💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › paul-bowman-what-is-communism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 13:13:21. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: What is communism?
Author: Paul Bowman
Date: 2005
Language: en
Topics: Communism, introductory, Red & Black Revolution
Source: Retrieved on 9th August 2021 from http://struggle.ws/wsm/rbr/extra/communism.html
Notes: This article is from Red & Black Revolution (no 10, Winter 2005)

Paul Bowman

What is communism?

What is communism? Well according to the Concise Oxford dictionary,

communism is

“1 a political theory derived from Marx, advocating class war and

leading to a society in which all property is publicly owned and each

person is paid and works according to his or her needs and abilities. 2

(usu. Communism) a the communistic form of society established in the

USSR and elsewhere.”

If that was correct then this would be a very short article. However, as

so often, the Concise Oxford is wrong again. In fact the terms socialism

and communism appear in England around the 1820s as terms adopted by

members of the cooperative movement who were sick of hearing their

politics referred to as “Owenism”. Originally the two terms were

undifferentiated but by the 1840s communism was used by revolutionaries

to differentiate themselves from reformists such as J.S.Mill who had

adopted socialism to cover an indigestible mess of reformisms.

By the 1870s the terms had moved from differentiating means to

distinguishing ends. The proper Oxford English Dictionary notes in its

sources:

“Forster Diary 11 May in T. W. Reid Life (1888) .... I learn that the

great distinction between communism and socialism is that the latter

believes in payment according to work done and the former does not”.

It is this meaning of communism as opposed to socialism that evolved in

the late nineteenth century that this article discusses. Of course its

not that important to get hung up on a name, for many people the Concise

definition of communism being something to do with Marx and the USSR is

the one they know. For us the name of the post-capitalist society we aim

to help construct is a detail, what matters is the content of the ideas.

Nonetheless for the purposes of this article we need to choose a name so

we stick with the historical one.

Beginnings

As long as society has been divided into the privileged and the

exploited there has been resistance and that resistance has found voice

and expression in the language of the oppressed seeking to define the

road to their freedom. Communism, however is the product of the rise of

capitalist society and the new conditions of oppression and new

possibilities for freedom it brought. The introduction of capitalism

involved the struggle for power of a new class excluded from the

governance of pre-capitalist agrarian based society and the voice they

found to express and direct that struggle was political economy.

Communism then begins as the other new class, the proletariat or working

class, seeks to find its voice and finding itself in contest with the

emerging capitalist class is forced to take on confront and subvert the

voice of their opponent. Thus communism as a discourse begins as a

response to political economy.

Political Economy

Political economy begins with the work of Adam Smith in the late 17^(th)

century. Smith’s “Wealth of Nations” was a project of leaving behind the

religious discourse of the previous century’s Civil War where political

tendencies couched their class aspirations and ambitions in the language

of theology. To do so he followed the enlightenment push to create a

secular, rational and “scientific” discourse which attempted to avoid

the murderous and indeterminable controversies of religion by reference

to “facts”. The aim was to determine the best course of government

action or policy directed to the end of increasing overall wealth. In

order to do this the challenge was to define a reliable measure of

wealth or “value”. Given the history of inflation, currency alone was

clearly not viable as a direct measure. In the end Smith settled for a

theory of value based on the amount of labour embodied in goods

produced.

This was the basis of what was to be further developed by subsequent

political economists such as James Mill and David Ricardo as the “labour

theory of value” — that is the theory that the underlying value of that

makes a given amount of grain exchangeable for a given amount of wrought

iron or cloth is determined by the average amount of labour time

necessary for the production of each product. The main question

addressed by Smith’s political economy was how changes in the

distribution of wealth affected the rate of growth of the overall wealth

of the nation. The main argument was that those government policies

which, through taxation, re-distributed wealth from the manufacturing

and commerce sectors to the land-owners retarded growth as the latter

group, being unwilling to re-invest the extra income into more

wealth-generating industry, simply frittered it away in excess personal

consumption.

From the outset political economy was a subject with an agenda, namely

that of defending the interests of the rising manufacturing classes

against those of the dominant land-owning gentry and aristocracy who had

a monopoly on governmental power. At the same time, through the

arguments of political economists like Thomas Malthus, they argued

against the effectiveness of the Poor Relief taxes the manufacturing

bosses had to pay for the feeding of the poor and unemployed during

periods of economic slump and high unemployment. This latter aspect came

particularly to the fore in the great economic slump that followed the

ending of the Napoleonic wars in 1815 [?] and the struggle around the

proposed legalisation of unions in 1824.

William Thompson

One of the first people to critically engage with political economy and

attempt to turn it around to defend the improvement of the condition of

the working class and rural poor was the scion of an Anglo- Irish

landowning family from West Cork by the name of William Thompson. Born

in 1775 in Cork, the young Thompson had been an enthusiastic supporter

of the enlightenment, republicanism and the French Revolution. He later

became a leading figure in the Co-operative movement in radical

opposition to Robert Owen.

In the 1820s, outraged by the use of political economy by a local

“eminent speaker” to argue the supposed necessity and benefit of the

absolute poverty of the “lower orders” Thompson set about an

investigation into political economy which resulted in his “An Inquiry

into the Principles of the Distribution of Wealth Most Conducive to

Human Happiness” of 1824. As the lengthy title indicates his attention

was like the political economists also focused on the effects of the

distribution of wealth, however his yardstick for the outcome was the

utilitarian “greatest good for the greatest number” rather than the

overall abstraction of the “wealth of the nation”.

He addressed Bentham’s three principles governing distribution — the

right to security, the right to the produce of labour and the right to

subsistence. The right to subsistence was the principle of distribution

by need which, in Bentham’s reasoning, had to be subordinate to the

right to the produce of labour which recognised the priority of the

producers claim to the product of his or her own labour. Bentham

over-ranked both with the right to security i.e. that the individual’s

right to his or her existing property had to be defended from arbitrary

abstraction by society or all medium to long term incentives to economic

activity would be nullified by the possibility of having any gains taken

away in the future.

Thompson’s first point of attack was to recognise that under the guise

of the right to security Bentham and the utilitarians were in fact

defending the existing property status quo without any interest into the

legitimacy of how this division of ownership had come about. In

Thompson’s native West Cork it was easy to recognise that the monopoly

of land by the Anglo-Irish protestant ascendancy had been brought about

not through thrift, hard work and parsimonious virtue but by military

main force. Further Thompson exposed that exchanges between the

dispossessed and property-monopolising classes could not be seen as free

or equal in any way as the propertyless had to accept unfair wages for

the sale of their labour under duress of starvation as the alternative.

Thompson went on to analyse the process of exploitation of the wage

labourer by their employers and how the lion’s share of the product was

appropriated by the latter as surplus value in an account later adopted

by Marx.

From here Thompson moved to posit a system of “free exchange” where

equal access to land and the means of production was guaranteed to all,

but distribution was governed by the right to the produce of labour

taking precedence over the right to subsistence. As the anarchist

historian Max Nettlau noted “[Thompson’s] book, however, discloses his

own evolution; having started with a demand for the full product of

labour as well as the regulation of distribution, he ended up with his

own conversion to communism, that is to unlimited distribution”.

That is, having proposed a system based on the right to the full product

of labour he re-examined it compared to a system of equal distribution

by the same utilitarian yardstick that he had used to dismiss the status

quo and found, to his initial surprise that the system of “free

exchange” was inferior to that of unlimited equal distribution. In

examining the hypothetical system of “free exchange” he discovered its

competitive nature — the term “competitive” in fact was first applied to

describe capitalist exchange by him. The evils Thompson ascribed to the

competitive system were not simply ethical or moral — that the system

made each look upon his or her peers as rivals and means to an end — but

also in terms of efficiency — that competition would encourage people to

hide their innovations and discoveries and that market intelligence

would also be kept secret thus causing waste and inefficiency.

In the year Thompson’s “Distribution of Wealth” was published he spent

much time in London engaging in a series of public debates defending the

rights of trade unions against the bourgeois political economists such

as J. S. Mill and also on the way forward for the workers with Thomas

Hodgskin at the newly formed London Mechanics Institute.

The Thompson vs Hodgskin debate

Thomas Hodgskin was the son of a storekeeper at the naval dockyards at

Chatham Kent and had served in the British navy during the Napoleonic

wars. Expelled from the navy at the end of the war due to conflict with

upper ranks, he became a radical journalist and a fierce critic of

authority and the upper classes. He shared with Thompson the view that

the upper classes monopoly on land and the means of production allowed

them to exploit those compelled by necessity to sell their labour to

them. Where he differed with Thompson was that he considered the right

to the full product of labour freed from capitalist exploitation to be

the ultimate goal of radical reform. In Hodgskin’s vision groups of

workers organised as unions, could take possession of the means of

production and exchange their products amongst each other on a “market”

basis. The ensuing debate between Hodgskin and Thompson resulted in the

publication of “Labour Defended” and “Labour Rewarded” respectively and

in many ways outlined the division between the advocates of socialism

and communism that has continued to run through the radical

anti-capitalist movement to this day.

Hodgskin’s eclipse of Thompson

In the end it was Hodgskin’s analysis that won out over Thompson’s.

Thompson suffered the marginalising effects of his West Cork base, his

early death and his association with the strategy of setting up

experimental communities. In addition his theoretical writings were too

lengthy, challenging and, above all, too expensive for the ordinary

worker to afford. In contrast Hodgskin was concise and skilled in making

his arguments in a language the ordinary worker could both readily

understand and re-use amongst his or her peers. Above all Hodgskin was

“good enough” for the purposes of the nascent trades union movement.

Radical enough to turn the tables on the political economy of the bosses

but avoiding the truly radical total inversion of the existing order

that Thompson’s proto-communism called for. With Hodgskin the trade

union agitators could conjure up the vision of a future society free of

the worker’s exploitation by the bosses but still retaining the

familiarity of money and exchange. The “natural wage” undiminished by

the exploitative abstractions by the capitalists and landlords.

Joseph Dejacque — the revolutionary approach

Just as the crushing defeat and savage repression of republican

revolution in Ireland and Britain pushed Thompson and Hodgskin, the

cooperators and trade unionists to steer their frame of action away from

the society-wide or revolutionary scope, so the fact of the revolution

in France cast all progressive thought into this framework. However it

was also exclusively a statist and authoritarian framework until

Proudhon broke the mould by proposing a society-wide and revolutionary

solution that did away with the state. Despite his originality in

breaking with the statist stranglehold on French radical thought,

Proudhon still retained many reactionary elements in his outlook. It was

his neanderthal stance on the emancipation of women that provoked a

young sympathiser of the new anarchist ideal, Joseph Dejacque, to first

openly break with and attack Proudhon’s failings. But in addition to

taking him to task for his opposition to female emancipation Dejacque

also denounced Proudhon’s economic critique of capitalism as inadequate

and incomplete. Proudhon’s position was in fact similar to Hodgskin in

aiming for the elimination of the monopolies on land and means of

production by the capitalist and landlord classes, but the retention of

the wage, money and exchange as the means of organising the transmission

of goods between producers. In other words, capitalism without

capitalists.

In Dejacque’s view this is too conservative. Taking Proudhon’s slogan of

“property is theft” to its, as he saw it, logical conclusions Dejacque

denounced as property claims any claim by producers on that part of what

they had produced that was not for their own consumption or use. In this

context he distinguishes between possessions — those goods you have

reasonable exclusive claim over for your own use — and property claims —

where you seek to deny others the use of goods that you have no use for

yourself. Dejacque uses the example of a shoemaker who can make shoes of

his or her own size and to their personal taste and claim them as their

own possessions to use. The same shoemaker can also make for different

sizes of feet and different tastes or fashions. These latter shoes are

not possessions as the shoemaker is not intending to use them

personally. Instead in claiming them as property he or she is denying

their use to others, in effect holding them hostage until they can be

exchanged for other goods the maker judges to be of enough value to

satisfy them.

Dejacque’s critique of exchange is couched very much in the language of

justice and injustice coming out of the enlightenment discourse of the

French Revolution. It lacks the fullness of Thompson’s more laboured and

wide-ranging critique of capitalist political economy, yet it integrates

the aim of communism into the whole of a revolutionary and explicitly

anti-state and anarchist goal. As such Dejacque is the first libertarian

or anarchist communist. Though Dejacque identified himself as an

anarchist and, through the title of his periodical, introduced the term

libertarian as a synonym for the same, he did not attach the label

communism to his economic ideas.

Marx — a failed synthesis

This label was at the time being used by proponents of the authoritarian

and statist conspiracies Proudhon had struck out against. Specifically

the Communist League which includes at that time the German radicals

Friedrich Engels and Karl Marx. The latter producing the “Communist

Manifesto” for the league.

In his studies in the 1840s, Marx had come across the work of both

Thompson and Hodgskin and from their common ground critique of

capitalist exploitation he takes the broad outline of his critique of

the same in “Capital” and other works. However on the issue of the main

contention dividing the two Marx ended up choosing neither one nor the

other. Concentrating most of his effort on elaborating the critique of

capitalist political economy already outline by Thompson and Hodgskin in

the 1820s, Marx wrote remarkably little on the principles governing

post-capitalist society. What little he wrote in the “Critique of the

Gotha Programme” seems an attempt to reconcile the two opposing

principles. On the one hand Marx argues that as society emerges from

capitalism with the expropriation of the land and means of production

from the landowning and capitalist classes, it must retain the forms of

money, the wage and exchange. This, Marx’s “lower phase of communism”

(which n.b. is not communist in the way this term is used in this

article) corresponds to Hodgskin’s vision of capitalism without

capitalists. Yet on the other hand, Marx sees this first stage not as an

end in itself but only as a transitional stage towards the “higher phase

of communism” corresponding to Thompson’s vision of a society from which

wage, money and exchange have been abolished. Marx’s attempt at a

synthesis of the two positions is undeveloped and fails to answer basic

questions. Namely why the first stage is not a sufficient goal in

itself, how exactly does the first stage create the (unspecified)

conditions for the second stage and how and when does the transition

from one to the other actually take place?

These failings in Marx’s work are in many ways the flipside about

strengths and originality of the other aspects of his contribution.

Whereas Thompson, Hodgskin and Dejacque approached the problem of social

liberation from the ahistorical starting points of utilitarianism,

radical and enlightenment revolutionary analysis respectively, Marx

brings the perspective of historical development from his Hegelian

background. Whereas the previous three were all acutely aware of the

clashing interests of the labouring and owning classes and the extent to

which the bosses ideologies suited their class interests, it is Marx

that puts forward the theory of the class struggle as the motor of

history. What is original in Marx’s “Capital” is not the theory of

exploitation and surplus value which he inherits from Thompson, but the

role of class struggle in limiting the working day and shaping the

introduction of productivity-enhancing technology as a response to

working class resistance to exploitation. This focus on the historical

and contestational dynamics of the process is what gives Marx’s work

continuing relevance to theorists today, yet it is accompanied by a lack

of attention to specifics of the goal of a post-capitalist society.

Despite his many contributions, Marx’s work on its own represents a

backwards step in comparison to Thompson’s work when it comes to

investigating the social relations of a post-capitalist society.

The bourgeoisie strikes back — taking the politics out of Political

Economy

By the late nineteenth century, the legal proponents of capitalist

political economy realised they faced huge challenges which necessitated

a major change of direction. Continuing the line of development of

classical political economy was no longer a viable option for them. Some

of the reasons were technical — classical political economy saw only the

production of physical goods as wealth-producing and had no account of

the economics of the service industry. Other reasons were more

historical — in international terms the classical political economists

had been fierce critics of colonialism and the war in America as

policies that taxed the wealth-producing manufacturing industry but

benefited only the then dominant landowning and aristocratic class.

Historically classical political economy had been the agitational

propaganda of a capitalist class excluded from power. Now, in the late

nineteenth century that same class had now been brought into the

governing class through political reform, and many of them now had an

interest and share in the profits of the “New Imperialism” of the late

Victorian era. Most importantly the capitalist class had never

considered that the discourse of political economy could be taken from

them and used to enable the real wealth-producing class — the working

class — to articulate its own interests and critique of power. To

address all these issues a new generation of apologists of power stepped

forward to take the political out of economics and re-make this “social

science” (1) as a technical tool for market analysis for capitalists.

So anxious was William Jevons, one of the first of these post-classical

economists, to undo the damage of the labour theory of value, that he

claimed that the price of goods and services were set by demand alone,

with no link to the amount of labour involved in their production.

Naturally this extreme position was completely unsustainable in practice

so Jevon’s theories were eclipsed by those of Alfred Marshall who

grudgingly admitted labour cost as one of cost factors involved in

determining price. Lest anybody think this position made him any less of

an enemy of socialism than Jevons, Marshall was quick to make his

political perspective clear from the outset, stating his opposition to

the “socialist programme” on the grounds that “the collective ownership

of the means of production would deaden the energies of mankind and

arrest economic progress”. It was Marshall who eventually produced the

theory of marginal utility and the supply and demand price curve diagram

that today graces the front of all conventional economics text books.

The neo-classical economists ditching of the labour theory of value was

only achieved by abandoning the central aim of political economy — that

of finding a measure of value with which to gauge the rate of growth of

the national economy and the impact of government policy on this growth.

Consequently by abandoning the measure of value to focus on the

determination of price alone, the neo-classicists threw out the baby

with the bathwater. Their resulting framework was indeed useful as a

technical tool for capitalists for calculating prices and investment

opportunities, but for overall policy their “marginalist revolution” was

itself of marginal utility.

The need for a theory that addressed “the big picture” led to the

evolution of “macroeconomics” which in turn relegated the

neo-classicists efforts to microeconomics. The problem for

macro-economists remained the same as for the original political

economists, how to get a stable measure of wealth undistorted by

monetary inflation. In the end the measure they have chosen is the

Retail Price Index (in the UK — similar indexes exist by different names

in different countries). This is an index based on a basket of gods to

reflect the consumption of an “average” worker which additions to

reflect utility and housing costs, etc. In other words a measure of the

cost of labour. The RPI is thus the re-introduction of the labour theory

of value as a base measurement of the value of money. In this and other

areas such as development economics honest commentators have had to

admit the practical need to re-introduce a measure of the value of

labour as a base unit of analysis.

The continuing appeal of the labour theory of value

It is worth taking a parenthesis to examine why the valuing of products

by the labour time necessary for their production has lasting appeal to

the extent that our everyday existence in capitalist society continually

reinforces it as a seemingly “natural” measure. Partly this is because

there is a biological basis — any living organism must ensure that the

calories it gains from its activity must at least balance the calories

it burns up in staying alive and active for that same time period or

else it will perish. For a large part of human history, until relatively

recently fro most of us, human economic activity has not moved that far

away from that biological basis. While most economic activity was in the

agricultural production of basic food subsistence and most of that work

measured in physical effort over time, care had to be taken that the

exchange of goods produced in the marginal time surplus to the

production of basic subsistence had to be exchanged for a similar amount

of time value otherwise the eventual outcome would be lack of food.

Although today we live in a world revolutionised productivity-wise by

capitalism where less than 5% of societies labour goes into basic food

production and we have been in a global food surplus for half a century,

it is no surprise that we have not yet adjusted to a post

calorifically-limited world. Yet the basis of estimating the “going

rate” of time necessary for production of a given good or service is

that the process of production is such that most people are capable of a

similar rate of production. As we will see below, that assumption

becomes less and less tenable as the division of labour increases and

production moves more and more away from basic physical effort and more

towards intellectual problem solving or creative work.

From visionaries to a movement

Although Dejacque had died penniless and isolated in the 1860s,

despairing of any real progress towards libertarian communism being

achieved for centuries, yet by the 1870s the ideas of libertarian

communism were taking root amongst some of the followers of Bakunin in

the First International. Through the French anarchist brothers Elie and

Elisee Reclus, the Swiss militants of the Jura Federation like James

Guillaume and the Italian section of the International, including Errico

Malatesta, Andrea Costa and Carlo Cafiero — a one time secretary to Marx

sent by the latter to Italy to convert the Italian International to

Marxism, he ended instead being converted to anarchism. During the

period of the struggle in the International between Marx and Bakunin

these militants preferred not to challenge Bakunin over the issue of

collectivism. Bakunin’s collectivism defended the right to the full

product of labour like Hodgskin, along with the consequent distribution

of products by hours worked — i.e. the wage — and exchange.

In the wake of the definitive split in the International and Bakunin’s

subsequent death, these restraints were lifted. The term “anarchist

communism” first appeared in print in publications of the Swiss

anarchists in 1876 and in the Summer of that year the Florence Congress

of the Italian International resolved to abandon collectivism and adopt

communism as their aim, stating: “We believe that the necessary

complement to the common ownership of the means of production is the

common ownership of the products of labour”. Through the work of the

Italian, Swiss, French and individual militants like the Russian

Kropotkin, libertarian communism became not simply an idea but the aim

and goal of European-wide revolutionary movement.

Yet that movement’s clarity of vision in relation to its goal suffered a

weakness of analysis of the progress of the class struggle and the

dynamic that could lead from capitalism to its overthrow. Consequently

the actions of the libertarian communist minority’s militants tended

towards voluntarist attempts at insurrection such as the failed

Benevento uprising by the Italians or clandestine armed action or

assassination attempts against representatives of the bosses or ruling

aristocracy. The failure of this “propaganda by the deed” era of the

movement led towards the turn to syndicalism as a way of re-engaging

with the practical class struggles of the mass of workers. However,

despite its many positive effects, this form of re-engagement with the

living process and dynamic of the class struggle brought with it

problems.

The Syndicalist Ambiguity

Syndicalism as a theory proposed a seductive confusion of means and ends

at once distinct from and yet in other ways analogous to that offered by

Marxist and statist currents of socialism. On the one hand syndicalism

opposed the use of state power to introduce post-capitalist society.

Syndicalism proposed the direct exercises of power by the democratically

federated trades unions themselves. As the productive organisations of

the working class, this held out the prospect of the direct management

of society by the producers themselves without the intermediary of the

state. But on the other hand, just as the Marxist reduction of the

question of social emancipation to the task of the Marxist party seizing

state power, so syndicalism too reduced the question of social

transformation to the question of power, albeit power to the

organisations of the workers rather than the state under “revolutionary”

dictatorship. Just as the Marxist tendencies concentration on the

question of power had led them to neglect the question of the shape of

the future relations of post-revolutionary society, so the syndicalist

focus on power, albeit in a different form, similarly led to a tendency

of at best agnosticism and at worst indifference to the question of

whether post-capitalist society should be socialist or communist.

Inevitably there was a tendency within syndicalism to consider the

question an irrelevancy and drift, by default, towards the old

Hodgskinian utopia of capitalism without capitalists.

The tendency was aggravated in Spain which, isolated from the rest of

Western European anarchism, had not followed the break with Bakuninist

collectivism and adopted the compromise position of the choice between

collectivism/socialism and communism to be left for individual

communities to decide for themselves in the post-revolutionary period.

In fact the effects, if not necessarily the cause, of this political

agnosticising tendency within syndicalism came to be recognised as a

threat by the Spanish anarchist movement to the extent that they found

it necessary to form a specifically anarchist political organisation —

the AIT — to combat reformist tendencies within the CNT.

But in the end it was the rise of fascism in Italy and Germany followed

by the defeat in Spain which ended the “classical” phase of libertarian

communism as a movement in the 1930s (2), caught in a pincer movement

between fascism and stalinism.

What is Libertarian Communism?

It is time to pause the narrative of the historical emergences, eclipses

and re-emergences of libertarian communism to examine, in the abstract,

what it is. A libertarian communist society is not a pre- but a

post-capitalist society. That is it is a society that is economically

dominated by social or cooperative production — i.e. there is an

advanced division of labour with only a small minority of labour being

engaged in basic food production and most labour is engaged in producing

goods or services that are mostly consumed by others. As a corollary

there is a high level of communication and general scientific and

technological development. What distinguished libertarian communism from

capitalism is that the delivery or transmission of goods and services to

their consumers is done on the basis to the satisfaction of their needs

and desires not linked or restricted in any way to their contribution to

the production process. That is there is no money or wages and products

are not exchanged either for money or for other products judged to be of

equal value — whether that value be measured in labour time necessary

for its production or some other hitherto undreamt of measure.

Stated baldly like that to those used to the workings and logics of

capitalist society — and that is all of us these days — it seems at

first sight an absurdity or at the very least an unworkable pipe-dream.

To explain the existence of libertarian communists then, it is necessary

to add the following proviso: Libertarian communists believe that

private property (in the means of production), class society, money and

the wage relation are all interrelated aspects of capitalist society and

the attempt to change society to abolish some of those aspects while

retaining others — e.g. abolishing class society and private property

while retaining money and the wage as socialism proposes — will only

result in an unstable and violently contradictory mess that can only end

in collapsing back into the relative stability of the capitalist dynamic

unless it is taken forward to full communism. In other words libertarian

communists believe that attempts to make a post-capitalist society by

halves, such as socialism proposes, are doomed to end up being

transitional stages not to communism but to capitalism — as in fact the

historical experience of the 20^(th) century has born out, at least as

far as the project of Marxian state socialism is concerned. The

libertarian communist critique of Leninism and all its unpalatable 57

different varieties is not that it is not libertarian, but that it is

not communist.

On that point we must emphasise that by using the term libertarian or

anarchist communism we are signalling our opposition to the abuse of the

word communism by the state socialists, not that we have chosen an

alternative to authoritarian or state socialism because these latter

phrases are contradictions in terms. The state relies on the wage

relation to exercise any authority, indeed to even exist. Without paid

enforcers the state cannot exercise power as the Serbian president

Slobodan Milosevic discovered when he stopped paying the wages of the

Serbian riot police who were supposed to be repressing the

demonstrations of other unpaid public sector workers on the streets of

Belgrade.

In this sense communism is always libertarian or anarchist as the

abolition of the wage brings about the abolition of the relation of

command which structures the organs of state power such as the police,

army and bureaucracy.

Though the failings of state socialism have been amply exposed by recent

history, we do need to re-examine the case of proposed libertarian

socialism — a society where land and the means of production have been

taken into common ownership but the products of labour are owned by

their producers and exchanged for the products of others on the basis of

equal value measured by labour time embodied in them. It is the

contention of libertarian communists that such a system would make all

producers into competitors with each other. The system of exchange

valued by labour time introduces the “productivity paradox” — the longer

you take to produce a given output the more of another’s output you can

exchange it for. Conversely the more efficient you are in producing your

output, the less you get in exchange for it. The productivity paradox is

that labour value incentivizes inefficiency and disincentivizes

efficiency. This is why capitalism necessitates that the promotion of

efficiency is specialised off as a management function over and against

the interests of the productive workforce. The roots of class conflict

in production are to be found in the productivity paradox arising

directly out of exchange by labour time value itself.

The system of competition of individual interests also produces the

negative effects of people seeing each other as potential rivals rather

than as allies and promoting their narrow sectional interests rather

than the general good. Thus we have doctors who are paid to treat

disease and unsurprisingly they have little interest in disease

prevention.

But by far the greatest evil resulting from the system of individual

competition — bellum omni contra omnes, the war of all against all — is

the outcome that our most important social product, the society we live

in, becomes an alien impersonal “other” that none of us control yet we

are all controlled by. By competing all against all to maximise our

little individual share of the social product to own, we lose the

ownership of the society we live in. Libertarian communists believe that

trading in the measly shares of the social product we own under

capitalist relations and in return gaining the ownership and control

over the direction of the whole society we make will result in a net

gain for all both materially and in terms of freedom.

Fine words indeed, but it logically follows that if the trading in of

individual ownership rights over the product of ones own labour in

return for the common ownership of a post-capitalist society were to

result in a net loss for all or most of humanity then libertarian

communists would be shown to be mistaken and those who preach the

capitalist gospel that the end of history has come and that the

capitalist world is truly the best of all possible worlds would be

proved right.

Up until recently this was seen by all sides as a question that could

not be settled this side of a revolution — without making the

experiment. However in the last few years new developments taking place

even within current capitalist society have thrown this pre-conception

into doubt.

Beyond the commune — de-centred anarchy

Before we re-engage with a historical narrative to examine these recent

developments we need to examine some other aspects of the productive

process, both as it has developed under capitalism and how it can be

expected to further develop under post-capitalist relations.

The first tendency is the increasing de-territorialisation of

production. By that we mean the increase of the number of fields of

production that are not tied to a specific place. Food production via

agriculture is territorial or tied to a specific place. The bit of land

from which you harvest must also be the same bit of land you previously

prepared and sowed. Consequently for those people and those periods of

history where agricultural subsistence was the dominant mode of

production, settled living in or by the territory of production was the

norm for the greatest number. Those settled agricultural communities

unified the spheres of production, consumption, reproduction and nearly

all social interaction within a single space. This largely

self-sufficient and potentially self-governing community is a social

form that has existed for centuries throughout nearly all human cultures

around the globe up until the last century or tow of capitalist

upheaval. As such it still had a powerful hold over the political

imaginations of anarchists no less than the rest of the different

progressive tendencies of the late nineteenth and early twentieth

centuries. The Russian “Mir” influenced Kropotkin’s vision of

libertarian communism just as the Spanish, particularly Andalusian

“pueblo” influenced the vision of the CNT’s Isaac Puentes.

But as the productivity levels and related division of labour increase a

larger and larger percentage of the working population are pushed out of

agriculture, out of the rural setting and into urban spaces. In the

beginning some of these non-agricultural settlements were themselves

based around territorially-specific sites of production — whether mines,

fishing harbours or river crossing points. This last case points us

towards an important feature — non-agricultural settlements necessarily

imply the existence of flows of goods and people, if only in bringing to

the urban spaces the food they cannot produce. In fact even prior to the

development of urban spaces, agricultural settlements required

interaction with marginal but indispensable itinerant populations to

bring them goods impossible to produce locally and be the medium of

communication of news and culture from afar. Despite the often deep

divides of incomprehension and mutual suspicion between settled and

itinerant communities and the tendency of the numerically superior

former to discount or “forget” the latter from inclusion in the notion

of “productive society”, the two bodies are both mutually interdependent

elements of the social whole despite the de-territorialised nature of

the itinerant minorities contribution.

As industrialisation proceeded, the creation of large centralised mass

workspaces with large immovable plant continued the appearance of

territorially-specific production. At this stage the workforces of large

mills or factories lived in their shadow and the workforce walked to

work. Industrial disputes were neighbourhood affairs.

However as the continuing specialisation, sub-division and proliferation

of the different strands of social production has progressed it has

become more and more evident that an increasing amount of production is

not territorially specific. That is, many workplaces can be moved more

or less arbitrarily from one place to another. [globalisation & class

struggle?] This de-territorialisation of production is particularly

pronounced for those engaged in non-material production — i.e. the

production of information and communicative work, an increasingly

significant sector of social production. Communication is a necessary

part of any social production process and as long as face-to-face

communication was unrivalled, in terms of cost and effectiveness, the

workplace had the irreplaceable role of the physical assembly point for

that communication. Recently, with advances in telecommunications we

have seen the emergence of the ultimately de-territorialised social

production process — one that no longer has any “work-place” at all

where the participants need to assemble.

One social sphere remains territorially specific for the majority

settled population however — the domestic sphere, i.e. where we live.

What has changed is that this domestic and reproductive sphere no longer

maps directly onto a productive sphere. In a given urban neighbourhood

the residents will typically be engaged in many diverse productive

roles, attending many different workplaces or no static workplace at

all. Similarly in the static workplaces the workers will be from many

different neighbourhoods. Unlike the rural commune there is no longer a

single unifying point of assembly where all matters affecting

production, consumption and reproduction can be made directly by those

directly affected by them. For people to take part in making the

decisions that they are affected by they must enter into a number of

different communicative assemblies, each with different sets of

associates. This element of de-centring finally bids goodbye to the

ideal of the “commune” as the basic social form with which to

reconstruct society. The old federalist vision of an ordered tree-like

structure of decision-making from the local to the global — albeit

governed democratically from the bottom up, rather than autocratically

from the top down — must now be replaced with a multiplicity of

interconnected but distinct networks with no dominant centre. The

commune is dead, long live the commune!

Free Software and Intellectual Property

We should now move away from the abstract back to the real-world

historical developments that we mentioned earlier that have overturned

assumptions about the possibility of making any practical tests of the

effectiveness of production free of capitalist constraints this side of

a revolution. In fact such a practical experience has already been

underway for some years, not at the instigation of any pre-meditated

anti-capitalist or revolutionary movement, but as a reaction to the

actions of capitalist businesses in the field of software development.

The rise of the free software and open source movements is a story in

itself and one that is still very much in the process of being written.

Indeed a number of books have already been turned out by media and

academic commentators struggling to explain the phenomena and

particularly to get to grips with the aspects of it that have most

perplexed and disturbed the received truths of capitalist economics. In

short the free software movement is the product of thousands of software

writers or hackers working collaboratively without pay to create whole

systems of software that are owned not by the producers but the common

property of all.

In the space of little more than 10 years an entirely voluntary and

unwaged network of producer consumers have collectively produced an

operating system — GNU/Linux — that is not only comparable to, but in

many aspects, superior to the flagship commercial product of global

capitalism’s most successful hi-tech company — Microsoft. Given the

short space of the time the free software movement has taken for this

achievement compared to the decades Microsoft has invested in its

product and the fact that the unwaged hackers have done this work in

their spare time, the case for the relative efficiency of unwaged,

property-claim free production has already made a strong opening

argument.

As you might expect the explanation for these novel results are related

to specific characteristics of the object of production, i.e. computer

software. To see what is different lets take a counter-example say a

motor car. Conceptually we can divide the production of a car into two

different production processes. The first is the production of a design

for the car the second is the production of a car from that design. In

the world of mass production such as that of car production, the

physical product — the actual car — dominates the design for that model

of car. That is the cost of manufacturing the physical parts for each

individual car is far more significant than the cost of the whole of the

designers wages. To the extent that it makes economic sense for a car

company to hire an engineer to work for two years on shaving 5 pence of

the production cost of a plastic moulding for a car sidelight (genuine

example).

In complete contrast, with computer software the cost of creating an

individual copy of a software product and distributing it to the user is

so negligible in relation to the effort to produce the original design

that we can say that the design or prototype is the product. This is

important because it means the labour cost of producing software is

basically unchanged whether the end product is distributed to 10, 1000

or 1,000,000 users. This has an important implication — it is impossible

to exchange software for product of equal labour value. Consider a

single hacker spends 30 days producing a given software utility, he then

distributes it to 30 end users for the equivalent of an average days

wage apiece. This has the appearance of exchange but consider what

happens when the hacker then distributes the same software to another 30

users for the same terms, and then another 300, then to a further

300,000?

There is a further difference between the car and the piece of software.

If a fault is found on a car and it is fixed all the other existing cars

of that model would need to be fixed individually. With a piece of

software however, any user who detects and or fixes a fault in their

copy of that software can then share that fix or improvement with the

entire community of users and developers of that software at virtually

no cost. It is this multiplier effect that helps make the collaborative

process of free software so productive. Every additional user is a

potential adder of value (in the sense of utility) to the product and

the communicative feedback between developers and users is an important

part of the productive process.

There is a second barrier to incorporating software production into a

scheme of labour valuation. That is the uncommodifiability of original

or creative labour. By commodifiability we mean the ability to reduce a

given buyable item to a level of interchangeability where a given volume

is equal to any other given volume of the same thing. Potatoes are

commodifiable, roughly speaking one five kilo bag of spuds can be

swapped for another without any appreciable change in the outcome. The

logic of much capitalist production is to reduce labour to

commodifiability where the output of a given number of workers is

comparable to that of the same number of another group of workers.

However this process breaks down when the output relies centrally on

individual original creativity. It is recognised that the productivity

of the most gifted hackers is enough orders of magnitude beyond that of

that of mediocre or averagely competent hackers that one gifted hacker

can achieve in a few weeks what a large team of merely average coders

would be unable to produce in months.

It is this possibility of excelling which forms part of the motivation

for the core productive participants of the free software movement to

participate. No less than climbing mountains or running marathons the

acheivement of doing something well is a motivation in itself,

particularly in a society where our waged-work conditions often force us

to do things in ways well below what we are capable of. There is a

saying within the free software community that “people will do the jobs

they are interested in”. But by the same token the jobs people find

interesting are often the ones that mobilise their individual strengths.

Freed from the constraints of exchange, people are free to seek out the

particularly lines of activity in which they can out-perform the

“average socially necessary labour time” to the extent that such an

estimate can even be made. Naturally if enough participants in a

collective labour process manage to do this successfully, the whole

process will be significantly more performant than any waged process.

If all the above features emerging from the relatively new field of

software production and the even more recent phenomena of the free

software movement were limited to that sphere alone then they would be

an intriguing case but little more. However many of the special features

of software — i.e. the relation between the single design or pattern and

potentially unlimited replication and distribution at little or no cost

— also apply to many other “intellectual” products such as cultural

artifacts like books, music and films and the results of scientific and

academic research now that computers and the internet have liberated

them from the material media of paper, vinyl and celluloid. Indeed the

whole area of products covered by so-called “Intellectual Property

Rights” are equally problematic to reduce to a “just” exchange value.

Further the proportion of overall economic activity involved in the

production of these non-material products is ever growing to the extent

of becoming the majority sector in the metropolitan hubs of the

capitalist world. This tendency will of course not automatically bring

in its wake radical social change, but its counter-tendencies — the

growth of exchange-free productive networks and the increasing direct

appropriation of consumer intellectual products like music, films,

software and texts through free online sharing networks — will continue

to make the struggle to defend capitalist Intellectual Property (IP)

rights a contested battleground. In the struggle to extend and defend IP

rights, both legally and practically, the champions of capitalism will

be undermining the core justificatory ideology of exchange — that of

labour value. The role of libertarian communists is in many ways

unchanged — to participate in the present dynamic of class struggles

while advocating a future beyond capitalist relations. Today however, we

have the advantage that post-capitalist exchange-free collaborative

production processes are no longer hypotheses but reality. In contrast

it is the theories of the orthodox “a-political” economist defenders of

capitalist that people will never produce socially useful goods without

the incentive of money that is shown to be an empty hypothesis — a false

god.