💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › rudolf-rocker-anarchism-and-anarcho-syndicalism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 13:43:26. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Anarchism and Anarcho-Syndicalism
Author: Rudolf Rocker
Date: 1949
Language: en
Topics: class struggle, syndicalist, anarcho-syndicalist, history
Source: Retrieved on April 26, 2009 from http://flag.blackened.net/rocker/aasind.htm

Rudolf Rocker

Anarchism and Anarcho-Syndicalism

Ideology of Anarchism

Anarchism is a definite intellectual current of social thought, whose

adherents advocate the abolition of economic monopolies and of all

political and social coercive institutions within society. In place of

the capitalist economic order, Anarchists would have a free association

of all productive forces based upon cooperative labour, which would have

for its sole purpose the satisfying of the necessary requirements of

every member of society. In place of the present national states with

their lifeless machinery of political and bureaucratic institutions,

Anarchists desire a federation of free communities which shall be bound

to one another by their common economic and social interests and arrange

their affairs by mutual agreement and free contract.

Anyone who studies profoundly the economic and political development of

the present social system will recognise that these objectives do not

spring from the utopian ideas of a few imaginative innovators, but that

they are the logical outcome of a thorough examination of existing

social maladjustments, which, with every new phase of the present social

conditions, manifest themselves more plainly and more unwholesomely.

Modern monopoly capitalism and the totalitarian state are merely the

last stages in a development which could culminate in no other end.

The portentous development of our present economic system, leading to a

mighty accumulation of social wealth in the hands of privileged

minorities and to a constant repression of the great masses of the

people, prepared the way for the present political and social reaction

and befriended it in every way. It sacrificed the general interests of

human society to the private interests of individuals, and thus

systematically undermined a true relationship between men. People forgot

that industry is not an end in itself, but should be only a means to

insure to man his material subsistence and to make accessible to him the

blessings of a higher intellectual culture. Where industry is

everything, where labour loses its ethical importance and man is

nothing, there begins the realm of ruthless economic despotism, whose

workings are no less disastrous than those of any political despotism.

The two mutually augment one another; they are fed from the same source.

Our modern social system has internally split the social organism of

every country into hostile classes, and externally it has broken up the

common cultural circle into hostile nations; both classes and nations

confront one another with open antagonism, and by their ceaseless

warfare keep the communal social life in continual convulsions. Two

world wars within half a century and their terrible after-effects, and

the constant danger of new wars, which today dominates all peoples, are

only the logical consequences of this unendurable condition which can

only lead to further universal catastrophes. The mere fact that most

states are obliged today to spend the better part of their annual income

for so-called national defence and the liquidation of old war debts is

proof of the untenability of the present status; it should make clear to

everybody that the alleged protection which the state affords the

individual is certainly purchased too dearly.

The ever-growing power of a soulless political bureaucracy which

supervises and safeguards the life of man from the cradle to the grave

is putting ever-greater obstacles in the way of co-operation among human

beings. A system which in every act of its life sacrifices the welfare

of large sections of the people, of whole nations, to the selfish lust

for power and the economic interests of small minorities must

necessarily dissolve the social ties and lead to a constant war of each

against all. This system has merely been the pacemaker for the great

intellectual and social reaction which finds its expression today in

modern Fascism and the idea of the totalitarian state. far surpassing

the obsession for power of the absolute monarchy of past centuries and

seeking to bring every sphere of human activity under the control of the

state. “All for the state; all through the state; nothing without the

state!” became the leitmotiv of a new political theology which has its

various systems of ecclesiastical theology God is everything and man

nothing, so for this modern political creed the state is everything and

the citizen nothing. And just as the words the “will of God” were used

to justify the will of privileged castes, so today there hides behind

the will of the state only the selfish interests of those who feel

called upon to interpret this will in their own sense and to force it

upon the people.

In modern Anarchism we have the confluence of the two great currents

which before and since the French Revolution have found such

characteristic expression in the intellectual life of Europe: Socialism

and Liberalism. Modern Socialism developed when profound observers of

social life came to see more and more dearly that political

constitutions and changes in the form of government could never get to

the root of the great problem that we call the social question. Its

supporters recognised that an equalising of social and economic

conditions for the benefit of all, despite the loveliest of theoretical

assumptions is not possible as long as people are separated into classes

on the basis of their owning or not owning property, classes whose mere

existence excludes in advance any thought of a genuine community. And so

there developed the conviction that only by the elimination of economic

monopolies and by common ownership of the means of production does a

condition of social justice become feasible, a condition in which

society shall become a real community, and human labour shall no longer

serve the ends of exploitation but assure the wellbeing of everyone. But

as soon as Socialism began to assemble its forces and become a movement,

there at once came to light certain differences of opinion due to the

influence of the social environment in different countries. It is a fact

that every political concept from theocracy to Caesarism and

dictatorship have affected certain factions of the socialist movement.

Meanwhile, two other great currents in political thought, had a decisive

significance on the development of socialist ideas: Liberalism, which

had powerfully stimulated advanced minds in the Anglo-Saxon countries,

Holland and Spain in particular, and Democracy in the sense, to which

Rousseau gave expression in his Social Contract, and which found its

most influential representatives in the leaders of French Jacobinism.

While Liberalism in its social theories started off from the individual

and wished to limit the state’s activities to a minimum, Democracy took

its stand on an abstract collective concept, Rousseau’s general will,

which it sought to fix in the national state. Liberalism and Democracy

were pre-eminently political concepts, and since most of the original

adherents of both did scarcely consider the economic conditions of

society, the further development of these conditions could not be

practically reconciled with the original principles of Democracy, and

still less with those of Liberalism. Democracy with its motto of

equality of all citizens before the law, and Liberalism with its right

of man over his own person, both were wrecked on the realities of

capitalist economy. As long as millions of human beings in every country

have to sell their labour to a small minority of owners, and sink into

the most wretched misery if they can find no buyers, the so-called

equality before the law remains merely a pious fraud, since the laws are

made by those who find themselves in possession of the social wealth.

But in the same way there can be no talk of a right over one’s own

person, for that right ends when one is compelled to submit to the

economic dictation of another if one does not want to starve.

In common with Liberalism, Anarchism represents the idea that the

happiness and prosperity of the individual must be the standard in all

social matters. And, in common with the great representatives of liberal

thought, it has also the idea of limiting the functions of government to

a minimum. Its adherents have followed this thought to its ultimate

consequences, and wish to eliminate every institution of political power

from the life of society. When Jefferson clothes the basic concept of

Liberalism in the words: “That government is best which governs least,”

then Anarchists say with Thoreau: “That government is best which governs

not at all.”

In common with the founders of Socialism, Anarchists demand the

abolition of economic monopoly in every form and shape and uphold common

ownership of the soil and all other means of production, the use of

which must be available to all without distinction; for personal and

social freedom is conceivable only on the basis of equal economic

conditions for everybody. Within the socialist movement itself the

Anarchists represent the viewpoint that the struggle against capitalism

must be at the same time a struggle against all coercive institutions of

political power, for in history economic exploitation has always gone

hand in hand with political and social oppression. The exploitation of

man by man and the domination of man over man are inseparable, and each

is the condition of the other.

As long as a possessing and a non-possessing group of human beings face

one another in enmity within society, the state will be indispensable to

the possessing minority for the protection of its privileges. When this

condition of social injustice vanishes to give place to a higher order

of things, which shall recognise no special rights and shall have as its

basic assumption the community of social interests, government over men

must yield the field to the administration of economic and social

affairs, or, to speak with Saint Simon: “The time will come when the art

of governing men will disappear. A new art will take its place, the art

of administering things.” In this respect Anarchism has to be regarded

as a kind of voluntary Socialism.

This disposes also of the theory maintained by Marx and his followers

that the state, in the form of a proletarian dictatorship, is a

necessary transitional stage to a classless society, in which the state,

after the elimination of all class conflicts and then the classes

themselves, will dissolve itself and vanish from the canvas. For this

concept, which completely mistakes the real nature of the state and the

significance in history of the factor of political power, is only the

logical outcome of so-called economic materialism, which sees in all the

phenomena of history merely the inevitable effects of the methods of

production of the time. Under the influence of this theory people came

to regard the different forms of the state and all other social

institutions as a “juridical and political superstructure on the

economic edifice” of society, and thought that they had found in it the

key to every historic process. In reality every section of history

affords us thousands of examples of the way in which the economic

development of countries was set back for centuries by the state and its

power policy.

Before the rise of the ecclesiastical monarchy, Spain, industrially, was

the most advanced country in Europe and held the first place in economic

production in almost every field. But a century after the triumph of the

Christian monarchy most of its industries had disappeared; what was left

of them survived only in the most wretched condition. In most industries

they had reverted to the most primitive methods of production.

Agriculture collapsed, canals and waterways fell into ruin, and vast

stretches of the country were transformed into deserts. Princely

absolutism in Europe, with its silly “economic ordinances” and

“Industrial Legislation”, which severely punished any deviation from the

prescribed methods of production and permitted no new inventions,

blocked industrial progress in European countries for centuries, and

prevented its natural development. And even now after the horrible

experiences of two world wars, the power policy of the larger national

states proves to be the greatest obstacle to the reconstruction of

European economy,

In Russia, however, where the so-called dictatorship of the proletariat

has ripened into reality, the aspirations of a particular party for

political power have prevented any truly socialistic reorganisation of

economic life and have forced the country into the slavery of a grinding

state-capitalism. The proletarian dictatorship, which naive souls

believe is an inevitable transition stage to real Socialism, has to-day

grown into a frightful despotism and a new imperialism, which lags

behind the tyranny of Fascist states in nothing. The assertion that the

state must continue to exist until society is no longer divided into

hostile classes almost sounds in the light of all historical experience,

like a bad joke.

Every type of political power presupposes some particular form of human

slavery, for the maintenance of which it is called into being. Just as

outwardly, that is, in relation to other states the state has to create

certain artificial antagonisms in order to justify its existence, so

also internally the cleavage of society into castes, ranks and classes

is an essential condition of its continuance. The development of the

Bolshevist bureaucracy in Russia under the alleged dictatorship of the

proletariat — which has never been anything but the dictatorship of a

small clique over the proletariat and the whole Russian people — is

merely a new instance of an old historical experience which has repeated

itself countless times. This new ruling class, which to-day is rapidly

growing into a new aristocracy, is set apart from the great masses of

the Russian peasants and workers just as clearly as are the privileged

castes and classes in other countries from the mass of the people. And

this situation becomes still more unbearable when a despotic state

denies to the lower classes the right to complain of existing

conditions, so that any protest is made at the risk of their lives.

But even a far greater degree of economic equality than that which

exists in Russia would be no guarantee against political and social

oppression. Economic equality alone is not social liberation. It is

precisely this which all the schools of authoritarian Socialism have

never understood. In the prison, in the cloister, or in the barracks one

finds a fairly high degree of economic equality, as all the inmates are

provided with the same dwelling, the same food, the same uniform, and

the same tasks. The ancient Inca state in Peru and the Jesuit state in

Paraguay had brought equal economic provision for every inhabitant to a

fixed system, but in spite of this the vilest despotism prevailed there,

and the human being was merely the automaton of a higher will on whose

decisions he had not the slightest influence. It was not without reason

that Proudhon saw in a “Socialism” without freedom the worst form of

slavery. The urge for social justice can only develop properly and be

effective when it grows out of man’s sense of freedom and

responsibility, and is based upon it. In other words, Socialism will be

free or it will not be at all. In its recognition of this fact lies the

genuine and profound justification of Anarchism.

Institutions serve the same purpose in the life of society as physical

organs do in plants and animals; they are the organs of the social body.

Organs do not develop arbitrarily, but owe their origin to definite

necessities of the physical and social environment. Changed conditions

of life produce changed organs. But an organ always performs the

function it was evolved to perform, or a related one. And it gradually

disappears or becomes rudimentary as soon as its function is no longer

necessary to the organism.

The same is true of social institutions. They, too, do not arise

arbitrarily, but are called into being by special social needs to serve

definite purposes. In this way the modern state was evolved, after

economic privileges and class divisions associated with them had begun

to make themselves more and more conspicuous in the framework of the old

social order. The newly arisen possessing classes had need of a

political instrument of power to maintain their economic and social

privileges over the masses of their own people, and to impose them from

without on other groups of human beings. Thus arose the appropriate

social conditions for the evolution of the modern state as the organ of

political power for the forcible subjugation and oppression of the

non-possessing classes. This task is the essential reason for its

existence. Its external forms have altered in the course of its

historical development, but its functions have always remained the same.

They have even constantly broadened in just the measure in which its

supporters have succeeded in making further fields of social activities

subservient to their ends. And, just as the functions of a physical

organ cannot be arbitrarily altered so that, for example, one cannot, at

will, hear with one’s eyes or see with one’s ears, so also one cannot,

at pleasure, transform an organ of social oppression into an instrument

for the liberation of the oppressed.

Anarchism is no patent solution for all human problems, no Utopia of a

perfect social order (as it has so often been called), since, on

principle, it rejects all absolute schemes and concepts. It does not

believe in any absolute truth, or in any definite final goals for human

development, but in an unlimited perfectibility of social patterns and

human living conditions which are always straining after higher forms of

expression, and to which, for this reason, one cannot assign any

definite terminus nor set any fixed goal. The greatest evil of any form

of power is just that it always tries to force the rich diversity of

social life into definite forms and adjust it to particular norms. The

stronger its supporters feel themselves, the more completely they

succeed in bringing every field of social life into their service, the

more crippling is their influence on the operation of all creative

cultural forces, the more unwholesomely does it affect the intellectual

and social development of power and a dire omen for our times, for it

shows with frightful clarity to what a monstrosity Hobbes’ Leviathan can

be developed. It is the perfect triumph of the political machine over

mind and body, the rationalisation of human thought, feeling and

behaviour according to the established rules of the officials and,

consequently, the end of all true intellectual culture.

Anarchism recognises only the relative significance of ideas,

institutions, and social conditions. It is, therefore not a fixed, self

enclosed social system, but rather a definite trend in the historical

development of mankind, which, in contrast with the intellectual

guardianship of all clerical and governmental institutions, strives for

the free unhindered unfolding of all the individual and social forces in

life. Even freedom is only a relative, not an absolute concept, since it

tends constantly to broaden its scope and to affect wider circles in

manifold ways. For the Anarchist, freedom is not an abstract

philosophical concept, but the vital concrete possibility for every

human being to bring to full development all capacities and talents with

which nature has endowed him, and turn them to social account. The less

this natural development of man is interfered with by ecclesiastical or

political guardianship, the more efficient and harmonious will human

personality become, the more will it become the measure of the

intellectual culture of the society in which it has grown. This is the

reason why all great culture periods in history have been periods of

political weakness, for political systems are always set upon the

mechanising and not the organic development of social forces. State and

Culture are irreconcilable opposites. Nietzsche, who was not an

anarchist, recognised this very clearly when he wrote: “No one can

finally spend more than he has. That holds good for individuals; it

holds good for peoples. If one spends oneself for power, for higher

politics, for husbandry, for commerce, parliamentarism, military

interests — if one gives away that amount of reason, earnestness, will,

self-mastery which constitutes one’s real self for one thing, he will

not have it for the other. Culture and the state — let no one be

deceived about this — are antagonists: the Culture State is merely a

modern idea. The one lives on the other, the one prospers at the expense

of the other. All great periods of culture are periods of political

decline. Whatever is great in a cultured sense is non-political, is even

anti-political.”

Where the influence of political power on the creative forces in society

is reduced to a minimum, there culture thrives the best, for political

rulership always strives for uniformity and tends to subject every

aspect of social life to its guardianship. And, in this, it finds itself

in unescapable contradiction to the creative aspirations of cultural

development, which is always on the quest for new forms and fields of

social activity, and for which freedom of expression, the many-sidedness

and the continual changing of things, are just as vitally necessary as

rigid forms, dead rules, and the forcible suppression of ideas are for

the conservation of political power. Every successful piece of work

stirs the desire for greater perfection and deeper inspiration; each new

form becomes the herald of new possibilities of development. But power

always tries to keep things as they are, safely anchored to stereotypes.

That has been the reason for all revolutions in history. Power operates

only destructively, bent always on forcing every manifestation of social

life into the straitjacket of its rules. Its intellectual expression is

dead dogma, its physical form brute force. And this unintelligence of

its objectives sets its stamp on its representatives also, and renders

them often stupid and brutal, even when they were originally endowed

with the best talents. One who is constantly striving to force

everything into a mechanical order at last becomes a machine himself and

loses all human feelings.

It was from this understanding that modern Anarchism was born and draws

its moral force. Only freedom can inspire men to great things and bring

about intellectual and social transformations. The art of ruling men has

never been the art of educating and inspiring them to a new shaping of

their lives. Dreary compulsion has at its command only lifeless drill,

which smothers any vital initiative at its birth and brings forth only

subjects, not free men. Freedom is the very essence of life, the

impelling force in all intellectual and social development, the creator

of every new outlook for the future of mankind. The liberation of man

from economic exploitation and from intellectual, social and political

oppression, which finds its highest expression in the philosophy of

Anarchism, is the first prerequisite for the evolution of a higher

social culture and a new humanity.

History of Anarchist Philosphy From Lao-Tse to Kropotkin

Anarchist ideas are to be found in almost every period of known history.

We encounter them in the Chinese sage, Lao-Tse (The Course and The Right

Way), and the later Greek philosophers, the Hedonists and Cynics and

other advocates of so-called natural right, and particularly, in Zeno,

the founder of the Stoic school and opposer of Plato. They found

expression in the teachings of the Gnostic Carpocrates in Alexandria,

and had an unmistakable influence on certain Christian sects of the

Middle Ages in France, Germany, Italy, Holland and England, most of

which fell victims to the most savage persecutions. In the history of

the Bohemian Reformation they found a powerful champion in Peter

Chelcicky, who in his work, The Net of Faith, passed the same judgment

on the Church and the State as Tolstoy did centuries later. Among the

great Humanists there was Rabelais, who in his description of the happy

Abbey of Theleme (Gargantua) presented a picture of life freed from all

authoritarian restraints. Of other pioneers of libertarian thinking we

will mention here only La Boetie, Sylvain Marechal, and, above all,

Diderot, in whose voluminous writings one finds thickly strewn the

utterances of a really great mind which had rid itself of every

authoritarian prejudice.

Meanwhile, it was reserved for more recent history to give a clear form

to the Anarchist conception of life and to connect it with the immediate

process of social evolution. This was done for the first time by William

Godwin (1756–1836) in his splendidly conceived work, An Enquiry

Concerning Political Justice and its Influence upon General Virtue and

Happiness (London, 1793). Godwin’s work was, we might say, the ripened

fruit of that long evolution of the concepts of political and social

radicalism in England which proceeds from George Buchanan through

Richard Hooker, Gerard Winstanley, Algernon Sidney, John Locke, Robert

Wallace and John Bellers to Jeremy Bentham, Joseph Priestley, Richard

Price and Thomas Paine.

Godwin recognised very clearly that the cause of social evils is to be

sought, not in the form of the state, but in its very existence. But he

also recognised that human beings can only live together naturally and

freely when the proper economic conditions for this are given, and the

individual is no longer subject to exploitation by others, a

consideration which most of the representatives of mere political

radicalism almost wholly overlooked. Hence they were later compelled to

make constantly greater concessions to the state which they had wished

to restrict to a minimum. Godwin’s idea of a stateless society assumed

the social ownership of the land and the instruments of labour and the

carrying on of economic life by free co-operatives of producers.

Godwin’s work had a strong influence on advanced circles of the English

workers and the more enlightened sections of the liberal intelligentsia.

Most important of all, he contributed to the young socialist movement in

England, which found its maturest exponents in Robert Owen, John Gray

and William Thompson, that unmistakably libertarian character which it

had for a long time, and which it never assumed in Germany and many

other countries.

Also the French Socialist Charles Fourier (1772–1832), with his theory

of attractive labour must be mentioned, here as one of the pioneers of

libertarian ideas.

But a far greater influence on the development of Anarchist theory was

that of Pierre Joseph Proudhon (1809–1865), one of the most gifted and

certainly the most many-sided writer of modern Socialism. Proudhon was

completely rooted in the intellectual and social life of his period, and

these influenced his attitude upon every question with which he dealt.

Therefore he is not to be judged, as he has been even by many of his

later followers, by his special practical proposals, which were born of

the needs of the hour. Among the numerous socialist thinkers of his time

he was the one who understood most profoundly the cause of social

maladjustment, and possessed, besides, the greatest breadth of vision.

He was the outspoken opponent of all artificial social systems, and saw

in social evolution the eternal urge to new and higher forms of

intellectual and social life; it was his conviction that this evolution

could not be bound by any definite abstract formulas.

Proudhon opposed the influence of the Jacobin tradition, which dominated

the thinking of the French democrats and most of the Socialists of that

period, with the same determination as the interference of the central

state and economic monopoly in the natural progress of social advance.

To him ridding society of those two cancerous growths was the great task

of the nineteenth century revolution. Proudhon was not a Communist. He

condemned property as merely the privilege of exploitation, but he

recognised the ownership of the instruments of labour for all, made

effective through industrial groups bound to one another by free

contract, so long as this right was not made to serve the exploitation

of others and as long as the full product of his individual labour was

assured to every member of society. This association based on

reciprocity (mutuality) guarantees the enjoyment of equal rights by each

in exchange for social services. The average working time required for

the completion of any product becomes the measure of its value and is

the basis of mutual exchange by labour notes. In this way capital is

deprived of its usurial power and is completely bound up with the

performance of work. Being made available to all it ceases to be an

instrument for exploitation. Such a form of economy makes any political

coercive apparatus superfluous. Society becomes a league of free

communities which arrange their affairs according to need. by themselves

or in association with others, and in which man’s freedom is the equal

freedom of others not its limitation, but its security and confirmation.

“The freer, the more independent and enterprising the individual is the

better for society.”

This organisation of Federalism in which Proudhon saw the immediate

future of mankind sets no definite limitations on future possibilities

of development and offers the widest scope to every individual and

social activity. Starting out from the point of Federation, Proudhon

combated likewise the aspiration for political and national unity of the

awakening nationalism of the time which found such strong advocates in

Mazzini, Garibaldi, Lelewel and others. In this respect he recognised

more clearly the real nature of nationalism than most of his

contemporaries. Proudhon exerted a strong influence on the development

of Socialism, which made itself felt especially in the Latin countries.

Ideas similar to the economic and political conceptions of Proudhon were

propagated by the followers of so-called Individualist Anarchism in

America which found able exponents in such men as Josiah Warren, Stephen

Pearl Andrews, William B. Greene, Lysander Spooner, Benjamin R. Tucker,

Ezra Heywood, Francis D. Tandy and many others, though none of them

could approach Proudhon’s breadth of view. Characteristic of this school

of libertarian thought is the fact that most of its representatives took

their political ideas not from Proudhon but from the traditions of

American Liberalism, so that Tucker could assert that “Anarchists are

merely consistent Jeffersonian democrats”.

A unique expression of libertarian ideas is to be found in Max Stirner’s

(Johann Kaspar Schmidt) (1806–1856) book, Der Einzige und sein Eigentum,

which, it is true, passed quickly into oblivion and had no influence on

the development of the Anarchist movement as such. Stirner’s book is

predominantly a philosophic work which traces man’s dependence on

so-called higher powers through all its devious ways, and is not timid

about drawing inferences from the knowledge gained by the survey. It is

the book of a conscious and deliberate insurgent, which reveals no

reverence for any authority, however exalted, and, therefore appeals

powerfully to independent thinking.

Anarchism found a virile champion of vigorous revolutionary energy in

Michael A. Bakunin (1814–1876), who based his ideas upon the teachings

of Proudhon, but extended them on the economic side when he, along with

the federalist wing of the First International, advocated collective

ownership of the land and all other means of production, and wished to

restrict the right of private property only to the product of individual

labour. Bakunin also was an opponent of Communism, which in his time had

a thoroughly authoritarian character, like that which it has again

assumed to-day in Bolshevism — “I am not a Communist, because Communism

unites all the forces of society in the state and becomes absorbed in

it; because it inevitably leads to the concentration of all property in

the hands of the state, while I seek the complete elimination of the

principles of authority and governmental guardianship, which under the

pretence of making men moral and civilising them, has up to now always

enslaved, oppressed, exploited and ruined them.”

Bakunin was a determined revolutionary and did not believe in an

amicable adjustment of the existing conflicts within society. He

recognised that the ruling classes blindly and stubbornly opposed every

possibility for larger social reforms, and accordingly saw the only

salvation in an international social revolution, which would abolish all

institutions of political power and economic exploitation and introduce

in their stead a Federation of free Associations of producers and

consumers to provide for the requirements of their daily life. Since he,

like so many of his contemporaries, believed in the close proximity of

the revolution, he directed all his vast energy to combining all the

genuinely revolutionary and libertarian elements within and outside the

International to safeguard the coming revolution against any

dictatorship or any retrogression to the old conditions. Thus he became

in a very special sense the creator of the modern Anarchist movement.

Anarchism found a valuable exponent in Peter Kropotkin (1842–1921), who

set himself the task of making the achievements of modern natural

science available for the development of the sociological concept of

Anarchism. In his ingenious book, Mutual Aid — Factor of Evolution, he

entered the lists against so-called Social Darwinism, whose exponents

tried to prove the inevitability of the existing social conditions from

the Darwinian theory of the Struggle for Existence by raising the

struggle of the strong against the weak to the status of an iron law of

nature, to which man is also subject. In reality this conception was

strongly influenced by the Malthusian doctrine that life’s table is not

spread for all, and that the unneeded will just have to reconcile

themselves to this fact. Kropotkin showed that this conception of nature

as a field of unrestricted warfare is only a caricature of real life,

and that along with the brutal struggle for existence, which is fought

out with tooth and claw, there exists in nature also another tendency

which is expressed in the social combination of the weaker species and

the maintenance of races by the evolution of social instincts and mutual

aid. In this sense man is not the creator of society, but society the

creator of man, for he inherited from the species that preceded him the

social instinct which alone enabled him to maintain himself in his first

environment against the physical superiority of other species, and to

make sure of an undreamed-of height of development. This second as is

shown by the steady retrogression of those species whose tendency in the

struggle for existence is far superior to the first, have no social life

and are dependent merely upon their physical strength. This view, which

to-day is meeting with constantly wider acceptance in the natural

sciences and in social research, opened wholly new vistas to the

prospects concerning human evolution.

According to Kropotkin the fact remains that even under the worst

despotism most of man’s personal relations with his fellows are arranged

by social habits, free agreement and mutual cooperation, without which

social life would not be possible at all. If this were not the case,

even the strongest coercive machinery of the state would not be able to

maintain the social order for any length of time. However, these natural

forms of behaviour, which arise from man’s innermost nature, are to-day

constantly interfered with and crippled by the effects of economic

exploitation and governmental tutelage, representing the brutal form of

the struggle for existence in human society which has to be overcome by

the other form of mutual aid and free co-operation. The consciousness of

personal responsibility and the capacity for sympathy with others, which

make all social ethics and all ideas of social justice, develop best in

freedom.

Like Bakunin, Kropotkin too was a revolutionary. But he, like Elisee

Reclus and others, saw in revolution only a special phase of the

evolutionary process, which appears when new social aspirations are so

restricted in their natural development by authority that they have to

shatter the old shell by violence before they can function as new

factors in human life.

In contrast to Proudhon’s Mutualism and Bakunin’s Collectivism,

Kropotkin advocated common ownership not only of the means of production

but of the products of labour as well, as it was his opinion that in the

present state of technology no exact measure of the value of individual

labour is possible, but that, on the other hand, by rational direction

of our modern methods of labour it will be possible to assure

comparative abundance to every human being. Communist Anarchism, which

before Kropotkin had already been urged by Joseph Dejacque, Elisee

Reclus, Carlo Cafiero and others, and which is recognised by the great

majority of Anarchists to-day, found in him its most brilliant exponent.

Mention must also be made here of Leo Tolstoy (1828–1910), who, from

primitive Christianity and on the basis of the ethical principles laid

down in the gospels, arrived at the idea of a society without rulership.

Common to all Anarchists is the desire to free society of all political

and social coercive institutions which stand in the way of the

development of a free humanity. In this sense Mutualism, Collectivism

and Communism are not to be regarded as closed economic systems,

permitting no further development, but merely as economic assumptions as

to the means of safeguarding a free community. There will even probably

be in every form of a free society of the future different forms of

economic co-operation existing side by side, since any social progress

must be associated with free experimentation and practical testing out

of new methods for which in a free society of free communities there

will be every opportunity.

The same holds true for the various methods of Anarchism. The work of

its adherents is pre-eminently a work of education to prepare the people

intellectually and psychologically for the tasks of their social

liberation. Every attempt to limit the influence of economic monopolism

and the power of the state is a step nearer to the realisation of this

goal. Every development of voluntary organisation in the various fields

of social activity towards the direction of personal freedom and social

justice deepens the awareness of the people and strengthens their social

responsibility, without which no changes in social life can be

accomplished. Most Anarchists of our time are convinced that such a

transformation of society will take years of constructive work and

education and cannot be brought about without revolutionary convulsions

which till now have always accomplished every progress in social life.

The character of these convulsions, of course, depends entirely on the

strength of resistance with which the ruling classes will be able to

oppose the realisation of the new ideas. The wider the circles which are

inspired with the idea of a reorganisation of society in the spirit of

freedom and Socialism, the easier will be the birth pains of new social

changes in the future. For even revolutions can only develop and mature

the ideas which already exist and have made their way into the

consciousness of men: but they cannot themselves create new ideas or

generate new worlds out of nothing.

Before the appearance of totalitarian states in Russia, Italy, Germany

and later in Portugal and Spain, and the outbreak of the second world

war, Anarchist organisations and movements existed almost in every

country. But like all other socialist movements of that period, they

became the victims of Fascist tyranny and the invasions of the German

armies, and could only lead an underground existence. Since the end of

the war a resurrection of Anarchist movements in all Western European

countries is to be noticed. The Federations of the French and Italian

Anarchists already held their first conventions, and so did the Spanish

Anarchists of whom many thousands are still living in exile, mostly in

France, Belgium and North Africa. Anarchist papers and magazines are

published again in many European countries and in North and South

America.

The Origins of Anarcho-Syndicalism

Many anarchists spent a great part of their activities in the labour

movement, especially in the Latin countries, where in later years the

movement of Anarcho-Syndicalism was born. Its theoretical assumptions

were based on the teachings of libertarian or anarchist Socialism, while

its form of organisation was taken from the movement of Revolutionary

Syndicalism which in the years from 1895 to 1910 experienced a marked

upswing, particularly in France, Italy and Spain. Its ideas and methods,

however, were not new. They had already found a deep resonance in the

ranks of the First International when the great association had reached

the zenith of its intellectual development. This was plainly revealed in

the debates at its fourth congress in Basel (1869) concerning the

importance of the economic organisations of the workers. In his report

upon this question which Eugene Hins laid before the congress in the

name of the Belgian Federation, there was presented for the first time a

wholly new point of view which had an unmistakable resemblance to

certain ideas of Robert Owen and the English labour movement of the

1830s.

In order to make a correct estimate of this, one must remember that at

that time the various schools of state-socialism attributed no, or at

best, only little importance, to the trade unions. The French Blanquists

saw in these organisations merely a reform movement, with a socialist

dictatorship as their immediate aim. Ferdinand Lassalle and his

followers directed all their activities towards welding the workers into

a political party and were outspoken opponents of all trade union

endeavours in which they saw only a hindrance to the political evolution

of the working class. Marx and his adherents of that period recognised,

it is true, the necessity of trade unions for the achievement of certain

betterments within the capitalist system, but they believed that their

role would be exhausted with this, and that they would disappear along

with capitalism, since the transition to Socialism could be guided only

by a proletarian dictatorship.

In Basel this idea underwent for the first time a thorough critical

examination. The views expressed in the Belgian report presented by Hins

which were shared by the delegates from Spain, the Swiss Jura and the

larger part of the French sections, were based on the premise that the

present economic associations of the workers are not only a necessity

within the present society, but were even more to be regarded as the

social nucleus of a coming socialist economy, and it was, therefore, the

duty of the International to educate the workers for this task. In

accordance with this the congress adopted the following resolution:

“The congress declares that all workers should strive to establish

associations for resistance in their various trades. As soon as a trade

union is formed the unions in the same trade are to be notified so that

the formation of national alliances in the industries may begin. These

alliances shall be charged with the duty of collecting all material

relating to their industry, of advising about measures to be executed in

common, and of seeing that they are carried out, to the end that the

present wage system may be replaced by the federation of free producers.

The congress directs the General Council to provide for the alliance of

the trade unions of all countries.”

In his argument for the resolution proposed by the committee, Hins

explained that “by this dual form of organization of local workers’

associations and general alliances for each industry on the one hand and

the political administration of labour councils on the other, the

general representation of labour, regional, national and international,

will be provided for. The councils of the trades and industrial

organisations will take the place of the present government, and this

representation of labour will do away, once and forever, with the

governments of the past.”

This new idea grew out of the recognition that every new economic form

of society must be accompanied by a new political form of the social

organism and could only attain practical expression in this. Its

followers saw in the present national state only the political agent and

defender of the possessing classes, and did, therefore, not strive for

the conquest of power, but for the elimination of every system of power

within society, in which they saw the requisite preliminary condition

for all tyranny and exploitation. They understood that along with the

monopoly of property, the monopoly of power must also disappear.

Proceeding from their recognition that the lordship of man over man had

had its day, they sought to familiarise themselves with the

administration of things. Or, as Bakunin, one of the great forerunners

of modern Anarcho-Syndicalism, put it:

“Since the organization of the International has as its goal, not the

setting up of new states or despots, but the radical elimination of

every separate sovereignty, it must have an essentially different

character from the organisation of the state. To just the degree that

the latter is authoritarian, artificial and violent, alien and hostile

to the natural development of the interests and the instincts of the

people, to the same degree must the organization of the International be

free, natural and in every respect in accord with those interests and

instincts. But what is the natural organization of the masses? It is one

based on the different occupations of their actual daily life, on their

various kinds of work, organization according to their occupations,

trade organisations. When all industries, including the various branches

of agriculture, are represented in the International, its organisation,

the organization of the toiling masses of the people, will be finished.”

And at another occasion: “All this practical and vital study of social

science by the workers themselves in their trades sections and their

chambers of labour will — and already has — engender in them the

unanimous, well-considered, theoretically and practically demonstrable

conviction that the serious, final complete liberation of the workers is

possible only on one condition: that of the appropriation of capital,

that is, of raw materials and all the tools of labour, including land,

by the whole body of the workers ... The organisation of the trade

sections, their federation in the International, and their

representation by the Labour Chambers, not only create a great academy

in which the workers of the International, combining theory and

practice, can and must study economic science, they also bear in

themselves the living germs of the new social order, which is to replace

the bourgeois world. They are creating not only the ideas but also the

facts of the future itself ...”

After the decline of the International and the Franco-German War, by

which the focal point of the socialist labour movement was transferred

to Germany, whose workers had neither revolutionary traditions nor that

rich experience possessed by the Socialists in the Western countries,

those ideas were gradually forgotten. After the defeat of the Paris

Commune and the revolutionary upheavals in Spain and Italy the sections

of the International in these countries were compelled for many years to

carry on only an underground existence. Only with the awakening of

revolutionary Syndicalism in France were the ideas of the First

International rescued from oblivion and inspired once more larger

sections of the labour movement.

Socialism and Anarcho-Syndicalism in France

Modern Anarcho-Syndicalism is a direct continuation of those social

aspirations which took shape in the bosom of the First International and

which were best understood and most strongly held by the libertarian

wing of the great workers’ alliance. Its development was a direct

reaction against the concepts and methods of political Socialism, a

reaction which in the decade before the first world war had already

manifested itself in the strong upsurge of the Revolutionary Union

movement in France, Italy and especially Spain, where the great majority

of the organised workers had always remained faithful to the doctrines

of the libertarian wing of the International.

It was in France that the opposition against the ideas and methods of

the modern labour parties found a clear expression in the theories and

tactics of revolutionary Syndicalism. The immediate cause for the

development of these new tendencies in the French labour movement was

the continual split of the various socialist parties in France. All

these parties, with the exception of the Allemanists, which later gave

up parliamentary activities completely, saw in the trade unions merely

recruiting schools for their political objectives and had no

understanding for their real functions. The constant dissensions among

the various socialist factions was naturally carried over into the

labour unions, and it happened quite frequently that when the unions of

one faction went on strike the unions of the other factions walked in on

them as strike breakers. This untenable situation gradually opened the

eyes of the workers. So the trade union congress in Nantes (1894)

charged a special committee with the task of devising means for bringing

about an understanding among all the trade union alliances. The result

was the founding in the following year of the Confederation Generale du

Travail at the congress in Limoges, which declared itself independent of

all political parties. From then on there existed in France only two

large trade union groups, the C.G.T. and the Federation des Bourses du

Travail, and in 1902, at the congress of the Montpellier the latter

joined the C.G.T.

One often encounters the widely disseminated opinion, which was fostered

by Werner Sombart in particular, that revolutionary Syndicalism in

France owes its origin to intellectuals like G. Sorel, E. Berth and H.

Lagardelle, who in the periodical Le Mouvement Socialiste, founded in

1899, elaborated in their way the intellectual results of the new

movement. This is utterly false. None of these men belonged to the

movement, nor had they any appreciable influence in its internal

development. Moreover, the C.G.T. was not composed exclusively of

revolutionary syndicates; certainly half of its members were of

reformist tendency and had joined the C.G.T. because even they

recognised that the dependence of the trade unions on political parties

was a misfortune for the movement. But the revolutionary wing, which had

had the most energetic and active elements of organised labour on its

side as well as the most brilliant intellectual forces in the

organization, gave the C.G.T. its characteristic stamp, and it was they

who determined the development of the ideas of revolutionary

Syndicalism. Many of them came from the Allemanists, but even more from

the ranks of the Anarchists, like Fernand Pelloutier, the highly

intelligent secretary of the Federation of the Labour Exchanges, Emile

Pouget, the editor of the official organ of the C.G.T. La Voix du

Peuple, P. Delesalle, G. Yvetot and many others. It was mainly under the

influence of the radical wing of the C.G.T. that the new movement

developed and found its expression in the Charter of Amiens (1906), in

which the principles and methods of the movement were laid down.

This new movement in France found a strong echo among the Latin workers

and penetrated also into other countries. The influence of French

Syndicalism at that time on larger and smaller sections of the

international labour movement was strengthened in great degree by the

internal crisis which at that period infected nearly all the socialist

labour parties in Europe. The battle between the so-called Revisionists

and the rigid Marxists, and particularly the fact that their very

parliamentary activities forced the most violent opponents of the

Revisionists of natural necessity to travel along the path of

Revisionism, caused many of the more thoughtful elements to reflect

seriously. They realised that participation in the politics of the

nationalist states had not brought the labour movement a hair-breadth

nearer to socialism, but had helped greatly to destroy the belief in the

necessity of constructive socialist activity, and, worst of all, had

robbed the people of their initiative by giving them the ruinous

delusion that salvation always comes from above.

Under these circumstances Socialism steadily lost its character of a

cultural ideal, which was to prepare the workers for the dissolution of

the present capitalist system and, therefore, could not let itself be

halted by the artificial frontiers of the national states. In the mind

of the leaders of the modern labour parties the alleged aims of their

movement were more and more blended with the interests of the national

state, until at last they became unable to distinguish any definite

boundary whatever between them. It would be a mistake to find in this

strange about-face an intentional betrayal by the leaders, as has so

often been asserted. The truth is that we have to do here with a gradual

assimilation to the modes and thoughts of the present society which

necessarily had to affect the intellectual attitude of the leaders of

the various labour parties in every country. Those very parties which

had once set out to conquer political power under the flag of Socialism

saw themselves compelled by the iron logic of conditions to sacrifice

their socialist convictions bit by bit to the national policies of the

state. The political power which they had wanted to conquer had

gradually conquered their Socialism until there was scarcely anything

left but the name.

The Role of the Trade Unions: Anarcho-Syndicalist View

These were the considerations which led to the development of

Revolutionary Syndicalism or, as it was later called,

Anarcho-Syndicalism in France and other countries. The term workers’

syndicate meant at first merely an organization of producers for the

immediate betterment of their economic and social status. But the rise

of Revolutionary Syndicalism gave this original meaning a much wider and

deeper import. Just as the party is, so to speak, a unified organization

with definite political effort within the modern constitutional state

which seeks to maintain the present order of society in one form or

another, so, according to the Unionist’s view, the trade unions are the

unified organization of labour and have for their purpose the defence of

the producers within the existing society and the preparing for and

practical carrying out of the reconstruction of social life in the

direction of Socialism. They have, therefore, a double purpose:

raising of their standard of living;

and economic life in general and prepare them to take the socio-economic

organism into their own hands and shape it according to socialist

principles.

Anarcho-Syndicalists are of the opinion that political parties are not

fitted to perform either of these two tasks. According to their

conceptions the trade union has to be the spearhead of the labour

movement, toughened by daily combats and permeated by a socialist

spirit. Only in the realm of economy are the workers able to display

their full strength; for it is their activity as producers which holds

together the whole social structure and guarantees the existence of

society. Only as a producer and creator of social wealth does the worker

become aware of his strength. In solidary union with his followers he

creates the great phalanx of militant labour, aflame with the spirit of

freedom and animated by the ideal of social justice. For the

Anarcho-Syndicalists the labour syndicate are the most fruitful germs of

a future society, the elementary school of Socialism in general. Every

new social structure creates organs for itself in the body of the old

organism; without this prerequisite every social evolution is

unthinkable. To them Socialist education does not mean participation in

the power policy of the national state, but the effort to make clear to

the workers the intrinsic connections among social problems by technical

instruction and the development of their administrative capacities, to

prepare them for their role of re-shapers of economic life and give them

the moral assurance required for the performance of their task. No

social body is better fitted for this purpose than the economic fighting

organisation of the workers; it gives a definite direction to their

social activities and toughens their resistance in the immediate

struggle for the necessities of life and the defence of their human

rights. At the same time it develops their ethical concepts without

which any social transformation is impossible: vital solidarity with

their fellows in destiny and moral responsibility for their actions.

Just because the educational work of Anarcho-Syndicalists is directed

toward the development of independent thought and action, they are

outspoken opponents of all centralising tendencies which are so

characteristic of most of the present labour parties. Centralism, that

artificial scheme which operates from the top towards the bottom and

turns over the affairs of administration to a small minority, is always

attended by barren official routine; it crushes individual conviction,

kills all personal initiative by lifeless discipline and bureaucratic

ossification. For the state, centralism is the appropriate form of

organisation, since it aims at the greatest possible uniformity of

social life for the maintenance of political and social equilibrium. But

for a movement whose very existence depends on prompt action at any

favourable moment and on the independent thought of its supporters,

centralism is a curse which weakens its power of decision and

systematically represses every spontaneous initiative.

The organisation of Anarcho-Syndicalism is based upon the principles of

Federalism, on free combination from below upward, putting the right of

self-determination of every union above everything else and recognising

only the organic agreement of all on the basis of like interests and

common conviction. Their organisation is accordingly constructed on the

following basis: The workers in each locality join the unions of their

respective trades. The trade unions of a city or a rural district

combine in Labor Chambers which constitute the centres for local

propaganda and education, and weld the workers together as producers to

prevent the rise of any narrow-minded factional spirit. In times of

local labour troubles they arrange for the united co-operation of the

whole body of locally organised labour. All the Labour Chambers are

grouped according to districts and regions to form the National

Federation of Labor Chambers, which maintains the permanent connection

among the local bodies, arranges free adjustment of the productive

labour of the members of the various organisations on; co-operative

lines, provides for the necessary co-ordination in the work of education

and supports the local groups with council and guidance.

Every trade union is, moreover, federatively allied with all the

organisations of the same industry, and these in turn with all related

trades, so that all are combined in general industrial and agricultural

alliances. It is their task to meet the demands of the daily struggles

between capital and labour and to combine all the forces of the movement

for common action where the; necessity arises. Thus the Federation of

the Labor Chambers and the Federation of the Industrial Alliances

constitute the two poles about which the whole life of the labour

syndicates revolves.

Such a form of organisation not only gives the workers every opportunity

for direct action in the struggle for their daily bread, but it also

provides them with the necessary preliminaries for the reorganisation of

society, their own strength, and without alien intervention in case of a

revolutionary crisis. Anarcho-Syndicalists are convinced that a

socialist economic order cannot be created by the decrees and statutes

of any government, but only by the unqualified collaboration of the

workers, technicians and peasants to carry on production and

distribution by their own administration in the interest of the

community and on the basis of mutual agreements. In such a situation the

Labour Chambers would take over the administration of existing social

capital in each community, determine the needs of the inhabitants of

their districts and organise local consumption. Through the agency of

the Federation of Labour Chambers it would be possible to calculate the

total requirements of the whole country and adjust the work of

production accordingly. On the other hand it would be the task of the

Industrial and Agricultural Alliances to take control of all the

instruments of production, transportation, etc., and provide the

separate producing groups with what they need. In a word:

of the Industrial Alliances and direction of work by labour councils

elected by the workers themselves;

Chambers.

In this respect, also, practical experience has given the best

instruction. It has shown that the many problems of a socialist

reconstruction of society cannot be solved by any government, even when

the famous dictatorship of the proletariat is meant. In Russia the

Bolshevist dictatorship stood helpless for almost two years before the

economic problems and tried to hide its incapacity behind a flood of

decrees and ordinances most of which were buried at once in the various

bureaus. If the world could be set free by decrees, there would long ago

have been no problems left in Russia. In its fanatical zeal for power,

Bolshevism has violently destroyed the most valuable organs of a

socialist order, by suppressing the Co-operative Societies, bringing the

trade unions under state control, and depriving the Soviets of their

independence almost from the beginning. So the dictatorship of the

proletariat paved the way not for a socialist society but for the most

primitive type of bureaucratic state capitalism and a reversion to

political absolutism which was long ago abolished in most countries by

bourgeois revolutions. In his Message to the Workers of the West

European countries Kropotkin said, rightfully: “Russia has shown us the

way in which Socialism cannot be realised, although the people,

nauseated with the old regime, expressed no active resistance to the

experiments of the new government. The idea of workers’ councils for the

control of the political and economic life of the country is, in itself,

of extraordinary importance ... but so long as the country is dominated

by the dictatorship of a party, the workers’ and peasants’ councils

naturally lose their significance. They are hereby degraded to the same

passive role which the representatives of the Estates used to play in

the time of the absolute Monarchy.”

The Struggle In Germany and Spain

In Germany, however, where the moderate wing of political socialism had

attained power, Socialism, in its long years of absorption with routine

parliamentary tasks, had become so bogged down that it was no longer

capable of any creative action whatever. Even a bourgeois paper like the

Frankfurter Zeitung felt obliged to confirm that “the history of

European peoples had not previously produced a revolution that has been

so poor in creative ideas and so weak in revolutionary energy.” The mere

fact that a party with a larger membership than any other of the various

labour parties in the world, which was for many years the strongest

political body in Germany, had to leave the field to Hitler and his gang

without any resistance speaks for itself and presents an example of

helplessness and weakness which can hardly be misunderstood.

One has only to compare the German situation of those days with the

attitude of the Anarcho-Syndicalist labour unions in Spain and

especially in Catalonia, where their influence was strongest, to realise

the whole difference between the labour movement of these two countries.

When in July, 1936 the conspiracy of the Fascist Army leaders ripened

into open revolt, it was by the heroic resistance of the C.N.T.

(National Federation of Labour) and the F.A.I. (Anarchist Federation of

Iberia) that the Fascist uprising in Catalonia was put down within a few

days, ridding this most important part of Spain of the enemy and

frustrating the original plan of the conspirators to take Barcelona by

surprise. The workers could then not stop half way; so there followed

the collectivisation of the land and the taking over of the plants by

the workers’ and peasants’ syndicates. This movement, which was released

by the initiative of the C.N.T. and F.A.I. with irresistible power,

overran Aragon, the Levante and other sections of the country and even

swept along with it a large part of the unions of the Socialist Party in

the U.G.T. (General Labour Union). This event revealed that the

Anarcho-Syndicalist workers of Spain not only knew how to fight, but

that they were also filled with the constructive ideas which are so

necessary in the time of a real crisis. It is to the great merit of

Libertarian Socialism in Spain that since the time of the First

International it has trained the workers in that spirit which treasures

freedom above all else and regards the intellectual independence of its

adherents as the basis of its existence. It was the passive and lifeless

attitude of the organised workers in other countries, who put up with

the policy of non-intervention of their governments that led to the

defeat of the Spanish workers and peasants after a heroic struggle of

more than two and one half years.

The Political Struggle: Anarcho-Syndicalist View

It has often been charged against Revolutionary Unionism that its

adherents had no interest in the political structure of the different

countries and consequently no interest in the political struggles of the

time. This idea is altogether erroneous and springs either from outright

ignorance or wilful distortion of the facts. It is not the political

struggle as such which distinguishes the Anarcho-Syndicalists from the

modern labour parties, both in principles and tactics, but the form of

this struggle and the aims which it has in view. Revolutionary Unionists

pursue the same tactics in their fight against political suppression as

against economic exploitation. But while they are convinced that along

with the system of exploitation its political protective device, the

state, will also disappear to give place to the administration of public

affairs on the basis of free agreement, they do not at all overlook the

fact that the efforts of organised labour within the existing political

and social order must always be directed against any attack of reaction,

and constantly widening the scope of these rights wherever the

opportunity for this presents itself. The heroic struggle of the C.N.T.

in Spain against Fascism was, perhaps, the best proof that the alleged

non-political attitude of the Revolutionary Unionists is but idle talk.

But according to their opinion the point of attack in the political

struggle lies not in the legislative bodies but in the people.

Political rights do not originate in parliaments; they are rather forced

upon them from without. And even their enactment into; law has for a

long time been no guarantee of their security. They do not exist because

they have been legally set down on a piece of paper, but only when they

have become the ingrown habit of a people, and when any attempt to

impair them will meet with the violent resistance of the populace. Where

this is not the case, there is no help in any parliamentary opposition

or any Platonic appeals to the constitution. One compels respect from

others when one knows how to defend one’s dignity as a human being. This

is not only true in private life; it has always been the same in

political life as well.

All political rights and liberties which people enjoy to-day, they do

not owe to the good will of their governments, but to their own

strength. Governments have always employed every means in their power to

prevent the attainment of these rights or render them illusory. Great

mass movements and whole revolutions have been necessary to wrest them

from the ruling classes, who would never have consented to them

voluntarily. The whole history of the last three hundred years is proof

of that. What is important is not that governments have decided to

concede certain rights to the people, but the reason why they had to do

this. Of course, if one accepts Lenin’s cynical phrase and thinks of

freedom merely as a “bourgeois prejudice’, then, to be sure, political

rights have no value at all for the workers. But then the countless

struggles of the past, all the revolts and revolutions to which we owe

these rights, are also without value. To proclaim this bit of wisdom it

hardly was necessary to overthrow Tzarism, for even the censorship of

Nicholas II would certainly have had no objection to the designation of

freedom as a bourgeois prejudice.

If Anarcho-Syndicalism nevertheless rejects the participation in the

present national parliaments, it is not because they have no sympathy

with political struggles in general, but because its adherents are of

the opinion that this form of activity is the very weakest and most

helpless form of the political struggle for the workers. For the

possessing classes, parliamentary action is certainly an appropriate

instrument for the settlement of such conflicts as arise, because they

are all equally interested in maintaining the present economic and

social order. Where there is a common interest mutual agreement is

possible and serviceable to all parties. But for the workers the

situation is very different. For them the existing economic order is the

source of their exploitation and their social and political subjugation.

Even the freest ballot cannot do away with the glaring contrast between

the possessing and non-possessing classes in society. It can only give

the servitude of the toiling masses the stamp of legality.

It is a fact that when socialist labour parties have wanted to achieve

some decisive political reforms they could not do it by parliamentary

action, but were obliged to rely wholly on the economic fighting power

of the workers. The political general strikes in Belgium and Sweden for

the attainment of universal suffrage are proof of this. And in Russia it

was the great general strike in 1905 that forced the Tsar to sign the

new constitution. It was the recognition of this which impelled the

Anarcho-Syndicalists to centre their activity on the socialist education

of the masses and the utilisation of their economic and social power.

Their method is that of direct action in both the economic and political

struggle of the time. By direct action they mean every method of the

immediate struggle by the workers against economic and political

oppression. Among these the outstanding are the strike in all its

gradations, from the simple wage struggle to the general strike,

organised boycott and all the other countless means which workers as

producers have in their hands.

One of the most effective forms of direct action is the social strike,

which was hitherto mostly used in Spain and partly in France, and which

shows a remarkable and growing responsibility of the workers to society

as a whole. It is less concerned with the immediate interests of the

producers than with the protection of the community against the most

pernicious outgrowths of the present system. The social strike seeks to

force upon the employers a responsibility to the public. Primarily it

has in view the protection of the consumers, of which the workers

themselves constitute the great majority. Under the present

circumstances the workers are frequently debased by doing a thousand

things which constantly serve only to injure the whole community for the

advantage of the employers. They are compelled to make use of inferior

and often actually injurious materials in the fabrication of their

products, to erect wretched dwellings, to put up spoiled foodstuffs and

to perpetrate innumerable acts that are planned to cheat the consumer.

To interfere vigorously is, in the opinion of the Revolutionary

Unionists, the great task of the labour syndicates. An advance in this

direction would at the same time enhance the position of the workers in

society, and in larger measure confirm that position.

Direct action by organised labour finds its strongest expression in the

general strike, in the stoppage of work in every branch of production in

cases where every other means is failing. It is the most powerful weapon

which the workers have at their command and gives the most comprehensive

expression to their strength as a social factor. The general strike, of

course, is not an agency that can be invoked arbitrarily on every

occasion. It needs certain social assumptions to give it a proper moral

strength and make it a proclamation of the will of the broad masses of

the people. The ridiculous claim, which is so often attributed to the

Anarcho-Syndicalists, that it is only necessary to proclaim a general

strike in order to achieve a socialist society in a few days, is, of

course just a ludicrous invention of ignorant opponents. The general

strike can serve various purposes. It can be the last stage of a

sympathetic strike, as, for example, in Barcelona in 1902 or in Bilbao

in 1903, which enabled the miners to get rid of the hated truck system

and compelled the employers to establish sanitary conditions in the

mines. It can also be a means of organised labour to enforce some

general demand, as, for example, in the attempted general strike in the

U.S.A. in 1886, to compel the granting of the eight-hour day in ail

industries. The great general strike of the English workers in 1926 was

the result of a planned attempt by the employers to lower the general

standard of living of the workers by a cut in wages.

But the general strike can also have political objectives in view, as,

for example, the fight of the Spanish workers in 1904 for the liberation

of the political prisoners, or the general strike in Catalonia in July

1909, to force the government to terminate its criminal war in Morocco.

Also the general strike of the German workers in 1920, which was

instituted after the so-called Kapp putsch and put an end to a

government that had attained power by a military uprising, belongs to

this category. In such critical situations the general strike takes the

place of the barricades of the political uprisings of the past. For the

workers, the general strike is the logical outcome of the modern

industrial system, whose victims they are to-day, and at the same time

it offers them their strongest weapon in the struggle for their social

liberation, provided they recognise their own strength and learn how to

use this weapon properly.

Anarcho-Syndicalism Since the First World War

After the First World War the peoples in Europe faced a new situation.

In Central Europe the old regime had collapsed. Russia found herself in

the midst of a social revolution of which no one could see the end. The

Russian revolution had impressed the workers of every country very

deeply. They felt that Europe was in the midst of a revolutionary crisis

and that if nothing decisive came out of it now their hopes would be

dispelled for many years For this reason they based the highest hopes on

the Russian revolution and saw in it the inauguration of a new era in

European history. In 1919, the Bolshevist party, which had attained

power in Russia, issued an appeal to all the revolutionary workers

organisations of the world and invited them to a congress in the

following year in Moscow to set up a new International. Communist

parties at this time existed only in a few countries; on the other hand

there were in Spain. Portugal, France, Italy, Holland, Sweden, Germany,

England and the countries of North and South America Unionist

organisations, some of which exercised a very strong influence. It was,

therefore, the deep concern of Lenin and his followers to win these

particular organisations for their purpose. So it came about that at the

congress for the founding of the Third International in the summer of

1920 almost all the Revolutionary Unions of Europe were represented.

But the impression which the Anarcho-Syndicalist delegates received in

Russia was not calculated to make them regard collaboration with the

Communists as either possible or desirable. The dictatorship of the

proletariat was already revealing itself in its true light. The prisons

were filled with Socialists of every school, among them many Anarchists

and Unionists. But above all it was plain that the new dominant caste

was in no way fitted for the task of a genuine socialist construction of

life. The foundation of the Third International with its dictatorial

apparatus and its efforts to make the whole labour movement in Europe

into an instrument for the foreign policy of the Bolshevist state,

quickly made plain to the Anarcho-Syndicalist that there was no place

for them in the Third International. For this reason the congress in

Moscow decided to set up alongside the Third International a separate

international alliance of revolutionary trade unions, in which the

Unionist organisations of all shades could also find a place. The

Unionist delegates agreed to this proposal, but when the Communists

demanded that this new organisation should be subordinate to the Third

International, this demand was unanimously rejected by the Revolutionary

Unionists.

In December, 1920 an international Anarcho-Syndicalist conference

convened in Berlin to decide upon an attitude toward the approaching

congress of the Red Trade Union International, which was prepared in

Moscow for the following year. The conference agreed upon seven points

on whose acceptance the entrance of the Unionists in that body was made

dependent. The importance of those seven points was the complete

independence of the movement from all political parties, and insistence

on the viewpoint that the socialist reconstruction of society could only

be carried out by the economic organisations of the producing classes

themselves. At the congress in Moscow in the following year the Unionist

organisations were in the minority. The Central Alliance of Russian

Trade Unions dominated the entire situation and put through all the

resolutions. In October, 1921, an international conference of Unionists

was held in Dusseldorf, Germany, and it decided to call an international

convention in Berlin during the following year. This convention met from

December 25, 1922 until January 2, 1923. The following organisations

were represented. Argentina by the Federacion Obrera Regional Argentina,

with 200,000 members; Chile by the Industrial Workers of the World with

20,000 members; Denmark by the Union for Unionist Propaganda with 600

members; Germany by the Freie Arbeiter Union with 120,000 members

Holland by the National Arbeids Sekretariat with 22,500 members, Italy

by the Unione Sindicale Italiana with 500,000 members; Mexico by the

Confederacion General de Trabajadores, Norway by the Norsk Syndikalistik

Federasjon with 20,000 members; Portugal by the Confederacao Geral do

Trabalho with 150,000 members; Sweden by the Sveriges Arbetares

Centralorganisation with 32,000 members. The Spanish CNT at that time

was engaged in a terrific struggle against the dictatorship of Primo de

Rivera and had sent no delegates, but they re-affirmed their adherence

at the secret congress in Saragossa in October, 1923. In France, where

after the war a split in the CGT had led to the founding of the CGTU,

the latter had already joined Moscow. But there was a minority in the

organization which had combined to form the Comite de Defence Unioniste

Revolutionaire, representing about 100,000 workers, which took part in

the proceedings of the Berlin congress. From Paris the Federation du

Batiment with 32,000 members and the Federation des Jeunesses de la

Seine were likewise represented. Two delegates represented the Unionist

Minority of the Russian workers.

The congress resolved unanimously on the founding of an international

alliance of all Unionist organisations under the name International

Workingmen’s Association. It adopted a declaration of principles which

presented an outspoken profession of Anarcho-Syndicalism. The second

item in this declaration runs as follows,

“Revolutionary Syndicalism is the confirmed opponent of every form of

economic and social monopoly, and aims at the establishment of free

communities and administrative organs of the field and factory workers

on the basis of a free system of labour councils, entirely liberated

from subordination to any government and parties. Against the politics

of the state and political parties it proposes the economic organization

of labour; against the government of men it sets the management of

things. Consequently, it has for its object, not the conquest of power,

but the abolition of every state function in social life. It believes

that, along with the monopoly of property, should also disappear the

monopoly of domination, and that any form of the state, including the

dictatorship of the proletariat, will always be the creator of new

monopolies and new privileges, and never an instrument of liberation.”

With this the breach with Bolshevism and its adherents in the various

countries was completed. The I.W.M.A. from then on travelled its own

road, held its own international congresses, issued its bulletins and

adjusted the relations among the Revolutionary Unions of the different

countries.

The most powerful and influential organization in the IWMA was the

Spanish CNT, the soul of all the hard labour struggles in Spain and

later the backbone of the resistance against Fascism and the social

reorganisation of the country. Before the triumph of Franco, the CNT

embraced a membership of about two millions of industrial workers,

peasants and intellectual workers. It controlled thirty-six daily

papers, among them Solidaridad Obrera in Barcelona, with a circulation

of 240,000, the largest of any paper in Spain, and Castilla Libre, which

was the most widely read paper in Madrid. The CNT has published millions

of books and pamphlets and contributed more to the education of the

masses than any other movement in Spain.

In Portugal the Confederacao Geral do Trabalho, founded in 1911, was the

strongest labour organization in the country, and based on the same

principles as the CNT in Spain. After the victory of dictatorship, the

CGT was forced out of public activity and could only lead an underground

existence.

In Italy, under the influence of the ideas of French Syndicalism, the

Anarcho-Syndicalist wing of the Conlederazione del Lavoro left that

organisation on account of its subservience to the Socialist Party and

formed the Unione Sindacale Italiana. This group was the soul of a long

list of severe labour struggles and played a prominent part in the

occurrences of the so-called Red Week in June, 1914, and later in the

occupation of the factories in Milan and other cities in Northern Italy.

With the reign of Fascism the whole Italian labour movement disappeared

along with the U.S.I.

In France the Anarcho-Syndicalists left the CGTU in 1922, after that

organization yielded entirely to the influence of the Bolshevists, and

formed the Confederation Generale du Travail Syndicaliste

Revolutionaire, which joined the IWMA.

In Germany there existed for a long time before the first world war the

so-called Localists whose stronghold was the Freie Vereinigung deutscher

Gewerkschaften, founded in 1897. This organization was originally

inspired by Social Democratic ideas, but it combated the centralising

tendencies of the German Trade movement. The revival of French

Syndicalism had a great influence on the F.V.D.G. and led to its

adoption of pure Anarcho-Syndicalist principles. At its congress in

Dusseldorf, 1920, the organisation changed its name to Freie

Arbeiter-Union Deutschlands. This movement rendered a great service

through the tireless labours of its active publishing house in Berlin

which printed a large number of valuable works. After Hitler’s accession

to power the movement of the F.A.U.D. vanished from the scene. A great

many of its supporters languished in the concentration camps or had to

take refuge abroad.

In Sweden there still exists a very active Unionist movement, the

Sveriges Arbetares Centralorganisation, the only Unionist organisation

in Europe which escaped the reaction of Fascism and German invasion

during the war. The Swedish Anarcho-Syndicalists participated in all the

great labour struggles in their country and carried on for many years

the work of socialist and libertarian education.

In Holland the Revolutionary Union movement concentrated in the

Nationale Arbeids Secretariat; but when this organisation came steadily

under increasing Communist influence, nearly half of its members split

off and formed the Nederlandisok Syndikalistisch Vakverbond which joined

the I.W.M.A.

In addition to these organisations there were Anarcho-Syndicalist

propaganda groups in Norway, Poland and Bulgaria, which were affiliated

with the I.W.M.A. The Japanese Jiyu Rengo Dantal Zenkoku Kaigi also

joined the ranks of the I.W.M.A.

In Argentina the Federacion Obrera Regional Argentina, founded in 1891,

was for many years the centre of most of the big labour struggles in

that country. Its history is one of the most tempestuous chapters in the

annals of the labour movement. The movement ran a daily organ, La

Protesta, for over twenty-five years and quite a number of weekly papers

all over the country. After the coup d’etat of General Uriburu, the FORA

was suppressed, but it carried on underground activity, as it also did

under Peron. In May, 1929 the F.O.R.A. summoned a congress of all the

South American countries to meet in Buenos Aires. At this congress,

besides the F.O.R.A. of Argentina there were represented: Paraguay by

the Centro Obrero del Paraguay: Bolivia by the Federacion Local de la

Paz, La Antorcha and Luz y Libertad; Mexico by the Confederacion General

de Trabajo; Guatemala by the Comite pro Accion Sindical; Uruguay by the

Federacion Regional Uruguaya. Brazil was represented by trade unions

from seven of the constituent states. Costa Rica was represented by the

organization Hacia la Libertad. At this congress the Continental

American Workingmen’s Association was brought into existence,

constituting the American division of the I.W.M.A. The seat of this

organisation was at first at Buenos Aires, but later, because of the

dictatorship, it had to be transferred to Uruguay.

These were the forces which Anarcho-Syndicalism had at its disposal in

the various countries before the reign of Fascism and the outbreak of

the second world war.