

synthesize all the components of production so as to reduce lettuce and

skirts as commensurable: the necessary labor time.

That which escaped the G.I.C. was that the evaluation of resources (both

human and otherwise) necessary for all activity take on different

meanings depending on the society. Sewing clothes and planting salad

greens do not require the same effort or the same material elements, and

communism will take this into account: but it will not need to start

from abstraction (even calculated directly without money) of comparable

energy expenditure contained in these two activities. Communism will

count and compare quantities and any eventual losses and waste will be

much lower than those imposed by the calculus of a kind of universal

production time.

“The theory of measuring goods or forecasting investments [in communism]

by the amount of work done is incorrect. (…) This not a question

regarding a quarrel of method but a fundamental problem which concerns

the very nature of communism. The measurement of work remains economist.

This sort of measurement desires the end of the law of value but does

not see all that it implies. (…) The mistake is not in continuing to

take into account need, sacrifice or production in the new society. The

mistake is in packaging all this and to stick on it a label that reads

“labor time” in an effort to reduce labor time and to globally oppose it

to free time.”[10]

No matter the goal of this calculus or its method, a society founded on

labor time supposes that work remains distinct from non-work, and thus

separated from the rest of all activities: if not then how or why would

you measure it?

On the other hand, if Marx implicitly kept the firm as a value-chain led

by the collective worker, the G.I.C. puts it explicitly at the center as

an economic unit. The partisans of this project did not ignore that

certain firms, and certain workers within such firms, would inevitably

be more productive than others: they foresaw a way of a way of

correcting this inequality with a complex weighing method. We have

rarely gone so far in a program that preserves the foundations of

capitalism while placing them under the complete control of workers.

Bordiga was a bit off when he saw here an “entrepreneurial socialism,”

but his councilist error arose from an essential preoccupation which he

misunderstood: the desire for the emancipation of workers is a task set

aside for the workers themselves. As Jan Appel noted, the real reason

behind this plan was not so much a question of technics but rather of

politics: to make it so that every worker participates in their

management.

The G.I.C.’s plan owns a lot to the era after the crisis of 1929 where

capitalism was seen as on the way towards concentration, nationalization

and planification: this was an opinion shared by different people such

as Otto Rühle, Bruno Rizzi, the Trostkyist dissidents Burhnham and

Schactman, the councilists, Socialism or Barbarism, Karl Kosch in 1950

and even held by non-Marxists like A. Berle, G. Means and Schumpeter

(Bordiga was one of rare few who did not share in this opinion.)[11]

Russia served as a counter-model: it was necessary to avoid repeating

what happened after October 1917. The calculation of labor time would

allow them to maintain control over firms and of the economy. The

accounting of labor time is at once a condition and a guarantor of real

and efficacious worker management: no one could know better than

workers’ collectives how much time was exactly necessary to produce this

or that and to thus determine the contribution of each within the common

effort.

With their desire to present communism as a superior mode of production

and to provide supporting figures that “this could work,” the Dutch

comrades left behind a critique of work (let us remember that 1930 was

the most favorable time to bring the question of work into the light… ).

If we raise the project of the G.I.C. along side our commentary of the

Grundrisse in the last paragraph, we see that the councilists are

faithful to Marx, as well (unbeknown to them) as faithful to the

Grundrisse, which they could have not have known of in the 1930s:

communism for them was collective administration made possible by the

experienced gained through a phase of transition, which would finally

serve as a school for rational management.

1.7 Does value abolish itself?

This question may surprise. Nonetheless, if the Grundrisse has had such

a grand influence the past 40 years, it is because its reading allows

for diverse interpretations and among those interpretations includes the

notion of a capitalism forced to overcome itself.

In 1857-58, anticipating the future of capitalism, and commenting on the

first automated machines by Charles Babbage, forerunner of the computer,

Marx wrote:

“(…) immediate work ceases to be as such the base for production; since

on one hand work is transformed from an activity under surveillance and

management, and on the other hand, the product [of work] ceases to be

the result of isolated and direct work: it is the combination of social

activity which appears as such as the producer.” (p. 308)

“While in its immediate form, labor ceases to be the grand source of

wealth, labor time will cease to be, and should cease to be, the measure

of labor, just as exchange-value will cease to be the measure of

use-value. The surplus-labor of masses of humans will cease to be the

condition of development of general wealth. (…) From then, production

founded on exchange-value will collapse (…).” (p. 306)

In other terms, from this moment on it will be impossible to identify

what the individual worker brings into the creation of wealth, value (by

which we mean the regulation of production and the redistribution of

goods by the measure of socially-necessary labor time) would become

incompatible with the expansion of production and absurd within

capitalism itself.

Let’s think about what Marx thought around the same time:

“At a certain stage of their development, the material productive forces

of a society enter into contradiction with the existing productive

relations. (…) So then opens up an era of social revolution.” (Preface

to A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy, 1859).

Although this preface later affirms that it is the proletariat which

forms the principal of the productive forces, Marx did not share in the

confidence of historical “progress” common to his time: for him

capitalist development leads to communism. In the same way that merchant

power had shattered the feudal framework and replaced it with

aristocratic domination, he saw that economic socialization, the

concentration of the masses of workers would prove incompatible with

private property and bourgeois management of society. Suffice to say

that proletarian revolution was conceived in much the same way as the

model for bourgeois democratic revolution.

Marx cannot be reduced to this position, but it there is enough within

his work to justify such a program, since capitalism ends up negating

itself:

“In the same way that the bourgeois economic system develops bit by bit,

likewise, so the ultimate result of this system gradually develops its

own negation.” (Grundrisse, p. 311)

Many theorists (their names are legion) then applied themselves in the

demonstration of how the “law of value” tends towards its own abolition

(the word law demonstrates the transformation of critique into a

science, that is to say it became a knowledge independent of proletarian

practice).

Said in another way, capitalism will set into motion change at a

revolutionary scale…but without revolution. For the social question

resolves itself if there is a threshold where the wage laborer finds

themselves obsolete, socially-average labor time becomes an inadequate

measure and the inoperative regulator of a very socialized production

will not last long before tearing apart wage laborers like a seam sown

too tight.

1.8 Marxist Marx

To underline what separates communist Marx from his non-revolutionary

posterity, many, us included, have tried to make it so that Marx would

be the best critic of Marxism.[12] The intention is laudable but the

argument is flawed.

How does Marx conclude Capital?

“The transformation of scattered private property, arising from

individual labor, into capitalist private property is, naturally, a

process, incomparably more protracted, violent, and difficult, than the

transformation of capitalistic private property, already practically

resting on socialised production, into socialised property. In the

former case, we had the expropriation of the mass of the people by a few

usurpers; in the latter, we have the expropriation of a few usurpers by

the mass of the people”.[13]

Is capitalism already a “collective mode of production”? Since the end

of the 19th c., the socialist movement has exploited these lines (and

others in the same way) to explain why a capitalism organized into firms

ever more globally-interdependent would sooner or later escape both

private property and the anarchy of production: it would therefore be

enough to replaces bourgeois bosses with worker representatives and

socialism would come along on its own, without revolution, its arrival

being a quasi-natural phenomenon.

It is not unreasonable for Marxists to seek in Marx a theory of

capitalist socialization that would ultimately prevent capitalism from

perpetuating itself. Here’s a good definition of “Marxism”: the

replacement of proletarian action for gradual evolution, or with a

beneficial catastrophe, which in both cases would appear to be

comparable to the process of mutation among natural species. At the end

of the 19th c. the manuscripts for Capital Vol. 2 and 3, published after

the death of Marx, were read as the theory of the inexorable

contradiction between bourgeois private property and the huge growth in

the productive forces which even trusts and cartels would be unable to

control.

100 years later, the 1857-58 manuscripts now available were interpreted

as theorizing [Capital’s] unparalleled and yet irresistible structural

limit. It is the very sources and forms of contemporary wealth which

would call for a supersession [of Capital] which we need only put into

effect. Toni Negri would not be the last to read into these lines of the

Grundrisse that value (the regulation of production by labor-time and by

finding the minimum production cost) has already ceased to govern

contemporary society: it would thus only be a question of realizing this

and to draw its consequences so that society radically changes. The

world now resting on a collective intelligence, if this general

intellect were to become aware of itself, would lead to us liberating

ourselves. Briefly, in 1900 as in the 21st c., the production forces are

presented as evading the control of those who control them and further,

evading the logic of valorization and of wage laborers. With a

difference only in size: the historical subject is no longer labor,

definitely not the worker, but rather it is all of us, since the

lecturer, just as the mingong, contributes to the world’s wealth.

Such an interpretation is partial and biased but can claim the letter

and the spirit of Marxian works.

We need not oppose a young Marx to an old Marx, since these

contradictions traverse and animate his texts from 1840 until the end of

his life.[14]

Marx led a continuous and discontinuous project, from his first

unpublished texts to his manuscripts written late in age(which are not

yet all published). From the moment he showed his intuitions in the

Grundrisse, he was in preparation for a grand voyage never fulfilled,

Capital, a title revealing its priority: to go into the depths of

capitalism to thus understand its possible overthrow. The means became

the end: to comprehend that which was historically novel in the

proletariat he sunk 20 years of study into capitalism. Moreover, in the

later volumes of Capital foreseen by Marx – economic theories, the world

market, classes, the State – none were to be devoted to the proletariat.

Communism was thought of as coming from capitalism.

Undoubtedly, it is thanks to Marx that we can critique him and one of

the most illuminating commentaries of him was that by Bordiga, writing

more than a half century later, that we must read the ensemble of the

Marxian oeuvre as a “description of characters in a communist society.”

But today, on pain of behaving like an heir, we must see what dominated

Marx. His dazzling intuitions, still in manuscript form, mix the

supersession of the economy with the project of a communitarian economy.

Marx is more a critic of value (the commodity, money) than of work

(time, productivity). If Marxist thought allowed for the communist

revival of the mir to be accorded a minor place compared to the

industrialization of the world, it is because capitalist progress was

accompanied by a worker’s movement that Marx saw as the true mainspring.

To understand Marx is also to distinguish Marx from Marxism without

denying the link between the two. If not we run the risk of rewriting a

Marx set to everyone’s taste or to the latest fashion.

1.9 Marxism

With such a subject so vast and abundantly documented, we will confine

ourselves here to Engels and Lafargue.

That which Marx sketched out, Engels systematized, often stripping Marx

of his profound ambiguities. For Engels, the passage from the ape to the

human being was brought about by labor and language.[15] Work, which

“started with the making of tools,” is described as natural, useful and

conscious, its birth accompanied by language. Like Marx, but more

straightforward, Engels identified productive activity and work.

The dominant interpretation of The Right To Be Lazy (a text largely

distributed since its first edition in 1880, from social-democract to

anarchist milieus) finds within it a program that results from taking

what is good in capitalism (production in abundance) and removing what

is bad (exploitation of the producer). Paul Lafargue, this “redeemer of

humanity,” explains that by dividing productive tasks among all instead

of concentrating them in the hands of a few, thus forcing others to

employment, socialism would reduce the work day to 3 hours thanks to the

to suppression of useless production. Coincidentally, it is also a

3-hour workday which Keynes in 1930 promised would come to pass by the

end of the 20th c.[16]

Aristotle remains famous for his justification for slavery due to the

need to produce food and useful objects so that a privileged minority

could indulge in much more noble tasks: the Greek philosopher added that

there would be no more slaves “if weaver’s looms weaved all by

themselves” : it was Lafargue who proclaimed this day had come.

Social-democrats and Stalinists had little trouble in “recuperating” The

Right To Be Lazy: for them socialism was an extension of industrial

development oriented until now for the benefit of the bourgeoisie, an

extension supposedly done in the interests of the masses.

According to The Right To Be Lazy, work would hardly be work at all. A

century later with automation, the myth of a post-industrial society,

and more recently, the illusion of a new digital age, has lead some to

believe that the 3-hour day announced by Lafargue did not seem so bad at

all: work and leisure, manufacturing and creation would become one.

Finally reconciling the homo faber with the homo ludens and thus work

would cease to be work.

In 2009, Taillander published a collection of writings by Lafargue

titled Laziness and Revolution. In the past the association of these two

words would make for a provocative title, even an anarchist or

situationist one. (“Ne travaillez jamais”). By the start of the 21st c.,

redemption by machines is passé, but paradoxically, the omnipotence of

work allows a certain “criticism of work” to enter into social

morays.[17]

But what do we generally have against work? Above all, we see it is a

constraint, an alienation, an impoverisher of both the worker and of

nature.[18]

It’s certainly all of those things, but such a critique does not engage

with wage-laborers themselves (purchase-sale of human activity), nor

work as separation (to make one’s living by producing to later consume

thanks to the money gained).

2. Work and value

We will only deal here with societies where the constitutive features of

work exist, knowing that they have only been fully developed in the last

few centuries.

Every social analysis which implicates a definition of what is specific

to human beings, for as long as this definition is explicit, at its bare

minimum says: the human contributes in the production of their nature,

which they are the co-creator of. The human does not model itself at

will, but further becomes evolved by changing what surrounds them. In

producing their material living conditions, human beings do more than

this: to produce means to act in society, to speak, to travel … human

beings produce themselves and take their activity along with the

activity of other human beings as an object: the human is a subject and

has a history. The human sets themselves apart from themselves (and can

even become alien to themselves). This implies a choice, this implies

freedom (and its eventual loss).

This objectification contains the possibility of work.

2.1 Whomever speaks of work speaks of classes

So that this potentiality becomes realized, there needs to be a surplus

and this surplus would need to be more than a simple reserve (of food,

notably): a useful surplus is necessary to liberate a member of society

from the obligation of producing for themselves, thus allowing this

member to produce for other members. Work is a form of human activity

taken when work creates a surplus which escapes it. Work is a relation

between necessary work and surplus labor : there is a separation between

the expenditure of energy necessary to maintain the worker, and the

expenditure of energy beyond this maintenance, which creates a surplus.

Workers only exist for as long as a non-worker is making them labor for

their benefit. Work, an activity whose product recurs to others, implies

(and maintains) the division of groups within a society with opposed

interests. Society is divided among workers and non-workers, where

non-workers are reaping the production of workers. The worker may

maintain some control of their means of production and organize them

themselves, but the result of his labor does not belong to them. Work is

a class relation.

2.2 Work reduces all activity to a single substance

Human activity begins to take the form of work when humanity, over

thousands of years and in places which we will never know, arrives at

certain practices, few in number at the beginning, which have ceased to

be lived and received in such a way that each can have and produce what

they specifically need, e.g. flour or fabric. From that moment on, that

flour or fabric had begun to exist, above all, by and for their capacity

to be able to be exchanged one for the other, and have been treated ever

since in light of what they have in common: being both different results

but comparable within the same practice known as work, now susceptible

to be reduced to a universal and quantifiable given, the humanly

necessary average amount of effort needed to make that flour or fabric.

From then on these two objects have been produced for what they have in

common, this substance known as value.

Then came a decisive change, the passage of the exchange of one

commodity for another (flour/fabric), looking to satisfy two needs that

meet, an exchange aiming to obtain not a particular useful object, flour

or fabric, but the money destined to buy any kind of object, or to be

saved or invested.

Crystallized labor, money gave value a material form.

Money is not the result of practical necessity, for example to

facilitate barter or as a convenient means of exchanging a sack of flour

for a length of fabric so that those in this barter don’t “lose

anything.” Credit and debt precede money and as a proof we have the

masses of ancient peasants who were in debt before the invention of

money.

Whatever their origins, work and money have become inseparable. Even

under their immaterial forms of credit card chips and lines of credit,

they materialize the way in which activities and human being relate to

each other, and lastly how classes relate to each other.

If value reveals and manifests exchange, its source lies within work and

money serves to link up that which the division of labor separates.

As the history of the longue durée Fernand Braudel said one day: “The

misfortune is that the market exists and then you do not get to see what

goes on underneath.”

2.3 Wage laborers make of work a commodity

With wage laborers, work is not just activity done for money: it also an

activity which is bought and sold.

With the generalized sale-purchase of labor power, for the first time in

history, social classes distinctly distinguish themselves from their

respective place (bourgeois or proletariat) occupied by each within

production. The relation between necessary work and surplus labor

structures the world. No society can survive without productive

activity, but modern society is the first to live under the domination

of (waged) work.

This crucial fact is doubly obscured. First, there’s the general

tendency of making everyone need a wage and thus “everyone works,” even

the CEO, blurring the opposition between the worker and the non-worker.

Then, there’s two or three thousand proletarians without work or some

who are semi-proletarianized who stand outside the class of wage

laborers which they nonetheless form a part of.

This generalization of a class of wage laborers creates a completely

novel situation, even for those condemned to total or partial

unemployment. The slave, the serf and the sharecropper shared the

historical perspective that they need only get rid of the domination of

the master, the lord of the landowner to be able to work freely. Today,

the computer assembler or the palm oil wage laborer can only free

themselves by putting an end to their own existence as a bearer of labor

power, this commodity which potentially contains all other commodities.

Only commodified work can get rid of work. The program is no longer one

of liberating work, but to liberate ourselves from work. Work is that

which transforms activity into salable labor power and which only

recognizes the whole of human capacities as labor power.

2.4 Work as separated activity

Work is the form taken by the production of the material conditions

necessary for life when that productive activity has become detached

from the rest of activities, in varying degrees and forms. The

modern-day workforce cuts up their time between work, homelife, school,

hobbies, vacations, etc. and the space between places to earn money,

live, shop, be entertained and so on.

The space-time of non-work is not a capitalist creation: it has

coexisted with the space-time of work ever since the appearance of work.

The capitalist novelty lies in pushing this separation to the extreme,

accentuating the split between that which is productive and

non-productive of value.

2.5 Work is productivity and accounting

Organized into a series of competitive firms, where each is a

value-chain in search of optimal growth, capitalism logically tends to

increase surplus labor at the expense of necessary labor. Work brings

along with it productivity and normalization, with a permanent search

for ever more efficient methods of diminishing the cost of renewing

manufacturing processes: the famous “development of productive forces.”

Work and value – one cannot go without the other – implying production

for production’s sake – for the accumulation of value – and with it

“productivism” and planned obsolescence.

Today we constantly measure things against each other, compare and

exchange them according to the average labor-time they require or are

supposed to require, which also leads us to evaluate acts and people.

The augmentation in productivity (the growth of surplus labor which

creates new value in relation to the necessary labor compared to the

simple reproduction of labor power) is essential to all which we have

recounted here. If the search for productivity is an irresistible force,

with such destructive effects for humanity and nature, it is because the

race for ever more profitability is the engine of capitalism; this race

is its power and also the cause of its crises. So as to become more

profitable than their competitors, each firm is led by an

intensification of work, a development of mechanization and the growth

of capital invested in equipment, tools, robots, etc., increasing its

mass of value and ending up suffering diminishing returns.

2.6 Work is the reduction of everything to its minimum time

If human societies have over the last few centuries moved towards the

evermore precise and rigorous measure of time, it is so that they may

economize it so that production time may be reduced. The obsession with

“winning” time and the fear of “losing” it are integral to capitalism.

To work is to struggle against time.

On the contrary, human beings for whom the frantic search for

productivity is not an imperative, have no need to measure everything by

the seconds and minutes as they produce.

The best way to render energy-use in the most productive way possible is

to measure it by time so as to shorten it. For this reason the

separation between work and the rest of life is essential to the

accounting of time which finds itself at the core of value: one cannot

measure a moment and the effort expended in that moment unless that

segment of time is detached from all others.

We know how much to pay for a housekeeper: we cannot know the “worth” of

what a housewife does in their own home. Even if the two accomplished

the same tasks between 9AM and noon, those 180 minutes do not have the

same meaning for the employee who came to perform a three-hour task and

for the housewife who is busy at home performing various tasks.

Even the “by piece” wage of a single worker alone at his machine will be

calculated according to the number of seconds need to make each piece.

Indeed, one cannot really reduce labor time, because labor time, by its

socially-average definition, is not calculable for each task or for each

object. A worker’s wage at their machine will be the price of a work

whose value cannot be calculated, the specific contribution of this

worker to all the value created in the firm. Money really is

crystallized labor, only existing as an instrument within the

circulation of goods under the condition that these commodities also set

in motion other commodities and not by the calculation of the quantity

of labor each carries within it. A specific loaf of bread and a teapot

can be comparable in weight and not by the energy expenditure need to

produce either of them. Whatever Taylor may have believed, no scientific

method will ever quantify the new value added by a specific work task

within a workshop or an office.

“Rational madness,” Taylorism is none the less consistent with the

necessities of Capital.[19] As soon as a computer mousepad plant begins

to use equipment which requires the worker to produce more but at the

same wage, management ignores the precise resulting increase of value,

meanwhile it knows exactly how much it will pay the worker, how many

mousepads the worker is supposed to make within a given time and how

much they will sell each mousepad for. What is important here is that

the introduction of new equipment forces the worker to be more

productive. All the bourgeois knows, and which they count, are the

prices, first the wages and the profits and although economists speak of

value and creation of value, they openly consider “value” to be a

metaphysical speculation.

The capitalist struggle against time bears the effect of a planned

permanent obsolescence of commodities. Another consequence is the

obsession with saving time in everyday life. These two phenomena have

accelerated in the last twenty and thirty years, giving rise to a

denunciation of speed and “the dictatorship of immediacy”; we see

eulogies to slowness, slow food…reactions with little impact because

they do not ascend to recover labor time.

30 years ago, a study by Barbara Garson showed how computers are

transforming the office of the future into the factory of the past.[20]

The wage worker charged with taking airline ticket reservations by phone

sees their work cut up into four mandatory phrases, timed and monitored.

“To control everything, that’s the goal of the system,” declared one

employee. It’s not simply that “the system” knows everything done at

each moment but that for this end “the system” decomposes each gesture

to such a degree that the work becomes more and more incomprehensible

for those who do it (at the very moment where the operation of our daily

objects become infinitely more mysterious to us than the motor in the

fridge).

In 1966 when an MIT researcher came up with the ELIZA program, an

automated therapist who responded without human intervention to medical

questions, this expert system found widespread approval, many

considering it already a human therapist “as an information processor

and decision-taker.”If this shortening of human skills was possible, it

was because knowledge and social relations have already previously been

reduced to mechanics, to the quantifiable.

Computerization is not the cause: a machine does not create a social

relation. Capitalism privileges the result (the product) over the

process, the (measurable) object over relations and privileges the

decomposable and quantifiable tasks over the continuity of the ensemble.

But why bother to reduce the cost of labor which remains a small part of

the cost of production? According to official statistics, around 1980,

in the metal industry, direct work accounted for 10% of total costs. 30

years later, a pair of Nike Air Pegasus would sell for $70 in the United

States, which includes a $3 wage for Asian workers, $16 for raw

materials and $16 for design and advertising which adds up to $35. In

summary, $3 in labor, a production cost of $35 for a sale price of

$70.[21]

This is so because the game is not played from an accounting point of

view. It is about controlling the direct workers who, unlike executives,

advertisers and machines, are likely to resist or strike. “That’s why,”

concluded B. Garson,” any large mass of workers that can be automated

will be. Automated does not necessarily mean that robots will replace

them, but that their work is organized so as to become controllable at

all times. At least in theory, because it is always the one who execute

the work that will be best able to control the work. As the old worker

at Renault said: “Your boss pays you for your work, not for the way you

do the work.” At the beginning of the 20th century, counters were

installed on typewriters to check the number of keystrokes: some typists

responded by leaving wider spaces, by not hitting the space bar one

time, but two, three, four, even five times.

2.7 The society of king-labor

Our order of presentation is not chronological: we did not go back to

the origin of work, knowing that in real history these elements related

to work did not take on the same importance at the same time. It has

taken millenia before there was an exchange of equivalents, that is to

say, an exchange based on the more or less rigorous estimates of

necessary labor time and that “the law of value” would come and equalize

private work. Moreover, “money,” as the means to count in terms of value

and production and to circulate goods according to an exchange of

equivalents indeed precedes currency as we know it: there were not

instruments specifically reserved for the function of money (which also

did not have other uses, whether everyday or ritualistic). The arrival

of coinage is late (7th. Century B.C.).

In the world in which we live, each of the aspects which we have

conveniently distinguished in the exposition are the conditions for all

the others. For example, to force humans to “make a living” via the

wage, it was necessary to deprive them of autonomous means of existence

(§2.1). Further, measuring work supposes that it is separated from all

other activities (§2.4). It is only modern capitalism which has fully

developed the constitutive elements of work.

Despite the fact that only a minority of the world’s population receive

a wage and that even smaller minority benefits from a good labor

contract (with fixed & duly paid wages, labor rights, social security

contributions and union dues), the wage-employment nonetheless

dominates.

Capitalist forms determine pre-capitalist forms. A 9 year old Turkish

girl shepherding her parent’s herd of goats contributes to the family’s

income. Meanwhile, one of her brothers lives by working odd jobs in a

neighboring city, and the eldest brother works in a factory in Germany,

where in 10 years maybe the young Turkish girl may work as a cleaning

lady. This family is integrated into the global reproduction of the

Capital/labor relation. The global market brings in more and more people

into its logic, a minority of Earthlings today live on a purely “economy

of subsistence” and work and money penetrate into the heart of slums.

It all depends on the point of view. For a sociologist or an

anthropologist the activity of the young girl remains “entrenched” in

precapitalist relations and he would describe how her kinship ties are

saturated with archaisms, since, for example, her family has destined

her to an arranged marriage. The anthropologist is not wrong. But for

those who want to understand the nature of work, the method consists in

finding what is in common between the young Turkish girl and a worker of

Maruti Suzuki, or with a Bolivian bank employee (which is not to say

that the three would have the same impact on the course of history).

The dominant social relation (wage labor) is not the sole one, but it

determines all the others, including any sort of benevolent activity

(which is labor indirectly remunerated), as well as including slavery

(forced unpaid labor with absolute boss control over the worker,

estimated at between 20 and 30million worldwide). And while we may read

that the informal economy makes up 40% (made up of mostly women) of the

so-called active world population, this statistic utilizes a category

produced by the existence of wage-laborers which distinctly classifies

that which does not enter its strict framework (labor contract) of

work.[22]

Let us not confuse work with employment. The undeniable fact that there

are and will be fewer hires than the unemployed in the world does not

prevent productive work from remaining the center of the world today.

What is called “social security” refers to the place of work: the money

paid (or not) to the student, the unemployed, the sick, to families, to

the elderly, the disabled is granted to categories that either cannot,

cannot yet or cannot any longer work. Although public opinion denounces

king-money (and more subtle theoreticians denounce the domination of

value), it would be more accurate to say that we live under the reign of

work, that is to say, wage labor.[23]

3. Neither work nor economy

§2 sought out to identify six characteristics which altogether

constitute work: necessary work/surplus-labor and class divisions;

value; commidification; separation; productivity and accounting; and

time. Our ambition was not to construct a theoretical machine which

would cease to function as soon as you remove one piece, as though,

missing three of these six components, work would only partially

continue to exist: only abstraction requires the separation into

categories that which in reality is nested.

To comprehend the possible link between capitalism and a revolution

which would abolish work, instead of taking these six elements

separately, let’s consider them next as a whole.

3.1 Production is not economy

“Production” is often assimilated into artisanal or industrial

fabrication of objects. It would seem to be more apropos to consider, as

Alain Testart, does that there is production “whenever the means of work

are applied to raw material to turn it into a consumable product in a

form in which it was not before.”[24] Hunter, harvester and fisher,

unlike predators, make use of weapons and knowledge. By producing, the

human also produces instruments and means of production, for example a

bow for hunting. With agriculture, the human modifies nature with the

intentional sowing of nutritional plants: from hunter-gather, the human

becomes a “producer.”

But production is not synonymous with economy.

The difficulty lies in understanding that the production of the material

conditions for existence has become a reality we call economy,

progressively more autonomous from the rest of life, to the point where

in the modern era it is a distinct sphere, with a separation between the

time-space consecrated to making a living (work) and all other

activities.

There is no “economic history,” because economy is a historical fact

that has not reigned at all times and everywhere. For example, the

noting of “per capita income” or “of households” only has any meaning

when there exists individual persons or nuclear households.[25]

Malthus attributed the possible crisis of capitalism to a growth of

population that goes over the growth of resources, particularly food.

Ecologists explain history by the capacity or the incapacity for

societies to adjust to the environment to their needs. Rejuvenated by

its taking into account of natural resources and the need to renew these

resources, economic thought is nonetheless economic: it’s number one

problem is the creation of a balance between means and ends. It’s a

morality based on accounting.

Gregory Clark wrote in a well-documented book: “during the Malthusian

era economic laws governing human society are the same as those

governing all animal societies.”[26] The driving thread within history

would be the evolution of the relationship between available resources

and the population, whether human or animal: the same reasoning was

applied to the residents Charleville-Mézières, as the deer of the nearby

Ardennes [forests].

Nonetheless, far from being an apologist for progress, Gregory Clark

argues, with backing figures, that hunter-gathers spent between 4 and 5

hours a day gathering food; that in 1800 the average Earthling did not

live better than those who lived 100,000 years before Christ; that in

Asia the conditions were even worse, and that the so-called primitive

“produced” more calories per hour of “work” than the civilized did in

England. These facts are sobering, but what these figures show is a

desire to reduce everything to measurability, as if the Amazonian and

the Yorkshire laborer lived the same social relationship, separated only

by different degrees on a scape of production and consumption.

The dominant mental schema has changed little since [Henri de]

Saint-Simon’s time: “the production of useful things is the sole

reasonable, and positive goal that political societies can propose for

themselves.” The ideal would then be a society where “all men work. This

obligation is imposed on all to constantly give their personal efforts

toward a useful direction for society.” (L’Industrie, 1811-1812). For

Saint-Simon, the merchant or farmer are as much “producers” as the

worker or the industrialist (For him socialism would mean the

suppression of the merchant and to meld the worker and the industrialist

into one figure).

Under economic thought, society relies on the production and the

allotment of resources. The socialist economist also brings into the

fold the criterion of utility and of justice; the ecological economist

brings the obligation of harmony with nature; but it is still a question

of administrating a surplus: the relation between necessary labor and

surplus labor become thought of as self-evident: it is a matter of

producing something to eat, somewhere to live, somewhere to heal

oneself…then finally arrive to the spice of life. Utility before what is

pleasant. Soup before the concert. We must first be ants to then become

a cicada.

To retain the relationship between necessary labor and surplus-labor is

to retain work itself.

The fundamental mistake is to make everything about meeting the need to

satisfy basic needs. Without food, I die: this self-evident statement

only makes sense if it is connected to the fact that human existence is

social. I don’t eat first so I can then be in society. Hunger is always

lived and treated in function to the conditions imposed upon by human

beings (whether they’re in Alaska or Tahiti) and their social

organization. Hunger does not further intervene: both play at the same

time: the cold is not more the cause of social life of the Inuit than

the tropical humidity is the cause of the Tahitians. No vital necessity

takes precedence over social links: between the two there is a

simultaneity. The same is true under capitalism. Likewise in revolution.

Similarly in communism. Except that production will no longer play the

same role.

It is not a question of how do human beings produce themselves?; nor,

what do they produce? (whether education software or assault weapons)

But rather: what place do they take within the production of human life.

According to a widespread idea in the radical milieu, the objective will

not be to “produce just to produce,” but rather to create the minimum

abundance necessary without which human emancipation will not be

possible.

Alfred Rosemer wrote in 1923: “Communism supposes and demands abundance

because the distribution of products should be simple and easy.”[27]

The real motive of this imperative for production is to not allow

overconsumption: Rosmer prioritizes abundance because he sees in it the

necessary condition for a just distribution.

Inversely, others make of a frugal moderation the condition of a free

and solidarity-based community. In The Dispossessed by Ursula Le Guin

(1974), on the planet Anarres owes much of its rather libertarian[28]

way of life to its harsh climates, which lends itself to favor mutual

aid and also makes accumulation difficult.

Whether one prefers abundance or a soberness in production, in both

visions, the priority is economic. This what we must criticize.

3.2 Communism as an activity

A frequent criticism of capitalism is that it fabricates goods without

taking care of real needs, and then goes on to sell its wares on the

market: the satisfaction of needs is but a side consequence. This

conception then leads some to do the opposite: to start off based on

needs, but this time based on supposed real needs which are decided upon

collectively; a conception which desires to satisfy these needs through

adequate production and equitable distribution, without the mediation of

the market, thanks to a communitarian, democratic and self-organized

organization.

This ignores that needs also make up an economic category.

Let’s observe that needs are almost always defined in the negative: to

not die of hunger, of cold or of sickness; to not be forced to sleep in

the rain, etc. When we speak of needs, we speak of a lack.

It is self-evident that human beings have basic necessities, such as to

eat and to sleep, just as it is imperative to match these with existing

resources. That which is untrue is the idea that human life consists of,

above all, satisfying these needs. The only way we satisfy these needs,

or fail in doing so, is by way of social interrelations. It is only

under exceptional circumstances that we eat just so that we will not

die. For human beings, to eat will always be more than just eating.

Generally, we eat in the company of others, chosen or not, or we choose

to eat alone, or we are forced to eat alone, which is also itself a

social situation. Often we follow a diet, either dietary or not.[29]

Sometimes we have to skip a meal so as to not eat or drink too much. The

same is true of all our other vital activities. As Marx wrote in The

German Ideology, meeting vital needs also creates new needs, and “this

production of new needs is the first historical fact.”

Contrary to a common error, the “materialist conception of history” does

not say that “the economy” leads the world. This is often the way that

the first part of The German Ideology is read, although Marx intended

something else altogether. Firstly, social relations depend on how we

produce our material conditions for life and not what our ideas are of

the world. Secondly, we produced these material conditions in relation

with other human beings, and in class societies, we create them through

class relations. The “materialist conception” does not make “the

economy” the motor of human evolution, but it can explain how the

current domination of the economy over our world is a historical

phenomena; a phenomena that was unknown in pre-history and one which was

less important in Athens 500b.c. than in Athens 2015; and it is a

phenomena which will disappear with communism.

Without developing what is said within From Crisis to Communization, let

us say here that our problem lies not in inventing a new society which

will put in parallel our needs and resources (as the economists may

want), or transform artificial and extravagant needs into reasonable

needs so as to attain a sufficient frugality (as the ecologists may

want). It is rather a matter of understanding what our basic needs truly

are. The first human need, wrote Marx, is the need for the other. We

would say: the need to feed ourselves is indissoluble from the need of

the other, and the two are satisfied (or not) at the same time. We must

eat, that much is self-evident, and social relations do not fill empty

stomachs, but we eat within those social relations.

All of this is verified during revolutionary periods: “without

reserves,” the proletarian having neither money or food, or arms (at

first), find their only strength is their acting with other

proletarians.

Admittedly, at first the pressure of circumstances (internal conflicts,

armed struggle, shortages…) will sometimes lead the insurgents to share

and distribute as justly as possible (in both sense of the word), so,

whether it they like it or not, they must ration. But the revolution

would be damned if it proved incapable of distinguishing a social

emergency from the rest of its fundamental “program,” it would be damned

if it were to allow social emergency to determine its base.

We will not ask ourselves: “How many roof tiles are necessary for that

house?” but rather: “how many could it house?” Starting from there, we

will then figure out how many x tiles are necessary by how many y

squared meters for the roof: to suppress accounting does not mean we

will renounce the use of measurements.

The communizing motor of action will not be the search for the best or

the most equal way of distributing goods, but rather the human relations

and activities found therein: within communization, activity is more

important than its productive result because this result depends on an

activity and of ties that could and would strengthen bonds among the

insurgents. That which stirs the proletarian to act is not the need to

eat, it is the need to create among other proletarians a social

relation, which among other things will also feed them.

The need to create food, to cultivate carrots for example, will be

satisfied by way of social relations which, among other activities, will

cultivate beans, which will not mean that each minute or hour of

horticulture will be lived as a kind of a joy without cloudy skies.

Counter-revolution will of course exploit our inevitable disarray and

local shortages. The revolution will not respond by bringing back to

life an even-more productive industry, nor will it do away with

bourgeois armies by creating an even stronger army. “Realism” is to be

found where you least expect it. It is the bureaucrats whom of course

will try to pass themselves as “practical,” explaining that after

insurrectionary spontaneism must follow productive organization, which

solely could resolve the most vital and urgent problems. Through means

of some large and small transformations, the ideology of “common sense”

(a hammer or computer are neutral, they will tell us, and that they’re

neither capitalist nor communist) will promote a concern for efficiency

which, despite a shift in discourse, will contain all the traits of

productivity. However, work and productivity are linked. Work normalizes

things. Keeping track of time during production demands that we separate

it from the rest of the day, thus we detach it from life by distinctly

calling it work. Revolution cannot make time-saving one of its

priorities.

The division of labor will neither be overcome by a simple permanent

sharing of duties. A varied form of work remains work. Working

cooperatively is also work: collective work is also work. Working two

hours a day is also work. The replacement of private producers with

communitarian production, or the systematic re-distribution of tasks,

only makes communist sense if the products are not compared – and thus

incomparable – among each other (nor the activities which have produced

them) by way of some calculus (implicit or not) of the real or supposed

average labor time to make them. Because if we count, if social life

revolves around this measure, whatever the mode of association, sooner

or later value will reappear, even in a community with the most

fraternal intentions.[30]

This text started with a fictitious boss who offered illusory

employment. In the so-called real world, many of our contemporaries

“make a living” by making up marketing campaigns, which others print,

then are deposited into mailboxes, which then are recovered at the dump

to make into recycled paper, on which will be printed new prospectus,

while experts are hired to analyze it all and intellectuals are hired to

deplore them. The surrealists asked themselves if we suffered either too

little or too much from reality… At any rate, the “absurdity” of work

will never be enough to do away with it. We will need nothing less than

a revolution. We do not ignore that “there is something ridiculous in

talking about revolution”: “But the whole rest of it is even more

ridiculous, since it is that which exists, along with the various forms

its accepted.”[31]

[1] A curious destiny was set for these reading notes commonly called

the Grundrisse which were only published in Moscow in German during the

maelstrom that was World War II. There were almost unknown until their

second edition in German in 1953, the text was not available in French

until 1967-68, and it was even later when they were published in other

European languages (English in 1973).

[2] Engels, Anti-Dühring, 1873, Section 3, Chp. 2

https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1877/anti-duhring/ch24.htm

[3] Notes sur F. List,Œuvres, Gallimard, III, 1982, pp. 1418-1451.

[4] Ibid., pp. 1111 et 1123.

[5] Capital, Vol. I, Œuvres, Gallimard, I, 1963, p.570.

[6] Ibid., p. 1420

[7] Ibid., p. 605.

[8] Groupe des Communistes Internationalistes de Hollande (GICH),

Principes fondamentaux de la production et de la distribution

communistes : http://www.mondialisme.org/spip.php?article1308

[9] Short biography of J. Appel (in French) :

http://www.collectif-smolny.org/article.php3?id_article=676collectif-smilny.org.

[10] OJTR,Un Monde sans argent : le communisme, Chap. V, Ed. du Sandre,

2013.

[11] In 1932, Berle and Means were among the first to theorize a

capitalism of managers in Property and control within the large

enterprise. Bruno Rizzi (1901-1977) publie en 1939 La bureaucratisation

du monde. Pour un compte-rendu par Pierre Souyri de la réédition du

livre chez Champ Libre en 1976 :

http://www.persee.fr/doc/ahess_03952649_1979_num_34_4_294092_t1_0894_0000_002

Sur la critique de la thèse d’un capitalisme « bureaucratique » ou «

d’Etat » par Bordiga, voir entre autres : La Doctrine du diable au

corps, 1951 :

http://classiques.uqac.ca/classiques/bordiga_amedeo/doctrine_diable_au_corps/doctrine_diable_au_corps.html

Et ses Thèses sur la Russie, 1952 :

https://bataillesocialiste.wordpress.com/documents-historiques/1952-theses-sur-la-russie-bordiga/

[12] Maximilien Rubel, Marx critique du marxisme (1974 et 1983),

Entremonde, 2011 : http://entremonde.net/IMG/pdf/CAHIERS04-Livre.pdf

[13] Œuvres, I, Gallimard, p. 1240.

[14] “Let’s not idealize the 1840 years as proof of an authentic

communism which was then abandoned. The Principals of Communism by

Engels in 1847 prefigure that which would become the socialist program a

few decades later: “(…) to concentrate more and more within the hands of

the State all of Capital, agriculture and industry, transportation and

exchanges. (…) These measures (…) will become ever more centralized

along with the growth of the productive forces thanks to the work of the

proletariat. Finally, when the whole of Capital, production and

exchanges are concentrated in the hands of the State, private property

would also fall, money would become superfluous (…).”

https://www.marxists.org/francais/marx/47-pdc.htm A good history book on

this time period:Alain Maillard, La Communauté des Égaux. Le communisme

néo-babouviste dans la France des années 1840, Kimé, 1999.

[15] Le Rôle du travail du travail dans la transformation du singe en

homme, 1876 : https://www.marxists.org/francais/marx/76-rotra.htm

[16] Perspectives économique pour nos petits-enfants :

http://s182403251.onlinehome.fr/IMG/pdf/keynes_essais_de_persuasion.pdf

[17] In their Manifest contre le travail (1999), Krisis describes work

as no longer necessary under capitalism, which on the one hand becomes

less and less necessary and that the little work it retains is

completely devoid of meaning.

[18] Bob Black sums up the dominant perception to found in radical

milieus: “My definition of work is forced labor, obligatory production.

These two parameters are essential. (…) Work violates freedom.”

(Abolition of work, 1985)

[19]

B. Doray, Le Taylorisme, une folie rationnelle ?, Dunod, 1981.

[20] The Electronic Sweatshop. How Computers are Transforming the Office

of the Future into the Factory of the Past, Penguin, 1988.

[21]

D. Cohen, Trois leçons sur la société post-industrielle, Seuil, 2006.

[22]

B. Lautier, L’Economie informelle dans le tiers-monde, Repères, 2004.

[23] G.D., La boulangère & le théoricien (sur la théorie de la

forme-valeur), 2014 : https://ddt21.noblogs.org/?s=forme-valeur

[24] Avant l’histoire, Gallimard, 2012.

[25] This is not stopped Thomas Piketty from measuring the relationship

between the return on capital (from patrimonial wealth ) and the rate of

growth of the last 2,000 years as though these realities had similar

worth in ancient Rome as they do in contemporary New York.

[26] A Farewell to Alms. A Brief Economic History of the World,

Princeton UP, 2007.

[27] L’Humanité, 3 février 1923, cité dans Ch. Gras, Alfred Rosmer

(1877-1964) et le mouvement révolutionnaire international, Maspéro,

1971.

[28] Translator’s note: here ‘libertarian’ is closer to ‘anarchist’ than

those who, in the English-speaking world, have taken on this term as a

way to align with small gov’t and free-market capitalism.

[29] Translator’s note: in French the word for “diet” is “régime” which

can mean either a diet taken on for health reasons (‘dietary’) or just a

diet that we follow on custom (‘or not’).

[30] To learn more on what would make a communist revolution, see

chapter 5 (« L’Insurrection créatrice ») of this book, which this is an

excerpt of : De la Crise à la communisation, Entremonde, 2017.

[31] Internationale Situationniste, n°6, 1961 :

https://www.larevuedesressources.org/IMG/pdf/internationale_situationniste_6.pdf