💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › murray-bookchin-were-we-wrong.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 12:37:23. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Were We Wrong?
Author: Murray Bookchin
Date: 1985
Language: en
Topics: capitalism, class struggle, critique
Source: Retrieved on 26th October 2020 from https://libcom.org/library/were-we-wrong-murray-bookchin
Notes: Published in Telos, Vol. 65, Fall, 1985, pp. 59–74.

Murray Bookchin

Were We Wrong?

Is it possible that the Left has been wrong about capitalist development

and revolutionary change? Is it possible that 20^(th)-century capitalism

is not “moribund;” that the Russian Revolution did not usher in an “era

of wars and revolutions,” as predicted by Lenin; that capitalism does

not unfold according to an “immanent” dialectic in which lie the “seeds”

of its own destruction? Could it be that we are in a ceaseless

“ascending phase” of capitalism?

We grasp at straws — Hungary in 1956, Paris in 1968, Czechoslovakia in

1969, Poland in the early 1980s — for evidence of a revolutionary

proletariat without seeing the tragic marginality of these events. We

turn to China, Cuba, Southeast Asia, Portugal, and Nicaragua for

evidence of a “revolutionary era” or to the Korean and Vietnamese

conflicts for evidence of a “war-ridden era” without seeing their

nationalist limitations. We try to acknowledge how ambiguous they are in

relation to the larger fact of a greatly expanded capitalism, the extent

to which the marketplace has deepened its reach into the most intimate

aspects of social life, the striking stability of the system as a whole,

its chilling technological sophistication that has made meaningless all

images of insurrectionary revolutions in the major centers of

capitalism.

Nor can we continue to use “betrayals” to explain the failures of the

past lour generations. Such a consistent pattern of treachery suggests

an internal weakness in the traditional socialist “perspective” of

capitalism and revolution that raises more questions than it answers.

The socialist project is fragile indeed if betrayal can occur so easily

and if “success” yields bureaucratic traits so constrictive and

reactionary that history is the better for its failures. The Russian

Revolution was a catastrophe whose shadow has cast the entire century

into darkness, and lives in our dreams more as a nightmare than a vision

of hope.

The answers are not to be found in quietism and defeat. It is not

defeatist to acknowledge that our expectations were unwarranted and the

analyses that nourished them were equally faulty. Nor is accommodation

possible if capitalism remains irrational to the core; that it has

always been so (Marx’s arguments about its “progressive role” to the

contrary notwithstanding); and that it has always stood at odds with an

abiding potential for freedom and ecological balance. But before that

potential can be seen and a relevant practice developed from efforts to

realize it, we must clear away the ideological fog that obscures our

thinking. This fog arises from a conjuncture of forces that has been

seriously misjudged by radicals for more than a century and from a

misreading of phenomena that span the last four centuries.

The Failures of the Classical Analysis

Whether one chooses to call capitalism “progressive” and “permanently

revolutionary,” to use Marx’s words, or a “historically necessary evil,”

to use Bakunin’s in regard to the state, the fact remains that WWI

opened an entirely new era in radical social theory. The terrible

blood-letting of the war posed serious challenges to the exuberant

belief in progress that the previous century associated with the new

social order. At the same time the revolutionary upheavals of the

1917–23 period awakened new hopes about the imminent likelihood of a

rational society — of socialism and human emancipation. The universalism

and humanism of the socialist project as it was formulated at that time

has no equal in our own. Clearly, it was agreed, capitalism had ceased

to be “progressive” or “historically necessary” irrespective of whether

it was “evil” or not. If it had an “ascending phase” characterized by

dramatic advances in technology and the demystification of all

traditional human bonds, and between humanity and nature, it had

definitely not entered in a “descending phase” that guaranteed its

self-extinction.

The socialist project was very specific about the shift in the cycle of

capitalist development. In its “ascending phase,” capitalism had

presumably established the technical preconditions for socialism. It

seemed to foster internationalism by secularizing all hum an bonds and

experiences, making giant strides in cultural and political development,

expanding hum an productivity and needs, rationalizing experience as

well as production — and, above all, creating a special class, the

proletariat, whose interests and afflictions inexorably drove it toward

the abolition of the wage system, capitalism, and class society as such.

Even if it was reasonable to suppose that without class consciousness

the proletariat could no more become a “hegemonic class” than the most

quietistic peasantry, socialist theorists emphasized that “objective

events” — and in Lenin’s view, a party of conscious revolutionaries —

would provide the self-reflexivity that could have made a successful

proletarian revolution possible.

The outbreak of WWII provided conclusive evidence of the failure of this

entrenched analysis. For nearly ten years prior to the war, world

capitalism had reached an unprecedented period of stagnation and

decline. The economy was frozen in crises that appeared to be chronic

and intractable. Living standards, employment, hopes for recovery, and a

belief in the legitimacy the social order had ebbed to an all-time low

by comparison with the pre-WWI era. Following the 1929 financial

collapse, the proletariat emerged almost explosively as a social force.

Although largely defensive, workers’ insurrections led by socialists

flared up in Austria and Spain (1934); general strikes swept France,

marked by the raising of red flags over factories (1935); plant

occupations and combative struggles with police in the U.S. created an

illusion of a near-insurrectionary crisis, buttressed by agrarian unrest

in which armed farmers closed down auctions and obstructed the movement

of produce during farmers’ strikes with road barricades. Despite

revealing failures, this movement could claim definite if illusory

successes: the election of the Popular Front in France and Spain; the

recognition of industrial unions in the U.S.; and, finally, the

short-lived achievements of the Spanish Revolution in 1936–37 which set

an unprecedented example of workers’ and peasants’ self-management.

Rarely had an insurgent mass movement achieved such ongoing persistence

and militancy. Indeed, fascism seemed not only like an expression of a

general crisis in the capitalist social order that called for a vigorous

imposition of totalitarian controls but also like a defensive reaction

by a traditional bourgeoisie to a growing and increasingly menacing

labor movement whose militancy appeared to verge on outright social

revolution.

Capitalism in the 1930s also appeared to be a “historical materialist”

textbook example of a social order that had outlived its legitimacy. Not

only was the decade stagnant economically and ravaged by class conflict;

it was technologically stagnant as well. Judging from the literature of

the times, a convincing case could be made for Marx’s notion that “the

material forces of production” had “come into conflict with the existing

relations of production.” Technology was bound by sharp corporate and

monopolistic constraints that foreclosed innovation. Capitalism, it

seemed, could no longer perform its “historically assigned” function of

advancing the “material preconditions” for freedom; indeed, ii seemed to

block their development. A socialist revolution was needed, presumably,

to bring society back into history, that is, to restore the momentum of

technological advances which the bourgeois social order could no longer

sustain.

Finally the outbreak of WWII was seen as the culmination of the “chronic

crisis of capitalism ” — its climax and literally the battleground for a

resolution of the so-called “social question.” The mass defection of

leftist liberals to the Allied military cause did not induce despair

among the already contracting radical movements of the 1940s. WWII, it

was argued by traditional Marxists, was merely a continuation of WWI —

an imperialist adventure that would reopen all the wounds that caused

its predecessor to end in social revolution. Indeed, this second war was

now visualized as a more short-lived conflict. The proletarian masses of

the 1940s, presumably more educated by their experiences during the

interwar period of capitalist decay, social conflict, revolutions, the

usual diet of “betrayals” and “treachery” served up by social democracy

and Stalinism, and an expanded sense of class solidarity and

internationalism, would act to change society with greater determination

than the previous generation. Given a reasonable amount of time, the

contending imperialist blocs in the world conflict would reveal their

“bankruptcy” and a subterranean labor movement, even in fascist Germany

(to some, especially in fascist Germany) would pick up the dangling

threads of 1917–18 and soon terminate the war in social revolution.

It is difficult to convey how tenaciously this scenario was held by the

interwar generation of radicals. Nearly all of the radical theorizing of

a century fed into these visions of social change and the detailed

sequence of forecasts that the revolutionary socialist movement

projected for the future in 1940 and well into the war itself. By the

same token, any doubts about this analysis and its outcome yielded

reactions that were equally far-reaching. Trotsky, more than any of the

Bolsheviks, retained the classical perspective of the era, indeed, of

the traditional labor movement itself. Shortly before his death he

claimed that the war advanced very compelling challenges to the radical

tradition. After expressing the usual ritualistic confidence in the

above scenario and the certainties of its outcome, he turned to the

implications of an alternative outcome. If capitalism emerged from the

war intact, he warned, the revolutionary movement would have to

re-examine its most fundamental premises. His murder in 1940 foreclosed

the possibility of such a re-evaluation by his followers. But his words

doggedly haunt the entire revolutionary project as it developed from the

days of the earliest workers’ insurrections. Trotsky’s chilling

confrontation with the project’s failure enabled him to see WWII as a

test of a traditional Marxist and Leninist view of the entire history of

capitalist development.

WWII did not end early. It lasted for nearly six years. It did not

terminate in revolutions. The German workers fought to the very doors of

Hitler’s bunker in Berlin without even a significant mutiny. Far from

exhibiting any significant evidence of class solidarity and

internationalism, the war was fought out on largely nationalist term s

and for ideals redolent of 18^(th)-century “patriotism,” often

descending to a savage irredentism and even racism, without the

rationalist and utopian canons of the Enlightenment.

What is even more remarkable: capitalism emerged from WWII in a stronger

position than in past generations. Although the war devoured between 40

and 60 million lives, the social order that claimed this unprecedented

toll was never seriously questioned. With the exception of Russia and

Spain, countries whose “proletariat” largely consisted of peasants in

overalls, socialism and anarchism had failed to orient the European

proletariat toward social revolution. In the 50 years that followed the

last of the workers’ upsurges, there is no evidence that the long

experience of proletarian socialism has fostered any advance in human

freedom . Indeed, in the name of socialism, totalitarian states today

rule an immense portion of the world with a ruthlessness that is as

dismal as that of their antecedents.

Technological innovation, in turn, acquired a momentum that has

shattered every constraint — moral as well as economic — that society

could raise against its elevation to pre-eminence in the human mind. To

point to a ripening of the material conditions for socialism, communism,

or anarchism as a justification for this breakthrough verges on black

humor. A strong case can be made today for Adorno’s Luddism in Minima

Moralia — indeed, perhaps a stronger one that what he proposed. Never

before has technological innovation emerged so much as a force in its

own right to arrest any trend toward the realization of the “true

society.” The sophistication of today’s weaponry reduces insurrectionary

modes of social change to romanticism while hopes for the hegemony of

the proletariat are little more than mere nostalgia. But what today

haunts proletarian socialism even more than the end of the barricade as

anything other than a symbol is the numerical decline of the industrial

proletariat itself — the change in the very personality of what was once

called wage labor. This proletariat now faces near-extinction by

cybernation, a reality that is perhaps more persuasive testimony to the

archaic character of classical socialism and anarchosyndicalism than the

myth that this class will play a central role in social change. Long

gone are the days when technology could be seen as a force promoting

socialism. Technological innovation has taken on a life of its own and

can be adduced not only as a means of economic and political regulation

but as a causal factor in ecological breakdown. It is forming a history

that can be written in large part autonomously: as the story of an

avalanche of devices that make the citizen powerless, smother individual

expression, and submerge personal creativity. Capitalism has clearly

stabilized itself, assuming that it was ever unstable. And it has done

so by establishing itself as a social given that is now as unquestioned

as feudalism was in the 12^(th) century. That is to say, capitalism now

enjoys a psychological validity that renders its functions as free from

challenges, indeed, consciousness, as the operations of the autonomic

nervous system. The failure of the classical analysis is just as

complete and just as disturbing, for it too has had a significant role

in legitimating capitalism by its own interpretation of capitalism’s

origins and evolution.

The Failure of Classical Historiography

The contribution of the classical analysis to the legitimation of

capitalism is most evident in the way socialism has assumed the

institutional forms of recent capitalism. A disquieting similarity

exists between the centralization of the state under capitalism and

classical socialist goals. This goes back to Marx’s Capital itself,

which notwithstanding its brilliant analysis of the commodity, projects

capitalist development into a phase that is so akin to its author’s

conception of socialism that the work ceases to be authentically

critical in the sense of providing a point of departure for social

liberation. To the contrary: the work enters into unknowing complicity

with the development of capitalism toward its still unknown

“maturation.” It is not Marx’s analysis that lakes the commodity in hand

but rather the commodity that takes possession of Marx’s analysis and

subtlety carries it into implied realms that he could never have

anticipated or regarded as desirable.

But the real failure of “historical materialism” is a much deeper one.

Marx’s “class analysis,” a still active dimension of his theoretical

corpus, raises problems that have not been adequately dealt with by most

of his acolytes. His “class analysis” is structured around the

fundamental notion that the “ domination of nature” cannot be achieved

without the “domination of man by man,” an implied view of nature whose

practical implications have profoundly shaped the classical tradition.

Classes in Marx’s larger social views were indispensable for separating

humanity from “savagery,” for bringing it into history and forming the

material preconditions for liberation — liberation not only from the

domination of man by man but from the domination of nature that made

human domination “historically necessary.” Within this convoluted

dialectic, classical socialism remained blind to ecological and gender

problems, both of which are linked not only to the emergence of classes

and exploitation, but are rooted even more fundamentally in the

emergence of hierarchy and domination. Accordingly, attempts to

formulate a socialist ecology and feminism to keep pace with the social

movements of our day tend to be mere contrivances. Although sectarian

socialists criticize these movements for lacking a class analysis, we

are still flooded with gleanings from Marx on ecology and women that

verge on caricature. Marx’s class analysis reflects a very Victorian,

indeed, bourgeois, marketplace notion of nature as a realm of

domination, blindness, rivalry, and scarce resources that once defined

every major discipline of the time from economics to psychology. The

more contemporary ecological image of nature, particularly of

ecosystems, as nonhierarchical, self-formative, mutualistic, and fecund

has eluded the Marxian outlook with the result that American socialists

today are more comfortable with the journalism of Andre Gorz, for whom

“ecological” problems arise from the “decline in the rate of profit”

than they are with more incisive works of ecophilosophy that preceded

his Ecology as Politics.

This problem goes far beyond that of the weight that 19^(th)-century

notions impose on the classical socialist analysis. Nor can it be seen

only as the result of a patchwork refurbishing of Marxism with concepts

that are alien to its core ideas. Rather, what is most relevant here is

the mischief Marx’s “class analysis” has wrought in formulating a fresh

interpretation of the capitalist development and the politics needed to

deal with it. We are obliged to ask whether radical theory is well

served by an image of social development based primarily on conflicting

economic interests premised on the ownership or control of property. As

an alternative to this, we might consider the possibility that

capitalism itself represents an exception to a more widespread social

development based on status and the ways in which the socialization

process and society as a whole define the individual’s position in the

human community and maintain the individual’s place in it.

Has capitalism, in fact, really revealed the material self-interest that

has presumably guided society under the mask of ideology for thousands

of years, as Marx claims, or has it rather created that interest in a

basically different social dispensation that replaced status

arrangements with classes? As Karl Polanyi observes, man “does not act

so as to safeguard his individual interest in the possession of material

goods; he acts so as to safeguard his social standing, his social

claims, his social assets.” Thus, the core for social analysis is the

paramount social tie for which economic relations are merely a highly

variable means rather than the “basis” for social interaction. To go

beyond Polanyi’s observation, we can see that his social tie may follow

a libertarian pathway or an authoritarian one. Indeed, once early

egalitarian societies began to break down, the libertarian pathway,

interlaced with the authoritarian one, rises from subterranean depths in

periods of social upheaval and then submerges in eras of social

stability.

The notion that precapitalist society was primarily a society of orders,

not simply of classes, is hardly new, but its implications as well as

its premises have yet to be fully explored. One’s community and the

place one occupies in it is one of the most human attributes we possess.

It is also the way in which we situate ourselves throughout our lives,

the way in which familial care is projected beyond the family into the

larger context of hum an relations. Thus, nearly all precapitalist

societies projected family and kinship relations onto social life.

Despite the growth of a purely juridical concept of citizenship and a

rationalist concept of politics, lineage retained enormous importance in

secular communities. Monarchies dealt with the territories under their

control more as patrimonies than as nations or cultures, and it was by

these biosocial norms that people “ordered” their economic lives into

social orders, not according to economic elements which would have

structured them as classes.

We must keep this distinction between a society of orders and a society

of classes clearly in mind, inasmuch as it has important political and

practical implications. A class analysis based exclusively on economic

interests misleads history and misdirects practice. Social distortions

and regressions can no longer be explained primarily by property

relations, nor can they be rectified by socio-economic measures alone,

such as nationalization, collectivization, or “workplace democracy.” For

what explodes all these proffered solutions to the tainted nature of

modern society is the swollen legacy of command and obedience relations

— in a word, hierarchy as the more basic substrate of all class

relations.

To develop more fully the contrast between status societies and class

societies, it is necessary to reject altogether the idea that capitalism

as a society of classes could have emerged organically within the “womb”

of feudalism, a society of orders. Capitalism’s uniqueness must be seen

in the light that traditional society as a whole — oriented around

family and status — sheds upon it. No precapitalist world was equipped

to deal with the formidable social and cultural irresponsibility that an

uncontrolled market economy would foster. One does not have to accept

the canons of laissez-faire to recognize that a market lacking any

ethical, cultural, and institutional constraints would have horrified

people even in the commercial world of the Renaissance, with its nuanced

standards for commerce. The identification of the market with

capitalism, in fact, results only from a highly specious reworking of

historical fact. Markets existed for ages in many different forms, but

they were carefully integrated into larger, more demanding, and socially

more legitimate communities that structured life around orders, largely

united by kinship and craft ties. These elements of early tribalism and

village societies never disappeared completely from the precapitalist

world. It was precisely capitalism, the uncontrolled market, that became

society, or, more precisely, began to eat away at society as a cancer, a

malignancy that threatened the very existence of the social bond itself.

It is only in the 20^(th) century, especially in post-WWII America that

capitalism emerged from its position as a predominant force in society

to become a substitute for society, corroding all familial and kinship

ties — and reducing the population as a whole to buyers and sellers in a

universal, ever-expanding marketplace.

Capitalism, always a dormant system in the larger context of

precapitalist social orders, essentially burst upon the world in a

period of sweeping social decline. The feudal system of orders which the

absolutist monarchies of Europe seemingly held together had fallen into

complete decay. By the 18^(th) century, Europe existed in what was

little more than a social vacuum within which capitalism could grow and

ultimately flourish, a period in which there was a general erosion of

all mores, not least of which were traditions that inhibited the growth

and authority of the burgher strata itself. Capitalism began to emerge

as a predominant economy feeding on the decomposing corpses of all

traditional status-oriented societies. It pandered to the vices of; a

decadent nobility, to the profligacy of a malignant court, to the

indulgent pretentions of the nouveau riches and it battened on the

misery of abandoned masses — peasants, laborers, guildsmen, and

lumpenproletarians — that feudalism had cast aside to fend for

themselves with the decline of the patronal system and its traditional

nexus of rights and duties. The good “burghers” of the declining feudal

world and the era of absolutism — the so-called “ nascent bourgeoisie” —

were no less status-oriented and later no less royalist than the

“classes” they were supposed to oppose and displace. T here is nothing

to show that these nascent bourgeois were capitalist in any unique sense

other than their desire to accumulate capital with a view toward buying

titles that would make them part of the nobility or acquire land that

would validate their noble status.

Nor is there much evidence that the nascent bourgeois had political

aspirations that “historically” pitted them against the traditional

status structures of the ancien regime. Quite to the contrary: their

hostility was mainly directed against the arrogance of the nobility,

against its exclusively, not against the principle of ennoblement and

oligarchy as such. Nor did the bourgeoisie exhibit any republican, much

less democratic, proclivities. Their detestation of the masses was no

less savage, indeed often more so, than that of the nobility, which

often included enlightened, urban individuals riddled by a sense of

guilt over their wealth and prerogatives. England, not America, was the

political ideal of the French bourgeoisie — a constitutional monarchy

structured around a collaborative aristocracy joined with a socially

mobile commercial and industrial middle class. Republicanism was almost

universally regarded by the Enlightenment as the door to political

license and democracy was simply equated with “anarchy,” a word that

speckled the vocabulary of the revolutionary politicians throughout the

1790s.

Radical historians’ emphasis on Paris during the French Revolution makes

it difficult to bring the revolution into a clear perspective. Paris was

the administrative center of the monarchy and the urban playground of

the French aristocracy, a city that harbored thriving financial

establishments that pandered to the court and family-owned workships

given over to the production of luxury goods. The real centers of French

bourgeois life, particularly the textile industry around which the

industrial revolution was to develop, were cities like Lyons and Amiens,

which, taken together with commercial centers like Bordeaux and major

seaports like Marseilles and Toulon, more accurately reflected the

bourgeois spirit of the revolutionary period than Paris, a magnet for

the more radical elements of the intelligentsia and the shabby quarters

and decaying slums occupied by a huge petit bourgeoisie composed of

professionals, shopkeepers, printers, artisans, and a socially amorphous

mass of day laborers and lumpenproletarians, the well-known sans

culottes.

All of these cities were bitterly anti-Jacobin and often militantly

royalist. The suppression of the Lyons sans-culottes in May, 1793, was

the work, in Lefebvre’s words, of “the bourgeoisie who had remained

monarchist” as well as partisans of the old order from other strata of

the population. “Amiens never become solidly republican, ” notes Lynn

Hart in her book on the political culture of the revolution. In fact, as

late as 1799, five years after the counterrevolutionary Thermidorians

had dispatched Robespierre and the Jacobins, the city was torn by

anti-conscription riots that resounded with such denunciations as “Down

with the Jacobins! Long live the King! Long live Louis XVIII!” Even the

stolid bourgeois Thermidoreans found Amiens an embarrassment. The

Girondist seaports and commercial towns of Marseilles and Toulon

repressed the Jacobins (by no means the most radical faction in the

revolution) with the same vigor that Paris repressed the Girondists.

Indeed, Toulon had become so royalist by 1793 that that city delivered

itself over to the English rather than submit to the authority of

revolutionary Paris.

The image of the French or, for that matter, of the English or American

revolutions as “bourgeois” is a simplistic projection of present-day

ideological biases onto the past.[1] It is not helpful simply to note

that the bourgeoisie benefited in the long run from these revolutions.

This tells us very little about the forces, motives, and ideals of the

revolutionary era — an era opened by English Puritans in the 1640s and

brought to a close by Spanish anarchosyndicalists in the 1930s. English

yeomen, American farmers, and, most notably, French peasants were the

immediate beneficiaries of these revolutions no less than the early

bourgeoisie. Doubtless, the bourgeoisie ultimately became the greatest

beneficiary of the revolutions, but complete supremacy came to it very

unevenly over the course of time and in a very mixed form. The

Jeffersonian “Revolution of 1800” was largely a political victory of

U.S. agrarian strata: the American bourgeoisie’s interests were more

directly tied to Hamilton’s self-styled “Federalist Party” than

Jefferson’s Republican Party, and political power in America as in

England — was held by the gentry, occasionally in direct conflict with

the financiers, merchants, and industrialists who were not to gain

complete control of the republic until the Reconstruction Era. To say,

as Hunt does, that the French Revolution placed the bourgeoisie in the

political saddle because the revolutionary officials... were either

merchants with capital, professionals with skills, artisans with their

own shops, or, more rarely, peasants with land” is to make a grab-bag of

the word “ bourgeois” — indeed, to use the word more in a feudal sense

as burghers than a modern sense, as capitalists. This kind of

“bourgeoisie” was in no sense a stable class but a pot pourri of highly

disparate strata that was unified more by what it was not — namely,

nobles and priests than what it seemed to be. It was simply the Third

Estate. To add, as Hunt does, that it was “anti-feudal, anti-aristocrat,

and anti-absolutists” is to raise the question of what constitutes an

authentic bourgeoisie. Presumably, not the industrialists of Amiens and

the merchants of Toulon — if Hunt is correct. Least of all the Parisian

Thermidorians who so willingly turned the French state over to Napoleon

who, in Lefebvre’s own words, became reconciled with the church,

pardoned the emigres, and took into his service all of those —

aristocrats and bourgeoisie, royalists and republicans — who were

willing to support him.”

The fact is that radical theoreticians decided to designate the

revolutions of the Enlightenment as bourgeois and to deal with

monarchial absolutism as preparatory for the emergence of a

predetermined capitalism. Perry Anderson was to treat absolutism as a

basically feudal phenomenon to support a very ill-founded theory of the

stages of history. This is teleology with a vengeance a teleology that

denies any spontaneity to history by nailing it to the hard and

splintered cross of necessity. That history can have meaning and

direction is vulgarized into a concept of historical natural law,

operating in hum an affairs with the grim causality that is imputed to

its operation in socially conditioned images of nature. Capitalism, in

effect, ceases to be a result of a social process and turns into its

very substance. The fact that capitalism is the most asocial and

malignant system to emerge in human experience is in great part the

result of decay in history rather than a product of the elaboration of

world history. It is a “social order” that flourishes cancerously on the

corpses of traditional societies. Today, the interaction between the

traditional centers of capitalism and the noncapitalist world differs

significantly from earlier periods, when the contact between the two was

more equitable. Like a metastatic cell, the commodity has done its work

and the doors of traditional societies have been flung wide open to

unrestricted exploitation.

This lengthy discussion of the so-called bourgeois revolutions,

capitalist development, and the distinction between status and class

societies has been guided not by any abstract concern for the historical

record but by explicitly political reasons. Regarding the English,

American, and French revolutions as “bourgeois” has been very harmful

politically, resulting in a highly economistic exploration of the

revolutionary era. George Rude, to take a case in point, has so closely

correlated fluctuations of the price of bread with crowd behavior in the

French Revolution that the sans culottes emerge more as stomachs than as

vital, politically concerned hum an beings. Charles Beard’s

well-intentioned treatment of the American Revolution is so biased by a

preoccupation with class interest that his insightful correction of

purely ideological historical accounts suffers heavily from a crude

economic determinism . Such swings of the pendulum may be necessary to

correct exaggerations of both accounts — a starry-eyed idealism at one

extreme and crude self-interest at the other — but they have gone too

far. That men like the English Leveller, John Lilburne, or the American

yeoman radical, Dan Shays, were concerned with larger social issues than

the cost of bread or farm foreclosures tends to be lost in a welter of

statistical data aimed at proving the predominance of material interests

over ideological and cultural ones. David P. Szatmar’s Shays’ Rebellion

points out that Shays and the yeomen who followed him into insurrection

in 1787 rose against the newly founded U.S. to preserve a complex way of

life, not merely to cow the Boston merchants who threatened to

dispossess them of their lands.

The sinister side of radical historiography has been explored

repeatedly. If history uses humanity to fulfill ends of its own, then

suffering, cruelty, and despotism can be justified in the name of

progress and ultimately freedom. Ideology, ethics, culture, politics —

and, of course, leaders — are moved to act beyond their own

understanding of events by Hegel’s “cunning of reason. Lenin, by

superadding the party and its political consciousness to the objective

movement of history — a history that has a foresight, lawfulness, and

goal of its own — did not deny this Hegelian concept of Spirit in

history. He merely bureaucratized Spirit with an apparatus of

self-anointed professional revolutionaries who consciously executed the

designs of history in the ultimate interests of the unknowing masses.

The result of this authoritarian logic was the usurpation of the Russian

Revolution by a party that professed to represent the objective

interests of the proletariat often in the very course of suppressing the

proletariat itself.

We have paid for this “materialism ” by suffocating every ethical and

humanist dimension in history. We have tallied up the statistics for

economic growth and productivity in “ socialist societies” in

juxtaposition with the statistics for mass murder and the formation of

entire populations of slave laborers to render our ultimate verdict on

the “success” or “failure” of these seemingly “socialist” institutions.

Freedom plays no role whatever in this tally. More than any modern

ideology other than fascism, socialism has traded off liberty for

“distributive justice” — an exchange that has poisoned its very image of

everything hum an, turning society itself into a mere machine for the

conquest of nature. What is most disconcerting today is the

interpretation and the politics stemming from this disastrous vision of

history. If the English, American, and French revolutions are not

bourgeois revolutions, what are they? If the classical revolutionary era

has come to an end, what kind of politics follows from this? Finally, if

the proletariat is not a revolutionary class, w hat is the “historical

subject” that will transform a hierarchical, and exploitative society

into one that is egalitarian, classless, and free?

Toward a New Radical Agenda

Capitalism is a system that is permanently counter-revolutionary —

Marx’s views to the contrary notwithstanding. Now here did it rescue or

advance the hum an spirit of cooperation that existed in the most

despotic societies and the most parochial communities of the past; at no

time did its sense of charity extend beyond a utilitarian manipulation

of the masses. Few of its material benefits, technical advances, or

wealth were used to better the hum an condition. Capitalism was a blight

on society from the moment it began to rise. Almost every attempt to

arrest the development of capitalism early on was more progressive than

the progressive role imputed to the bourgeois mode of production. The

Luddites were essentially right. They were not reactionary when they

tried to halt the rapacious advance of the Industrial Revolution. So too

were the Critical-Utopian socialists and communists, the Proudhonians

and Fourierists on whom Marx and Engels heaped their scorn in the

Communist Manifesto. Even the English gentry who wrote the Speenham land

Law of 1795 were right, however self-serving their motives, when they

tried to prevent the peasantry from being delivered wholesale over to

the wage system. And the Russian populists were right when they tried to

rescue the village, particularly its mutualistic features, from the

travail of capitalist industrialism.

The list is almost endless. In large part, it consists of the hidden

libertarian tendency in history that tried to provide an alternative to

Speenham land as well as the wage system, to backbreaking manual labor

as well as soul-corroding factory work, to parochialism as well as the

world market system. To think that present-day urban misery is the only

alternative to rural poverty is to fall into a trap that so paralyzes

creative thought and practice that radical theory can no longer

distinguish what is from what could be. Movements did exist that opposed

status societies as well as class societies, feudalism as well as

capitalism, technological stagnation as well as mindless technological

innovation. In the 20^(th) century, one thinks of Russia and Spain, the

populists and the anarchists, as striking examples of highly moral

social movements that tried to bypass capitalist development without

acceding to the oppressive features of autocratic and quasi-feudal

societies. The “third way” these movements offered was simply suppressed

— not only by the state (Stalinist and fascist) but by radical

historians themselves, whose history of the Left was often highly

selective and biased toward the conventional socialism of our time.

In any case, this much is clear: We must acknowledge the permanent,

retrogressive nature of capitalism from its very inception. We must see

it as a saprophytic system that is by definition asocial, and recognize

it as a mechanism that will die on its own only like a cancer that

destroys its host. We have to understand that the economic

interpretation of history and society is the extension of the bourgeois

spirit into the totality of the hum an condition. Capitalism will not

decay. It will either destroy society as we have known it, and possibly

much of the biosphere along with it, or it will be corroded, weakened,

and hollowed out by libertarian traditions. It would be difficult to

explain why the “ Fourth World” has offered such massive resistance to

the “ blessings” of industrialism unless we invoke the power of strong

traditions, entrenched lifeways, deeply held values, beliefs and custom

s. It would be difficult to explain why the Barcelona

proletarian-peasants burned money and disdained every lure of opulence

after the city fell into their hands without invoking the moral power of

their libertarian beliefs — a sensibility that was to often stand in

sharp contrast to the pragmatic mentality of their leaders.

The only revolutionary era on which we can premise any future for

radical change is the one that lies behind us. No cycle of socialist or

anarchist revolution will follow the so-called “bourgeois” cycle

initiated some three centuries ago. The arsenal of our time has

developed so far beyond the classical insurrectionary models on which

traditional radical theory has been fixated as to make unthinkable the

recurrence of another Spain or Russia. Indeed, no creative discussion of

a radical politics can even begin without acknowledging the change this

simple technical fact has introduced into the “art of insurrection” — to

use Trotsky’s words.

By the same token, the only agent on which we can premise future radical

change emerges from the melding of traditional groups into a public

sphere, a body politic, a community imbued with a sense of cultural and

spiritual continuity and renewal. This community, however, is

constituted only in the ever-present act of an ever-dynamic effort of

public and self-assertion that yields a sharp sense of selfhood.

Collectivity thus melds with individuality to produce rounded hum an

beings in a rounded society. Direct action assumes the form of direct

democracy: the participatory form s of freedom that rest on face-to-face

assemblies, rotation of public functions, and, where possible,

consensus.

Such a community must presume that solidarity outweights status or class

interests, that its way of life can absorb the centrifugal interests

that separate hum an from hum an, that a shared ethics imparts the

consciousness, conscience, and sympathy needed to override a sense of

selfhood that risks degenerating into selfishness and that preoccupation

with private concerns so characteristic o f the contemporary therapeutic

age. No proletariat has ever fit these standards of social and political

propriety as a class phenomenon. Indeed, class is so integrally tied up

with interest that it precludes the ability to voice broadly human

concerns. Hence, no possibility ever existed that the proletariat,

particularly the hereditary one that had a long tradition of class being

behind it, could ever speak for the general interest of society. It is

noteworthy that the individual, who is so readily conglomerated into a

class existence by radical historiography, tends to behave with greater

decency than the mass. The denial of the individual’s role in history

has had the sinister effect of denying the moral integrity of the person

in contrast to the role assigned to masses as forces in history and to

demolish the only arm or people have against the degrading effects of

“civilization” — the personal ethics, simple etiquette, psychological

uniqueness, and human intimacy of care and understanding that can

challenge monstrous excesses with personal, day-to-day resistance and

delegitimation.

This brings us back to what was not bourgeois in the so-called bourgeois

revolutions — the utopian dimension of hum an liberty, equality, and

fraternity that panicked the real bourgeois into Hamilton’s royalist

conspiracies in America and, finally, the dissolution of the republic

into Napoleonic autocracy in France. The American yeomanry and the

Parisian sans culottes did not rise against their rulers because they

were interested in freeing trade or fostering capital accumulation. They

rose to defend their own conception of a distinctly ethical ideal:

freedom from arbitrary authority, an intensely communal world that

fostered intercourse among their people, humaneness in dealing with

individuals irrespective of status and wealth, in fact, a return to the

regulation of commerce (as evidenced by the sans-culottes demands for

price controls and Shays’ belief in the yeomanry’s right to land

irrespective of legal entailments). By all standards of historical

materialism, they were reactionaries who believed in a moral economy and

tried to hang onto traditional rights and duties as they construed them

. To revolt meant literally to restore ancient liberties, communal

lifeways, and responsibilities. Insofar as these revolutions invariably

went beyond the privileged institutions of English constitutionalism,

they were no more bourgeois than the Bolshevik take-over was

proletarian. They were first and foremost republican or democratic

revolutions that were foisted on the bourgeoisie — a class that

vigorously resisted their libertarian features, The bourgeoisie did not

make these revolutions; it was saddled with them two centuries ago.

The tension between the revolutionary tradition to which even the

bourgeoisie must make its obeisances and the corporate reality that

stands at odds with it constitutes the greatest single obstacle to the

unrestrained supremacy of capital. Like the estates generale that

blocked the French monarchy in 1789, the bourgeoisie carries the

heritage of its beginnings on its shoulders like a lead weight. More

importantly, this alien heritage is also the mystique that lends moral

legitimacy to the bourgeoise’s otherwise colorless and prosaic reality.

The aversion of Americans for the state, their mythology of self-

sufficiency, local control, and individualism are at once the disguise

for bourgeois rapacity and the Damocles sword that hangs over the

bourgeoisie. The identification of family with the family-farm, of

individuality with property, of self-reliance with self-employment, of

liberty with local control, and tyranny with the state, conscription,

surveillance, and police intervention into politics — all limit the

capitalist enterprise in America and are as obstructive as they are

self-serving.

Thus, a strong argument can be made for the need to recognize the hidden

libertarian content of the American Dream: the possibility of

democratizing the republic and radicalizing the democracy. Herein lies a

radical agenda, rooted in the tension between corporatism and

republicanism , centralism and democracy, bourgeois society and a

libertarian society, that may create from the failed “perspectives” of

the past a new reading of the future. A new libertarian politics must

emerge from the debris of the classical Left. Politics in its original

sense presupposed a very distinct public sphere — the community, be it a

town, a neighborhood, or a city articulated into neighborhoods — in

which passive residents could be transformed into active citizens by

virtue of their direct access to the levers of power. Hence, politics

cannot be divorced from an operational scale that fosters it: the

community. Lacking this operational scale, it withers away, or worse, it

becomes transformed into parliamentarism and the delegation of all power

to professional politicians. Politics, so conceived, is municipalist or

it does not exist at all.

Municipalism is a politics structured around the assembly of the citizen

body, not its representatives. Collectively and individually, it must

acquire a sense of itself, its social personality, its form. It is a

politics that must not only involve citizens in communal administration;

it must also educate them in public life.

Politics, so conceived, is the communizing core of community, the

process of citizen-formation, the school in which character is developed

as well as the art of citizenship. It is the medium for expanding one’s

competence in the fully human sense of the term and not just in the

sense of skills in the performance of responsibilities.

The recreation of the polis has many aspects. Suffice it to say that an

ecological sensibility is fostered by the interdependence of a parent

and child, of children with each other and with adults, by production

conceived as a symbiotic relation, not a domineering one, with tools

that move with the grain of substance and its varied possibilities, not

by forcing them selves on “raw matter” and ruthlessly torturing it into

mere objects of utility. Finally, an ecological sensibility includes a

politics of creative citizenship that opens a new sphere for education

as well as administration, a politics of self-fulfillment and

solidarity.

Ultimately the democratization of the republic and the radicalization of

democracy is achievable only as a municipalist movement linked together

confederally in opposition to the centralized nation-state. Hence, it

will either move toward a radical form of libertarian municipalism or it

will degenerate into another form of liberal parliamentarism that will

end in the prevailing corporative politics. The contrast between

politics and parliamentarism, between the management of the polis and

statecraft, cannot be drawn too sharply. In this distinction, the role

of consciousness is decisive. Politics consists as much in the

attainment of self-reflexivity of goals and processes as it does in the

social functions it performs and the forms of freedom it

institutionalizes.

To this end, the polis must itself be created out of smaller units —

groups of people for whom the cultivation of consciousness is a calling

in its own right. Education within this grouping is both an effort to

realize the self-reflexivity that enters into an authentically creative

citizenship and the means of mobilizing people for a new praxis.

Self-reflexivity cannot be separated from selfadministration without

reducing the group to a cellular academy at one extreme or an affinity

group at the other. The formation of a collective subject that is not

burdened by authoritarian Bolshevism is thus attained in the crafting of

subjectivity as a participatory enterprise. Ultimately, this new radical

agenda is as meaningful as the force-field and confrontation it creates

between two powers: the centralized corporate state and the

decentralized municipalities.

If the dissolution of the state is not an imminent possibility, the

creation of a counterpower to it in the form of the libertarian

municipalist confederation is a reasonable possibility at some time in

the future. In any case, the problem of discriminating between politics

and statecraft, the nature of one’s participation in liberation

movements, and finally the distinction between the municipality and the

state itself, all pose problems that must be resolved with due regard

for the nature of capitalist development.

Capitalism is not a decaying social order; it is an ever-expanding order

that grows beyond the capacity of any society to contain its ravages and

cope with its predatory activities. If capitalism is not abolished in

one way or another, it will annihilate social life as such or, at least,

do an excellent job of undermining it and the biosphere on which all

life depends. The revolutions that we so facilely designate as

bourgeois, i.e., the revolutions that created enough social instability

to remove traditional constraints to capitalism’s growth, were not

cherished by the bourgeoisie. Rather, they saddled it with a heritage

that now constitutes a major obstacle to its complete and unchecked

dominance.

What appeals to Americans today is not the decorative side of their

dream but its authentically libertarian side. Ideology still counts

enough in the U.S. to bind a highly industrialized and increasingly

centralized society in the straitjacket of a largely agrarian,

individualistic, and still somewhat federal constitution with all the

traditions that support this imagery. Nationalized or even collectivized

property may be as onerous to most Americans as corporatized and

monopolistic property. The municipal control of economic resources, by

contrast, is much easier to accept. The current withdrawal of the

nation-state from involvement with localities, economically as well as

politically, poses the issue of municipal control more poignantly than

at any time in American history, and the public uneasiness that

accompanies the growth of state power is a desideratum in an

increasingly totalitarian world.

[1] Perez Zagorin scornfully deflates Eric Hobsbawm’s depiction of the

English Revolution as a “bourgeois revolution” resulting from a chronic

crisis within feudalism that forms the historical materialist correlate

of the “chronic crisis” within capitalism. What is wrong with Hobsbawn’s

thesis, Zagorin says, “is the absence of evidence that could demonstrate

the actuality of a general crisis in terms described.” The details of

Zagorin’s criticism are too numerous to repeat here. Nor is it possible

here to deal with the liberties Hobsbawn takes in dealing with

precapitalist movements, notably his atrocious treatment of Spanish

anarchosyndicalism in Primitive Rebels. Cf. Perez Zagorin, Rebels and

Rulers, 1500–1660 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982) and my

The Spanish Anarchists (New York: Harper and Row, 1977).