💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › grigori-petrovitch-maximov-my-social-credo.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 10:39:23. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: My Social Credo
Author: Grigori Petrovitch Maximov
Language: en
Topics: communism, syndicalist
Source: Retrieved on 19 January 2011 from http://www.anarchosyndicalism.net/newswire/display_any/193
Notes: Published by Rebel Worker Press, Sydney

Grigori Petrovitch Maximov

My Social Credo

“I believe that it behooves every honest individual to urge the toiling

masses not to let the flames of revolution be extinguished. On the

contrary, their orbit should be widened, through a stimulated alertness

and independence and the creation of free labour institutions. These

should be of a type suitable to take into the workers’ own hands, on the

overthrow of capitalism, the organisation of a free life upon the just

principles of dignified work.”

My View of Capitalism

At the base of contemporary capitalist society lies the principle of

private property, owing to which society is divided into two fundamental

classes — the capitalists and the proletariat. The former and less

numerous class possesses all the capital, the tools and-means of

production, while the latter and more numerous class is deprived of all

these and possesses only its labour-power, both physical and

intellectual. Under the pressure of need, the working class sells this

power to the capitalists at a price below its real value; the

unremunerated part of labour power finds its way, in the form of surplus

value, into the pockets of the capitalists. As a result, the latter

class is in possession of fabulous wealth, while the proletariat and

kindred social groups are afflicted by dire poverty. This contrast

stands out most boldly in countries of highly developed capitalism. This

contemporary economic order is defended by the entire might of the

state, with its morality and its religions.

Capitalist production is commodity production; that is to say, its

products are made for the market. The market is the most important

feature of the system of distributing goods under capitalism. In such a

society, everything is based on purchase and sale. The people, selling

to the capitalists their physical and intellectual energy, are a kind of

commodity — a living commodity — and the results of their activities,

both in the material field and in the domains of science, art and

morals, are also marketable goods. Hence a small group of exploiters

enjoys the greater share of the fruits of modern science and technology,

the fruits — in other words — of the progress of mankind as a whole.

Owing to the economic inequality of the two parties, the principles of

free labour and voluntary contract, inherent in the hire of workers, are

advantageous only to the capitalists, and any attempt on the part of the

proletariat to equalise the conditions of the two parties to the

agreement results in persecution by the state, which is intent on

defending the privileges of capital.

Scientific and technological progress leads to an enormous mechanisation

of production, and this process, in turn, results in the concentration

of capital and the proletarianisation of the population. The

mechanisation of production makes the capitalists increasingly

independent of manpower, and enables them to exploit the socially weaker

elements among the people — children, women and the aged. Consequently,

in the wake of mechanisation there appears growing unemployment, which

in due course makes labour even more dependent on capital, thus

enhancing the exploitation and destitution of the workers. Present-day

industrial techniques make it possible to produce in a shorter time more

than is required to cover the needs of all humanity. Yet many millions

are in no position to satisfy their most elementary needs of food,

clothing and shelter, and are unable to put to use their powers and

abilities, since unemployment, formerly a recurrent condition, has

become a permanent phenomenon.

In such a situation, the people sink steadily into the abyss of lasting

poverty owing to their lack of purchasing power. Innumerable warehouses

are filled with unsold wares, while other goods are destroyed so as to

prevent a slump in market prices. Production comes to a standstill,

unemployment increases, the destitution and political oppression of the

people reach an unprecedented intensity, and bourgeois democracy turns

into open dictatorship, characterised by an irresponsible and

high-handed rule of the police. With a view to forestalling an

inevitable economic crisis, and at the same time in the hope of

garnering large fortunes, capitalists engage in an intensified search

for foreign markets. Competition with capitalists of other lands ensues,

and in the meantime the ruling classes of the various countries

endeavour to put distant markets under their monopolistic control with

the assistance of their respective states, so that the governments

readily offer their armies and navies for the furthering of capitalist

ambitions. This is the prelude to war, and in this very way the First

World War (1914–18) originated. For the same reason we are today (1933)

witnessing the armed pillage, accompanied by mass killing, of the

peace-loving populace of China. Capitalism is thus the main source of

war; as long as it exists no end to conflict can be seen.

Chaotic production and unorganised, uncontrolled competition for markets

have compelled the capitalists to form powerful monopolistic

associations, frequently on an international scale — trusts, cartels and

syndicates. From the beginning of the twentieth century these

associations have gained colossal influence over the economic and

political life of every country with a highly developed industry and

since that time the development of capitalism has taken the course of

merging industrial and financial capital. In other words, capitalism has

entered upon a new stage of its growth, a stage called the period of

imperialism. One of the main features of this phase is the steadily

growing supremacy of financial over industrial capital. At present this

supremacy has assumed the form of a dictatorship of banks and stock

exchanges; in other words, a dictatorship of the plutocracy. Imperialism

is the final stage of capitalism’s expansion; beyond which the ultimate

process of its decline and decay will inevitably take place.

The modern phenomenon of imperialism, then, is the stage of fully mature

capitalism, wherein finance occupies all the commanding positions and we

therefore live in a time when capitalism, having attained the goal of

its development, has started on the road of degradation and

disintegration. This process of decline dates from the time just after

the First World War, and it has-assumed the form of increasingly acute

and growing economic crises, which, during recent years, have sprung up

simultaneously in the countries of the victors and the vanquished. At

the time of writing (1933–34) the crisis has attacked nearly every

country in a veritable world crisis of the capitalist system. Its

prolonged nature and its universal scope can in no way be accounted for

by the theory of periodical capitalist crises. Much rather do these

features signify the beginning of a degenerative process within the

system itself, a process of dissolution which reacts painfully on the

vast toiling masses of humanity, and is bound, in the future, to do so

in a still more drastic way.

The 1929 crash of the New York stock exchange (an event of world wide

significance) inevitably plunged into bankruptcy innumerable small and

medium-sized industrial concerns. It ruined a multitude of financial and

commercial institutions, and brought about a triumphal ascendancy of

financial capital, which has overwhelmingly subordinated to its control

the industry, commerce and agriculture of our country; it brought in its

wake vast unemployment and a catastrophic impoverishment of the broad

masses of the people.

Thus the New York stock exchange crash meant, fundamentally, the

world-wide establishment of an absolute dictatorship of financial

capital, a dictatorship of a small group of potentates who are mutually

antagonistic on account of their monetary interests. Yet, despite its

inner contradictions and notwithstanding all the assertions of the

Marxian economists, capitalism in its modern imperialistic guise has

managed to eliminate unorganised market competition and to gauge

accurately the market’s capacities. More than this, it has proved

capable of establishing — to use a Bolshevik phrase — a “planned

economy”, based on a calculation of purchasing power, as well as upon a

“nationalisation of production.” However, the inner contradictions of

capitalism could not be removed in this way. On the contrary, they have

tended to grow and to become increasingly more acute. The “planned

economy” of imperialism, with its “nationalised” production, founded on

the principle of private property whose driving force is personal

interest and the thirst for unlimited gain at the expense of the toiling

masses, is itself becoming the source of the decline of the capitalist

system, Its calculations are based not upon the real needs of the

people, but upon their purchasing power. In accordance with the

fluctuations of this purchasing power the production of goods is

expanded or curtailed. But, keeping in mind the fact that financial

dictatorship implies the ruin of numberless small and medium sized

proprietors and enterprisers, and the creation of millions of unemployed

among workers who had formerly been serving those masters who are not

destitute, one can rightly expect that a heavy curtailment of production

must naturally take place. The making of goods is cut in proportion to

the reduced purchasing power, and accordingly the army of the unemployed

increases, while at the same time the impoverishment of the masses

steadily grows.

Now, therefore, in order to make goods available to the impoverished

consumer, capitalism is forced to lower prices. Yet any price reduction,

without a concurrent decline in the business man’s rate of profit, can

only be attained by means of lowering the cost of production, or the

cost-price of the product. This, in turn, can be achieved, in the first

place, by wage cuts, i.e. a still greater impoverishment of a still

greater number of people, and secondly, by the rationalisation of

production through increased mechanisation of production processes and a

lesser dependence of the manufacturer on man-power. In consequence of

this, a rise in the number of unemployed is bound to occur once again,

with an ever greater contraction of the people’s purchasing power. Thus

ta further lowering of production results, with the recurrence of an the

consequences briefly described above. Hence the “planned economy ’ of

capitalism and its “rationalised production” process, aimed essentially

at one single target — private gain — lead logically to an increasingly

brutal dictatorship and to an intensifying concentration of financial

capital, as well as to an unnecessary curtailment of national production

and constantly rising unemployment and poverty. In short, capitalism,

which has given birth to a new social scourge, is unable to get rid of

its own evil offspring without killing itself in the process. The

logical development of this trend must unavoidably bring about the

following dilemma: either a complete disintegration of human society, or

the abolition of capitalism and the creation of a new, more progressive

social and political system. There can be no other alternative. The

modern form of social organization has run its course and is proving, in

our times, an obstacle to human advance, as well as a source of social

decay; This outworn system is therefore due to be relegated to the

museum of social evolutionary relics.

The days of capitalism are numbered. In its organism the process of

decomposition moves forward very rapidly indeed. All the cures, under

the guise of various reforms (towards which, incidentally, capitalism

puts up an obstinate resistance) can only prolong the agony, but are

useless as a means for full recovery. In the past, capitalism would have

saved itself from deadly crisis by seizing colonial markets and those of

agrarian nations. Nowadays, most of the colonies are themselves

competing in the world market with the metropolitan countries, while the

agrarian lands are proceeding in the direction of intensive

industrialisation; For the sake of their own security, but with an utter

disregard of the people’s interests, the capitalist countries keep on

erecting high tariff barriers between themselves, thus endeavouring to

escape from an inevitable fate. This, however, proves of as little avail

to the moribund system as medicine would be to a corpse.

Since political life is determined by economic forms, the degenerative

process which is turning bourgeois democracy into dictatorship is

self-explanatory. With an economic dictatorship of financial capital

there must arise a corresponding political dictatorship over the nation.

Accordingly, we are now witnessing parliaments degenerating either into

personal dictatorships (Italy, Poland, etc.) or into group dictatorships

(U.S.A., France, Germany, etc.) the government becoming an obedient and

submissive tool in the hands of banks and stock exchanges. Parliamentary

democracy, at present, is no more than a protective covering for

disguised dictatorship. And dictatorship in any shape is merely an

outward symptom of the dissolution of the old social form, an attempt on

the part of the dying capitalism to stop the forward march of progress,

which, despite all obstacles, clears for us the road of transition, an

uphill and narrow road, to the more perfect forms of organised social

existence.

My View of State Communism

The greatest attempt in all history to effect a transition into a newer

social form, the Russian Revolution of 1917–21, has made it possible

actually to undertake the construction of state communism, and this

example offers an opportunity of defining and analysing the regime of

authoritarian communism.

One of its typical features lies in production being based upon

bureaucratic relationships. In other words, all instruments and means of

production and distribution, as well as the people’s labour and the

human individual himself, are entirely vested in the state, which in its

turn is the exclusive property of a scanty class of Bureaucracy. The

rest of the people are proletarianised and forced to give their labour

power to state trusts, thus creating by their toil the might of these

trusts and providing a higher economic position for the ruling class.

The bureaucratic production relationships cover the whole of social life

and place the working class in absolute dependence on the state, i.e. on

the bureaucracy. The entire population is subdivided by the state into

occupational groups and is subjected to the control of a class of

officials under whom it is compelled to labour. Moreover, the state

creates new grounds for economic inequality through the principle of a

differentiated scale of wages in accordance with the differences in

usefulness of various occupations; it grants privileges, and regards the

human person as nothing more than a source of labour power. The state,

moreover shuffles the mass of labour power at will over the length and

breadth of the land, paying no attention to any other circumstances than

its own interests, thus forcing men and women to toil under the strict

and rigorous conditions of military discipline.

In this way, the state commune transforms the workers into soulless

parts in the huge, centralised communist machine, parts who are obliged

to be directed for their whole lives to a single purpose — the maximum

fulfilment of certain production tasks decreed by the state, and who are

condemned to a minimum field of initiative, independent action and

personal choice. Such a state of affairs postulates social inequality

while, at the same time, it reinforces the class structure of society

and the predominance of the bureaucracy.

An unavoidable result of this kind of social organization is a strong

police state, which subjugates to itself every manifestation of the

citizens’ lives. Strong by reason of its centralised power, the

communist state subjects everybody to police regimentation and, with the

help of espionage, keeps a vigilant eye upon each and all. Such a system

is bound to destroy all liberty and inevitably institutes state slavery;

one can look in vain for freedom of association, of assembly, of

knowledge and enlightenment and education, while the inviolability of

personal liberty and the privacy of the home are conspicuously absent.

The development of this system leads inevitably to an exacerbation of

its inner contradictions, and just as under private capitalism — to a

class struggle. It is, however, a more difficult struggle, and one which

is likely to be suppressed with even fiercer cruelty than under

bourgeois capitalism. The Russian experiment, judged quite independently

of its builders, has fully demonstrated the unworkableness of such a

regime.

The Russian revolution, having set out with liberty and the liquidation

of bourgeois society as its starting point, has, owing to its recourse

to the aristocratic principle of dictatorship, brought us back via

“military communism” to the point of departure, to capitalism or — more

correctly — to state capitalism.

Under the bankrupt state capitalism of Russia and the discredited

socialist democracy of Germany, and also as a consequence of the

intensified decline of capitalist society throughout the world, the

fight of the workers is growing and expanding against the existing

regime and its tendency to replace the moribund bourgeois world by a

regime of state slavery. In this respect a particular importance must be

given to the revolutionary struggle of the Spanish proletariat, an event

of the greatest historical significance.

Meanwhile, continuous technical progress, leading as it does to the

consolidation of industrial concerns and the socialization of their

production, creates the indispensable material circumstances for the

transition of capitalist economy both feasible and realistic a

successful social revolution, which is the supreme goal of the

international anarchist movement of the working classes.

What I Believe

I believe that it behooves every honest man to urge the toiling masses

not to let the flames of revolution be extinguished. On the contrary,

their orbit should be widened, through a stimulated alertness and

independence and the creation of free labour institutions. These should

be of a type suitable to take into the workers’ own hands, on the

overthrow of capitalism, the organization of a free life upon the just

principles of dignified work.

I fully agree with the slogan of the First International: “The

liberation of the workers must be the task of the workers themselves,”

and I believe in the class struggle as a powerful means to freedom. I

believe that the proletariat is capable of attaining its full liberty

only through revolutionary violence; that is, by direct action against

capitalism and the state, and therefore I am a revolutionary.

I believe that only a stateless form of society is compatible with human

progress, and that only under such a form of commonwealth will humanity

be able to attain full liberty, and therefore I am an anarchist.

I believe that anarchy as a political form of society is only feasible

in circumstances of the complete liberty of the constituent members of

the social body, as opposed to centralised rule over them. This liberty

can only be safeguarded through the principle of federalisation;

Therefore I am a Federalist, or, more precisely, a Confederalist.

I believe that for the utmost realisation and independence within a

federation, the latter must be formed of primary political

organisations. This kind of organization implies the setting up of

communes. Therefore, I am a Communalist.

But either liberty or anarchism is unthinkable unless, within the

commune, the principle of the free individual is stringently observed.

Society has been established in order to satisfy the many and diverse

needs of the human being, and these individual needs are by no means to

be scarified to the community. Personality and its interests, and first

of all its freedom, are the fundamentals of the new world of a free and

creative society of workers. Therefore I am an Individualist.

I believe, however, that it is not enough to enjoy political liberty

alone. In order to be free, in the real sense of the word, one must also

be endowed with economic freedom. This kind of freedom, I am convinced,

is unattainable without the abolition of private property and the

organization of communal production on the basis of “from each according

to his ability” and of communal consumption on the principle of “to each

according to his needs.” Therefore I am a Communist.

I believe that anarchism and communism are feasible on an international

scale only, and I do not believe in them in one country alone. Therefore

to my mind it is urgently necessary that the proletariat should be

organised in the form of international producers’ unions (or

associations). I consider that only by direct action, based upon

international proletarian solidarity, can the rule of the bourgeoisie

and the state be overcome, and that only by the international of

productive workers’ unions can the moribund capitalist world be

superseded. Therefore I am an Internationalist, for whom it is essential

to belong to a class and not to a nationality. Yet I nevertheless hold

nationality in high esteem as a form of collective manifestation of

personality.

The means by which capitalism can be overthrown and communism installed

and organised is the seizure of production by the producers’ labour

unions. Therefore I am a Syndicalist.

Men do not live in order to engage in reciprocal murder, but for the

sake of creation and enjoyment, of leading a full, abundant and happy

existence, based upon liberty, mutual respect and work by each for all

and all for each. Humanity therefore aspires undeniably to peace, which,

also, is beyond its reach as long as it lives in circumstances of

government and capitalism which lead to perpetual warfare. I deem it my

duty to share these aspirations; I am for world peace. But I know that

mankind is able to attain peace only through victorious revolutionary

class war against the bourgeoisie. This also implies the annihilation of

the capitalist regime with all its institutions, which are shameful and

offensive in the eyes of freedom-loving human beings. One among such

institutions is the army, with its compulsory service. I am therefore

for the abolition of armies and of military budgets in all countries. I

am opposed to militarism, and consequently I am an Anti-Militarist.

The lessons of history have convinced me that all religions sanctify and

justify slavery, as well as the exploitation of the weak by the strong,

and place their Gods on the side of those who represent physical might.

Religion is thus an obstacle to human progress. Besides, I have no need

for divine morality, and consider human ethics, derived from instincts

and folk customs, the best of all moral systems. Religion has outlived

its right to existence, and I fight against it as a survival of the

past. Consequently I am an Atheist.

I believe that the hour for the practical realisation of anarchism has

struck. Anarchism has ceased to be a Theory and has become a program,

and, accordingly, it has entered upon a Constructive period of its

development. I co-operate fervently in this development, and so I am a

Constructionist.

I am no maximalist in anarchism, since I hold-in view of all the

objective factors — that anarchism can hardly be fully realised at once.

On the other hand, I am no minimalist either, for I regard it as

inexpedient and unhistorical to break up the realisation of anarchism

and communism into a series of consecutive steps in imitation of the

socialists. Therefore I reject the “minimum program.” I wish to see

anarchism being brought to life today, but the degree to which anarchism

and communism would actually be made a reality, I relate directly to the

given historical moment. Therefore, within the province of anarchism, I

am a Realist.

My realistic belief in the substantiation of anarchism — now and not in

the remote and indefinite future — leads me to analyse the present

historical time as a whole, and to deduce from such analysis the

positive scope, nature and form in which anarchist communism can be

realised under the given historical circumstances. This assertion brings

me to postulate an inevitable Transition Period from capitalism to an

evolving anarchist communism. And in this way the realisation of

anarchism and communism in the given moment of history assumes, in my

view, the form of a transitional stage, which I designate a

Communalist-Syndicalist regime. The nature of that regime I define

below.

My View of the Realization of Anarchism and Communism

The future social revolution must take into account the circumstance

that the industry and agriculture inherited by it from capitalism would

not be uniform in the degrees of development of their various branches.

On the strength of this self-evident fact of insufficient maturity, it

might be impractical to communise many individual enterprises.

Furthermore, there are entire forms of production, for instance

agriculture, whose communisation might prove inadvisable.

Those types of production would be regarded as ripe for communisation in

which labour had already been socialised by capitalism, without the

socialization of possessions having yet taken place. This category would

undoubtedly include almost all branches of the manufacturing and service

industries. But those branches in which, side by side with individual

labour, there would also be found individual possession, as is the case

in many forms of extractive industry and particularly in farming, would

not be considered ripe for communication. Here the path to be followed

in the transition to communism is directly opposite to the course to be

steered in the manufacturing and service industries. In the latter, the

transition would follow this road: from collective labour through

collective possession to communism, whereas in the extractive industries

the collectivisation of possession ought to be established first. and

once this had been done, the transition towards collective labour could

begin.

Socialization of possession is a revolutionary act, involving violence

and its success depends on the use of force, whereas the socialisation

of labour is a process, which demands tor its unfolding the presence of

both favorable circumstances and correct timing. Social revolutions,

therefore, can immediately introduce the collectivisation of possessions

in the whole country but cannot effect the collectivisation of Labour.

Yet collectivisation of labour is virtually the basis of communism,

which is impossible without it.

In consequence of this indisputable fact, society on the day after the

social revolution would have to reckon with two basic economic systems

which in principle are mutually hostile: a communist and an

individualist system — as well as an intermediate and transitional

system, the co-operatives. Society would have to establish a form of

relationship with the individualist economy which would favour the

latter’s speedy and painless dissolution in communism. The system of the

transitional period would therefore be characterised by Economic

Dualism, that is to say, a coexistence of communism and individualism,

the brmer, however, taking over the commanding positions. From this

standpoint my view of society in the transitional period is as follows.

Economic Structure of Society

The System of Communist Economy. All the branches of industry where

labour has already been socialised by capitalism would be syndicalised;

that is, they would pass into the hands of labour organization, united

from below on productive industrial lines upon the principle of

Federalism, thus allowing full administrative autonomy to each link in

the organisational chain. Furthermore, syndicalised industry would be

built on the basis of Communist Industrial Relations.

All manufacturing industry would be subject to syndicalisation, with the

exception of the handicraft and domestic industries. Syndicalisation

would also apply to all service industries, including transportation,

post, telegraph, telephone, radio, public utilities, medical and public

health services, statistical, accountancy and distribution

organisations, public instruction, science, arts and the theatre; also,

to the branches of extractive industry to which capitalism has already

socialised labour, such as those connected with extraction of useful

minerals (coal, ore, metals), as well as forestry, fisheries, and the

farms where labour, through mechanisation, has already been socialised

in the course of the industrial process itself.

The organisational machinery of the communist economy is based upon

autonomous factories turned into industrial communes. In its fully

developed form this represents an economic Confederation, consisting of

the following links:

Culture.

The industrial or producers’ commune would be supplemented by the

organization of the consumers’ commune, which would be complementary to

it, since production and consumption are inseparably bound together. The

consumers’ commune, which incidentally would carry out the broader

functions of accountancy and distribution as well would be composed of

consumers’ co-operatives, whose previously existing apparatus could be

utilised for the present purpose. The structure of a consumers’ commune

would be composed of:

and distribution;

Inasmuch as the products of economic activity would be the common

property of the National Commune, all members of it would be equals in

property rights over the common products. Consumption would therefore be

based upon the principle: To each according to his needs, the full

realisation of this principle to be dependent on the given commune’s

wealth and prosperity.

It follows then that the National Commune would be composed of

Syndicalised Production, built upon the basis of Communist Relations

between the Producers.

Outside the commune, there would remain numerous elements carrying on

the methods of individual economy, to wit: handicraftsmen workers in

home industries, and a great proportion of the farmers.

Among artisans and home industry workers the principle of voluntary

co-operation must be applied; by offering full scope for

self-development, and for initiative, this would open the way for the

use of all the achievements of technical progress. These branches of

production, united on the pattern of syndicalised communal industries,

would be included in the proper unions, forming part of the National

Confederation of Labor. But their economic relations with the commune

would be regulated along the same lines as those of the individually

owned farms.

This principle of co-operation, furthermore, would apply to the

privately owned farms, that is to say, individual farms, operating on

plots of the socialised land, which plots would of course, cease to be

subject to purchase and sale and could not be transferred by

inheritance.

Just as the various forms of communal production would be under the

jurisdiction of the corresponding industrial unions. so the land, its

reclamation and redistribution and also domestic colonisation and

agronomy, etc., would be under the control of the Union of Farm

Communities, as a constituent element of the National Confederation of

Labor.

The farm economy of the transitional period would be represented by the

three following basic types: i. individual, ii. co-operative, and iii.

communist, the last being part and parcel of the National Commune. The

prevailing roles would of course be played by the individual type of

farming, in which productive relations based upon private ownership of

the product of labour would predominate.

The commune would abstain from entering into any economic relations with

the separate individual farms. In consequence, during the transitional

period, cooperative activities would assume the function of serving as

the only intermediary between the commune and the individualist farms of

the entire country. Cooperation would thus integrate, fully and on every

level, the millions of individual farms. The cooperative machinery would

take approximately the following shape:

The cooperative organs of the individual farms would enter into the

closest contact with the accounting and distributive organs of the

communes. The commune on its side would establish a Bank of Exchange and

Credit with numerous branch offices throughout the country. This would

transact all exchange and credit operations both at home and abroad.

Thus the individual farms would voluntarily pass on all their surplus

produce to their own co-operative associations, which would take upon

themselves the functions of purchase and sale. The co-operative

associations would transfer their produce to the Bank of the Commune and

its branches. They would be paid both by monetary tokens and by all the

commodities demanded by consumers. Thus, the market, speculation,

commercial capital, and commerce itself, would all be abolished.

The individualist farms, on a basis of equality with the commune, would

be able to avail themselves, free of charge, of the transport

facilities, roads, telephones, telegraph, radio, public instruction,

medical and public health services, and other public utilities of the

commune. However the commune would ask a certain annual contribution

from the individual farms, to be paid in kind. The form and amount of

this taxation would be laid down by the Convention of the National

Confederation of Labor, but its collection would be entrusted to the

Bank of the Commune and its branches. to be executed through commodity

exchange.

This, as I visualise it, would be the economic regime of the new society

on the day after the social revolution.

Political Structure of Society

In the political sphere. the Slate would be replaced by a Confederation

of Free Communes with their Councils (soviets); that is, Communalism

would be substituted tor Statism. The councils (soviets) of the Communes

together with the associations of such councils. up to and including the

Confederal Association of Councils, would not be endowed with any

prerogatives of power.

With the liberty of the individual as a starting point, the communalist

regime — through a free union of individuals into communes, of communes

into provinces and of provinces into nations offers the only right

solution of the national problem, namely, a natural national unity in

diversity, founded on liberty and equality.

As to the organization of military defence for this society, one can

think only of a General Arming of the Workers as the basis for a

People’s Militia, reinforced by all the technical and organisational

attainments of military science. The people’s militia, organised on an

industrial basis, would be subordinated to the productive associations,

and in times of peace would be engaged in productive efforts of a useful

kind.

As to peace and public security, a citizen guard’s service would be

organised for this purpose, with the help of the House Committees. The

citizens themselves would in turn fulfil the general duty of defence;

that is to say, a self-defence with no central organ from above.

The existing courts would be replaced by voluntary tribunals of

arbitration, and in cases of grave crimes, connected with manslaughter

or offences against liberty and equality, a special communal court of a

non-permanent nature would be set up, since courts as permanent

institutions would be abolished. Prisons would also be done away with.

Schools, hospitals, doctors and-above all- public welfare and liberty

might prove the safest means to get rid of criminals and crimes

altogether.

Thus, as the warp of the fabric of future anarchist society, there can

be laid down, in my opinion, the following three essential and basic

institutions:

production, to a fruitful communism of producers;

co-operation, towards a consumers. communism;

in diversity, that is, a Confederation of Peoples based upon liberty and

equality.

However, I do not imagine the future society to be cast in just this

rather simplified and schematic mould. To my mind, indeed, it is likely

to take on a far more complex configuration, wherein the main texture

would be interwoven with such an infinite variety of interlinked groups,

that it would readily respond to the most diverse demands and needs of

the free human person.