💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › jacques-camatte-the-wandering-of-humanity.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 11:12:57. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: The Wandering of Humanity
Author: Jacques Camatte
Date: 1973
Language: en
Topics: capitalism, class struggle, marxism
Source: Retrieved on December 3, 2009 from http://www.marxists.org/archive/camatte/wanhum/index.htm
Notes: Translation: Fredy Perlman. Published: In French in Invariance Année 6, Série II No. 3, 1973. Published in English by Black & Red (Detroit) in 1975. Transcription from the John Gray website. Markup by Rob Lucas, 2006. Public domain.

Jacques Camatte

The Wandering of Humanity

Original Black & Red Introduction

The essays included in the present work first appeared in the journal

Invariance (Année 6, Série II No. 3, 1973) with the titles, “Errance de

l’humanité; Conscience repressive; Communisme,” and “Declin du mode de

production capitaliste ou declin de l’humanité?” The author of these

essays, Jacques Camatte, worked with Amadeo Bordiga and the group of

Marxist theoreticians who were known as the Italian communist left.

After the events which took place in France in May of 1968, Camatte,

together with his comrades on Invariance, began a critical analysis of

the activities of the Italian communist left, the work of Bordiga as

well as the work of Marx. The title of the journal originally referred

to “the invariance of the theory of the proletariat,” the theory of the

League of Communists and the First International. By 1973 critics said

of this journal that “nothing varies more than Invariance.” Camatte and

his comrades, pursuing the critical analysis they had begun, were led to

conclude that “what is invariant is the aspiration to rediscover the

lost human community, and this cannot take place through a

reestablishment of the past, but only through new creation.” Their

theoretical quest led them to a complete rejection of the theory of

revolutionary parties and organizations, the theory of revolutionary

consciousness, the theory of the progressive development of productive

forces. “The French May movement showed that what is needed is a new

mode of living, a new life.” (The above quotations are from the last

article in Invariance No. 3, 1973.)

(...) The essays in the present work were translated from French by

Fredy Perlman with assistance from Camatte; the illustrations were

selected and prepared by Allan Foster; Lorraine Perlman and Judy

Campbell participated in the photography, printing and binding. (...)

I. Repressive Consciousness — Communism

1. Despotism of Capital

When capital achieves real domination over society, it becomes a

material community, overcoming value and the law of value, which survive

only as something “overcome.” Capital accomplishes this in two ways: 1)

the quantity of labor included in the product-capital diminishes

enormously (devalorization); 2) the exchange relation tends increasingly

to disappear, first from the wage relation, then from all economic

transactions. Capital, which originally depended on the wage relation,

becomes a despot. When there is value it is assigned by capital.

Capital is capital in process. It acquired this attribute with the rise

of fictive capital, when the opposition valorization/devalorization

still had meaning, when capital had not yet really overcome the law of

value.

Capital in process is capital in constant movement; it capitalizes

everything, assimilates everything and makes it its own substance.

Having become autonomous, it is “reified form” in movement. It becomes

intangible. It revitalizes its being — that vast metabolism which

absorbs ancient exchanges or reduces them to exchanges of a biological

type — by despoiling all human beings in their varied activities,

however fragmented these may be (this is why capital pushes human beings

to engage in the most diverse activities). It is humanity that is

exploited. More than ever the expression “exploitation of man by man”

becomes repulsive.

In its perfected state, capital is representation. Its rise to this

state is due to its anthropomorphization, namely to its capitalization

of human beings,[1] and to its supersession of the old general

equivalent, gold. Capital needs an ideal representation, since a

representation with substance inhibits its process. Gold, if it is not

totally demonetized, can no longer play the role of standard.

Capitalized human activity becomes the standard of capital, until even

this dependence on value and its law begin to disappear completely. This

presupposes the integration of human beings in the process of capital

and the integration of capital in the minds of human beings.

Capital becomes representation through the following historical

movement: exchange value becomes autonomous, human beings are

expropriated, human activity is reduced to labor, and labor is reduced

to abstract labor. This takes place when capital rises on the foundation

of the law of value. Capital becomes autonomous by domesticating the

human being. After analyzing-dissecting-fragmenting the human being,

capital reconstructs the human being as a function of its process. The

rupture of the body from the mind made possible the transformation of

the mind into a computer which can be programmed by the laws of capital.

Precisely because of their mental capacities, human beings are not only

enslaved, but turned into willing slaves of capital. What seems like the

greatest paradox is that capital itself reintroduces subjectivity, which

had been eliminated at the time of the rise of exchange value. All human

activity is exploited by capital. We can rephrase Marx’s statement,

“Labor, by adding a new value to the old one, at the same time maintains

and eternizes [capital]” [2] to say: all human activity “eternizes”

capital.

Capital as representation overcomes the old contradiction between

monopoly and competition. Every quantum of capital tends to become a

totality; competition operates between the various capitals, each of

which tends to become the totality. Production and circulation are

unified; the ancient opposition between use value and exchange value

loses its raison d’être. Besides, consumption is the utilization of not

only material products but mostly representations that increasingly

structure human beings as beings of capital and revitalize capital as

the general representation. Prices no longer have the function they had

in the period of formal domination of capital, when they were

representations of value; they become mere indices or signs of

representations of capital. Free goods are not impossible. Capital could

assign a specific quantity of its products to each programmed

individual; this quantity might depend on the required activity imposed

on this individual. Such a despotism would be more powerful than the

present one. Human beings would wish they had the money which had

“given” them free access to the diversity of products.

During its development capital always tended to negate classes. This has

finally been accomplished through the universalization of wage labor and

the formation — as a transitional stage — of what is called the

universal class, a mere collection of proletarianized men and women, a

collection of slaves of capital. Capital achieved complete domination by

mystifying the demands of the classical proletariat, by dominating the

proletarian as productive laborer. But by achieving domination through

the mediation of labor, capital brought about the disappearance of

classes, since the capitalist as a person was simultaneously

eliminated.[3] The State becomes society when the wage relation is

transformed into a relation of constraint, into a statist relation. At

the same time the State becomes an enterprise or racket which mediates

between the different gangs of capital.

Bourgeois society has been destroyed and we have the despotism of

capital. Class conflicts are replaced by struggles between the

gangs-organizations which are the varied modes of being of capital. As a

result of the domination of representation, all organizations which want

to oppose capital are engulfed by it; they are consumed by phagocytes.

It is the real end of democracy. One can no longer hold that there is a

class which represents future humanity, and a fortiori there is no

party, no group; there can be no delegation of power.

Advertising crassly reflects the fact that capital is representation,

that it survives because it is representation in the mind of each human

being (internalizing what was externalized). Advertising is the

discourse of capital:[4] everything is possible, all norms have

disappeared. Advertising organizes the subversion of the present for the

sake of an apparently different future.

“We now face the problem of letting the average American feel moral when

he flirts, when he spends, even when he buys a second or third car. One

of the basic problems of this prosperity is to give people sanction and

justification to enjoy it, to show them that making their lives a

pleasure is moral and not immoral. This permission given to the consumer

to freely enjoy life, this demonstration that he has a right to surround

himself with products that enrich his existence and give him pleasure,

should be one of the main themes of all advertising and of every project

designed to increase sales.”[5]

The disintegration of consciousness which can be seen in manifestations

like the women’s liberation movement, the gay liberation movement and

anti-psychiatry (which are only possible after the work of Freud, Reich,

and the feminist movement at the beginning of this century) is not part

of the simultaneous emergence of revolutionary consciousness, but only

reflects the end of bourgeois society based on value, on a fixed

standard which affected all levels of human life. The disintegration

began when the general equivalent conflicted with circulation. If the

former general equivalent gave way, it was lost. The State had to force

all subjects to respect a normalcy based on a standard which established

the values of society. The law of value imprisoned human beings, forcing

them into stereotypes, into fixed modes of being. The highest

development of morality appeared in Kant’s categorical imperative. By

engulfing the general equivalent, by becoming its own representation,

capital removed the prohibitions and rigid schemas. At that point human

beings are fixed to its movement, which can take off from the normal or

abnormal, moral or immoral human being.

The finite, limited human being, the individual of bourgeois society, is

disappearing. People are passionately calling for the liberated human

being, a being who is at once a social being and a Gemeinwesen. But at

present it is capital that is recomposing man, giving him form and

matter; communal being comes in the form of collective worker,

individuality in the form of consumer of capital. Since capital is

indefinite it allows the human being to have access to a state beyond

the finite in an infinite becoming of appropriation which is never

realized, renewing at every instant the illusion of total blossoming.

The human being in the image of capital ceases to consider any event

definitive, but as an instant in an infinite process. Enjoyment is

allowed but is never possible. Man becomes a sensual and passive voyeur,

capital a sensual and suprasensual being. Human life ceases to be a

process and becomes linear. Aspired by the process of capital, man can

no longer be “himself.” This aspiration evacuates him, creating a vacuum

which he must continually satisfy with representations (capital). More

generally, capital in process secures its domination by making every

process linear. Thus it breaks the movement of nature, and this leads to

the destruction of nature. But if this destruction might endanger its

own process, capital adapts itself to nature (by anti-pollution, for

example).

The non-living becomes autonomous — and triumphs. Death in life: Hegel

had intuited it, Nietzsche described it, Rainer Maria Rilke sang about

it, Freud almost institutionalized it (the death instinct), Dada

exhibited it as buffoon art, and the “fascists” exalted it: “Long live

death.” The U.S. feminist movement has individualized it:

“The male likes death — it excites him sexually and, already dead

inside, he wants to die.”[6]

The autonomy of form affects all aspects of life dominated by capital.

Knowledge is valid only if it is formalized, if it is emptied of

content. Absolute knowledge is tautology realized; it is dead form

deployed over all knowledge. Science is its systematization;

epistemology is its redundancy.

In the era of its real domination, capital has run away (as the

cyberneticians put it), it has escaped.[7] It is no longer controlled by

human beings. (Human beings in the form of proletarians might, at least

passively, represent a barrier to capital.) It is no longer limited by

nature. Some production processes carried out over periods of time lead

to clashes with natural barriers: increase in the number of human

beings, destruction of nature, pollution. But these barriers cannot be

theoretically regarded as barriers which capital cannot supersede. At

present there are three possible courses for the capitalist mode of

production (in addition to the destruction of humanity — a hypothesis

that cannot be ignored):

become simple accessories of an automated system, though still retaining

an executive role;

production of a perfectly programmable being which has lost all the

characteristics of the species Homo sapiens. This would not require an

automatized system, since this perfect human being would be made to do

whatever is required;

their present limitations, capital realizes everything they desire

(normal or abnormal), but human beings cannot find themselves and

enjoyment continually lies in the future. The human being is carried off

in the run-away of capital, and keeps it going.[8]

The result is ultimately the same: the evolution of the human being is

frozen, sooner in one case than in another. These possibilities are

abstract limits; in reality they tend to unfold simultaneously and in a

contradictory manner. To continue on its indefinite course, capital is

forced to call on the activity of human beings, to exalt their

creativity. And to secure its permanence, capital has to act quickly. It

runs into barriers of time and space which are linked to the decrease of

natural resources (which cannot all be replaced by synthetic

substitutes) and the mad increase of human population (which causes the

disappearance of numerous forms of life).

It becomes clear that raising the banner of labor or its abolition

remains on the terrain of capital, within the framework of its

evolution. Even the movement toward unlimited generalization of desire

is isomorphic to the indefinite movement of capital.

The capitalist mode of production is not decadent and cannot be

decadent. Bourgeois society disintegrated, to be sure, but this did not

lead to communism. At most we can say that communism was affirmed in

opposition to bourgeois society, but not in opposition to capital. The

run-away of capital was not perceived; in fact this run-away was

realized only with the rise of the fascist, Nazi, popular front

movements, the New Deal, etc., movements which are transitions from

formal to real domination. It was thought that communism was emerging

from the socialization of human activity and thus from the destruction

of private property, while in fact capital was emerging as a material

community.

2. Growth of Productive Forces; Domestication of Human Beings

The capitalist mode of production becomes decadent only with the

outbreak of effective revolution against capital. As of now, human

beings have been decaying for a century, they have been domesticated by

capital. This domestication is the source of the proletariat’s inability

to liberate humanity. Productive forces continue to grow, but these are

forces of capital.

“Capitalist production develops technique and the combination of the

social production process only by simultaneously using up the two

sources from which all wealth springs: the land and the laborer.”[9]

It makes no sense to proclaim that humanity’s productive forces have

stopped growing, that the capitalist mode of production has begun to

decay. Such views reveal the inability of many theoreticians to

recognize the run-away of capital and thus to understand communism and

the communist revolution. Paradoxically, Marx analyzed the decomposition

of bourgeois society and the conditions for the development of the

capitalist mode of production: a society where productive forces could

develop freely. What he presented as the project of communism was

realized by capital.

Man elaborated a dialectic of the development of productive forces.[10]

He held that human emancipation depended on their fullest expansion.

Communist revolution — therefore the end of the capitalist mode of

production — was to take place when this mode of production was no

longer “large enough” to contain the productive forces. But Marx is

trapped in an ambiguity. He thinks that the human being is a barrier to

capital, and that capital destroys the human being as a fetter to its

development as productive power. Marx also suggests that capital can

escape from the human barrier. He is led to postulate a self-negation of

capital. This self-negation takes the form of crises which he perceived

either as moments when capital is restructured (a regeneration carried

out by the destruction of products inhibiting the process: another

reason why capitalism must disappear), or as the actual moment when

capital is destroyed.

In other words, while providing the elements necessary for understanding

the real domination of capital over society, Marx did not develop the

concept; he did not recognize the run-away of capital. For Marx, gold

remained a barrier to capital, the contradiction between valorization

and devalorization remained in force, and the plunder and estrangement

of proletarians remained an obstacle to the evolution of capital.

“In the development of productive forces there comes a stage when

productive forces and means of intercourse are brought into being,

which, under the existing relationships, only cause mischief, and are no

longer productive but destructive forces (machinery and money)...”

(Before continuing the citation, we should mention the retardation of

those who proclaim that capital now develops only destructive forces. It

turns out that for Marx, in 1847, capital is destruction; he continued

to hold this view.)

“... and connected with this a class is called forth, which has to bear

all the burdens of society without enjoying its advantages, which,

ousted from society, is forced into the most decided antagonism to all

other classes; a class which forms the majority of all members of

society, and from which emanates the consciousness of the necessity of a

fundamental revolution, the communist consciousness, which may, of

course, arise among the other classes too through the contemplation of

the situation of this class.”[11]

The proletariat is the great hope of Marx and of the revolutionaries of

his epoch. This is the class whose struggle for emancipation will

liberate all humanity. Marx’s work is at once an analysis of the

capitalist mode of production and of the proletariat’s role within it.

This is why the theory of value and the theory of the proletariat are

connected, though not directly:

“The above application of the Ricardian theory, that the entire social

product belongs to the workers as their product, because they are the

sole real producers, leads directly to communism. But, as Marx indicates

too in the above-quoted passage, formally it is economically incorrect,

for it is simply an application of morality to economics. According to

the laws of bourgeois economics, the greatest part of the product does

not belong to the workers who have produced it. If we now say: that is

unjust, that ought not to be so, then that has nothing immediately to do

with economics. We are merely saying that this economic fact is in

contradiction to our sense of morality. Marx, therefore, never based his

communist demands upon this, but upon the inevitable collapse of the

capitalist mode of production which is daily taking place before our

eyes to an ever greater degree...”[12]

Marx did not develop a philosophy of exploitation, as Bordiga often

recalled. How will the capitalist mode of production be destroyed, and

what does the “ruin” consist of? (Engels, in 1884, provided arguments

for those who today speak of the decadence of capitalism.) This is not

specified. After Marx the proletariat was retained as the class

necessary for the final destruction, the definitive abolition of

capitalism, and it was taken for granted that the proletariat would be

forced to do this.

Bernstein grasped this aspect of Marx’s theory, and applied himself to

demonstrating that there were no contradictions pushing toward

dissolution.[13] But this led Bernstein to become an apologist for the

old bourgeois society which capital was about to destroy, especially

after 1913; consequently his work does not in any way clarify the

present situation.

Marx left us material with which to overcome the theory of value, and

also material necessary for overcoming the theory of the proletariat.

The two theories are related, and justify each other. In the Grundrisse,

Marx praises the capitalist mode of production, which he considers

revolutionary. What is not stated explicitly is that the proletariat has

this attribute to the extent that it carries out the internal laws of

capitalism. The proletariat is present in the analysis. Marx postulates

that the proletariat’s misery will necessarily push it to revolt, to

destroy the capitalist mode of production and thus to liberate whatever

is progressive in this mode of production, namely the tendency to expand

productive forces.

In Capital the proletariat is no longer treated as the class that

represents the dissolution of society, as negation at work. The class in

question here is the working class, a class which is more or less

integrated in society, which is engaged in revolutionary reformism:

struggle for wage increases, struggle against heavy work imposed on

women and children, struggle for the shortening of the working day.

At the end of the first volume, Marx explains the dynamic which leads to

the expropriation of the expropriators, to the increase of misery[14]

which will force the proletariat to rise against capital.[15]

In the third volume, and also in the Critique of the Gotha Programme,

Marx does not describe a real discontinuity between capitalism and

communism. Productive forces continue to grow. The discontinuity lies in

the fact that the goal of production is inverted (after the revolution;

i.e., the discontinuity is temporal). The goal ceases to be wealth, but

human beings. However, if there is no real discontinuity between

capitalism and communism, human beings must be wilfully transformed; how

else could the goal be inverted? This is Marx’s revolutionary reformism

in its greatest amplitude. The dictatorship of the proletariat, the

transitional phase (in the Grundrisse it is the capitalist mode of

production that constitutes this transitional phase: this is obviously

extremely relevant to the way we define communism today) is a period of

reforms, the most important being the shortening of the working day and

use of the labor voucher. What we should note here, though we cannot

insist on it, is the connection between reformism and dictatorship.

The proletariat seems to be needed to guide the development of

productive forces away from the pole of value toward the pole of

humanity. It may happen that the proletariat is integrated by capital,

but — and this is abused by various Marxists — crises destroy the

proletariat’s reserves and reinstate it into its revolutionary role.

Then the insurrection against capital is possible again.

Thus Marx’s work seems largely to be the authentic consciousness of the

capitalist mode of production. The bourgeoisie, and the capitalists who

followed, were able to express only a false consciousness with the help

of their various theories. Furthermore, the capitalist mode of

production has realized Marx’s proletarian project. By remaining on a

narrowly Marxist terrain, the proletariat and its theoreticians were

outflanked by the followers of capital. Capital, having achieved real

domination, ratifies the validity of Marx’s work in its reduced form (as

historical materialism). While German proletarians at the beginning of

this century thought their actions were destroying the capitalist mode

of production, they failed to see they were only trying to manage it

themselves. False consciousness took hold of the proletariat.

Historical materialism is a glorification of the wandering in which

humanity has been engaged for more than a century: growth of productive

forces as the condition sine-qua-non for liberation. But by definition

all quantitative growth takes place in the sphere of the indefinite, the

false infinite. Who will measure the “size” of the productive forces to

determine whether or not the great day has come? For Marx there was a

double and contradictory movement: growth of productive forces and

immiseration of proletarians; this was to lead to a revolutionary

collision. Put differently, there was a contradiction between

socialization of production and private appropriation.

The moment when the productive forces were to reach the level required

for the transformation of the mode of production was to be the moment

when the crisis of capitalism began. This crisis was to expose the

narrowness of this mode of production and its inability to hold new

productive forces, and thus make visible the antagonism between the

productive forces and the capitalist forms of production. But capital

has run away; it has absorbed crises and it has successfully provided a

social reserve for the proletarians. Many have nothing left to do but to

run on ahead: some say the productive forces are not developed enough,

others say they have stopped growing. Both reduce the whole problem

either to organizing the vanguard, the party, or resort to activities

designed to raise consciousness.

Development in the context of wandering is development in the context of

mystification. Marx considered mystification the result of a reversed

relation: capital, the product of the worker’s activity, appears to be

the creator. The mystification is rooted in real events; it is reality

in process that mystifies. Something is mystified even through a

struggle of the proletariat against capital; the generalized

mystification is the triumph of capital. But if, as a consequence of its

anthropomorphization, this reality produced by mystification is now the

sole reality, then the question has to be put differently. 1) Since the

mystification is stable and real, there is no point in waiting for a

demystification which would only expose the truth of the previous

situation. 2) Because of capital’s run-away, the mystification appears

as reality, and thus the mystification is engulfed and rendered

inoperative. We have the despotism of capital.

The assertion that the mystification is still operative would mean that

human beings are able to engage in real relations and are continually

mystified. In fact the mystification was operative once and became

reality. It refers to a historical stage completed in the past. This

does not eliminate the importance of understanding and studying it so as

to understand the movement which leads to the present stage of the

capitalist mode of production and to be aware of the real actors through

the ages.

Both the mystifying-mystified reality as well as the previously

mystified reality have to be destroyed. The mystification is only

“visible” if one breaks (without illusions about the limitations of this

break) with the representations of capital. Marx’s work is very

important for this break. But it contains a major flaw: it fails to

explain the whole magnitude of the mystification because it does not

recognize the run-away of capital.

Earlier, revolution was possible as soon as the mystification was

exposed; the revolutionary process was its destruction. Today the human

being has been engulfed, not only in the determination of class where he

was trapped for centuries, but as a biological being. It is a totality

that has to be destroyed. Demystification is no longer enough. The

revolt of human beings threatened in the immediacy of their daily lives

goes beyond demystification. The problem is to create other lives. This

problem lies simultaneously outside the ancient discourse of the

workers’ movement and its old practice, and outside the critique which

considers this movement a simple ideology (and considers the human being

an ideological precipitate).

3. Repressive Consciousness

Mystification does not only affect capitalist society but also affects

the theory of capitalism. Marxist theory elevated to the rank of

proletarian consciousness is a new form of consciousness: repressive

consciousness. We will describe some of its characteristics, leaving

aside the problem of determining whether or not all forms of

consciousness throughout history are repressive.

The object of repressive consciousness is the goal which it thinks it

controls. Since there is a gap between this goal and immediate reality,

this consciousness becomes theological and refines the differences

between the minimum or immediate program and the maximum, future, or

mediate program. But the longer the path to its realization, the more

consciousness makes itself the goal and reifies itself in an

organization which comes to incarnate the goal.

The project of this consciousness is to frame reality with its concept.

This is the source of all the sophisms about the divergence between

objective and subjective elements. It exists but it cannot be. And

precisely because of its inability to be, it has to negate and scorn

whatever is trying to emerge, to be.

In other words, it exists but it needs certain events to be real. Since

it is a product of the past it is refuted by every current event. Thus

it can only exist as a polemic with reality. It refutes everything. It

can survive only by freezing, by becoming increasingly totalitarian. In

order to operate it has to be organized: thus the mystique of the party,

of councils, and of other coagulations of despotic consciousness.

All direct action which does not recognize this consciousness (and every

political racket pretends to embody the true consciousness) is condemned

by it. Condemnation is followed by justification: impatience of those

who revolt, lack of maturity, provocation by the dominant class. The

picture is completed by litanies on the petit-bourgeois character of the

eternal anarchists and the utopianism of intellectuals or young people.

Struggles are not real unless they revive class consciousness; some go

so far as to wish for war, so that this consciousness will at last be

produced.

Theory has turned into repressive consciousness. The proletariat has

become a myth, not in terms of its existence, but in terms of its

revolutionary role as the class which was to liberate all humanity and

thus resolve all socio-economic contradictions. In reality it exists in

all countries characterized by the formal domination of capital, where

this proletariat still constitutes the majority of the population; in

countries characterized by the real domination of capital one still

finds a large number of men and women in conditions of 19^(th) century

proletarians. But the activity of every party and every group is

organized around the myth. The myth is their source. Everything begins

with the appearance of this class which is defined as the only

revolutionary class in history, or at least as the most revolutionary.

Whatever happened before is ordered as a function of the rise of this

class, and earlier events are secondary in relation to those lived or

created by the proletariat. It even defines conduct. Whoever is

proletarian is saved; one who is not must expiate the defect of

non-proletarian birth by various practices, going so far as to serve

terms in factories. A group achieves revolutionary existence only at the

moment when it is able to exhibit one or several “authentic”

proletarians. The presence of the man with calloused hands is the

guarantee, the certificate of revolutionary authenticity. The content of

the program defended by the group, its theory, even its actions, cease

to be important; all that matters is the presence or absence of the

“proletarian.” The myth maintains and revives the antagonism between

intellectual and manual. Many councilists make a cult of

anti-intellectualism which serves them as a substitute for theory and

justification. They can pronounce any idiocy; they’ll be saved; they’re

proletarians.

Just as it is thought by many that one who leaves the party thereby

ceases to be revolutionary, so it is considered impossible to be

revolutionary without claiming one’s proletarian position, without

taking on the virtues thought to be proletarian. The counter-revolution

ends at the mythical frontiers which separate the proletariat from the

rest of the social body. Any action is justified in the name of the

proletarian movement. One does not act because of a need to act, because

of hatred for capital, but because the proletariat has to recover its

class base. Action and thought are unveiled by intermediaries.

This is how, especially after 1945, the proletariat as revolutionary

class outlived itself: through its myth.

A historical study of proletarian revolutionary movements would shed

light on the limited character of this class. Marx himself clearly

exposed its reformist character. Fundamentally, from 1848, when it

demanded the right to work, to 1917–1923, when it demanded full

employment and self-management by workers’ unions, the proletariat

rebelled solely within the interior of the capitalist system. This seems

to conflict with Marx’s statements in his “Critical Notes on the Article

‘The King of Prussia and Social Reform.’ By a Prussian”. But at this

moment the proletariat really manifested itself as a class without

reserves, as a total negation. It was forced to create a profound

rupture which makes possible an understanding of what communist

revolution and therefore communism can be.[16] Marx was right; but the

capitalist mode of production, in order to survive, was forced to

annihilate the negation which undermined it. The proletariat which is

outside of society, as Marx and Engels say in The German Ideology, is

increasingly integrated into society; it is integrated to the extent

that it struggles for survival, for reinforcement; the more it organizes

itself, the more it becomes reformist. It succeeds, with the German

Socialist Party, in forming a counter-society which is finally absorbed

by the society of capital, and the negating movement of the proletariat

is over.[17]

Didn’t Kautsky, Bernstein and Lenin simply recognize the reality of the

workers’ movement when they declared that it was necessary to unite it

with the socialist movement: “The workers’ movement and socialism are in

no way identical by nature” (Kautsky)?

Doesn’t Lenin’s discredited statement that the proletariat, left to

itself, can only attain trade-union consciousness, describe the truth

about the class bound to capital? It can be criticized only from the

standpoint of the distinction, made by Marx in The Poverty of

Philosophy, between class as object of capital and class as subject.

Without a revolutionary upheaval the proletariat cannot become a

subject. The process through which it was to become a subject implied an

outside, external consciousness, which at a given moment would become

incarnated in the proletariat. This consciousness coming from the

outside is the most reified, the most estranged form of repressive

consciousness! Consequently, the point is not to rehash the debate and

return to Marx, but to recognize that the cycle of the proletarian class

is now over, first of all because its goals have been realized, secondly

because it is no longer the determinant in the global context. We have

reached the end of the historical cycle during which humanity

(especially the part situated in the West) moved within class societies.

Capital has realized the negation of classes — by means of

mystification, since it retains the conflicts and collisions which

characterize the existence of classes. The reality is the despotism of

capital. It is capital we must now face, not the past.

Almost all social democrats were aware of the divorce between the real,

reformist movement of the working class and the socialist goal.

Bernstein proclaimed that it was necessary to adapt once and for all,

clearly and straightforwardly, not hypocritically (like the majority of

the socialists) by making revolutionary proclamations in order to hide

compromises.[18] At the same time, it became increasingly problematic to

define and delimit the proletarian class. This problem became so acute

that by the beginning of this century almost all revolutionaries were

trying to define the proletariat in terms of consciousness: Luxemburg,

Pannekoek directly, Lenin, Trotsky indirectly through the party, etc.

The Russian revolution merely increased the urgency of specifying the

proletarian class; this is the context of Korsch’s attempts, and

especially of Lukacs’ History and Class Consciousness. Later on Bordiga

held that the class should be defined in terms of the mode of production

which it builds. Thus it can be a class for itself only from the moment

when its actions move toward this goal, only to the extent that it

recognizes its program (which describes this mode of production). For

Bordiga, it exists when the party exists, because the program can only

be carried by the party. “We still need an object, the party, to

envision the communist society.”[19] But to the extent that men and

women are able to move on their own toward communism, as is evident

among young people today, it becomes obvious that this object, the

party, is not needed.

In sum, for party as well as council advocates, the problem of action

would largely be reduced to finding a direct or indirect means for

making the proletariat receptive to its own consciousness — since in

this view the proletariat is itself only through its consciousness of

itself.

4. Communism

Revolutionary reformism — the project of creating socialism on the

foundation of capitalism and in continuity with the capitalist mode of

production — disintegrated between 1913 and 1945. It is the end of what

turned out to be an illusion: the illusion of being able to direct the

development of the productive forces in a direction which differed from

the one they had taken in reality. We can actually agree with Marx’s

view that after 1848 communism was possible precisely because the

irruption of the capitalist mode of production had broken all social and

natural barriers and made free development possible. But the mentality,

the representations of people were such that they could neither concieve

nor perceive such a future. They were too dependent on the millenarian

movement of value, or they were too debilitated by the limitations of

the perverted remains of their ancient communities, to be able to set

out on a new path to reach another community. Even Marx and Engels

ultimately considered capitalism a necessary moment, and thought that

all human beings everywhere would inevitably come to experience it. Only

the revolts of the Russian populists, and their desire to avoid the

capitalist road, made Marx understand his error. But this recognition

was insufficient. From the middle of the 19^(th) century, with the

justification provided by Marxist theory (the theory of the

proletariat), all humanity set out to wander: to develop productive

forces.

If we can no longer accept Marx’s theoretical analysis of the role of

the productive forces, we can nevertheless agree with him after a

detour. Capital enslaves humanity in the very name of humanity because

it is anthropomorphized. This is nothing other than the reign of death.

Human beings are dominated by their past being, while they contemplate

it. It is a process which continually starts over again. Capital

penetrates thought, consciousness, and thus destroys human beings such

as they have been produced by centuries of class society. Their loss of

substance is the loss of their former being, which capital has pumped

out of them. Since this process is almost over, capital is now turning

from its attack against the past dimension of humanity to an attack

against its future dimension: it must now conquer imagination. The human

being is thus despoiled and tends to be reduced to the biological

dimension. The phenomenon reaches the roots. In other words, the

development of productive forces appears to have been necessary for the

destruction of old schemas, modes of thought, archaic representations

which limited human beings (this destruction is now being analyzed by

philosophers like Foucault). Threatened in their purely biological

existence, human beings are beginning to rise against capital. It is at

this point that everything can be re-conquered by generalized creation.

But this becoming is not simple, unilinear. Capital can still profit

from the creativity of human beings, regenerating and resubstantializing

itself by plundering their imaginations. The importance and profundity

of the struggle can be grasped in the face of the alternative: communism

or destruction of the human species. And it should not be forgotten that

during the wandering various revolutionary movements looked for an exit

and various possibilities were blocked; they can now manifest

themselves.[20]

We have to stop wandering and destroy the repressive consciousness which

inhibits the emergence of communism. To do this we have to stop

perceiving communism as a prolongation of the capitalist mode of

production, and stop thinking it is enough to suppress exchange value

and make use value triumphant. This dichotomy no longer signifies

anything. Use value is tied to value even if it revolves around the

principle of utility instead of productivity; related to the direct

domination of human beings, it is inseparable from private property.

Communism is not a new mode of production[21] ; it is the affirmation of

a new community. It is a question of being, of life, if only because

there is a fundamental displacement: from generated activity to the

living being who produced it. Until now men and women have been

alienated by this production. They will not gain mastery over

production, but will create new relations among themselves which will

determine an entirely different activity.

Nor is communism a new society.[22] Society grows out of the subjugation

of some ethnic groups by others, or out of the formation of classes.

Society is the network of social relations which quickly become despotic

intermediaries. Man in society is man enslaved by society.

Communism puts an end to castes, classes and the division of labor (onto

which was grafted the movement of value which in turn animates and

exalts this division). Communism is first of all union. It is not

domination of nature but reconciliation, and thus regeneration of

nature: human beings no longer treat nature simply as an object for

their development, as a useful thing, but as a subject (not in the

philosophic sense) not separate from them if only because nature is in

them. The naturalization of man and the humanization of nature (Marx)

are realized; the dialectic of subject and object ends.

What follows is the destruction of urbanization and the formation of a

multitude of communities distributed over the earth. This implies the

suppression of monoculture, another form of division of labor, and a

complete transformation of the transportation system: transportation

will diminish considerably. Only a communal (communitarian) mode of life

can allow the human being to rule his reproduction, to limit the (at

present mad) growth of population without resorting to despicable

practices (such as destroying men and women).

The domination of one group over another, the society of classes,

originates in the sedentarization of the human being. We still live with

the myths generated at the time of this fixation somewhere in our

mother-earth: myths of the homeland, the foreigner; myths which limit

the vision of the world, which mutilate. It is obvious that the reaction

cannot be a return to a nomadism of a type practiced by our distant

ancestors who were gatherers. Men and women will acquire a new mode of

being beyond nomadism and sedentarism. Sedentary lives compounded by

corporeal inactivity are the root cause of almost all the somatic and

psychological illnesses of present-day human beings. An active and

unfixed life will cure all these problems without medicine or

psychiatry.

The passage to communism implies a transformation of technique.

Technology is not a neutral thing; it is determined by the mode of

production. In the West, more than elsewhere, the various modes of

production increasingly separated human beings from technology, which

was originally no more than a modality of human being. The call for a

convenient technology is a call for a technology which is again a

prolongation of the human being and not an autonomous thing at the

service of an oppressive being.[23]

Human beings in communism cannot be defined as simple users; this would

be communism conceived as a terestrial paradise where people dispose of

what there is with such immediacy that human beings are

indistinguishable from nature (man, as Hegel said in this context, would

be an animal). Human beings are creators, producers, users. The entire

process is reconstituted at a higher level, and for every individual. In

relations between individuals, the other is no longer considered in

terms of utility; behavior in terms of utility ends. The sexes are

reconciled while retaining their differences; they lose the differences

and rigid oppositions produced by millenia of antagonism.

These few characteristics should adequately clarify how the movement of

ascent to the human community can be conceived.

We are all slaves of capital. Liberation begins with the refusal to

perceive oneself in terms of the categories of capital, namely as

proletarian, as member of the new middle class, as capitalist, etc. Thus

we also stop perceiving the other — in his movement toward liberation —

in terms of those same categories. At this point the movement of

recognition of human beings can begin. This is obviously only the

beginning of the liberation movement, and is continually threatened with

failure. Refusing to take this into account denies the power of capital.

What has to be perceived is a dynamic. We are slaves; our goal is not to

become masters, even without slaves, but to abolish the entire dialectic

of master and slave. This goal cannot be realized by the establishment

of communities which, always isolated, are never an obstacle to capital,

can easily be surrounded by capital, and are no more than deviations in

relation to its norm (deviations which make that norm visible for what

it is). Nor can the goal be reached by the cultivation of one’s

individual being, in which one would finally find the real human being.

In reality these approaches should be connected. Perceiving oneself as a

human being unshackled by any attributes already removes the dog collar

imposed by class society. The desire for community is absolutely

necessary. The reaffirmation of individuality (especially in its

temporal aspect) is a rejection of domestication. But this is inadequate

even as a first element of rebellion; the human being is an

individuality and a Gemeinwesen. The reduction of the human being to his

present inexpressive state could take place only because of the removal

of Gemeinwesen, of the possibility for each individual to absorb the

universal, to embrace the entirety of human relations within the

entirety of time. The varied religions, philosophies and theories are

mere substitutes for this essential component of human being. Since

communism is the death of sameness, of repetition, human beings will

emerge in all their diversity; Gemeinwesen will be affirmed by each.

This implies that as of now we reject the despotism of a religion, a

philosophy, a theory.

The refusal to be trapped by a theory is not a rejection of all

theoretical reflection. It is just the opposite. But this refusal does

postulate that the theoretical act is insufficient. Theory can call for

the reconciliation of senses and brain but it remains within the

boundaries of this separation. What must be affirmed is the whole of

life, the entirety of its manifestations, the whole unified being. It

may still be necessary to proceed with the help of Marx’s insights, for

example, but it becomes increasingly imbecile to proclaim oneself a

Marxist. Furthermore, like repressive consciousness, theory can become a

simple alibi for inaction. At the start, the refusal to act might be

perfectly justifiable. Nevertheless, separation from reality often leads

to failure to perceive new phenomena which shape it. At that point

theory, instead of helping establish contact with reality, becomes an

agent of separation, of removal, and in the end is transformed into a

protrusion, an ejection from the world. Waiting is particularly

difficult for those who do not want to recognize that others can arrive

at theory without us, our group, or our party as intermediaries. Theory,

like consciousness, demands objectification to such an extent that even

an individual who rejects political rackets can elevate theory to the

status of a racket. In a subject posing as revolutionary, theory is a

despotism: everyone should recognize this.

After the domination of the body by the mind for more than two millenia,

it is obvious that theory is still a manifestation of this domination.

It is the whole of life that becomes determining. All the varied

productions of the past — art, philosophy, science — are fragments. They

are elements of the vast despoliation of human beings as well as

attempts to remedy it. But the point is no longer to realize art or

philosophy; capital has already done this in its way; the point is to

conquer and create another world: a world where all the biological

potentialities of the species can finally develop. In this vast

movement, it is futile to want to present oneself as the repository of

truth. First of all truth, like value, needs a measure, a standard, a

general equivalent, a norm, hence a State. Secondly, truth is never more

than one truth. The historical inflation of this concept parallels the

ever more thorough destruction of human beings. Nothing less can be

proposed than another life where the gestures, the words, the

imaginations and all the feelings of human beings will no longer be

chained, where senses and brain will unite — only this union can

eliminate all the fixations of madness. It is obvious that all this can

only be conquered by the destruction of the capitalist mode of

production. It is all of humanity perceived through time that is hostile

to capital. Human beings will have to undergo a profound

revolutionization to be able to oppose capital; the actions of this

movement are accompanied by the production of revolutionaries.

The emergence of revolution in all the domains of our lives leads some

people to overemphasize the places where they felt this emergence.

Revolution does not emerge from one or another part of our being — from

body, space or time. Our revolution as a project to reestablish

community was necessary from the moment when ancient communities were

destroyed. The reduction of communist revolution to an uprising which

was to resolve the contradictions posed by the capitalist mode of

production was pernicious. Revolution has to resolve all the old

contradictions created by the class societies absorbed by capital, all

the contradictions between relatively primitive communities and the

movement of exchange value currently being absorbed by the movement of

capital (in Asia and especially in Africa). Beyond this, the

revolutionary movement is the revolution of nature, accession to

thought, and mastery of being with the possibility of using the

prefrontal centers of the brain which are thought to relate to the

imagination. Revolution has a biological and therefore cosmic dimension,

considering our universe limited (to the solar system); cosmic also in

the meaning of the ancient philosophers and mystics. This means that

revolution is not only the object of the passion of our epoch, but also

that of millions of human beings, starting with our ancient ancestors

who rebelled against the movement of exchange value which they saw as a

fatality, passing through Marx and Bordiga who, in their dimension as

prophets, witnessed this inextinguishable passion to found a new

community, a human community. Wanting to situate the revolution is like

wanting to fix its height. Saint-Just said that revolution could not

stop until happiness was realized, thus showing the falsity of wanting

to judge men in terms of the purely historical-material facts of a given

epoch. The human being is never a pure being-there. He can only be by

superseding and he cannot be only that which has to be superseded

(Nietzsche). Structurally and biologically man is a supersession because

he is an overpowerful being. In other words, human beings are explorers

of the possible and are not content with the immediately realizable,

especially if it is imposed on them. They lose this passion, this thirst

for creation — for what is the search for the possible if not invention?

— when they are debased, estranged, cut off from their Gemeinwesen and

therefore mutilated, reduced to simple individuals. It is only with the

real domination of the capitalist mode of production that the human

being is completely evacuated.

All the revolutions of the species are revolutions which try to go

beyond the present moment, beyond what is permitted by the development

of productive forces (Bordiga). This reach beyond the possible is what

constitutes the continuity among the human generations, just as the

perspective of communism conceived as the destruction of classes,

exchange, and value constitutes the continuity among the varied

revolutionaries; this is what, following Marx, we call the historical

party.[24]

The struggle against reduction of the amplitude of the revolution is

already a revolutionary struggle. The reader should not be astonished if

to support this amplitude we refer to authors classically tagged

religious, mystical, etc. What matters is the reappropriation of

Gemeinwesen (and past beings are part of it), which can only be done

after the unification of the species, and this unification can only be

conceived by grasping the aspiration, desire, passion and will for

community expressed through the ages. The human being can simultaneously

be a Gemeinwesen only if humanity lives in community. As soon as

fragmentation appears, the need to recompose a unity emerges. In the

West this unity had a mediate and coercive form: the individual was

defined by the State; knowledge was a means for hierarchization and for

justification of the established order; the vicious circle of

practice-theory emerged.

Communist revolution is complete revolution. Biological, sexual, social,

economic revolutions are no more than partial attributes; the

predominance of one is a mutilation of revolution, which can only be by

being all.

Communist revolution can be conceived only if it is grasped through the

history and paleontology of human beings as well as all other living

beings. By grasping this we become aware that, if this revolution has

long been necessary, it can now be realized. Earlier it was possible but

not unavoidable. There were still other “human” paths in that they still

allowed a human development; specifically, they allowed the

externalization of human powers. Now almost everything has been

externalized and plundered by capital, which describes the only path

other than communist revolution: the total negation of human beings.

Therefore we must understand our world; we must understand the despotism

of capital and the movement of rebellion breaking out against it. This

act of understanding which is taking place not only intellectually but

also sensually (the rebellion is to a large extent bodily rebellion) can

only be reached by rejecting the wandering and the repressive

consciousness.

II. Decline of the Capitalist Mode of Production or Decline of

Humanity?

It has often been thought and written that communism would blossom after

the destruction of the capitalist mode of production, which would be

undermined by such contradictions that its end would be inevitable. But

numerous events of this century have unfortunately brought other

possibilities into view: the return to “barbarism,” as analyzed by R.

Luxemburg and the entire left wing of the German workers’ movement, by

Adorno and the Frankfurt School; the destruction of the human species,

as is evident to each and all today; finally a state of stagnation in

which the capitalist mode of production survives by adapting itself to a

degenerated humanity which lacks the power to destroy it. In order to

understand the failure of a future that was thought inevitable, we must

take into account the domestication of human beings implemented by all

class societies and mainly by capital, and we must analyze the

autonomization of capital.

We do not intend to treat these historical deviations exhaustively in a

few pages. By commenting on a passage in Marx’s Grundrisse we can show

that it is possible to understand the autonomization of capital on the

basis of Marx’s work, and we can also see the contradictions in Marxist

thought and its inability to solve the problem. The passage is from the

chapter on the process of circulation. To understand it, we should keep

in mind what Marx had said shortly before this passage:

“Circulation time thus appears as a barrier to the productivity of

labour = an increase in necessary labour time = a decrease in surplus

labour time = a decrease in surplus value = an obstruction, a barrier to

the self-realization process [Selbstverwertungsprozess] of capital.”[25]

Here Marx makes an extremely important digression:

“There appears here the universalizing tendency of capital, which

distinguishes it from all previous stages of production and thus becomes

the presupposition of a new mode of production, which is founded not on

the development of the forces of production for the purpose of

reproducing or at most expanding a given condition, but where the free,

unobstructed, progressive and universal development of the forces of

production is itself the presupposition of society and hence of its

reproduction; where advance beyond the point of departure is the only

presupposition.”[26]

What makes capital a barrier is not stated here, whereas its

revolutionary, positive aspect is emphasized (this aspect is emphasized

on many other pages of the Grundrisse, and of Capital): the tendency

toward universal development of the forces of production. However, and

this is what interests us here, capital cannot realize this; it will be

the task of another, superior mode of production. The future of society

here takes the form of an indefinite, cumulative movement.

“This tendency — which capital possesses, but which at the same time,

since capital is a limited form of production, contradicts it and hence

drives it towards dissolution — distinguishes capital from all earlier

modes of production, and at the same time contains this element, that

capital is posited as a mere point of transition.[27]

Hence capital is driven towards dissolution by this contradiction. It is

a pity that Marx did not here mention what he understands by “limited

form of production,” since this keeps us from “seeing” clearly what he

means by contradiction in this specific case. This conditions the

understanding of the statement that the capitalist mode of production is

a transitory form of production. Even without an explanation of the

contradiction, we can understand it as follows: the capitalist mode of

production is not eternal — Marx’s polemical argument against the

bourgeois ideologues. This is the content of his main statements. But

another argument is embedded in the preceding one: the capitalist mode

of production is revolutionary and makes possible the passage to

another, superior social form where human beings will no longer be

dominated by the sphere of necessity (the sphere of the production of

material life) and where alienation will cease to exist.

Today, after the blossoming of Marxism as a theory of development,

another part of this sentence appears basic: there is a continuum

between the two periods. What is a transition if not the opposite of a

break? This continuum consists of the development of the forces of

production. From which follows the shameful but real relationship:

Marx-Lenin-Stalin! But this is not our topic. Our aim is to determine

what constitutes the productive forces and for whom they exist,

according to Marx in the Grundrisse.

“All previous forms of society — or, what is the same, of the forces of

social production — foundered on the development of wealth.”[28]

Wealth resides in the productive forces and in the results of their

action. There is a contradiction here which, according to Marx,

characterizes the totality of human history: wealth is necessary and

therefore sought, but it destroys societies. Societies must therefore

oppose its development. This is not the case in the capitalist mode of

production (it thus destroys all other social formations), which exalts

the productive forces, but for whom?

“Those thinkers of antiquity who were possessed of consciousness

therefore directly denounced wealth as the dissolution of the community

[Gemeinwesen]. The feudal system, for its part, foundered on urban

industry, trade, modern agriculture (even as a result of individual

inventions like gunpowder and the printing press). With the development

of wealth — and hence also new powers and expanded intercourse on the

part of individuals — the economic conditions on which the community

[Gemeinwesen] rested were dissolved, along with the political relations

of the various constituents of the community which corresponded to those

conditions: religion, in which it was viewed in idealized form (and both

[religion and political relations] rested in turn on a given relation to

nature, into which all productive force resolves itself); the character,

outlook, etc. of the individuals. The development of science alone —

i.e. the most solid form of wealth, both its product and its producer —

was sufficient to dissolve these communities. But the development of

science, this ideal and at the same time practical wealth, is only one

aspect, one form in which the development of the human productive

forces, i.e. of wealth, appears. Considered ideally, the dissolution of

a given form of consciousness sufficed to kill a whole epoch. In

reality, this barrier to consciousness corresponds to a definite degree

of development of the forces of material production and hence of wealth.

True, there was not only a development on the old basis, but also a

development of this basis itself.”[29]

For Marx, the productive forces are human (from the human being) and

they are for the human being, for the individual. Science as a

productive force (thus also wealth, as was already shown in the 1844

Manuscripts and in The German Ideology) is determined by the development

of these forces and corresponds to the appearance of a large number of

externalizations, a greater possibility to appropriate nature. Even if

it takes an ambiguous form, the blossoming of the human being is

possible; it is the moment when, in the development of the dominant

class, individuals can find a model of a fuller life. For Marx, the

capitalist mode of production, by pushing the development of productive

forces, makes possible a liberating autonomization of the individual.

This is its most important revolutionary aspect.

“The highest development of this basis itself (the flower into which it

transforms itself; but it is always this basis, this plant as flower;

hence wilting after the flowering and as a consequence of the flowering)

is the point at which it is itself worked out, developed, into the form

in which it is compatible with the highest development of the forces of

production, hence also the richest development of the individuals. As

soon as this point is reached, the further development appears as decay,

and the new development begins from a new basis.”[30]

There is decay because the development of individuals is blocked. It is

not possible to use this sentence to support the theory of the decline

of the capitalist mode of production[31] since it would have to be

stated that the decline started, not at the beginning of this century,

but minimally in the middle of the previous century; or else it would

have to be shown that the decline of individuals is simultaneously the

decline of capital, which contradicts what can be observed; Marx himself

repeatedly explained that the development of capital was accompanied by

the destruction of human beings and of nature.

When did the development of productive forces accompany the development

of individuals in different societies? When was the capitalist mode of

production revolutionary for itself and for human beings? Do the

productive forces advance continually, in spite of moments when

individuals decay? Marx said: “... the further development appears as

decay...” Do the productive forces stagnate; does the capitalist mode of

production decay?[32]

The remainder of Marx’s digression confirms that the decay refers to

human beings. Individuals blossom when the productive forces allow them

to develop, when the evolution of one parallels the evolution of the

other. By means of a comparison with the pre-capitalist period, Marx

shows that capital is not hostile to wealth but, on the contrary, takes

up its production. Thus it takes up the development of productive

forces. Previously the development of human beings, of their community,

was opposed to the development of wealth; now there is something like

symbiosis between them. For this to happen, a certain mutation was

necessary: capital had to destroy the limited character of the

individual; this is another aspect of its revolutionary character.

“We saw earlier that property in the conditions of production was

posited as identical with a limited, definite form of the community

[Gemeinwesen], hence of the individual with the characteristics —

limited characteristics and limited development of his productive forces

— required to form such a community [Gemeinwesen]. This presupposition

was itself in turn the result of a limited historic stage of the

development of the productive forces, of wealth as well as the mode of

creating it. The purpose of the community [Gemeinwesen], of the

individual — as well as the condition of production — is the

reproduction of these specific conditions of production and of the

individuals, both singly and in their social groupings and relations —

as living carriers of these conditions. Capital posits the production of

wealth itself and hence the universal development of the productive

forces, the constant overthrow of its prevailing presuppositions, as the

presupposition of its reproduction. Value excludes no use value; i.e.

includes no particular kind of consumption etc., of intercourse etc. as

absolute condition; and likewise every degree of the development of the

social forces of production, of intercourse, of knowledge etc. appears

to it only as a barrier which it strives to overpower.”[33]

This passage has momentous consequences. There is no reference to the

proletariat; it is the revolutionary role of capital to overthrow the

prevailing presuppositions. Marx had already said this, in a more

striking manner:

“It is destructive towards all of this, and constantly revolutionizes

it, tearing down all the barriers which hem in the development of the

forces of production, the expansion of needs, the all-sided development

of production, and the exploitation and exchange of natural and mental

forces.”[34]

We are forced to take a new approach toward the manner in which Marx

situated the proletarian class in the context of the continual upheaval

carried out by the capitalist mode of production. What is immediately

evident is that the capitalist mode of production is revolutionary in

relation to the destruction of ancient social relations, and that the

proletariat is defined as revolutionary in relation to capital. But it

is at this point that the problem begins: capitalism is revolutionary

because it develops the productive forces; the proletariat cannot be

revolutionary if, after its revolution, it develops or allows a

different development of the productive forces. How can we tangibly

distinguish the revolutionary role of one from that of the other? How

can we justify the destruction of the capitalist mode of production by

the proletariat? This cannot be done in a narrowly economic context.

Marx never faced this problem because he was absolutely certain that the

proletarians would rise against capital. But we have to confront this

problem if we are going to emerge from the impasse created by our

acceptance of the theory according to which the production relations

come into conflict with the development of the productive forces (forces

which were postulated to exist for the human being, since if this were

not the case, why would human beings rebel?) If the productive forces do

not exist for human beings but for capital, and if they conflict with

production relations, then this means that these relations do not

provide the proper structure to the capitalist mode of production, and

therefore there can be revolution which is not for human beings (for

example, the general phenomenon which is called fascism). Consequently

capital escapes. In the passage we are examining, Marx makes a

remarkable statement about the domination of capital:

“Its own presupposition — value — is posited as product, not as a

loftier presupposition hovering over production.”[35]

Capital dominates value. Since labor is the substance of value, it

follows that capital dominates human beings. Marx refers only indirectly

to the presupposition which is also a product: wage labor, namely the

existence of a labor force which makes valorization possible:

“The barrier to capital is that this entire development proceeds in a

contradictory way, and that the working-out of the productive forces, of

general wealth etc., knowledge etc., appears in such a way that the

working individual alienates himself [sich entaussert]; relates to the

conditions brought out of him by his labor as those not of his own but

of an alien wealth and of his own poverty.”[36]

How can this be a limit for capital? One might suppose that

under-consumption by the workers causes crises, and the final crisis.

This is one possibility; at least it appears that way at certain times.

Marx always refused to ground a theory of crises on this point, but this

did not keep him from mentioning this under-consumption. For Marx

capital has a barrier because it despoils the working individual. We

should keep in mind that he is arguing against apologists for capital

and wants to show that the capitalist mode of production is not eternal

and does not achieve human emancipation. Yet in the course of his

analysis he points to the possibility for capital to escape from human

conditions. We perceive that it is not the productive forces that become

autonomous, but capital, since at a given moment the productive forces

become “a barrier which it strives to overpower.” This takes place as

follows: the productive forces are no longer productive forces of human

beings but of capital; they are for capital.[37]

The despoliation (alienation) of the working individual cannot be a

barrier for capital, unless Marx means barrier in the sense of a

weakness; such a weakness would make capitalism inferior to other modes

of production, particularly if we contrast this weakness to the enormous

development of productive forces which it impels. In Marx’s work there

is an ambiguity about the subject to which the productive forces refer:

are they for the human being or for capital? This ambiguity grounds two

interpretations of Marx. The ethical interpretation (see especially

Rubel) emphasizes the extent to which Marx denounces the destruction of

the human being by capital, and vigorously insists that the capitalist

mode of production can only be a transitory stage. The interpretation of

Althusser and his school holds that Marx does not succeed in eliminating

the human being from his economic analyses, which reflects his inability

to abandon ideological discourse, from which follows Althusser’s problem

of correctly locating the epistemological break.

It is possible to get out of this ambiguity. If capital succeeds in

overcoming this barrier, it achieves full autonomy. This is why Marx

postulates that capital must abolish itself; this abolition follows from

the fact that it cannot develop the productive forces for human beings

while it makes possible a universal, varied development which can only

be realized by a superior mode of production. This contains a

contradiction: capital escapes from the grasp of human beings, but it

must perish because it cannot develop human productive forces. This also

contradicts Marx’s analysis of the destruction of human beings by

capital. How can destroyed human beings rebel? We can, if we avoid these

contradictions, consider Marx a prophet of the decline of capital, but

then we will not be able to understand his work or the present

situation. The end of Marx’s digression clarifies these contradictions.

“But this antithetical form is itself fleeting, and produces the real

conditions of its own suspension. The result is: the tendentially and

potentially general development of the forces of production — of wealth

as such — as a basis; likewise, the universality of intercourse, hence

the world market as a basis. The basis as the possibility of the

universal development of the individual, and the real development of the

individuals from this basis as a constant suspension of its barrier,

which is recognized as a barrier, not taken for a sacred limit. Not an

ideal or imagined universality of the individual, but the universality

of his real and ideal relations. Hence also the grasping of his own

history as a process, and the recognition of nature (equally present as

practical power over nature) as his real body. The process of

development itself posited and known as the presupposition of the same.

For this, however, necessary above all that the full development of the

forces of production has become the condition of production; and not

that specific conditions of production are posited as a limit to the

development of the productive forces.”[38]

If this process is to concern individuals, capital has to be destroyed

and the productive forces have to be for human beings. In the article,

“La KAPD et le mouvement proletarien,”[39] we referred to this passage

to indicate that the human being is a possibility, giving a foundation

to the statement: the revolution must be human. This is in no way a

discourse on the human being conceived as invariant in every attribute,

a conception which would merely be a restatement of the immutability of

human nature. But we have to point out that this is still insufficient,

since the development of productive forces which, according to Marx,

will take place in a superior mode of production, is precisely the same

development presently carried out by capital. The limit of Marx is that

he conceived communism as a new mode of production where productive

forces blossom. These forces are undoubtedly important, but their

existence at a certain level does not adequately define communism.

For Marx, capital overcomes its contradictions by engulfing them and by

mystifying reality. It can only apparently overcome its narrow base, its

limited nature which resides in the exchange of capital-money against

labor force. Capital must inevitably come into conflict with this

presupposition; thus Marx speaks of the opposition between private

appropriation and socialization of production. Private appropriation of

what? Of surplus value, which presupposes the proletarian, and thus the

wage relation. But the entire development of capital (and Marx’s own

explanations are a precious aid in understanding it) makes the

mystification effective, making capital independent of human beings,

thus enabling it to avoid the conflict with its presupposition. One

might say that the conflict nevertheless persists, as a result of the

total process: socialization. This is true. But the socialization of

production and of human activity, the universal development of the

productive forces and thus the destruction of the limited character of

the human being — all this was only a possible ground for communism; it

did not pose communism automatically. Furthermore, the action of capital

tends constantly to destroy communism, or at least to inhibit its

emergence and realization. To transform this possible ground into

reality, human intervention is necessary. But Marx himself showed that

capitalist production integrates the proletariat. How could the

destruction of human beings and of nature fail to have repercussions on

the ability of human beings to resist capital and, a fortiori, to rebel?

Some will think we are attributing to Marx a position which is

convenient to us. We will cite an extraordinary passage:

“What precisely distinguishes capital from the master-servant relation

is that the worker confronts [capital] as consumer and possessor of

exchange values, and that in the form of the possessor of money, in the

form of money he becomes a simple center of circulation — one of its

infinitely many centers, in which his specificity as worker is

extinguished.”[40]

One of the modalities of the re-absorbtion of the revolutionary power of

the proletariat has been to perfect its character as consumer, thus

catching it in the mesh of capital. The proletariat ceases to be the

class that negates; after the formation of the working class it

dissolves into the social body. Marx anticipates the poets of the

“consumer society” and, as in other instances, he explains a phenomenon

which is observed only later and then falsely, if only in terms of the

name given to it.

The preceding observations do not lead to a fatalistic conception (this

time negative), such as: whatever we do, there’s no way out; it’s too

late; or any other mindless defeatism which would generate a sickening

patch-work reformism. First we have to draw the lesson. Capital has run

away from human and natural barriers; human beings have been

domesticated: this is their decadence. The revolutionary solution cannot

be found in the context of a dialectic of productive forces where the

individual would be an element of the contradiction. Present day

scientific analyses of capital proclaim a complete disregard for human

beings who, for some, are nothing but a residue without consistency.

This means that the discourse of science is the discourse of capital, or

that science is possible only after the destruction of human beings; it

is a discourse on the pathology of the human being. Thus it is insane to

ground the hope of liberation on science. The position is all the more

insane where, as with Althusser, it cannot make its own break, liquidate

its “archeology,” since it remains faithful to a proletariat — a

proletariat which in this conception is merely an object of capital, an

element of the structure. But this inefficient, destroyed human being is

the individual produced by class societies. And on this we agree: the

human being is dead. The only possibility for another human being to

appear is our struggle against our domestication, our emergence from it.

Humanism and scientism (and the followers of “ethical science” à la

Monod are the most absolute slaves of capital) are two expressions of

the domestication of humanity. All those who nurse the illusion of the

decadence of capital revive ancient humanist conceptions or give birth

to new scientific myths. They remain impermeable to the revolutionary

phenomenon running through our world.

Until now all sides have argued as if human beings remained unchanged in

different class societies and under the domination of capital. This is

why the role of the social context was emphasized (man, who was

fundamentally good, was seen to be modified positively or negatively by

the social context) by the materialist philosophers of the 18^(th)

century, while Marxists emphasized the role of an environment

conditioned by the development of productive forces. Change was not

denied, and after Marx it was repeated that history was a continual

transformation of human nature. Nevertheless it was held explicitly or

implicitly that an irreducible element continued to allow human beings

to revolt against the oppression of capital. And capitalism itself was

described in a Manichean manner: on one side the positive pole, the

proletariat, the liberating class; on the other the negative pole,

capital. Capital was affirmed as necessary and as having revolutionized

the life of human beings, but it was described as an absolute evil in

relation to the good, the proletariat. The phenomenon which emerges

today does not in the least destroy the negative evaluation of capital,

but forces us to generalize it to the class which was once antagonistic

to it and carried within itself all the positive elements of human

development and today of humanity itself. This phenomenon is the

recomposition of a community and of human beings by capital, reflecting

human community like a mirror. The theory of the looking glass could

only arise when the human being became a tautology, a reflection of

capital. Within the world of the despotism of capital (this is how

society appears as of today), neither a good nor an evil can be

distinguished. Everything can be condemned. Negating forces can only

arise outside of capital. Since capital has absorbed all the old

contradictions, the revolutionary movement has to reject the entire

product of the development of class societies. This is the crux of its

struggle against domestication, against the decadence of the human

species. This is the essential moment of the process of formation of

revolutionaries, absolutely necessary for the production of revolution.

Jacques Camatte May, 1973

 

[1] This does not exclude an opposite movement: capital forces human

beings to be human.

[2] Karl Marx, Grundrisse, London: Pelican, 1973, p. 365.

[3] Here we see a convergence with the Asiatic mode of production, where

classes could never become autonomous; in the capitalist mode of

production they are absorbed.

[4] See the book of D. Verres, Le discours du capitalisme, Ed. L’Herne.

interesting material will also be found in the works of Baudrillard: Le

systéme des objets and Pour une critique de l’économle politique du

signe, Ed. Gallimard.

[5] Dichter, cited by Baudrillard in Le système des objets, pp. 218–219.

[6] Valerie Solanas, The SCUM Manifesto (The Society for Cutting Up

Men), New York: Olympia Press, 1970.

[7] We analyzed the autonomization of capital in Le VIe chapitre inédit

du Capital et l’oeuvre économique de Marx (1966), particularly in the

notes added in 1972.

In a future article we will analyze this subject more thoroughly by

showing that Marx had raised the problem without recognizing it in its

totality, and by analyzing the capitalist mode of production of today.

This will also lead us to define labor and its role in the development

of humanity. G. Brulé already began such an analysis in his article in

Invariance No. 2, Série II: “Le travail, le travail productif et les

mythes de la classe ouvriére et de la classe moyenne.” (Labor,

productive labor and the myths of the working class and the middle

class).

In general we can say that the concept of labor is reductive: it

encompasses only one part of human activity. But the call for its

abolition is a call for the destruction of this remainder of activity,

which is a utopian demand of capital. The project of communism inserts

itself into the context of human life, activity being no more than a

modality of expression. Love, meditation, day-dreaming, play and other

manifestations of human beings are placed outside the field of life when

we trap ourselves within the concept of labor. Marx defined labor as an

activity which transforms nature or matter for one or another purpose,

but the concept of nature can no longer be accepted as it is. In the

period of domination of capital, the human being is no longer in contact

with nature (especially during work). Between nature and the individual

lies capital. Capital becomes nature.

On the other hand, in his so-called “philosophical” works, Marx clearly

refers to all human activity and asserts that communism cannot be

reduced to the liberation of labor. This position does not completely

disappear from the rest of Marx’s works, and survives alongside the

“revolutionary reformist” conception expressed in Capital. For the

Marxists the problem is subsequently simplified: they exalt labor, pure

and simple. In Trotsky’s work, for example, there is no longer a trace

of Marx’s complex analysis, but rather a display of the language of

domestication, the language of capital: “The entire history of humanity

is a history of the organization and education of social man for labor,

with a view to obtaining from him greater productivity.” (Terrorism and

Communism (French ed.: Paris: Ed. 10/18, 1963, p. 2181.)

[8] This possibility is described and exalted in Future Shock by Alvin

Toffler.

[9] Marx, Capital, Vol. I [ Le Capital, I. 1, t. 2, p. 182. ]

[10] This requires a detailed study which would include the analysis of

labor. In the article which follows we begin this study: it presents the

first conclusions we’ve reached. In particular we want to analyze the

stage of this decadence of humanity, how it is expressed, etc. In

addition we want to show the intimate connection between the movement of

value and the dialectic of the productive forces. The end of the

movement of value and of capital is the end of a mode of representation

and destroys its autonomy. The Marxian dialectic will be completely

overcome.

[11] Engels, Marx, The German Ideology, [ Moscow, 1964, p. 85. ]

[12] Engels, “Preface” to The Poverty of Philosophy by Marx, New York:

1963, p. 11.

[13] See particularly “The Movement of Income in Modern Society” and

“Crises and Possibilities of Adaptation” in Presuppositions of Socialism

and the tasks of Social Democracy, Rowohlt Verlag, pp. 75ff.

[14] Here we should be careful, as Bordiga justly observed, not to

reduce this to an economic concept.

[15] Marx, Capital, Vol. 1, New York: Random House, pp. 831–837.

[16] In the original Fredy Perlman translation the two sentences

immediately before this, beginning ‘But at this moment (...)’, were

shown as a quotation from Marx and a reference was given to an english

translation of Marx’s text ‘The King of Prussia (etc.)’. Looking at the

french text this is evidently an error based on a misprint and this

sentence is actually by Camatte. Thanks to Antagonism for drawing

attention to this.

[17] Which proves that it was impossible to hold on to a “classist”

discourse and behavior while maintaining the basic “aclassist” thesis of

the necessity of the proletariat’s self-negation.

[18] On this subject, see the book by H. Mueller published in 1892, Der

Klassenkampf in der Deutschen Sozialdemokratie, Verlags-kooperative

Heidelberg-Frankfurt-Hanover-Berlin, 1969. This book clearly shows the

duality-duplicity of men like Bebel, who expressed themselves as

“rightists” in parliament and as “leftists” at workers’ meetings, who

told one audience it would be very long before the principles of

socialism could be realized, while telling another that socialism was

around the corner. This book is also interesting because it contains

positions which were later to be taken up by the KAPD (German Communist

Workers’ Party).

[19] Bordiga at meeting in Milan, 1960.

[20] Absolute irreversibility is not a fact of history. Possibilities

which appeared thousands or hundreds of years ago were not abolished for

all time. History is not a Moloch which swallows possibilities,

condemning the human future to an inevitable and irremediable

despoliation. In that case history would be no more than a justification

for what happened. Many would like to reduce history to this, making it

the worst of despots.

Hegel’s philosophy with its dialectic of supersession (Aufhebung), of

movement which abolishes and preserves at one and the same time, was an

attempt to salvage what human beings had produced in earlier epochs.

Hegel was troubled by the problems of loss of reality, of the

multiplicity of manifestations and possibles, etc. Thus he attached

enormous importance to memory (see particularly the chapter “Absolute

Knowledge,” in the Phenomenology of Mind.)

By contrast, the movement of capital abolishes the memory of its

previous stages (by mystification and magic) as well as the stages of

humanity, and presents itself, as it is, at its highest level of

development — the “reified” (or ossified) form” (See Marx, Theories of

Surplus Value,[Moscow: 1971] , Vol. III, chapter on “Revenue and its

Sources. Vulgar Political Economy.”

[21] The concept of mode of production is in reality valid only for the

capitalist mode of production, just as the concept of class is in

reality operative only in bourgeois society. The concept of production

in Marx’s work is quite rich in attributes. It becomes impoverished when

we move from the 1844 Manuscripts and The German Ideology to Capital. It

is closely related to the concept of nature and also to a certain

conception of the human being. In other words, we have a much more

complex “given” when we can examine it only in relation to the existence

of initial communist communities and their dissolution. The separation

of the human being from the community (Gemeinwesen) is a despoliation.

The human being as worker has lost a mound of attributes which formed a

whole when he was related to his community.

The process of expropriation of human beings is real. Those who do not

understand this do not understand what capital is. Man has been reduced

to an inexpressive being; he has lost his senses, and his activity has

been reduced to quantified labor. Man turned into abstract being longs

for music which still preserves the ancestral sensuality (thus the vogue

of jazz and South American music). The reduced human being now has only

one element relating him to the external world: sexuality which fills

the void of the senses. It is precisely this which explains the

pansexuality, or more exactly the pansexualization of being which Freud

interpreted as an invariant characteristic of human beings, whereas it

is the result of their mutilation. What is the subconscious if not the

affective-sensual life of the human being repressed by capital? The

human being has to be domesticated, shaped to a rationality which he

must internalize — the rationality of the process of production of

capital. Once this domestication is achieved, the human being is

dispossessed of this repressed sensual life which becomes an object of

knowledge, of science; it becomes capitalizable. The unconscious,

becoming an object of commerce, is thinly sliced and retailed in the

market of knowledge. The unconscious did not always exist, and it exists

now only as a component in the discourse of capital; this is also true

of human perversions.

Reduced to perfect inexpressivity, the human being increasingly becomes

comparable point by point to the elementary particle studied by nuclear

physics, where one can find the principles of the psychology of the

capitalized human being who is moved by the field of capital.

[22] It is also unsound to speak of primitive society. We will

substantiate this by making a new analysis of primitive communities. If

it is true that Marx’s work does not deal adequately with the existence,

development and dissolution of primitive communities, it is not true

that Marx is absolutely wrong because of Europocentrism or the spirit of

enlightenment, namely that his work suffers from the same shortcomings

as bourgeois theory. The majority of those who hold this view have not

understood the question of community in Marx’s work and have reduced his

work to a simple historical materialism.

What Marx’s work lacks is a detailed analysis of the way “the economy”

appears in primitive communities and provokes their disintegration.

We should add that it is becoming increasingly misleading to speak of

capitalist society. We will return to this.

[23] In primitive communities human beings rule technology. Technology

starts to become autonomous in ancient Western society, and this was

feared by the ancients. Technology forces man to copy nature, even if

later he can find a procedure not found in nature; thus he is subjected

to a compulsory procedure, a how-to-do, a sort of natural order. He

seems to lose the capacity to create freely. (On this subject, see the

comments of J.P. Vernant in Mythe et pensée chez les grecs, Ed.

Maspéro.) When human beings no longer fear technology, they

simultaneously become reconciled with art, which had been disparaged at

the end of slave society. This took place at the time of the

Renaissance, when philosophers defined man as a being who makes himself

(See Cassirer, Individual and Cosmos in Renaissance Philosophy). But the

development of technology did not lead man toward nature; on the

contrary, it led to the expropriation of man and the destruction of

nature. The human being increasingly loses the faculty of creativity. In

this sense, the fear of the ancients was justified.

From the philosophers of the Renaissance, through Descartes and Hegel,

to Marx, the human being is defined in relation to technology (man is a

tool-maker: Franklin) and to production. To go beyond Marx, it is

necessary to reexamine the “human phenomenon” from the disintegration of

primitive communities until today and to rethink the works of

philosophers and economists from Aristotle to Marx in order to

understand more clearly how human beings perceived themselves in a

period when value and then capital dominated, and in order to understand

how, now that we have come to the end of the phenomenon value, we can

conceive humanity, and thus communism.

[24] “Origine et fonction de la forme parti” (1961), published in

Invariance, No. 1, Serie 1.

[25] Marx, Grundrisse, London: Pelican, 1973, p. 539.

[26] Ibid., p. 540.

[27] Ibid.

[28] Ibid.

[29] Ibid., pp. 540–541.

[30] Ibid., p. 541.

[31] As is done by Victor in Révolution Internationale No. 7, série 1,

p. 4 of the article “Volontarisme et confusion.”

[32] Various authors have spoken of stagnation and declining production

between the two world wars. Bordiga always rejected the theory of the

decline of the capitalist mode of production as a gradualist deformation

of Marx’s theory (see “Le renversement de la praxis dans la théorie

marxiste,” in Invariance No. 4, série 1.

[33] Marx, Grundrisse, p. 541.

[34] Ibid., p. 410.

[35] Ibid., P. 541.

[36] Ibid.

[37] This is what Marx shows when he analyzes fixed capital in the

Grundrisse, and also in Book I of Capital “where he analyzes the

transformation of the work process into a process of production of

capital (see also Un chapitre inédit du Capital, Paris: Ed. 10/18,

1971).

[38] Marx, Grundrisse, pp. 541–542.

[39] Invariance, Série II, No. 1.

[40] Marx, Grundrisse, pp. 420–421.