💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › crimethinc-rojava.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 08:46:31. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Rojava
Author: CrimethInc.
Date: May 19, 2016
Language: en
Topics: Rojava, Direct Democracy, communes
Source: https://crimethinc.com/2016/05/19/rojava-democracy-and-commune

CrimethInc.

Rojava

Democracy and Commune; This and That

Democracy: “a system of government in which all the people of a state or

polity… are involved in making decisions about its affairs, typically by

voting to elect representatives to a parliament or similar assembly,”

(a:) “government by the people; especially: rule of the majority” (b:)

“a government in which the supreme power is vested in the people and

exercised by them directly or indirectly through a system of

representation usually involving periodically held free elections.”

—Oxford English Dictionary

I hate democracy. And I hate organizations, especially communes. Yet, I

favor the organization of democratic communes.

This

Democracy is always about mediation. Whether it separates the subject

from decision-making, separates the subject from herself, or functions

as an excuse for graft and fraud. Democracy stands in the way of the

individual, blocks unmediated communication by imposing the requirement

of structure—an outcome, a decision. And when a decision is reached, it

is usually arrived at by the most banal and ruthless method ever

devised: the vote—the tyranny of the majority.

Anarchism has had a mixed history of criticism regarding democracy.

Étienne de La Boétie in his Discours lays out a first line of inquiry by

wondering why it is that people allow themselves to be governed at

all—and as he explores the problem, he points out that it seems not to

matter whether a tyrant is chosen by force of arms, by inheritance, or

by the vote. “For although the means of coming into power differ, still

the method of ruling is practically the same; those who are elected act

as if they were breaking in bullocks; those who are conquerors make the

people their prey; those who are heirs plan to treat them as if they

were their natural slaves.” [1] And it might be added that the subject

population submits to such abuse without question and little

contestation. La Boétie’s treatise is truly prescient; written in

(roughly) 1553—a full 250 years before the emergence of the modern

nation-state—it contemplates exactly the type of unbridled war,

oppression, and terror that democratically elected governments were to

unleash on subject populations, and each other.

Power cannot exist in stasis; it functions as a result of flows between

and among institutions and individuals. The monarchs of Europe learned

this lesson the hard way during the upheavals of 1848 as they watched

their respective regimes disintegrate one after the other. With

democracy came the calculation of exchange—one iota of power given to a

citizen via the vote—concentrating a vast quantity of power in

legislature, executive, and judiciary. It’s unsurprising that political

systems began to apply equations of power and exchange at the same time

that in the economic realm Capital was introducing similar equations in

order to usurp labor-time in trade for survival. Further, such an

exchange ties the population all that much closer to the rulers.

Vaneigem illustrates the mechanism thus: “Slaves are not willing slaves

for long if they are not compensated for their submission by a shred of

power: all subjection entails the right to a measure of power, and there

is no such thing as power that does not embody a degree of submission.”

[2]

It was Proudhon who had the most varied interaction with democracy, both

theoretically and practically. His career included writing and

publishing tomes of critical analysis denouncing democracy, running for

elected office, serving in the National Assembly during the 1848

Revolution, and finally returning to his original rejection of voting

and representation. He alternately urged his readers to abstain from

voting, then to vote, then to abstain from voting (again), and finally

to cast blank ballots to protest voting.

Proudhon unleashed a number of critiques on democracy. The critical

prisms he used vary from the purely psychological to the empirical, and

the targets of his barbs span the entire menagerie of democratic

platitudes from sovereignty to the myth of “The People” to the

realpolitik of how legislatures operate. Of interest is his critical

analysis of the democratic decision-making process itself. He

scrutinizes the mechanism of the vote and its outcome, specifically

majority rule: “Democracy is nothing but the tyranny of majorities, the

most execrable tyranny of all, for it is not based on the authority of a

religion, nor on a nobility of blood, nor on the prerogatives of

fortune: it has number as its base, and for a mask the name of the

People.” [3]

But Proudhon doesn’t finish there. He protests that those left in the

minority are forced by circumstance to follow the will of the majority—a

situation he finds untenable, not only for the explicit coercion, but

also because those in the minority are forced to abjure their ideas and

beliefs in favor of those who oppose them. This, he notes wryly, makes

sense only when political views are so loosely held by individuals so as

to hardly be worthy of the name. Analyzing the same scenario, William

Godwin declares, “nothing can more directly contribute to the

deprivation of the human understanding and character” than to require

people to act contrary to their own reason. A conclusion proven

empirically when one conducts even the most rudimentary survey of

representative government and its effects on humanity over the course of

the past 250 years.

In conclusion: for an anarchist, for myself, democracy—as a system of

self-governance, as a decision-making tool, as an ideal—is utterly

devoid of redeeming value. It functions as a mask for coercion, making

horror palatable while producing unbearable consequences for the

individual, for the species, and for the planet. A dead end.

That

It is at this point that most anarchists and critical theorists begin

backpedaling, some slowly (like Proudhon) and others rapidly (like

Bookchin). Historically, theorists have offered a scathing critique of

democracy and then immediately digressed, stating that the

representative form of democracy as conceived by bourgeois (or

socialist) society isn’t really democracy. That real democracy is

reflected in some other form—for Proudhon, delegated democracy, for

Bookchin, the Greek city-states or the Helvetican Confederation. The

argument then becomes that democracy can (and should) be recuperated [4]

by the Left as a workable form.

My own critique veers wildly off course at this point, having been

skewed by empirical observation of an alternate form of democratic

practice. I’ve recently returned from the Kurdish Autonomous Region in

Northern Syria, known as Rojava, where I had the opportunity to observe

a unique form of democracy implemented by a revolutionary libertarian

social movement.

Some theoretical context: in 1999, Abdullah Ă–calan, the head of the

Partiya Karkerên Kurdistanê (PKK, the Kurdistan Worker’s Party) was

captured by Turkish Security Forces, with assistance from the CIA and

Israel’s Mossad. Dodging a firing squad, he was eventually sentenced to

aggravated life imprisonment—and that’s where things get interesting.

Rather than making license plates or working in the laundry, Ă–calan

began the long slow intellectual journey out of Marxist-Leninist

gibberish into some pretty durable anarchist theory. He eventually

published his ideas in several works including Democratic Confederalism,

War and Peace in Kurdistan, and a multi-volume tome on civilization,

particularly the Middle East and Abrahamic religions. In his writing,

Ă–calan does what no one in the contemporary North American anarchist

milieu is even willing to think—he constructs, albeit vaguely, a

blueprint for a libertarian society. This simple exercise, content

aside, is incredible. His engagement resembles far more the utopian

socialist project of the early 19th Century than any of the ensuing

theoretics associated with social contestation, especially Marxism and

working class anarchism; indeed, his silence on class analysis, Marxist

teleology, historical materialism, and syndicalism is deafening. Ă–calan

is clear in his task when he states, in “The Principles of Democratic

Confederalism,” that “Democratic confederalism is a non-state social

paradigm. It is not controlled by a state. At the same time, democratic

confederalism is the cultural organizational blueprint of a democratic

nation. ” [emphasis mine] [5]

As implied in the name, there is a great reliance on democratic

processes in the system known as Democratic Confederalism. Yet Ă–calan is

silent about the definition of democracy—he never offers one—and it’s

implementation: he never discusses it with any specificity. In fact,

democracy is presented as a given, as a decision-making process, as an

approach to self-administration, and little else. There is no favoring

of voting versus consensus-based models, nor does he describe in any

detail or at any level (communal, cantonal, regional) the forms that he

foresees democracy taking. For example, “[Democratic Confederalism] can

be called a non-state political administration or a democracy without a

state. Democratic decision-making processes must not be confused with

the processes known from public administration. States only administrate

[sic] while democracies govern. States are founded on power; democracies

are based on collective consensus.” He expands on what he means by

“decision-making processes” in “The Principles of Democratic

Confederalism”: “Democratic Confederalism is based on grass-roots

participation. Its decision-making processes lie with the communities.”

Fair enough. So how does all this play out in Rojava? In other words,

how are Öcalan’s ideas being translated into revolutionary institutions?

I gained my first insight into democracy in Rojava over a plate of

hummus and pita in downtown KobanĂ®. I was sitting with Mr. Shaiko, a

TEV-DEM (Tevgera Civaka Demokratîk, Movement for a Democratic Society)

representative on a warm, dusty afternoon, some three days after we had

attended a commune meeting together. In that meeting, of the council of

Ĺžehid Kawa C commune, Mr. Shaiko had raised the issue of commune

boundaries and perhaps moving them to account for the number of people

returning to the rubbled, venerable hulk that is KobanĂ®. After some

discussion, Mr. Shaiko left the meeting, requesting a phone call to let

him know what they decided.

“So,” I asked Mr. Shaiko, “What happened with the commune? Did they

call?”

“No, no decision yet.”

“Oh, do they need to give one?”

“No, they’ll decide when they’re ready. That’s how it is,” Mr. Shaiko

looked at me over his glasses with a half-grin and then returned to the

plate of pita and hummus.

This is clearly a divergent view of democratic decision-making, in which

no conclusive result is as valid a response as a “yes” or a “no.” While

I only saw this adjustment to democratic decision-making in operation a

few times it seems to be fairly common, especially with the TEV-DEM

folks whose charge is implementing democratic confederalism. It is also

an interesting “fix” applied to the issue of decision-making processes.

In a sense, it negates the democratic process in favor of discourse,

argument, and engagement, without the concomitant requirement of an

outcome.

The response of the revolutionaries to the tyranny of majority rule has

been structural rather than directive. Here, Ă–calan describes his views

on a plural society and outlines how he plans to weaken or subsume

majority rule: “In contrast to a centralist and bureaucratic

understanding of administration and exercise of power confederalism

poses a type of political self-administration where all groups of the

society and all cultural identities can express themselves in local

meetings, general conventions and councils… We do not need big theories

here, what we need is the will to lend expression to… social needs by

strengthening the autonomy of the social actors structurally and by

creating the conditions for the organization of the society as a whole.

The creation of an operational level where all kinds of social and

political groups, religious communities, or intellectual tendencies can

express themselves directly in all local decision-making processes can

also be called participative democracy.”

So for the revolutionaries the formation, growth and proliferation of

all types of “social actors”—communes, councils, consultative bodies,

organizations and even militias—is to be welcomed, and encouraged.

This plays out in Rojava in a patchwork quilt of organizations,

interests, local collectives, religious affiliates, and… flags. For

example, TEV-DEM, the umbrella organization charged with implementing

democratic self-administration, is actually an agglomeration of several

smaller organizations and representatives from political parties. These

various organizations include groups centering around sport, culture,

religion, women’s issues, and more. For example, in December of 2015, a

new organization under the TEV-DEM system was born—TEV-ÇAND Jihn, which

focuses on women and cultural production. This new organization is in

addition to the generic TEV-ÇAND, which focuses on society, generally,

and cultural production. To sidestep the problems with majority rule,

the revolutionaries have introduced a structural caveat that allows

individuals to find an organization that suits their needs, and through

which their voice can be heard in society. Note that TEV-DEM and others

have not sought to tinker with the actual mechanics of how a commune or

organization operates or decides. Rather, they have changed the social

order such that if an individual refuses to uphold a decision by a

group, commune or council, she always has the ability to opt out and

find a more amenable assembly.

These innovations seem like good first steps towards turning democracy

from a worthless antiquity into a workable principle within anarchist

theory. As such, they should be encouraged and studied.

This

My essay regarding the organizational form and its various moments of

domination, “The Organization’s New Clothes,” was first published in

February of 1989 (and republished in 2015), and I see no reason to

retract any portion thereof. [6] That critique, therefore, resonates

throughout the following discussion, though time and space prohibit

using it in any way other than as a critical prism.

The commune is a scrambled term. Its origins lie in the smallest

administrative entity in France, the commune—corresponding roughly to a

municipality. The word itself is derived from the twelfth-century

Medieval Latin communia, meaning a group of people living a common or

shared life. This is an interesting point of departure in that, even

then, the concept implied some degree of autonomy, both political and

economic. It was, however, the Paris Commune during the French

Revolution (1789-1795) that wrote the term in large red letters in the

book of revolution. In that first great explosion, the Communards

distinguished themselves by their intransigence and demands for the

abolition of private property and social classes, eventually earning

themselves the nickname les enrages (“the enraged ones”).

The revolutionary commune, then, has a subversive nature. It is

dangerous. It is always dangerous when humans interact beyond the

terrain of Capital and state, or in opposition to them.

Throughout the 19th century, outside the administrative network of

France, the term commune came to be associated with socialist and

communist experiments and, in a looser sense, with all manner of utopian

projects and communities—Owen, Fourier, Oneida, Amana, Modern Times.

There was a slump for a few decades through the first part of the 20th

century, and then, to confuse things further, the 1960s happened. The

definition of the word “commune” ends for many North Americans somewhere

in 1972, in a tangerine swirl of bad acid, free love, and the Manson

Family.

Which is not to say that there weren’t some important projects. Among

the more interesting were the West Berlin-based Kommune 1(1967-1969) and

Wisconsin’s contribution to utopia, Dreamtime Village. There have been

thousands (likely tens of thousands) of communes over the past two

centuries: intentional communities, collectives, cooperatives, each with

its own “glue”—the stuff that brought people together and “stuck” them

to one another. In most cases, this glue has been a mix of politics,

anarchism, communism, utopianism, religious sentiment (usually wacky),

livelihood, necessity, drugs, sexuality, or just plain detesting the

dominant culture.

So what, exactly, is a commune? Who the hell knows? The problem is not

the vagueness with which the commune is understood; rather, it’s the

lack of theory (and experience) that would provide nuance to this

vagueness. The idea of the commune has been lost or diluted as a result

of its own jangled historical context and the easily recuperable forms

that it has recently taken. Ultimately, very much like democracy, the

commune seems a quaint and faded relic in the cabinet of anarchist

theory, filed under “V” for vestigial.

That

As above, so below. My own relation with the Commune spans several

articles on the Paris events of 1871, and includes my ongoing engagement

with the conundrum of anarchist organization. All of my interactions

with the concept of organizations operating in a revolutionary context

had been on paper—in theory—until I crossed into the Kurdish Autonomous

Region. Then things changed.

The commune and council meetings I attended varied widely, ranging from

an ad hoc encounter of a team of YPG militiamen near the Turkish border

in KobanĂ® Canton to a council of the Ĺžehid Kawa C commune, to a ceremony

and meeting between TEV-DEM representatives of Kobanî and Cizîrê Canton.

In each instance, I recall a series of similar impressions. First, each

encounter was characterized by a sense of purpose, of meaning. The

attendees seemed clear that what they were engaged in, the simple task

of meeting together—as a commune, as a team of YPG fighters—carried

within it a seed, a possible future, for Northern Syria, perhaps for the

planet. Many people commented on this when I asked their thoughts

regarding these political forms. A woman I met in Paris at an HDP rally

put it best: “We are here reinventing politics, in fact, the world.”

This perception, which could easily foster arrogance, seemed instead to

produce a mindset of quiet determination in these attendees. These folks

were not wealthy, they worked hard in an area where there was little

work. The men’s faces were lined and etched with long hours spent under

the harsh Middle East sun. The hands of the women were simultaneously

delicate and rough: while they bore callouses and cuts, they also

carried the scent of lotion and perfume. The voices, gestures, and faces

of the revolutionaries during the meetings were intent, searching,

serious. There was kindness, hugs for a developmentally disabled young

adult, a moment spent with a mother who had lost a son in the siege of

Kobanî, and respect—as each person spoke to the accompaniment of silent

nods from their peers.

There was also hope, a quantity that history has so long denied to

anarchists, and which some of us have reclaimed—not as an eventuality,

but as a birthright. These folks believed that they could change their

lives, their community; many believed they could change (and were

changing) the world.

Finally, and most importantly, in each of these meetings there was an

overwhelming sense of the ordinary. When they mentioned the cantonal

authority at all, these folks referred to it laconically as the

anti-government, or the anti-regime. They had seen and participated in

sweeping social changes and experimentation, and in the process it had

become commonplace, like lunch. This is not to say that there was no joy

in the proceedings, far from it. Rather, what was really missing was

fear, and in this sense the social revolution in Rojava may truly be

said to have passed into a phase of maturity and permanence. The sole

condition in the short-term being the defeat of Daesh.

Some theorists have been advancing on the idea of the commune, but from

strange directions, post-left directions. Peter Lamborn Wilson in The

Temporary Autonomous Zone (TAZ) and Pirate Utopias forces the issues of

time and failure/success in reference to the commune. He rejects

utterly, as we must, the technological reasoning that the longer a

commune exists the better or more successful it must be. In TAZ, he

specifically provides a formula for a new idea of a commune, a temporary

encounter—perhaps hours, perhaps minutes—characterized by conviviality,

joy. This encounter is autonomous in that it is as independent and free

of the fetters of Capital and state as possible. This is essential to

understand. The commune is combative, not subservient. That is the basis

of its autonomy.

Rather than bounding the definition of the commune or trying to refine

it, I believe that defocusing the concept seems a sound strategy. I

would argue that whether it is a phalanstère with all the Fourierist

fauna intact, or a meeting between friends to relive old times or create

new ones, it doesn’t matter—it is a commune. Why bound something, why

hem something in when it presents itself as a viable model for

organization? Rather, without a definition, we can move with tiny baby

steps towards an understanding of what works and what is useless in the

commune model. That strikes me as one promising, potential direction

towards both engaged social experimentation and ruthless social

contestation.

Finally, at a macro-level, the concept of federalism may make a

theoretical comeback. If the commune model makes any sense at all, then

federalism isn’t very far behind. This returns anarchism to its

philosophical roots—Proudhon especially, but also Pi i Margall and

Bakunin. The insurrectionary potential for federalism seems vastly

underestimated. The movement to divide society into smaller and smaller

units, the federation of these units by mutual agreement, and the

potential for economic cooperation and shared self-defense make

federalism a potentially daunting, though rather blunt, instrument. Note

here that the current usage of federalism—the nation-state’s

accumulation of power, wealth, and knowledge in order to control and

dominate subject populations—is precisely the opposite of the concept’s

standard historical definition. It is Pi i Margall, the non-anarchist

grandfather of Spanish anarchism, in his 1855 work La ReacciĂłn y la

RevoluciĂłn, who offers the final word on the potential of federalism:

“The constitution of a society without power is the ultimate of my

revolutionary aspirations,” stating he would, “divide and subdivide

power,” in order to “destroy it.” [7]

The formation of communes also seems a viable real world strategy in

that it fulfills two immediate functions. First, they can act as

support, a backbone for the movement of militants quickly to areas where

their services might be required. In this way, they may function very

much as the bookstores, infoshops, and alternative spaces did in the

anarchist milieu of the past several decades in the US, or as the

communes did in KobanĂ® during the siege. Their resources can assist in

the provision of shelter, food, medical aid, and comfort for fighters.

The communes can also provide valuable intelligence on local conditions,

law enforcement, and assist in identifying those specific targets most

noxious to the community. Put in contemporary military parlance, one

type of commune may not be a weapon, but it can function as a weapons

platform for the mobile anarchist fighters.

Secondly, the communes provide for the sedentary members of the milieu a

laboratory, a setting in which to experiment with new ideas, new forms,

coalescing, in protoplasmic form, the seeds of revolutionary

institutions yet to be. Communes are nurseries where budding

insurrections are reared. Ancillary to this effect, yet no less

important, is the possibility that communes will help to offset the

attrition that has plagued anarchism since its inception as a political

movement. A life dedicated to liberty is difficult to sustain, and most

anarchists [who can] eventually succumb to the Cthulhu call of new cars,

big houses, and squandered lives. At the age of 55, I have seen

thousands of anarchists come and go; only those too stubborn or

anti-social, like my friends and myself, seem to remain. Communes may

stem this drift by producing a social milieu that is amenable to the

various vagaries of the anarchist personality type, and by distributing

resources for assistance with the real world issues of food, shelter,

childbirth and rearing, loneliness, illness, old age and death.

The commune is a verb. The commune is a question.

The Other Thing

Anarchism has been adrift since the end of the Second World War. With

little understanding of its roots, history, and struggles, most of us

did the best we could with what we could find. There were no

organizations to criticize or join; it was difficult enough just to find

anarchists in NYC in 1984. We were orphans. The situation has changed:

there are more anarchists, they are more easily contacted and the

explosion of information has given us our story back. As a confluence,

the news out of Greece, Rojava, Europe, in fact just about everywhere

seems to be turning in our direction. Those in the milieu, therefore,

have some choices to make about where to place energy, where to invest

time and effort, in a word—what to do? There are at least as many

possible answers to this question as there are anarchists now alive. As

my response, I suggest the following:

Form democratic communes.

Federate.

Be ready.

[1] La Boetie, Etienne (1975) The Politics of Obedience: The Discourse

of Voluntary Servitude. Montreal; Black Rose Books.

[2] Vaneigem, Raoul. (1994) The Revolution of Everyday Life (Donald

Nicholson-Smith, Trans.). London: Rebel Press.

[3] Proudhon, Pierre-Joseph. (1867-1870) Oeuvres completes de P-J.

Proudhon. Paris: A. Lacroix, Verboeckhoven et Cie.

[4] Recuperation is a concept developed by the Situationists to describe

the process in which ideas and strategies that originally served a

revolutionary agenda, are appropriated by Capital and the state to

preserve the status quo.

[5] Ocalan, Abdullah (2011). Democratic Confederalism (transl.

International Initiative). Transmedia Publishing Ltd. London, Cologne

[6] Simons, Paul Z. (2015). “The Organization’s New Clothes,” Black Eye:

Pathogenic and Perverse. Ardent Press, Berkeley CA.

[7] Pi y Margall, Francisco. “Reaction and Revolution,” in Anarchism, A

Documentary History of Libertarian Ideas Volume One