đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș murray-bookchin-on-spontaneity-and-organisation.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 12:32:19. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: On Spontaneity and Organisation Author: Murray Bookchin Date: 1975? Language: en Topics: spontaneity, organization, ecology, social ecology, communism Source: Original âSolidarityâ pamphlet, 49. Bookchin, Murray. On Spontaneity and Organisation. London: Solidarity, 1975.
There can be few words more misused in politics than the word
âspontaneity.â It is often used to denote something which seems to
happen without obvious cause, without apparently being the result of
previous preparation. In the sense of âan effect without a causeâ there
is probably no such thing as âspontaneityâ â either in politics or life.
Human behaviour is always influenced by previous experience. If a person
is not consciously aware of why he is acting in a particular way, this
does not at all mean that there are no causes for what he is doing. It
only means that the causes elude him.
Murray Bookchin does not use the word âspontaneityâ in this crude and
unreflecting way. It is important to stress this semantic point in this
short introduction to his essay (first published in âLiberationâ
magazine early in 1972). In Bookchinâs own words âSpontaneity is not
mere impulseâ ... It does not imply âundeliberated behaviour and
feelingâ. âSpontaneity is behaviour, feeling and thought that is free of
external constraint, of imposed restrictionâ. It is ânot an uncontrolled
effluvium of passion and actionâ. âInsofar as the individual removes the
fetters of domination that have stifled her or his self-activity, she or
he is acting, feeling and thinking spontaneouslyâ.
Bookchin here uses the word âspontaneityâ as we would use the word
âautonomyâ. Literally speaking autonomous means âwhich makes its own
lawsâ and therefore, by implication âwhich acts in its own interestsâ.
With the advocacy of spontaneity, understood in this sense, we have no
significant disagreement with Bookchin. Our own views on this matter are
outlined in greater detail in our Discussion Bulletin âSolidarity and
the Neo-Narodniksâ (10p + postage).
Full autonomy has both organisational and ideological implications.
Bookchin deals with both in some depth. He points out that âspontaneity
does not preclude organisation and structureâ, thereby nailing a very
widespread leninist distortion of the libertarian case.[1] Bookchin
stresses that spontaneity, in the sense in which he uses the term
âordinarily yields non-hierarchical forms of organisationâ.
We would go perhaps further, and stress that no collective autonomy is
meaningful which does not have organisational repercussions. Autonomous
activity and life â whether in the realm of practice or in the realm of
ideas â is impossible in hierarchically-structured organisation. As
Bookchin points out âthe tragedy of the socialist movement is that it
opposes organisation to spontaneity and tries to assimilate the social
process to political and organisational instrumentalismâ.
The main impact of Bookchinâs essay is however on the need for
ideological autonomy, for breaking all the intellectual fetters of the
past, for sweeping the cobwebs away that still clutter so much of the
thinking of the left. His greatest insight is his statement of the need
to eliminate domination in all its forms, not merely material
exploitation.
He stresses âthe widespread erosion of authority as such â in the
family, in the schools, in vocational and professional areas, in the
Church, in the Army, indeed in virtually every institution that supports
hierarchical power and every relationship that is marked by dominationâ.
He takes the whole discussion into areas largely avoided by the left,
and is not scared of challenging many of their most fundamental
assumptions. In this his own writing is a vindication of his belief in a
creative, conscious and coherent spontaneity. âConsciousnessâ, he tells
us, âhas its own history within the material world, and increasingly
gains sway over the course of material reality. Humanity is capable of
transcending the realm of blind necessity, it is capable of giving
nature and society rational direction and purposeâ.
If the mass of the population is to become the creative subject of
history â and not just an inert object compelled to do certain things
because of the conditions of its existence â this kind of message must
be taken seriously and its implications thought out. For all those who,
whatever their age, are not suffering from a hardening of the
categories, Bookchinâs views are an important contribution to an
on-going debate.
âSolidarityâ (London), December 1975.[2]
This article elaborated a work I read at the Telos Conference on
Organisation at Buffalo, New York, on 21 November 1971. Space
limitations do not make it possible for me to deal concretely with my
view that we have already developed the technological bases for a
post-scarcity society or describe in greater detail the type of
organisation that I think is appropriate to our time. For a more
comprehensive discussion of these issues, I would refer the reader to my
book Post-Scarcity Anarchism (Berkeley: Ramparts Books, 1971),
especially the essay âToward a Liberatory Technologyâ and the
âDiscussion on âListen, Marxistââ.
It is supremely ironical that the socialist movement, far from being in
the âvanguardâ of current social and cultural developments, lingers
behind them in almost every detail. This movementâs shallow
comprehension of the counterculture, its anaemic interpretation of
womenâs liberation, its indifference to ecology, and its ignorance even
of new currents that are drifting through the factories (particularly
among young workers) seem all the more grotesque when juxtaposed with
its simplistic âclass analysisâ, its proclivity for hierarchical
organisation, and its ritualistic invocation of âstrategiesâ and
âtacticsâ that were inadequate a generation ago.
Contemporary socialism has shown only the most limited awareness that
people by the millions are slowly redefining the very meaning of
freedom. They are constitutively enlarging their image of human
liberation to dimensions that would have seemed hopelessly visionary in
past eras. In ever-growing numbers they sense that society has developed
a technology that could completely abolish material scarcity and reduce
toil to a near vanishing point. Faced with the possibilities of a
classless post-scarcity society and with the meaninglessness of
hierarchical relations, they are intuitively trying to deal with the
problems of communism, not socialism.[3] They are intuitively trying to
eliminate domination in all its forms, not merely material exploitation.
Hence the widespread erosion of authority as such â in the family, in
the schools, in vocational and professional areas, in the church, in the
army, indeed, in virtually every institution that supports hierarchical
power and every nuclear relationship that is marked by domination.
Hence, too, the intensely personal nature of the rebellion that is
percolating through society, its highly subjective, existential and
cultural qualities. The rebellion affects everyday life even before it
visibly affects the broader aspects of social life and it undermines the
concrete loyalties of the individual to the system before it vitiates
the systemâs abstract political and moral verities.
To these deep-seated liberatory currents, so rich in existential
content, the socialist movement continues to oppose the constrictive
formulas of a particularistic âworking classâ interest, the archaic
notion of a âproletarian dictatorshipâ, and the sinister concept of a
centralised hierarchical party. If the socialist movement is lifeless
today, this is because it has lost all contact with life.
We are travelling the full circle of history. We are taking up again the
problems of a new organic society on a new level of history and
technological development â an organic society in which the splits
within society, between society and nature, and within the human psyche
that were created by thousands of years of hierarchical development can
be healed and transcended. Hierarchical society performed the baneful
âmiracleâ of turning human beings into mere instruments of production,
into objects on a par with tools and machines, thereby defining their
very humanity by their usufruct in a universal system of scarcity, of
domination and, under capitalism, of commodity exchange. Even earlier,
before the domination of man by man, hierarchical society brought woman
into universal subjugation to man, opening a realm of domination for its
own sake, of domination in its most reified form. Domination, carried
into the depths of personality, has turned us into the bearers of an
archaic, millennia-long legacy that fashions the language, the gestures,
indeed, the very posture we employ in everyday life. All the past
revolutions have been too âolympianâ to affects these intimate and
ostensibly mundane aspects of life, hence the ideological nature of
their professed goals of freedom and the narrowness of their liberatory
vision.
By contrast, the goal of the new development towards communism is the
achievement of a society based on self-management in which each
individual participates fully, directly, and in complete equality in the
unmediated management of the collectivity. Viewed from the aspects of
its concrete human side, such a collectivity can be nothing less than
the fulfillment of the liberated self, of the free subject divested of
all its âthingificationsâ, of the self that can concretise the
management of the collectivity as an authentic mode of self-management.
The enormous advance scored by the countercultural movement over the
socialist movement is attested precisely by a personalism that sees in
impersonal goals, even in the proprieties of language, gesture,
behaviour and dress, the perpetuation of domination in its most
insidious unconscious forms. However marred it may be by the general
unfreedom that surrounds it, the countercultural movement has thus
concretely redefined the now innocuous word ârevolutionâ in a truly
revolutionary manner, as a practice that subverts apocryphal
abstractions and theories.
To identify the claims of the emerging self with âbourgeois
individualismâ is a grotesque distortion of the most fundamental
existential goals of liberation. Capitalism does not produce
individuals; it produces atomised egoists. To distort the claims of the
emerging self for a society based on self-management and to reduce the
claims of the revolutionary subject to an economistic notion of
âfreedomâ is to seek the âcrude communismâ that the young Marx so
correctly scorned in the 1844 manuscripts. The claim of the libertarian
communists to a society based on self-management asserts the right of
each individual to acquire control over her or his everyday life, to
make each day as joyous and marvellous as possible. The abrogation of
this claim by the socialist movement in the abstract interests of
âSocietyâ, of âHistoryâ, of the âProletariatâ, and more typically of the
âPartyâ, assimilates and fosters the bourgeois antithesis between the
individual and the collectivity in the interests of bureaucratic
manipulation, the renunciation of desire, and the subservience of the
individual and the collectivity to the interests of the State.
There can be no society based on self-management without self-activity.
Indeed, revolution is self-activity in its most advanced form: direct
action carried to the point where the streets, the land, and the
factories are appropriated by the autonomous people. Until this order of
consciousness is attained, consciousness at least on the social level
remains mass consciousness, the object of manipulation by elites. If for
this reason alone, authentic revolutionaries must affirm that the most
advanced form of class consciousness is self-consciousness: the
individuation of the âmassesâ into conscious beings who can take direct,
unmediated control of society and of their own lives. If only for this
reason, too, authentic revolutionaries must affirm that the only real
âseizure of powerâ by the âmassesâ is the dissolution of power: the
power of human over human, of town over country, of state over
community, and of mind over sensuousness.
It is in the light of these demands for a society based on
self-management, achieved through self-activity and nourished by
self-consciousness, that we must examine the relationship of spontaneity
to organisation. Implicit in every claim that the âmassesâ require the
âleadershipâ of âvanguardsâ is the conviction that revolution is more a
problem of âstrategyâ and âtacticsâ than a social process;[4] that the
âmassesâ cannot create their own liberatory institutions but must rely
on a state power â a âproletarian dictatorshipâ â to organise society
and uproot counterrevolution. Every one of these notions is belied by
history, even by the particularistic revolutions that replaced the rule
of one class by another. Whether one turns to the Great French
Revolution of two centuries ago, to the uprisings of 1848, to the Paris
Commune, to the Russian revolutions of 1905 and March 1917, to the
German Revolution of 1918, to the Spanish Revolution of 1934 and 1936,
or the Hungarian Revolution of 1956, one finds a social process,
sometimes highly protracted, that culminated in the overthrow of
established institutions without the guidance of âvanguardâ parties
(indeed, where these parties existed they usually lagged behind the
events). One finds that the âmassesâ formed their own liberatory
institutions, be these the Parisian sections of 1793â1794, the clubs and
militias of 1848 and 1871, or the factory committees, workersâ councils,
popular assemblies, and action committees of later upheavals.
It would be a crude simplification of these events to claim that
counterrevolution reared its head and triumphed where it did merely
because the âmassesâ were incapable of self-co-ordination and lacked the
âleadershipâ of a well-disciplined centralised party. We come here to
one of the most vexing problems in the revolutionary process, a problem
that has never been adequately understood by the socialist movement.
That co-ordination was either absent or failed â indeed, that effective
counterrevolution was even possible â raises a more fundamental issue
than the mere problem of âtechnical administrationâ. Where advanced,
essentially premature revolutions failed, this was primarily because the
revolutions had no material basis for consolidating the general interest
of society to which the most radical elements staked out an historic
claim. Be the cry of this general interest âLiberty, Equality,
Fraternityâ or âLife, Liberty, and the Pursuit of Happinessâ, the harsh
fact remains that the technological premises did not exist for the
consolidation of this general interest in the form of a harmonised
society. That the general interest divided again during the
revolutionary process into antagonistic particular interests â that it
led from the euphoria of âreconciliationâ (as witness the great national
fetes that followed the fall of the Bastille) to the nightmare of class
war, terror, and counterrevolution â must be explained primarily by the
material limits of social development, not by technical problems of
political co-ordination.
The great bourgeois revolutions succeeded socially even where they
seemed to fail âtechnicallyâ (i.e. to lose power to the radical
âday-dreaming terroristsâ) because they were fully adequate to their
time. Neither the army nor the institutions of absolutist society could
withstand their blows. In their beginnings, at least, these revolutions
appeared as the expression of the âgeneral willâ, uniting virtually all
social classes against the aristocracies and monarchies of their day,
and even dividing the aristocracy against itself. By contrast, all
âproletarian revolutionsâ have failed because the technological premises
were inadequate for the material consolidation of a âgeneral willâ, the
only basis on which the dominated can finally eliminate domination. Thus
the October Revolution failed socially even though it seemed to succeed
âtechnicallyâ â all Leninist, Trotskyist and Stalinist myths to the
contrary notwithstanding â and the same is true for the âsocialist
revolutionsâ of Asia and Latin America. When the âproletarian
revolutionâ and its time are adequate to each other â and precisely
because they are adequate to each other â the revolution will no longer
be âproletarianâ, the work of the particularised creatures of bourgeois
society, of its work ethic, its factory discipline, its industrial
hierarchy, and its values. The revolution will be a peopleâs revolution
in the authentic sense of the word.[5]
It is not for want of organisation that the past revolutions of radical
elements ultimately failed but rather because all prior societies were
organised systems of want. In our own time, in the era of the final,
generalised revolution, the general interest of society can be tangibly
and immediately consolidated by a post-scarcity technology into material
abundance for all, even by the disappearance of toil as an underlying
feature of the human condition. With the lever of an unprecedented
material abundance, the revolution can remove the most fundamental
premises of counterrevolution â the scarcity that nourishes privilege
and the rationale for domination. No longer need any sector of society
âtrembleâ at the prospect of a communist revolution, and this should be
made evident to all who are in the least prepared to listen.[6]
In time, the framework opened by these qualitatively new possibilities
will lead to a remarkable simplification of the historic âsocial
questionâ. As Joseph Weber observed in The Great Utopia, this revolution
â the most universal and totalistic to occur â will appear as the ânext
practical stepâ, as the immediate praxis involved in social
reconstruction. And, in fact, step by step the counterculture has been
taking up, not only subjectively but also in their most concrete and
practical forms, an immense host of issues that bear directly on the
utopian future of humanity, issues that just a generation ago could be
posed (if they were posed at all) only as the most esoteric problems of
theory. To review these issues and to reflect upon the dizzying rapidity
with which they emerged in less than a decade is simply staggering,
indeed unprecedented in history. Only the principal ones need be cited:
the autonomy of the self and the right to self-realisation; the
evolution of love, sensuality, and the unfettered expression of the
body; the spontaneous expression of feeling; the de-alienation of
relations between people; the formation of communities and communes; the
free access of all to the means of life; the rejection of the plastic
commodity world and its careers; the practice of mutual aid; the
acquisition of skills and countertechnologies; a new reverence for life
and for the balance of nature; the replacement of the work ethic by
meaningful work and the claims of pleasure; indeed, a practical
redefinition of freedom that a Fourier, a Marx, or a Bakunin rarely
approximated in the realm of thought.
The point to be stressed is that we are witnessing a new Enlightenment
(more sweeping even than the half-century of enlightenment that preceded
the Great French Revolution) that is slowly challenging not only the
authority of established institutions and values but authority as such.
Percolating downward from the intelligentsia, the middle classes, and
youth generally to all strata of society, this enlightenment is slowly
undermining the patriarchal family, the school as an organised system of
repressive socialisation, the institutions of state, and the factory
hierarchy. It is eroding the work ethic, the sanctity of property, and
the fabric of guilt and renunciation that internally denies to each
individual the right to the full realisation of her or his
potentialities and pleasures. Indeed, no longer is it merely capitalism
that stands in the dock of history, but the cumulative legacy of
domination that has policed the individual from within for thousands of
years, the âarchetypesâ of domination, as it were, that compromise the
State with our unconscious lives.
The enormous difficulty that arises in understanding this Enlightenment
is its invisibility to conventional analyses. The new Enlightenment is
not simply changing consciousness, a change that is often quite
superficial in the absence of other changes. The usual changes of
consciousness that marked earlier periods of radicalisation could be
carried quite lightly, as mere theories, opinions, or a cerebral
punditry that was often comfortably discharged outside the flow of
everyday life. The significance of the new Enlightenment, however, is
that it is altering the unconscious apparatus of the individual even
before it can be articulated consciously as a social theory or a
commitment to political convictions.
Viewed from the standpoint of a typically socialist analysis â an
analysis that focuses almost exclusively on âconsciousnessâ and is
almost completely lacking in psychological insights â the new
Enlightenment seems to yield only the most meagre âpoliticalâ results.
Evidently, the counterculture has produced no âmassâ radical party and
no visible âpoliticalâ change. Viewed from the standpoint of a communist
analysis, however â an analysis that deals with the unconscious legacy
of domination â the new Enlightenment is slowly dissolving the
individualâs obedience to institutions, authorities and values that have
vitiated every struggle for freedom. These profound changes tend to
occur almost unknowingly, as for example among workers who, in the
concrete domain of everyday life, engage in sabotage, work
indifferently, practice almost systematic absenteeism, resist authority
in almost every form, use drugs, acquire various freak traits â and yet,
in the abstract domain of politics and social philosophy, acclaim the
most conventional homilies of the system. The explosive character of
revolution, its suddenness and utter unpredictability, can be explained
only as the eruption of these unconscious changes into consciousness, as
a release of the tension between unconscious desires and consciously
held views in the form of an outright confrontation with the existing
order. The erosion of the unconscious restrictions on these desires and
the full expression of the desires that lie in the individual
unconscious is a precondition for the establishment of a liberatory
society. There is a sense in which we can say that the attempt to change
consciousness is a struggle for the unconscious, both in terms of the
fetter that restrain desire and the desires that are fettered.
Today it is not a question of whether spontaneity is âgoodâ or âbadâ,
âdesirableâ or âundesirableâ. Spontaneity is integrally part of the very
dialectic of self-consciousness and self-de-alienation that removes the
subjective fetters established by the present order. To deny the
validity of spontaneity is to deny the most liberatory dialectic that is
occurring today; as such, for us it must be a given that exists in its
own right.
The term should be defined lest its content disappear in semantic
quibbling. Spontaneity is not mere impulse, certainly not in its most
advanced and truly human form, and this is the only form that is worth
discussing. Nor does spontaneity imply undeliberated behaviour and
feeling. Spontaneity is behaviour, feeling and thought that is free of
external constraint, of imposed restriction. It is self-controlled,
internally controlled, behaviour, feeling, and thought, not an
uncontrolled effluvium of passion and action. From the libertarian
communist viewpoint, spontaneity implies a capacity in the individual to
impose self-discipline and to formulate sound guidelines for social
action. Insofar as the individual removes the fetters of domination that
have stifled her or his self-activity, she or he is acting, feeling, and
thinking spontaneously. We might just as well eliminate the word âselfâ
from âself-consciousnessâ, âself-activityâ and âself-managementâ as
remove the concept of spontaneity from our comprehension of the new
Enlightenment, revolution and communism. If there is an imperative need
for a communist consciousness in the revolutionary movement today, we
can never hope to attain it without spontaneity.
Spontaneity does not preclude organisation and structure. To the
contrary, spontaneity ordinarily yields non-hierarchical forms of
organisation, forms that are truly organic, self-created, and based on
voluntarism. The only serious question that is raised in connection with
spontaneity is where it is informed or not. As I have argued elsewhere,
the spontaneity of a child in a liberatory society will not be of the
same order as the spontaneity of a youth, or that of a youth of the same
order as that of an adult; each will simply be more informed, more
knowledgeable, and more experienced than its junior.[7] Revolutionaries
may see today to promote this informative process, but if they try to
contain or destroy it by forming hierarchical movements, they will
vitiate the very process of self-realisation that will yield
self-activity and a society based on self-management.
No less serious for any revolutionary movement is the fact that only if
a revolution is spontaneous can we be reasonably certain that the
ânecessary conditionâ for revolution has matured, as it were, into the
âsufficient conditionâ. An uprising planned by an elite is almost
certain today to lead to disaster. The state power we face is too
formidable, its armamentorium is too destructive, and, if its structure
is still intact, its efficiency is too compelling to be removed by a
contest in which weaponry is the determining factor. The system must
fall, not fight; and it will fall only when its institutions have been
so hollowed out by the new Enlightenment, and its power so undermined
physically and morally, that an insurrectionary confrontation will be
more symbolic than real. Exactly when or how this âmagic momentâ, so
characteristic of revolution, will occur is unpredictable. but, for
example, when a local strike, ordinarily ignored under ânormalâ
circumstances, can ignite a revolutionary general strike, then we will
know that the conditions have ripened â and this can occur only when the
revolutionary process has been permitted to find its own level of
revolutionary confrontation.[8]
If it is true that revolution today is an act of consciousness in the
broadest sense and entails a demystification of reality that removes all
its ideological trappings, it is not enough to say that âconsciousness
follows beingâ. To deal with the development of consciousness merely as
the reflection of subjectivity of the development of material
production, to say as the older Marx does that morality, religion and
philosophy are the âideological reflexes and echoesâ of actuality and
âhave no history and no developmentâ of their own, is to place the
formation of ideology and thereby to deny this consciousness any
authentic basis for transcending the world as it is given.[9] Here,
communist consciousness itself becomes an âechoâ of actuality. The âwhyâ
in the explanation of this consciousness is reduced to the âhowâ, in
typical instrumentalist fashion; the subjective elements involved in the
transformation of consciousness become completely objectified.
Subjectivity ceases to be a domain for itself, hence the failure of
Marxism to formulate a revolutionary psychology of its own and the
inability of the Marxists to comprehend the new Enlightenment that is
transforming subjectivity in all its dimensions.
Classical western philosophy in its broad, albeit often mystified,
notion of âspiritâ, recognised that reason increasingly âsubsumesâ the
material world â or, stated in a more âmaterialisticâ sense, that matter
becomes rational and reason forms its own âcortexâ, as it were, over
natural and social history. Reason is ultimately nature and society
rendered conscious. In this sense, it is insufficient to say that
âconsciousness follows beingâ, but rather that being develops towards
consciousness; that consciousness has its own history within the
material world and increasingly gains sway over the course of material
reality. Humanity is capable of transcending the realm of blind
necessity; it is capable of giving nature and society rational direction
and purpose.
This larger interpretation of the relationship between consciousness and
being is not a remote philosophical abstraction. On the contrary, it is
eminently practical. Followed to its logical conclusion, this
interpretation requires a fundamental revision of the traditional notion
of revolutionary consciousness as class consciousness. If the
proletariat, for example, is conceived of merely as the product of its
concrete being â as the object of exploitation by the bourgeoisie and a
creature of the factory system â it is reduced in its very essence to a
category of political economy. Marx leaves us in no doubt about this
conception. As the class that is most completely dehumanised, the
proletariat transcends its dehumanised condition and comes to embody the
human totality âthrough urgent, no longer disguisable, absolutely
imperative need...â. Accordingly: âThe question is not what this or that
proletarian, or even the whole proletariat at the moment considers as
its aims. The question is what the proletariat is, and what, consequent
on that being, it will be compelled to do.â (The emphasis throughout is
Marxâs and provides a telling commentary on the de-subjectification of
the proletariat.) I will leave aside the rationale that this formula
provides for an elitist organisation. For the present, it is important
to note that Marx, following in the tradition of classical bourgeois
political economy, totally objectifies the proletariat and removes it as
a true subject. The revolt of the proletariat, even its humanisation,
ceases to be a human phenomenon; rather, it becomes a function of
inexorable economic laws and âimperative needâ. The essence of the
proletariat as proletariat is its non-humanity, its creature nature as
the product of âabsolutely imperative needâ. Its subjectivity falls
within the category of harsh necessity, explicable in terms of economic
law. The psychology of the proletariat, in effect, is political economy.
The real proletariat resists this reduction of its subjectivity to the
product of need and lives increasingly within the realm of desire, of
possibility. As such, it becomes increasingly rational in the classical,
not the instrumentalist, sense of the term. Concretely, the worker
resists the work ethic because it has become irrational in view of the
possibilities for a non-hierarchical society. The worker, in this sense,
transcends her or his creature nature and increasingly becomes a
subject, not an object; a non-proletarian, not a proletarian. Desire,
not merely need, possibility, not merely necessity, enter into her or
his self-formation and self-activity. The worker begins to shed her or
his status of workerness, her or his existence as a mere class being, as
an object of economic forces, as mere âbeingâ, and becomes increasingly
available to the new Enlightenment.
As the human essence of the proletariat begins to replace its factory
essence, the worker can now be reached as easily outside the factory as
in it. Concretely, the workerâs aspect as a woman or man, as a parent,
as an urban dweller, as a youth, as a victim of environmental decay, as
a dreamer (the list is nearly endless), comes increasingly to the
foreground. The factory walls become permeable to the counter-culture to
a degree where it begins to compete with the workerâs âproletarianâ
concerns and values.
No âworkersâ groupâ can become truly revolutionary unless it deals with
the individual workerâs human aspirations, unless it helps to
de-alienate the workerâs personal milieu and begins to transcend the
workerâs factory milieu. The working class becomes revolutionary not in
spite of itself but because of itself, literally as a result of its
awakening selfhood.[10]
Revolutionaries have the responsibility of helping others become
revolutionaries, not of âmakingâ revolutions. And this activity only
begins when the individual revolutionary undertakes to remake herself or
himself. Obviously, such a task cannot be undertaken in a personal
vacuum; it presupposes existential relations with others of a like kind
who are loving and mutually supportive. This conception of revolutionary
organisation forms the basis of the anarchist affinity group. Members of
an affinity group conceive of themselves as sisters and brothers whose
activities and structures are, in Josef Weberâs words, âtransparent to
allâ. Such groups function as catalysts in social situations, not as
elites; they seek to advance the consciousness and struggles of the
larger communities in which they function, not assume positions of
command.
Traditionally, revolutionary activity has been permeated by the motifs
of âsufferingâ, âdenialâ and âsacrificeâ, motifs that largely reflected
the guilt of the revolutionary movementâs intellectual cadres.
Ironically, to the extent that these motifs still exist, they reflect
the very anti-human aspects of the established order that the âmassesâ
seek to abolish. The revolutionary movement (if such it can be called
today) thus tends, even more than ideology, to âechoâ the prevailing
actuality â worse, to condition the âmassesâ to suffering, sacrifice and
denial at its own hands and the aftermath of the revolution. As against
this latter-day version of ârepublican virtueâ, the anarchist affinity
groups affirm not only the rational but the joyous, the sensuous and the
aesthetic side of revolution. They affirm that revolution is not only an
assault on the established order but also a festival in the streets. The
revolution is desire carried into the social terrain and universalised.
It is not without grave risks, tragedies, and pain, but these are the
risks, tragedies and pain of birth and new life, not of contrition and
death. The affinity groups affirm that only a revolutionary movement
that holds this outlook can create the so-called ârevolutionary
propagandaâ to which the new popular sensibility can respond â a
âpropagandaâ that is art in the sense of a Daumier, a John Milton, and a
John Lennon. Indeed, truth today can exist only as art and art only as
truth.[11]
The development of a revolutionary movement involves the seeding of
America with such affinity groups, with communes and collectives â in
cities, in the countryside, in schools and in factories. These groups
would be intimate, decentralised bodies that would deal with all facets
of life and experiences. Each group would be highly experimental,
innovative and oriented toward changes in life-style as well as
consciousness; each would be so constituted that it could readily
dissolve into the revolutionary institutions created by the people and
disappear as a separate social interest. Finally, each would try to
reflect as best it could the liberated forms of the future, not the
given world that is reflected by the traditional âleftâ. Each, in
effect, would constitute itself as an energy centre for transforming
society and for colonising the present by the future.
Such groups could interlink, federate and establish communication on a
regional and national level as the need arises without surrendering
their autonomy and uniqueness. They would be organic groups that emerged
out of living problems and desires, not artificial groups that are
foisted on social situations by elites. Nor would they tolerate an
organisation of cadres whose sole nexus is âprogrammatic agreementâ and
obedience to functionaries and higher bodies.
We may well ask if a âmass organisationâ can be a revolutionary
organisation in a period that is not yet ripe for a communist
revolution? The contradiction becomes self-evident once we couple the
word âmassâ with âcommunist revolutionâ.[12] To be sure, mass movements
have been built in the name of socialism and communism during
non-revolutionary periods, but they have achieved mass proportions only
by denaturing the concepts of socialism, communism and revolution.
Worse, they not only betray their professed ideals by denaturing them,
but they also become obstacles in the way of the revolution. Far from
shaping the destiny of society, they become the creatures of the very
society they profess to oppose.
The temptation to bridge the gap between the given society and the
future is inherently treacherous. Revolution is a rupture not only with
the established social order but with the psyche and mentality it
breeds. Workers, students, farmers, intellectuals, indeed all
potentially revolutionary strata literally break with themselves when
they enter into revolutionary motion, not only with the abstract
ideology of the society. And until they make this break, they are not
revolutionaries. A self-styled ârevolutionaryâ movement that attempts to
assimilate these strata with âtransitional programmesâ and the like will
acquire their support and participation for the wrong reasons. The
movement, in turn, will be shaped by the people it has vainly tried to
assimilate, not the people by the movement. Granted that the number of
people who are revolutionary today is miniscule, granted, furthermore,
that the great majority of the people today is occupied with the
problems of survival, not of life. But it is precisely this
preoccupation with the problems of survival, and the values as well as
needs that promote it, that prevents them from turning to the problems
of life â and then to revolutionary action. The rupture with the
existing order will be made only when the problems of life infiltrate
and assimilate the problems of survival â when life is understood as a
precondition for survival today â not by rejecting the problem of life
in order to take up the problems of survival, i.e. to achieve a âmassâ
organisation made up only of âmassesâ.
Revolution is a magic moment not only because it is unpredictable; it is
a magic moment because it can also precipitate into consciousness within
weeks, even days, a disloyalty that lies deeply hidden in the
unconscious. But revolution must be seen as more than just a âmomentâ;
it is a complex dialectic even within its own framework. A majoritarian
revolution does not mean that the great majority of the population must
necessarily go into revolutionary motion all at the same time.
Initially, the people in motion may be a minority of the population â a
substantial, popular, spontaneous minority, to be sure, not a small,
âwell-disciplinedâ, centralised and mobilised elite. The consent of the
majority may reveal itself simply in the fact that it will no longer
defend the established order. It may âactâ by refusing to act in support
of the ruling institutions â a âwait and seeâ attitude to determine if,
by denying the ruling class its loyalty, the ruling class is rendered
powerless. Only after the testing the situation by its passivity may it
pass into overt activity â and then with a rapidity and on a scale that
removes in an incredibly brief period institutions, relations,
attitudes, and values that have been centuries in the making.
In America any organised ârevolutionaryâ movement that functions with
distorted goals would be infinitely worse than no movement at all.
Already the âleftâ has inflicted an appalling amount of damage on the
counter-culture, the womenâs liberation movement and the student
movement. With its overblown pretentions, its dehumanising behaviour,
and its manipulatory practices, the âleftâ has contributed enormously to
the demoralisation that exists today. Indeed, it may well be that in any
future revolutionary situation the âleftâ (particularly its
authoritarian forms) will raise problems that are more formidable that
those of the bourgeoisie, that is if the revolutionary process fails to
transform the ârevolutionariesâ.
And there is much that requires transforming â not only in social views
and personal attitudes, but in the very way ârevolutionariesâ
(especially male ârevolutionariesâ) interpret experience. The
ârevolutionaryâ, no less than the âmassesâ, embodies attitudes that
reflect an inherently domineering outlook towards the external world.
The western mode of perception traditionally defines selfhood in
antagonistic terms, in a matrix of opposition between the objects and
subjects that lie outside the âIâ. The self is not merely an ego that is
distinguishable from the external âothersâ, it is an ego that seeks to
master these others and to bring them into subjugation. The
subject/object relation defines subjectively as a function of
domination, the domination of objects and the reduction of other
subjects to objects. Western selfhood, certainly in its male forms, is a
selfhood of appropriation and manipulation in its very self-definition
and definition of relationships. This self- and relational definition
may be active in some individuals, passive in others, or reveal itself
precisely in the mutual assignment of roles based on a domineering and
dominated self, but domination permeates almost universally the
prevailing mode of experiencing reality.
Virtually every strain in Western culture reinforces this mode of
experiencing â not only its bourgeois and Judeo-Christian strains but
also its Marxian one. Marxâs definition of the labour process as mode of
self-definition, a notion he borrows from Hegel, is explicitly
appropriative and latently exploitative. Man forms himself by changing
the world; he appropriates it, refashions it according to his âneedsâ,
and thereby projects, materialises and verifies himself in the objects
of his own labour. This conception of manâs self-definition forms the
point of departure for Marxâs entire theory of historical materialism.
âMen can be distinguished from animals by consciousness, by religion or
anything else you likeâ, observes Marx in a famous passage from The
German Ideology. âThey begin to distinguish themselves from animals as
soon as they begin to produce their means of subsistence ... As
individuals express their life, so they are. What they are, therefore,
coincides with their production, both with what they produce and with
how they produce. The nature of individuals thus depends on the material
conditions determining their production.â
In Hegelâs Phenomenology of the Spirit the theme of labour is taken up
within the context of the master/slave relationship. Here, the subject
becomes an object in the dual sense that another self (the slave) is
objectified and concomitantly reduced to an instrument of production.
The slaveâs labour, however, becomes the basis for an autonomous
consciousness and selfhood. Through work and labour the âconsciousness
of the slave comes to itself ...â, Hegel observes. âLabour is desire
restrained and checked, evanescence delayed and postponed; in other
words, labour shapes and fashions the thing.â The activity of âgiving
shape and formâ is the âpure self-existence of [the slaveâs]
consciousness, which now in the work it does is externalised and passes
into the condition of permanence. The consciousness that toils and
serves accordingly attains by this means the direct apprehension of that
independent being as its self.â
Hegel transforms the imprisonment of labour in the master/slave
relationship â i.e. in the framework of domination â with the dialectic
that follows this âmomentâ. Eventually, the split between the subject
and object as an antagonism is healed, although as reason fulfilled in
the wholeness of truth, in the Absolute Idea. Marx does not advance
beyond the moment of the master/slave relationship. The moment is
transfixed and deepened into the Marxian theory of class struggle â in
my view a grave shortcoming that denies consciousness the history of an
emergent dialectic [13] â and the split between subject and object is
never wholly reconciled. All interpretations of the young Marxâs
âFeuerbachian naturalismâ notwithstanding, humanity, in Marxâs view,
transcends domination ambivalently, by dominating nature. Nature is
reduced to the âslaveâ, as it were, of a harmonised society, and the
self does not annul its Promethean content.[14] Thus, the theme of
domination is still latent in Marxâs interpretation of communism; nature
is still the object of domination. So conceived, the Marxian concept of
nature â quite aside from the young Marxâs more ambivalent notions â
vitiates the reconciliation of subject and object that is to be achieved
by a harmonised society.
That âobjectsâ exist and must be âmanipulatedâ is an obvious
precondition for human survival that no society, however harmonised, can
transcend. But whether âobjectsâ exist merely as objects or whether
their âmanipulationâ remains merely manipulation â or, indeed, whether
labour, as distinguished from art and play, constitutes the primary mode
of self-definition â in quite another matter. The key issue around which
these distinctions turn is domination â an appropriative relation that
is defined by an egotistical conception of need.[15] Insofar as the
selfâs need exists exclusively for itself, without regard to the
integrity (or what Hegel might well call the âsubjectivityâ) of the
other, the other remains mere object for the self and the handling of
this object becomes mere appropriation. But insofar as the other is seen
as an end in itself and need is defined in terms of mutual support, the
self and the other enter into a complementary relationship. This
complimentary relationship reaches its most harmonised form in authentic
play.[16] Complementarity as distinguished from domination â even from
the more benign forms of contractual relationships and mutual aid
designated as âreciprocityâ â presupposed a new animism that respects
the other for its own sake and responds actively in the form of a
creative, loving and supportive symbiosis.
Dependence always exists. How it exists and why it exists, however,
remain critical towards an understanding of any distinction between
domination and complementarity. Infants will always be dependent upon
adults for satisfying their most elemental physiological needs, and
younger people will always require the assistance of older ones for
knowledge and the assurance of experience. Similarly, older generations
will be dependent upon the younger for the reproduction of society and
for the stimulation that comes from inquiry and fresh views toward
experience. In hierarchical society, dependence ordinarily yields
subjugation and the denial of the otherâs selfhood. Differences in age,
in sex, in modes of work, in levels of knowledge, in intellectual,
artistic and emotional proclivities, in physical appearance â a vast
array of diversity that could result in a nourishing constellation of
inter-relationships and interdependencies â are all reassembled
objectively in terms of command and obedience, superiority and
inferiority, rights and duties, privileges and denials. This
hierarchical organisation of appearances occurs not only in the social
world; it finds its counterpart in the way phenomena, whether social,
natural or personal, are internally experienced. The self in
hierarchical society not only lives, acts and communicates
hierarchically, it thinks and feels hierarchically by organising the
vast diversity of sense data, memory, values, passions and thoughts
along hierarchical lines. Differences between things, people and
relations do not exist as ends in themselves; they are organised
hierarchically in the mind itself and pitted against each other
antagonistically in varying degrees of dominance and obedience even when
they could be complementary to each other in the prevailing reality.
The outlook of the early organic human community, at least in its most
harmonised form, remained essentially free of hierarchical modes of
perception; indeed, it is questionable if humanity could have emerged
from animality without a system of social reciprocities that compensated
for the physical limitations of a puny, savannah-dwelling primate. To a
large extent, this early non-hierarchical outlook was mystified; not
only plants and animals, but wind and stones were seen as animate. Each
was seen, however, as the spiritualised element of a whole in which
humans participated as one among many, neither above nor below the
others. Ideally, this outlook was fundamentally egalitarian and
reflected the egalitarian nature of the community. If we are to accept
Dorothy Leeâs analysis of Wintu Indian syntax, domination in any form
was absent even from the language; thus, a Wintu mother did not âtakeâ
her infant into the shade, she âwentâ with her child into the shade. No
hierarchies were imputed to the natural world, at least not until the
human community began to become hierarchical. Thereafter, experience
itself became increasingly hierarchical, reflecting the splits that
undermined the unity of the early organic human community. The emergence
of patriarchalism, of social classes, of the towns and the ensuing
antagonism between town and countryside, of the state, and finally of
the distinctions between mental and physical labour that divided the
individual internally undermined this outlook completely.
Bourgeois society, by degrading all social ties to a commodity nexus and
by reducing all productive activity to âproduction for its own sakeâ,
carried the hierarchical outlook into an absolute antagonism with the
natural world. Although it is surely correct to say that this outlook
and the various modes of labour that produced it also produced
incredible advances in technology, the fact remains that these advances
were achieved by bringing the conflict between humanity and nature to a
point where the natural fundament for life hangs precariously in the
balance. The institutions that emerged with hierarchical society,
moreover, have now reached their historical limits. Although once the
social agencies that promoted technological advance, they have now
become the most compelling forces for ecological disequilibrium. The
patriarchal family, the class system, the city and the state are
breaking down on their own terms; worse, they are becoming the sources
of massive social disintegration and conflict. As Iâve indicated
elsewhere, the means of production have become too formidable to be used
as means of domination. It is domination itself that has to go, and with
domination the historical legacy that perpetuates the hierarchical
outlook toward experience.
The emergence of ecology as a social issue reminds us of the extent to
which we are returning again to the problems of an organic society, a
society in which the splits within society and between society and
nature are healed. It is by no means accidental that the counter-culture
turns for inspiration to Indian and Asian outlooks toward experience.
The archaic myths, philosophies, and religions of a more unified,
organic world become alive again only because the issues they faced are
alive again. The two ends of the historic development are united by the
word âcommunismâ: the first, a technologically sophisticated utopia that
could live in reference for nature and bring its consciousness to the
service of life. Moreover, the first lived in a social network of
rigidly defined reciprocities based on custom and compelling need; the
second could live in a free constellation of complementary relations
based on reason and desire. Both are separated by the enormous
development of technology, a development that opens the possibility of a
transcendence of the domain and necessity.
That the socialist movement has failed utterly to see the implications
of the communist issues that are now emerging is attested by its
attitude towards ecology: an attitude that, when it is not marked by
patronising irony, rarely rises above petty muckraking. I speak, here,
of ecology, not environmentalism. Environmentalism deals with the
serviceability of the human habitat, a passive habitat that people use,
in short, an assemblage of things called ânatural resourcesâ and âurban
resourcesâ. Taken by themselves, environmental issues require the use of
no greater wisdom than the instrumentalists modes of thought and methods
that are used by city planners, engineers, physicians, lawyers â and
socialists. Ecology, by contrast, is an artful science or scientific
art, and at its best a form of poetry that combines science and art in a
unique synthesis. [17] Above all, it is an outlook that interprets all
interdependencies (social and psychological as well as natural)
non-hierarchically. Ecology denies that nature can be interpreted from a
hierarchical viewpoint. Moreover, it affirms that diversity and
spontaneous development are ends in themselves, to be respected in their
own right. Formulated in terms of ecologyâs âecosystem approachâ, this
means that each form of life has a unique place in the balance of nature
and its removal from the ecosystem could imperil the stability of the
whole. The natural world, left largely to itself, evolves by colonising
the planet with ever more diversified life forms and increasingly
complex interrelationships between species in the form of food chains
and food webs. Ecology knows no âking of beastsâ; all life forms have
their place in a biosphere that becomes more and more diversified in the
course of biological evolution. Each ecosystem must be seen as a unique
totality of diversified life forms in its own right. Humans, too, belong
to the whole, but only as one part of the whole. They can intervene in
this totality, even try to manage it consciously, provided they do so in
its own behalf as well as societyâs; but if they try to âdominateâ it,
i.e., plunder it, they risk the possibility of undermining it and the
natural fundament for social life.
The dialectical nature of the ecological outlook, an outlook that
stresses differentiation, inner development and unity in diversity,
should be obvious to anyone who is familiar with Hegelâs writings. Even
the language of ecology and dialectical philosophy overlap to a
remarkable degree. Ironically, ecology more closely realises Marxâs
vision of science as dialectics than any other science today, including
his own cherished realm of political economy. Ecology could be said to
enjoy this unique eminence because it provides the basis, both socially
and biologically, for a devastating critique of hierarchical society as
a whole, while also providing the guidelines for a viable, harmonised
future utopia. For it is precisely ecology that validates on scientific
grounds the need for social decentralisation based on new forms of
technology and news modes of community, both tailored artistically to
the ecosystem in which they are located. In fact, it is perfectly valid
to say that the affinity-group form and even the traditional ideal of
the rounded individual could be regarded as ecological concepts.
Whatever the area to which it is applied, the ecological outlook sees
unity in diversity as a holistic dynamic totality that tends to
harmoniously integrate its diverse parts, not as an aggregate of
neutrally co-existing elements.
It is not fatuity alone that blocks the socialist movementâs
comprehension of the ecological outlook. To speak bluntly, Marxism is no
longer adequate to comprehend the communist vision that is not emerging.
The socialist movement, in turn, has acquired and exaggerated the most
limiting features of Marxâs works without understanding the rich
insights they contain. What constitutes the modus operandi of this
movement is not Marxâs vision of a humanity integrated internally and
with nature, but the particularistic notions and the ambivalences that
marred his vision and the latent instrumentalism that vitiated it.
History has played its own cunning game with us. It has turned
yesterdayâs verities into todayâs falsehood, not by generating new
refutations but by creating a new level of social possibility. We are
beginning to see that there is a realm of domination that is broader
than the realm of material exploitation. The tragedy of the socialist
movement is that, steeped in the past, it uses the methods of domination
to try to âliberateâ us from material exploitation.
We are beginning to see that the most advanced form of class
consciousness is self-consciousness. The tragedy of the socialist
movement is that it opposes class consciousness to self-consciousness
and denies the emergence of the self as âindividualismâ â a self that
could yield the most advanced form of collectivity, a collectivity based
on self-management.
We are beginning to see that spontaneity yields its own liberated forms
of social organisation. The tragedy of the socialist movement is that it
opposes organisation to spontaneity and tries to assimilate the social
process to political and organisational instrumentalism.
We are beginning to see that the general interest can now be sustained
after a revolution by a post-scarcity technology. The tragedy of the
socialist movement is that it sustains the particular interest of the
proletariat against the emerging general interest of the dominated as a
whole â of all dominated strata, sexes, ages, and ethnic groups.
We must begin to break away from the given, from the social
constellation that stands immediately before our eyes, and try to see
that we are somewhere in a process that has a long history behind it and
a long future before it. In little more than half a decade, we have seen
established verities and values disintegrate on a scale and with a
rapidity that would have seemed utterly inconceivable to the people of a
decade ago. And yet, perhaps, we are only at the beginning of a
disintegrating process whose most telling effects still lie ahead. This
is a revolutionary epoch, an immense historical tide that builds up,
often unseen, in the deepest recesses of the unconscious and whose goals
continually expand with the development itself. More than ever, we now
know a fact from lived experience that no theoretical tomes could
establish: consciousness can change rapidly, indeed, with a rapidity
that is dazzling to the beholder. In a revolutionary epoch, a year or
even a few months can yield changes in popular consciousness and mood
that would normally take decades to achieve.
And we must know what we want lest we turn to means that totally vitiate
our goals. Communism stands on the agenda of society today, not a
socialist patchwork of âstagesâ and âtransitionsâ that will simply mire
us in a world we are trying to overcome. A non-hierarchical society,
self-managed and free of domination in all its forms, stands on the
agenda of society today, not a hierarchical system draped in a red flag.
The dialectic we seek is neither a Promethean will that posits the
âotherâ antagonistically nor a passivity that reaches phenomena in
repose. Nor is it the happiness and pacification of an eternal status
quo. Life when we are prepared to accept all the forbidden experiences
that do not impede survival. Desire is the sense of human possibility
that emerges with life, and pleasure the fulfillment of this
possibility. Thus, the dialectic we seek is an unceasing but gentle
transcendence that finds its most human expression in art and play. Our
self-definition will come from the humanised âotherâ of art and play,
not the bestialised âotherâ of toil and domination.
We must always be on a quest for the new, for the potentialities that
ripen with the development of the world and the new visions that unfold
with them. An outlook that ceases to look for what is new and potential
in the name of ârealismâ has already lost contact with the present, for
the present is always conditioned by the future. True development is
cumulative, not sequential; it is growth, not succession. The new always
embodies the present and past, but it does so in new ways and more
adequately as the parts of a greater whole.
Murray Bookchin
[1] A prime example of this kind of nonsense is to be found on p.143 of
Tariq Aliâs âThe Coming British Revolutionâ (Jonathan Cape, 1972).
Apparently âSolidarityâs âbelief in spontaneously-generated political
consciousnessâ leads us to âdeny the need for any organisationâ. Both
the premise and the conclusion are false. The âargumentâ, moreover, is a
non-sequitur.
[2] Published by âSolidarityâ (London), c/o 123 Lathom Road, London E.
6.
[3] âCommunismâ has come to mean a stateless society, based on the
maxim, âFrom each according to his ability and to each according to his
needsâ. Societyâs affairs are managed directly from âbelowâ and the
means of production are communally âownedâ. Both Marxists and anarchists
(or, at least, anarcho-communists) view this form of society as a common
goal. Where they disagree is primarily on the character and role of the
organised revolutionary movement in the revolutionary process and the
intermediate âstagesâ (most Marxists see the need for a centralised
âproletarian dictatorshipâ, followed by a âsocialistâ state â a view
anarchists emphatically deny) required to achieve a communist society.
In the matter of these differences, it will be obvious that I hold to an
anarchist viewpoint.
[4] The use of military or quasi-military language â âvanguardâ,
âstrategyâ, âtacticsâ â betrays this conception fully. While denouncing
students as âpetty bourgeoisâ and âshitâ, the âprofessional
revolutionaryâ has always had a grudging admiration and respect for that
most inhuman of all hierarchical institutions, the military. Compare
this with the counter-cultureâs inherent antipathy for âsoldierly
virtuesâ and demeanour.
[5] The word âpeopleâ (le peuple of the Great French Revolution) will no
longer be the Jacobin (or, more recently, the Stalinist and Maoist)
fiction that conceals antagonistic class interests within the popular
movement. The word will reflect the general interests of a truly human
movement, a general interest that expresses the material possibilities
for achieving a classless society.
[6] The utter stupidity of the American âleftâ during the late sixties
in projecting a mindless âpolitics of polarisationâ and thereby wantonly
humiliating so many middle-class â and, yes, let it be said: bourgeois â
elements who were prepared to listen and to learn can hardly be
criticised too strongly. Insensible to the unique constellation of
possibilities that stared it in the face, the âleftâ simply fed its
guilt and insecurities about itself and followed a politics of
systematic alienation from all the authentic, radicalising forces in
American society. This insane politics, couples with a mindless mimicry
of the âthird worldâ, a dehumanising verbiage (the police as âpigsâ,
opponents as âfascistsâ), and a totally dehumanising body of values,
vitiated all its claims as a âliberation movementâ. The student strike
that followed the Kent murders revealed to the âleftâ and the students
alike that they had succeeded only too well in polarising American
society, but that they, and not the countryâs rulers, were in the
minority. It is remarkable testimony to the inner resources of the
counter-culture that the debacle of SDS led not to a sizeable
Marxist-Leninist party but to the well-earned disintegration of the
âMovementâ and a solemn retreat back to the more humanistic cultural
premises that appeared in the early sixties â humanistic premises that
the âleftâ so cruelly ravaged in the closing years of that decade.
[7] Obviously I do not believe that adults today are âmore informed,
more knowledgeable and more experiencedâ than young people in any sense
that imparts to their greater experience any revolutionary significance.
To the contrary, most adults in the existing society are mentally
cluttered with preposterous falsehoods and if they are to achieve any
real learning, they will have to undergo a considerable unlearning
process.
[8] This is a vitally important point and should be followed through
with an example. Had the famous Sud-Aviation strike in Nantes of May 13,
1968, a strike that ignited the massive general strike in France of
May-June, occurred only a week earlier, it probably would have had only
local significance and almost certainly would have been ignored by the
country at large. Coming when it did, however, after the student
uprising, the Sud-Aviation strike initiated a sweeping social movement.
Obviously the tinder for this movement had accumulated slowly and
imperceptibly. The Sud-Aviation strike did not âcreateâ this movement;
it revealed it, which is precisely the point that cannot be emphasized
too strongly. What I am saying is that a militant action, presumably by
a minority â an action unknowingly radical even to itself â had revealed
the fact that it was the action of a majority in the only way it could
reveal itself. The social material for the general strike lay at hand
and any strike, however trivial in the normal course of events (and
perhaps unavoidable), might have brought the general strike into being.
Owing to the unconscious nature of the processes involved, there is no
way of foretelling when a movement of this kind will emerge â and it
will emerge only when it is left to do so on its own. Nor is this to say
that will does not play an active role in social processes, but merely
that the will of the individual revolutionary must become a social will,
the will of the great majority in society, if it is to culminate in
revolution.
[9] The young Marx in Toward the Critique of Hegelâs Philosophy of Law
held a quite different view: âIt is not enough that thought should seeks
its actualisation; actuality must itself strive toward thoughtâ.
[10] A fact which was already clearly in evidence during the May-June
events in France at the Champs de Mars gathering of students and workers
on 12 May. Here, worker after worker stood before the microphone and
spoke of his life, his values and his dreams as a human being, not
merely of his class interests. Indeed, the extent to which broader human
life issues emerged in the May-June events has yet to be adequately
explored. It was precisely the Stalinists, on the other hand, who
appealed to workers as âproletariansâ and maliciously stressed their
âsocial differencesâ with the âbourgeois studentsâ.
[11] As the decline of fictional literature attests. Life is far more
interesting than diction, not only as social life but as personal
experience and autobiography.
[12] I would argue that we are not in a ârevolutionary periodâ or even a
âpre-revolutionary periodâ, to use the terminology of the Leninists, but
rather in a revolutionary epoch. By this term I mean a protracted period
of social disintegration, a period marked precisely by the Enlightenment
discussed in the period sections.
[13] See my âDialectical Philosophyâ, to be published by Times Change
Press in the autumn of 1972.
[14] One sees this in Marxâs restless concept of practice and especially
of material âneedâ, which expands almost indefinitely. It is also
clearly seen in the exegetical views of Marxian theorists, whose
concepts of an unending, wilful, power-asserting practice assumes almost
Dionysian proportions.
[15] And âneedâ, here, in the sense of psychic as well as material
manifestations of egotism. Indeed, domination need not be exploitive in
the material sense alone, as merely the appropriation of surplus labour.
Psychic exploitation, notably of children and women, may well have
preceded material exploitation and even established its cultural and
attitudinal framework. And unless exploitation of this kind is totally
uprooted, humanity will have made no advance in humanness.
[16] Music is the most striking example where art can exist for itself
and even combine with play for itself. The competitive sports, on the
other hand, are forms of play that are virtually degraded to
market-place relations, notably in the frenzy for scoring over rivals
and the egocentric antagonisms that the games so often engender. The
reader should note that a dialectic exists within art and play, hence my
use of the words âtrue artâ and âauthentic playâ, i.e. art and play as
ends in themselves.
[17] âArtâ in the sense that ecology demands continual improvisation.
This demand stems from the variety of its subject matter, the ecosystem:
the living community and its environment that forms the basic unit of
ecological research. No one ecosystem is entirely like another, and
ecologists are continually obliged to take the uniqueness of each
ecosystem into account in their research. Although there is a regressive
attempt to reduce ecology to little more than systems analysis, the
subject matter continually gets in the way, and it often happens that
the most pedestrian writers are obliged to use the most poetic metaphors
to deal with their material.