💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › chomskyeffect.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 08:49:29. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: The Chomsky effect or anarchism of the State
Author: Claude Guillon
Date: 2002, summer
Language: en
Topics: noam chomsky, post-situationism, situationist, liberalism, libertarianism, communism, the state, socialism
Source: http://archivesautonomies.org/IMG/pdf/inclassables/oiseautempete/hight/oiseautempete-n09.pdf
Notes: 12th column from this journal: http://archivesautonomies.org/IMG/pdf/inclassables/oiseautempete/hight/oiseautempete-n09.pdf

Claude Guillon

The Chomsky effect or anarchism of the State

(From: Oiseau-tempĂŞte no. 9, summer 2002, originally in French,

translated into English by Anonymous)

The beginning of 2001 saw an editorial infatuation arise for the

writings of Noam Chomsky, noticeable since 1998. Several collections

have been published (notably by the publisher Agone), as well as

interviews; a part of the anarchist press makes moderate use of a fair

deal of Chomsky texts and interviews available on the Internet. Le Monde

libertaire, then, gave him the front page of their re-entry issue, with

prelude to a longer series on him[1]. The political texts of the famous

American linguist were before that hard to find for some twenty years.

This rediscovery happens almost always in a eulogistic way. “Noam

Chomsky is the most famous of the contemporary anarchists; he is also

one of the most famous living intellectuals”, writes N. Baillargeon

(L’ordre moins le pouvoir, Agone, 2001). In the preface of De la guerre

comme politique étrangère des États-Unis (Agone, 2001) J. Bricmont with

glory characterizes Chomsky as “underappreciated political giant”. The

“authors” of an interview curiously titled Two hours of lucidity (Les

Arènes, 2001), don’t go easy either, welcoming “one of the last living

authors and thinkers truly rebel in this young millennium”, for which

one must “wait six months in advance in the beaches of free time to

meet”. No doubt that these formulas, characteristics of of a foreign

personality cult in the libertarian tradition, make laugh the

interested, whom I don’t accuse of any crime. They aim, and it is there

that they are interesting, to persuade the reader that there is an

opportunity to discover a thinking so absolutely original and yet

hitherto unappreciated or ignored. From the part of libertarian journals

and commentators (Baillargeon, etc.), it is a matter of using the

reputation of the famous international linguist to spread political

positions quantifiable as anarchist that he defends, which are then

through authority legitimized by his academic and scientific prose. One

must therefore present Chomsky as celebrity linguist doubling as great

anarchist thinker. It is on legitimacy and the consequences of him as

such an object of propaganda that I wish to write this critique.

One must first note that while the anarchist is presented to the

militant public, the analyst of foreign politics (notably military) from

the United States sees himself largely and frequently respected in the

biggest (French) national presses, without necessarily getting presented

as libertarian. Le Monde, which offers him a full page in one of their

supplements on the war (22nd of november, 2001), qualifies him as

“incarnation of radical thinking”. Le Monde diplomatique, which

publishes “Terrorism, weapon of the powerful” (December 2001), does not

speak of their engagements. It is also Chomsky himself who abstains from

alluding to it. We may them notice – reserving ourselves to a future

examination – the separation which he reveals between academic

linguistics and militant activity (justified by the fact that the latter

mustn’t appear reserved to the specialists), yet we are conflicted on

why the “anarchist” Chomsky ignores similar large tribunes, and waits

for us to ask him questions on his anarchistic tendencies, as if it were

a matter of “personal affairs”, to hit on this side of things. Thus, he

contributes to his own instrumentalization by ideological fabricators,

still ignored (in the US, even his book 9-11, for September 11, sold

itself, without big press coverage, at over a hundred thousand pieces),

similarly celebrated (in France) with a perfume of anti-Americanism.

In his pamphlet of vulgarization The order minus power, unanimously

saluted by the anarchist press, Baillargeon estimates that Chomsky has

“prolonged and renovated” the anarchist tradition. He abstains at the

same time – and for reasons! – from describing in what way this

“renovation” would constitute itself. Chomsky himself seems closer to

the truth when he precises (in 1976): “I do not really fancy myself an

anarchist. Let us say that I am but a fellow traveler.” Outside of his

identification with revolutionary anarchist trade unionism, obtained in

numerous interviews with militant journals, it is not easy – in spite of

the plethora of recent publications – to give oneself a clear idea of

what Chomsky’s anarchistic companionship signifies. I have limited my

quest to the essential question of the destruction of the State and

doing away with the capitalist system.

I indicate here, for the convenience of my intent, that I consider

“revolutionary” precisely he or she who takes part in such a rupture,

judged by a prior necessity to construct an egalitarian and libertarian

society. Symmetrically, he who is “counter-revolutionary”, is he who

would proclaim such a rupture impossible, undesirable or ultimately

works to in reality go against this prospect.

Strengthening the State

In one of the recently published texts[2], Chomsky recommends a politics

which – from the anarchist point of view – merits the characterization

of being original: the strengthening of the State.

“The anarchist ideal, in whatever form, has always contended, by

definition, towards a dismantling of State power. I share this ideal.

However, it often comes directly into conflict with my immediate

objectives, which are to defend or even reinforce certain aspects of

State authority […]. Today, in the frame of our societies, I contend

that the strategy of the sincere anarchists must be to defend certain

State institutions against the assaults they undergo, while

simultaneously opening themselves up to a bigger and more effective

popular participation. This view is not inherently contradictory either

strategically or ideally; it proceeds naturally of a practical

hierarchization of ideals and of a just as practical evaluation of means

of action.”

Chomsky returns to the subject in another text not translated into

French, so I will provide us with the essence of its contents before

critiquing a thing or two.

Interviewed on the odds of realizing an anarchist society Chomsky, using

a slogan used by agricultural workers from Brazil, answers: “They say

they have to enlarge their cage until they can break the bars.” Chomsky

asserts that, in the current US state of things, one must defend the

cage against external predators; defend power – however certainly

illegitimate – of the State against private tyranny. It is, he says, “an

evidence for all people troubled by injustice and unfreedom, for example

someone who thinks children must be nourished, but this seems difficult

to make understand many who fancy themselves libertarian or anarchist.”

“In my view”, he adds, “it is one of the irrational and self-destructive

instincts of good people who consider themselves left who, in fact,

distance themselves from the legitimate lives and aspirations of

suffering people.”

Except for the reference, more precise than in the prior text, to only

the US, it is here again the same classic defense and illustration of

the so-called realistic reformist. This time, in spite of the oratory

precautions, the actual opponents of the State are supposed to be more

foolish than anyone else preoccupied with justice and, incidentally, are

incapable of understanding their contributions to letting children die

of hunger! The “sincere anarchists” are thus invited to recognize

honestly finding themselves in a reformist impasse.

Let us immediately observe that this Statist fatalism, doubled of a

crusty and reformist moralism, is not without echo here in France. The

French libertarian La Griffe published in its summer issue of 2001 a

“State dossier” in which the first article ended with the same formula,

signed Chomsky: “the State [sic] is today the last bulwark against the

private dictatorship which, in particular, will not give us any gifts.”

Since such similar enormities can be published today in libertarian

reviews without its authors seeing in it anything but a legitimate view

as any other, it is indispensable to counter the effects of the

Chomskyan “pedagogy” by putting the record straight.

“Ideal” and “realism”

Recent history provides us with examples of struggles led partially in

the name of defending “public services” (transportation, social

security, etc.) which certainly did not deserve to be condemned with an

abstract anti-State principle. I have, for example, analyzed the

dismantling of the traditional railway system and its replacement with

the “TGV system”, predestined first and foremost to a clientele of

roaming cadres between the large European metropolises. It was quite

apparently part of the larger historical push to privatize the valuable

“services” (transportation, health, mail and telecommunications, water,

gas, electricity) and the nefarious consequences which stem from them.

It did not occur to me to – because there exists no logical connection

between the two suggestions – to deduce from this a “practical

hierarchization of the ideals”, which should inevitably lead to theorize

a support to the State institution which would apparently be desired as

destroyed.

That there can exist, in a historical given moment, different enemies,

dangerous on unequal levels, and that a revolutionary may find the

painful (and aleatory) necessity to play one adversary against the

other, one would need a foolish dogmatism to not agree. It is then not

inconceivable to press on this attachment to “public service” (on the

condition that one desecrates it) to hit the brakes on, for as much as

it is possible, the appetites of the large firms. It is wrong that this

should be seen as equivalent to a necessary denouncing, of which the

quasi-Leninist “withering of the State” – which Chomsky precisely

reincarnates – would give us the calculated formula. In other words:

strengthening the State to better erase it afterwards, we have already

been pranked by this before! Consequently, if oppositional movements

within the current tendencies of capitalism lead to restore,

temporarily, certain State prerogatives, I do not see a reason to lose

any sleep.

We will notice that Chomsky also inverts the process. For him it is the

ideal (of the dismantling of the State) which enters in conflict with

the immediate objective. Or, the immediate objective is not reinforcing

the State (or is it?), but for example to delay the privatization of

public transportation in opposition to the restriction of circulation

they necessarily bring. The partial “reinforcing” of the State is thus a

consequence and not an objective. Elsewhere, we well see that the fact

of baptizing as “ideal” the destruction of the State it comes back to

reject this objective outside of the real. Qualification is worth

disqualification.

The veritable realism, it appears to me, consists in remembering that a

State disposes of but two eventual and complimenting strategies to

answer to social movements and even more a revolutionary agitation:

repression and/or reform/recuperation. A revolutionary movement,

beholden by a desire (conscious or not) to rupture with the system in

place cannot – by definition – obtain the approval of a State. On the

flip side, it can constrain it to play reform, retreat and demagoguery.

The inconvenience of reformism as strategy (increasing “popular

participation” of the democratic State, as per Chomsky) is that it never

reforms anything at all. This is for the excellent reason that the

auto-adaptive State arranges for itself reforms at least as well as

certain populae assemblies. The State defuses them, the phagocyte,

reduces them to nothing. The State as such does not exist, outside of

struggle, knowing that the guarantee of “progressive” reform will not be

emptied of its content, but we must realize this evidence, paradoxical

only in appearance, that it is indeed revolutionary action that is the

way of reforming society. Many institutions and social apparatuses are

truly the result of insurrectionary workers’ struggles. The fact that

they have been effectuated by either politician or capitalist can but

lead to see the welcoming of a strengthened “State”, conceived as

abstract entity or as a type of inert matter, a dyke for example, which

we would have to consolidate to protect ourselves from floods. The State

institutionalizes in a historical moment the matters of existing classes

in a society. Let us remind ourselves of the definition (in

constitutional rights) of the modern State which yields the monopoly on

violence. An anti-Leninist like Chomsky knows otherwise very well that

there can exist no “worker’s State”; speaking very well that the State

is by nature a bourgeois arm.

Critiqued in the USA

The positions defended by Chomsky and his Canadian admirers do not

reflect, without fault, the general viewpoint of militant libertarians

or anarchist trade unionists in the USA. They are very notably critiqued

in the trimonthly Anarcho-Syndicalist Review, to which he had accorded

an interview. The metaphor of the aggrandizing of the cage, which

Chomsky judges as particularly enlightening[3], sets off the ire of

James Herrod: “The predators are not outside of the cage; the cage, it’s

them and their practices. The cage itself is mortal. And when we realize

that the cage is of world-systemic proportions, and that there is no

“exterior” to which we may escape, then we can see that the only way to

not get culled, brutalized or oppressed, is to destroy the cage itself.”

If the ensemble of the contributors attribute to Chomsky the merit of

having analyzed the foreign policy of the USA[4], gives visibility to

the American anarchist trade unionist movement, furnishes a critique of

the media which seems novel outside of the Atlantic, three of which (out

of four[5]) absolutely notice and scorn his reformism. “It is possible

that Chomsky does this, as purported trade unionist [he is wearer of the

badge of supporter of the Industrial Workers of the World (IWW),

revolutionary trade unionist organization], and to defend the benefits

of liberal democracy, but that is neither anarchist trade unionist or

anarchist”, writes Graham Purchase. “It would be an error for us”, adds

James Herrod, “to turn ourselves towards Chomsky to ask him about his

opinion on subjects that he has not truly studied, because his

priorities were elsewhere, notably that which touches upon anarchist

theory, the revolutionary strategy, conceptions of a free life, etc.”

In France: at the service of what strategy?

Why forget today the texts of Chomsky on anarchism? Let us widen the

simplistic hypothesis of a French-Quebec co-editorial, financially

supported – including in France – by Quebec cultural institutions[6],

even if the originality of the editorial mode merits to be signaled. Is

it more a matter of publishing without proper judgment a theoretical

body – by its volume –, produced by a reputed scientific, and bringing a

real caution to an “anarchism” of which the precise content would bring

little? This second hypothesis is informed by the simultaneous

publication of N. Baillargeon’s texts, which takes in detail the

Chomskyan distinction between objectives (at very long terms) and

immediate goals, the latter being “determined while taking into account

possibilities enabled by circumstances”[7], which would serve to justify

a compromise of – and the word is of Baillargeon – “certain cyclical,

provisional and measuring matters with the State”. Baillargeon also

takes over from Chomsky his tear jerking arguments (little starving

children) and his calls for “intellectual honesty”: “This means then, if

we don’t play word games, to bring ourselves to defend certain aspects

[sic] of the State.” He advances even, achieving this way the Chomskyan

inversion of the historical perspective, that the obtaining of reforms

“is without a doubt the necessary condition” for the maintaining of an

anarchist ideal. Reformism is then thus not a lesser evil, but the

immediate way of laying the foundations upon which will be built an

apparatus allowing the obtaining of revolutionary aims. We doubt this:

neither the nature of this apparatus nor its mode of propulsion are

specified or even indicated.

This “libertarian” rehabilitation of reformism finds its echo in the

French or French-speaking anarchist milieus, as it does in other walks

like those of Attac, already critiqued in these columns, which does

certainly refer to the “libertarian ideal” but resorts to the

phraseological and the imaginary utopia of the proletarian world (cf.

Oiseau-tempĂŞte no. 8). The reformist-libertarian fashion expresses

itself equally in the echoes coming from the theses of the

“municipalists”, taken from Bookchin, in the attempt to create an

academic-libetarian caucus, within which participate the wise seminars

of the ACL (Lyon) editions and in certain measures the editorial

RĂ©fractions. That this or that initiative be accompanied by excellent

comrades is here not taken into account. At a time where libertarian

ideals arouse a certain renewed interest in the editorial or even the

militant, this fact is given testament through the creation of anarchist

libraries (in Rouen, Besançon, etc.) and numerous publications animate

themselves to present as compatible an anarchist tradition with an

original reformism, given as only possible ersatz the toppling of the

world.

As an American critic of Chomsky reminds us, each one has well the

privilege to take a position which is as such – to speak strictly – of

counter-revolutionary character. It must be deconstructed and critiqued

– with disciplined language –, and this must be done with as little

complacency as is found draped in the folds of the black flag which is

given plume and and pedigree to a flattering anarchism of opinion, which

has become academic discipline, actor of democratic plurality and

museological curiosity.

Within the rupture with the capitalist system, necessary path towards

towards the construction of a communistic and libertarian society,

dwells a point of fracture that is essential between those who accept

this world – liberal-libertarian cynics or citizen supplmenents – and

those who want to invent another world. On the most immediate level, we

would like that all honest libertarians who solicit Chomsky, publish

Chomsky and sell Chomsky in piles take from that the consequences and

tell us if, after considering it, they are rallying themselves behind

the strategy of compromise, the anarchism of the State.

Claude Guillon

[1] “Le capitalisme en ordre de guerre” (20th to 26th of September; text

taken from the Internet; found in the fourth cover of the review Les

temps maudits (theoretical review of the CNT), October 2001); “À propos

de la globalisation” (27th of September to the 3rd of October);

interview taken from the Internet (15th to the 21st of November 2001).

[2] Reponsabilité des intellectuels, Agone, 1998, p. 137.

[3] Outside of the cited text, Chomsky uses this metaphor in his

interviews with D. Barsamian, The Common Good, Odonian Press, 1998.

[4] In the analusys of geopolitics, the domain where his competences are

least subject of caution, Chomsky adopts the same democratic and

reformist twist. The new military humanism. Lessons from Kossovo (Page

deux editions, Laussane, 2000) makes a call to meditate on the merits of

iinternational human rights from which the principal advance would be,

according to the author Chomsky appreciatively cites, “the outlawing of

war and the prohibition of resorting to violence”. What the prefacing

author qualifies as “a reasoning of quasi-mathematical rigor” outlines

here a legalistic silliness.

[5] Only Mike Long delivers himself to a lengthy advocacy for pragmatism

which leads him to, for example, a sympathetic evaluation of the Castro

regime.

[6] It is the case for Instinct de liberté and De l’espoir en l’avenier

(Chomsky) and for Les Chiens ont soif (Baillargeon; cf. note suivante)

[7] Les chiens ont soif. Critiques et propositions libertaires, Agone,

Comeau and Nadeau, 2001. Released in Quebec. Published within the

competition of the Conseil des Arts du Canada, of the program of income

tax for the edition of the Quebec government and with the SODEC.