💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › m-korn-kropotkin-s-communism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 12:44:19. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Kropotkin’s Communism
Author: М. Korn
Date: 1931
Language: en
Topics: Pëtr Kropotkin, anarcho-communism, Communism
Source:  This translation was originally published in
Notes: Editor’s note: Korn, M. “Kropotkin’s Communism,” in *International collection

М. Korn

Kropotkin’s Communism

It was the development of the theory of anarchist communism that

Kropotkin believed to be his main contribution to the theory of

anarchism. Indeed, what had the economic ideal of the anarchist movement

been before Kropotkin published a series of his famous articles in the

Le Révolté newspaper in 1879, articles which eventually made up his book

Words of a Rebel?

At the time of the foundation of the International, socialist doctrines

were developed along two lines: state communism and Proudhonism.

Communists sought to concentrate economic power in the hands of the

state and to structure social life in a military fashion: strict

discipline, “detachments” and “labor armies,” compulsory collective

consumption in a barracks-like environment, etc. The communism of Louis

Blanc and [Étienne] Cabet was precisely that kind of “war communism”; it

may have proclaimed the principle “to each according to his needs,” but

the actual needs had to be determined from above, by means of a kind of

a “reallocation” system.[1]

A social ideal like this could not, of course, satisfy free minds, and

Proudhon put forward an arrangement of an entirely different, opposing

type. He based the economic system of the future on the notion of

equality and reciprocity: production and exchange were grounded on

cooperative principles with members of society exchanging services and

products of equal value. The privileges of capital are thus eliminated,

but private property — though exclusively property actively in use for

labor[2] — would continue, and the notion of its communalization does

not enter into this arrangement.

As long ago as in the early years of the International, both ideals

failed to satisfy the advanced socialists and, at the Congresses held in

1867 and 1868, the principle of public (in opposition to state)

ownership of land and instruments of labor was adopted. In the years

that followed, at the height of Bakunin’s activity, this idea was

further developed to constitute, under the name of collectivism, the

economic program of the federalist part of the International. The

original meaning of the word “collectivism” later suffered a number of

mutations, but at that time it meant: public (“collective”) possession

of the land and the implements of production along with the organization

of distribution within each anarchist federation community according to

the preferences of the members of that community.[3]

The members of the International defined “collectivism” as non-state

federalist communism, thus distancing themselves from the centralized

state communism professed by Babeuf, Louis Blanc, Cabet, and Marx and

his followers.[4] That’s what Bakunin meant when he said at a congress:

“I am not a communist, I am a collectivist.” When the “collectivists” of

the International proclaimed the principle: “to each the whole result of

his labor,” they did not mean that labor would be evaluated and rewarded

by someone; they meant only that it would not be exploited and all the

products of labor would be used to the benefit of the workers. How these

products would be distributed was an open question, left to the decision

of each community.

But as the development of ideas advanced, collectivism in that form

became unsatisfactory, and the thought of the members of the

International began to search for a definite answer to the open

question, an answer that would be compatible with the principle of

absence of a coercive force, of state power in society. An idea was

proposed that the only thing that could guide the distribution was

everyone’s needs, and that an exact evaluation of each worker’s labor

was an impossible thing. In 1876, the Italian Federation of the

International spoke in favor of “anarchist communism” at its congress in

Florence and, four years later, the Jura Federation, the most

influential one, arrived at the same decision (at the 1880 congress in

Chaux-de-Fonds). At this congress, the old “collectivism” that only

proclaimed communalization of the land and instruments of labor

encountered the new idea of anarchist communism defended by Kropotkin,

[Élisée] Reclus, and [Carlo] Cafiero, as the only idea compatible with a

stateless system.[5]

The new idea triumphed, and since that time communism has entered the

anarchist worldview as an inseparable part of it, at least in the eyes

of the vast majority of anarchists. The credit for developing this idea

on the basis of data drawn from both science and practical life must go

to Kropotkin. It’s owing to him that anarchism possesses this guiding

economic principle.

Kropotkin’s communism stems from two sources: on the one hand, from the

study of economic phenomena and their historical development, and, on

the other, from the social ideal of equality and freedom. His objective

scientific research and his passionate search for a social formation

into which maximum justice can be embodied consistently led him to the

same solution: anarchist communism.

Over the centuries, step by step, by the labor of countless generations,

by conquering nature, by developing productive forces, by improving

technology, humanity has accumulated enormous wealth in the fertile

fields, in the bowels of the earth, in vibrant cities. Countless

technical improvements have made it possible to facilitate and reduce

human labor; the broadest human needs can be satisfied to greater and

greater extent. And it is only because a small handful of people have

seized everything that is needed to create this wealth — land, machines,

means of communication, education, culture, etc. — these possibilities

remain possibilities without ever being translated into reality.

Our whole industry, says Kropotkin, our entire production, has embarked

on a false course: instead of serving the needs of society, it is guided

solely by the interests of profit. Hence the industrial crises,

competition, and struggle for the market with its inevitable companions

— constant wars. The monopoly of a small minority extends not only to

material goods, but also to the gains of culture and education; the

economic slavery of the vast majority makes true freedom and true

equality impossible, prevents people from developing social feelings

and, as this whole way of life is based on lies, lowers their moral

standards.

Adjusted to this abnormal situation, modern political economy — from

Adam Smith to Karl Marx — follows, in its entirety, a false path: it

begins with production (accumulation of capital, role of machines,

division of labor, etc.) and only then moves on to consumption, i.e., to

the satisfaction of human needs; whereas, if it were what it is meant to

be, i.e., the physiology of human society, it would “study the needs of

humanity, and the means of satisfying them with the least possible waste

of human energy.”[6] One must always bear in mind that “the goal of

every production is the satisfaction of needs.”[7]

Forgetting this truth leads to a situation which cannot last:

Under pain of death which has already befallen many states in antiquity,

human societies are forced to return to first principles: the means of

production being the collective work of humanity, they should be the

collective property of the race. Individual appropriation is neither

just nor serviceable. All things are for all people, since all people

have need of them, since all people have worked in the measure of their

strength to produce them, and since it is not possible to evaluate every

individual’s part in the production of the world’s wealth... Yes, all is

for all! If the man and the woman bear their fair share of work, they

have a right to their fair share of all that is produced by all, and

that share is enough to secure them well-being.[8]

In this total sum of social wealth, Kropotkin sees no way to distinguish

between the instruments of production and the commodities, a distinction

that characterizes socialist schools of the social-democratic type. How

may the former be separated from the latter, especially in a civilized

society?

We are not savages who can live in the woods, without other shelter than

the branches... For the worker, a room, properly heated and lighted, is

as much an instrument of production as the tool or the machine. It is

the place where the nerves and sinews gather strength for the work of

the morrow. The rest of the worker is the daily repairing of the

machine. The same argument applies even more obviously to food. The

so-called economists of whom we speak would hardly deny that the coal

burnt in a machine is as necessary to production as raw cotton or iron

ore. How then can food, without which the human machine is incapable of

a slightest effort, be excluded from the list of things indispensable

for production?[9]

The same is true for clothing and for everything else.

The distinction between instruments of production and commodities,

artificially established by economists, not only does not stand up to

logical criticism, but also cannot be put into practice. “In our society

everything is so closely interconnected that it is impossible to touch

one branch of the production without affecting all the others.”[10]

At the moment of transformation of capitalist order into a socialist

formation, expropriation must affect everything; half-measures will only

cause an enormous upheaval in society by disrupting its routines and

will lead to overall discontent. One cannot, for example, expropriate

the landed estates and hand them over to the peasants, while leaving the

factories in the possession of the capitalists; one cannot hand the

factories over to the workers, while leaving the trade, the banks, the

stock exchange in their present form. “It is impossible for society to

organize itself following two opposite principles: on the one hand, to

make common property of all that has been produced up to the present

day, and on the other hand, to keep strictly private property of what

will be produced by the individual with public instruments and

supplies…”[11] Kropotkin strongly condemns all labor remuneration, all

buying and selling.

It is impossible to reward everyone for his or her labor without

exploiting this labor and violating justice. All socialist systems

establishing remuneration in proportion to labor (be it in cash,

worker’s checks, or in kind) thus make an essential concession to the

spirit of capitalist society. At first glance, this seems to be a

paradox. “In fact,” writes Kropotkin in his critique of the wage labor

system,[12] “in a society like ours, in which the more that people work

the less they are remunerated, this principle, at first sight, may

appear to be a yearning for justice. But it is really only the

perpetuation of past injustice.”

“It was by virtue of this principle that wagedom began — ‘to each

according to his deeds’ — to end in the glaring inequalities and all the

abominations of present society. From the very day work was appraised in

currency, or in any other form of wage, from the very day it was agreed

upon that workers would only receive the wage they could secure for

themselves; the whole history of the State-aided Capitalist Society was

as good as written...

“Services rendered to society, be they work in the factory, or in the

fields, or intellectual services, cannot be valued in money. There can

be no exact measure of value (of what has been wrongly-termed exchange

value), nor of use value, with regard to production... We may roughly

say that the worker who during their lifetime has deprived themselves of

leisure ten hours a day has given far more to society than the one who

has only been deprived of leisure five hours a day, or who has not been

deprived at all. But we cannot take what the worker has done over two

hours and say that the yield is worth twice as much as the yield of

another individual, working only one hour, and remunerate the worker in

proportion. It would be disregarding all that is complex in industry, in

agriculture, in the whole life of present society; it would be ignoring

to what extent all individual work is the result of past and present

labor of society as a whole. It would mean believing ourselves to be

living in the Stone Age, whereas we are living in an age of steel.”[13]

Kropotkin, therefore, recognizes no real basis under the labor theory of

value, which plays, as we know, the most essential role in Marxist

economics. Similarly, he does not recognize the distinction between

simple labor and skilled labor which some socialist schools subscribe

to. On the basis of Ricardo’s and Marx’s theory of value, they try to

justify this distinction scientifically by arguing that training a

technician costs society more than training a simple worker, that the

“cost of production” of the former is greater. Kropotkin argues that the

colossal inequality existing in this respect in modern society is not

created by the “cost of production,” but by the existing monopoly on

knowledge: knowledge constitutes a kind of capital, which can be

exploited more easily because high pay for skilled labor is often simply

a matter of profit calculated by the entrepreneur. Kropotkin believes

that maintaining these distinctions in a socialist society — even if

they were to be considerably mitigated — is extremely harmful, because

it would mean “the Revolution sanctioning and recognizing as a principle

a brutal fact we submit to nowadays, but that we nevertheless find

unjust.”[14]

In general, the principle of evaluation and remuneration of labor must

be abandoned once and for all. If the social revolution does not do

this, says Kropotkin, it will put an obstacle to the further development

of humanity and maintain the unsolved problem that we have inherited

from the past. “‘The works of each!’ But human society would not exist

for more than two consecutive generations if everyone did not give

infinitely more than that for which he is paid... if workers had not

given, at least sometimes, without demanding an equivalent, if workers

did not give just to those from whom they expect no reward.”[15]

“If middle-class society is decaying, if we have got into a blind alley

from which we cannot emerge without attacking past institutions with

torch and hatchet, it is precisely because we have calculated too much;

because we have let ourselves be influenced into giving only to receive,

because we have aimed at turning society into a commercial company based

on debit and credit.”[16]

And so, Kropotkin calls for the courage of thought, for the courage of

building a new world on new foundations. And for this purpose, it is

first of all necessary to “put people’s needs above their works,” it is

necessary to “recognize, and loudly proclaim, that every one, whatever

their status in the old society, whether strong or weak, capable or

incapable, has, before everything, the right to live, and that society

is bound to share amongst all the means of existence at its

disposal.”[17]

“Let us have no limit to what the community possesses in abundance, but

equal sharing and dividing of those commodities which are scarce or apt

to run short.”[18] But what shall we be guided by when establishing

those necessary limitations? Who will have to endure them? It goes

without saying that Kropotkin cannot accept the existence of different

categories of citizens based on their value — economic or political — in

society, nor can he accept any importance in this respect of their

present occupation or past social position.

His measure is simpler and more humane; it is the only humane measure:

privileges are accorded to those who find it most difficult to endure

deprivation — the weak and the sick, the children and the old. This is

so natural, so understandable to everybody that, on this basis, it is

not difficult to come to a mutual agreement without any confrontation or

coercion.

Therefore, at the heart of the new society, there is voluntary labor and

the right of everyone to live. This immediately raises a number of

questions. Would not such a communist society be a society of hungry,

destitute people? Wouldn’t labor productivity fall in the absence of the

nudging spur of hunger? Kropotkin, on the contrary, shows by a number of

examples how much the productivity of human labor has always risen when

labor became at least comparatively free: after the abolition of feudal

rights in France in 1792, after the abolition of slavery of the Negroes

in America, and after the destruction of serfdom in Russia.

And — on a smaller scale — all of the examples of collective free labor

(in Russian, Swiss, and German villages, in worker’s cooperative

associations, among American pioneers, among the Russian Doukhobors in

Canada, in Mennonite communities, etc., etc.) — that they show such

productivity, such a surge of energy in the workers, that no enterprise

using wage labor can match.

“Wage labor is servile labor, which cannot and is not supposed to yield

all that it is capable of. It is time to put an end to this tale of

wages as the best means of obtaining productive labor. If today’s

industry yields a hundred times more than it did in the epoch of our

ancestors, we owe it to the rapid development of physics and chemistry

at the end of the last century; this happened not owing to the

capitalist system of wage labor, but in spite of it.”[19]

It is freedom that is able to raise labor productivity, while all other

measures, all pressure from above, whether in the form of disciplinary

measures, whether in the form of piecework wages, all share the opposite

effect. They are vestiges of slavery and serfdom, when Russian landlords

used to say amongst themselves that the peasants were lazy and would not

work the land if not watched.

And do we not now see in Russia a brilliant confirmation of Kropotkin’s

words: labor productivity is falling, the country is sliding into

poverty, while disciplinary measures are increasing and increasing,

turning the country into barracks and the workers into mobilized

soldiers?

Then there is another question: let us suppose that communism is able to

ensure well-being and even wealth to society, but will it not also kill

personal freedom? State communism will, answers Kropotkin, but anarchist

communism will not.

“Communism, as an economic institution, can take all forms, from total

personal freedom to the total enslavement of all.”[20] But any other

economic form is worse in this respect, because it inevitably requires

the existence of coercive power: where wage labor and private property

are preserved, some people are made dependent on others and the

privileges created must be forcefully guarded against possible

encroachments from the disadvantaged part of society. Not only is

communism not in conflict with personal freedom, but, on the contrary,

“without communism man will never attain the full development of his

personality, which is perhaps the most ardent desire of every thinking

being.”[21]

Communism, at least in relation to the necessities of life, constitutes

the solution to which modern societies are heading, and in a civilized

society, the only possible form of communism is the one proposed by

anarchists, i.e., communism without any authorities. Any other kind of

communism is impossible. We have outgrown it. Communism, in its essence,

presupposes the equality of all members of the commune and therefore

denies all power. On the other hand, no anarchical society of a certain

size is conceivable that would not begin by providing everyone with at

least a certain level of living comforts obtained jointly by all. Thus,

the concepts of communism and anarchism necessarily complement each

other.[22]

Objections are put forward against communism, among other things, on the

grounds of the failure that commonly befalls various communist societies

— religious communities or socialist colonies. Both suffer from

shortcomings that have nothing to do with communism, and it is from

these shortcomings that they perish. In the first place, Kropotkin

remarks, they are usually too small and unconnected; their members, by

force of things, live an artificial life in a too limited sphere of

interests. These communities withdraw from the life of the rest of

humanity, from its struggles, from its progress.

Besides, they always demand the total subordination of their members to

the collective: everyone’s life is controlled, they never belong to

themselves, all of their time is absorbed by the community. This is why

all at least remotely independent people, especially young people,

usually run away from such communities. “Phalansteries are repugnant to

millions of human beings.[23] It is true that even the most reserved

individual certainly feels the necessity of meeting their fellows for

the purpose of common work which becomes more attractive the more the

individual feels themselves a part of an immense whole. But it is not so

for the hours of leisure, reserved for rest and intimacy... Sometimes a

phalanstery is a necessity, but it would be hateful, were it the general

rule... As to considerations of economy, which are sometimes laid stress

on in favor of phalansteries, they are those of a petty tradesman. The

most important economy, the only reasonable one, is to make life

pleasant for all, because the person who is satisfied with their life

produces infinitely more than the person who curses their

surroundings.”[24]

These are some considerations that should now be well thought upon by

those who see the goal of socialist construction in the “socialization

of living” and expect in such a way to cure the evils created by using

similar methods imbued with military spirit.

In essence, Kropotkin notes, the objections to anarchist communism

raised by other socialist schools are not fundamental: almost all

recognize communism and anarchism as an ideal. After all, Marxists also

outline the disappearance of the state following the disappearance of

classes as a future endeavor. Anarchist communism is usually rejected on

the grounds of its allegedly utopian nature. The majority of socialists

do not see the possibility of a direct transition from capitalism to

anarchist communism and aim their practical work not at it, but at that

form of economic life which, in their opinion, will be realized during

the inevitable transitional period. Kropotkin did not seek to prove that

anarchist communism would necessarily be implemented immediately in its

perfect form, but he did put the question of the transitional period

differently.

“But we must remember that any discussion of the transitions that will

have to be made on the way to the goal will be utterly useless unless it

is based on the study of those directions, those rudimentary

transitional forms that are already emerging.”[25] And here, Kropotkin

points out that these directions lead exactly to communism. We cannot

dwell here on the numerous examples and proofs of this; we refer the

reader, therefore, to the text itself.

But, in this connection, it does not hurt to recall another expression.

We all know how often Kropotkin’s extreme optimism is mentioned — with

condescending praise by some (“idealist, wonderful man!”) and with

censure by others. Indeed, they usually say, such a social system does

not require a modern person, but a much more morally advanced one. And

they put aside any thought of this until the time when people develop in

some unknown way. Yes, of course, Kropotkin believes in people,

especially in their ability to develop and in those feelings of

sociality and solidarity inherent in their nature; but isn’t this kind

of optimism an indispensable characteristic of all people of progress,

revolutionaries and reformers? After all, the argument that people are

imperfect, that people are “immature,” that they are savage, ignorant,

etc., has always been the domain of conservatives of all kinds, of

defenders of the existing order against all attempts at liberation.

However, progressive people have always known that to raise people to be

better, more advanced, more cultured, they should first be raised to

better living conditions; that slavery can never teach you to be free;

and that a war of all against all can never engender humane

feelings.[26]

The same is true here: only the anarchist system will produce

accomplished anarchists like Kropotkin was, and like few others are

today. Therefore, it is necessary to work for it, to advance in its

direction without waiting for the quality of people to rise: people will

grow as freedom and equality in social formations expand. And, at any

rate, it is not the socialists, nor the people of the future, who can

ever be entitled to use the argument of the masses being imperfect and

unprepared.

Kropotkin’s anarchist communism is endorsed by a vast majority of

anarchists, but not by all. There are individualist anarchists, some of

whom are proponents of private property, while others have little

concern at all for future social organization, concentrating their

attention on the inner freedom of an individual in any social order;

there are also Proudhonist anarchists. But the fact that anarchist

communism is accepted by all those involved in the social struggle of

our time, chiefly in the workers’ movement, is not a coincidence nor a

question of the temporary success of one idea or another.

Only communism provides the guiding thread in solving a series of issues

of positive construction, because it constitutes the necessary condition

for making a stateless society possible. All other anarchist systems are

plagued by insoluble internal contradictions; anarchist communism alone

meets both the requirements of theoretical consistency and those that

can foster the creation of practical programs.

Author Biography

Marie Goldsmith (1871 – 1933), pseudonyms M. Korn or M. Isidine, was a

Russian anarchist and biologist who spent most of her life in France.

She was a close friend and colleague to Kropotkin and translated many of

his publications between French and Russian during their lifetime. Their

correspondences even reveal that there were plans for Goldsmith to help

him assemble a second volume of Mutual Aid. Although sadly overlooked

since her untimely passing, Goldsmith’s life and work are now the

subject of a research project meant to bring her scientific and

anarchist writing into the twenty-first century. Visit here for more

details:

mariegoldsmith.uk

.

[1] Ed: Louis Jean Joseph Charles Blanc (1811 – 1882) was a French

socialist politician and historian who was a staunch proponent of state

funded state-funded, worker-owned “social workshops”; Étienne Cabet

(1788 – 1856) was a French philosopher and utopian socialist who also

believed in workers’ cooperatives and government control of community

resources.

[2] Ed: Proudhon argued that while the means of production (land,

factories, housing, etc.) should be socialized to end wage labor, the

products of labor should be the property of the worker(s) who would

possess and control the means used to create them. Thus, possession (of

the means of life) would replace private property and the inequalities,

oppression, and exploitation it created. Such a system would be a form

of market socialism, with peasants, artisans, and worker-run

co-operatives selling the product of their labor on the market rather

than their labor to bosses and landlords.

[3] Ed: Implements can also be translated to “means.”

[4] Ed: François-Noël Babeuf (1760 – 1797) was an influential

revolutionary thinker and proto-communist theorist.

[5] Ed: Jacques Élisée Reclus (1830 – 1905) was a renowned French

geographer, writer and anarchist; Carlo Cafiero (1846 – 1892) was an

Italian anarchist, champion of Mikhail Bakunin, and one of the main

proponents of anarcho-communism.

[6] The Conquest of Bread (Bread and Freedom — Khleb i Volya), Golos

Truda (The Voice of Labor) Publishers, 172.

[7] Ibid., 173.

[8] Ibid., 27.

[9] Ibid., 58.

[10] Ibid., 57.

[11] Sovremennaya Nauka i Anarkhiya (Modern Science and Anarchism),

Golos Truda (The Voice of Labor) Publishers, 88.

[12] See the chapter “The Collectivist Wages System” in The Conquest of

Bread.

[13] The Conquest of Bread (Bread and Freedom — Khleb i Volya), Golos

Truda (The Voice of Labor) Publishers, 164–165.

[14] Ibid., 162.

[15] Ibid., 162.

[16] Ibid., 167–168.

[17] Ibid., 135.

[18] Ibid., 70.

[19] The Conquest of Bread (Bread and Freedom — Khleb i Volya), Golos

Truda (The Voice of Labor) Publishers, 146

[20] Sovremennaya Nauka i Anarkhiya (Modern Science and Anarchism), 140

[21] Ibid., 141.

[22] Ibid., 85.

[23] Ed: A phalanstery is a building containing a phalange, or group of

people living together in community, free of external regulation and

holding property in common. It was first conceptualized by the utopian

socialist Charles Fourier. Kropotkin cautions that this organizational

method becomes authoritarian in nature because the community’s needs

eventually subsume the individual’s autonomy.

[24] The Conquest of Bread (Bread and Freedom — Khleb i Volya), Golos

Truda (The Voice of Labor) Publishers, 118.

[25] Sovremennaya Nauka i Anarkhiya (Modern Science and Anarchism),

123.

[26] Ed: A reference to the political philosophy of Thomas Hobbes.

Hobbes wrote that a “war of all against all” would surely break out in

the absence of a state in his seminal work, Leviathan, a supposition

anarchists obviously rejected.