đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș endnotes-journal-1.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 09:36:39. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Endnotes 1 Author: Various Authors Date: 2008 Language: en Topics: Endnotes, communization, anti-work, class struggle, Left Communism, insurrection, self-abolition of the proletariat, communism, anti-capitalism, journal, criticism and critique Source: Retrieved on August 27, 2022 from https://libcom.org/article/endnotes-journal
âThe tradition of all dead generations weighs like a nightmare on the
brain of the living⊠The social revolution of the nineteenth century
cannot take its poetry from the past but only from the future. It cannot
begin with itself before it has stripped away all superstition about the
past. The former revolutions required recollections of the past in order
to smother their own content. In order to arrive at its own content, the
revolution of the nineteenth century must let the dead bury their
dead.â[1]
If this was true when Marx wrote this passage, when one could only speak
of communism in the future tense, it is all the more so of today, now
that anarchists and communists can speak of their own âhistoriesâ,
indeed seem to speak of little else. Marxism itself is now a tradition
of dead generations, and even latter-day situationists seem to have
difficulty in âleaving the twentieth century.â[2]
We write this not from any special infatuation with the present, or any
resultant desire to bring communist theory âup-to-dateâ. The
twenty-first century â just as much as the previous one â is formed by
the contradiction between labour and capital, the separation between
work and âlifeâ, and the domination of everything by the abstract forms
of value. It is therefore just as worth leaving as its predecessor. Yet
the âtwentieth centuryâ familiar to the situationists, its contours of
class relations, its temporality of progress, and its post-capitalist
horizons, is obviously behind us. Weâve become bored with theories of
novelty â with post-modernism, post-Fordism, and each new product of the
academy â not so much because they fail to capture an essential
continuity, but because the capitalist restructuring of the 1970s and
80s is no longer novel.
In this preliminary issue of Endnotes we have assembled a series of
texts (basically an exchange between two communist groups in France) all
concerned with the history of revolutions in the twentieth century. As
the texts make clear, the history of these revolutions is a history of
failure, either because they were crushed by capitalist
counter-revolution or because their âvictoriesâ took the form of
counter-revolutions themselves â setting up social systems which, in
their reliance on monetary exchange and wage-labour, failed to transcend
capitalism. Yet the latter was not simply a âbetrayalâ; any more than
the former was the result of âstrategic errorsâ or missing âhistorical
conditions.â When we address the question of these failures we cannot
resort to âwhat ifâ counterfactuals â blaming the defeat of
revolutionary movements on everything (leaders, forms of organisations,
wrong ideas, unripe conditions) other than the movements themselves in
their determinate content. It is the nature of this content which is at
issue in the exchange which follows.
In publishing such âhistoricalâ texts we have no wish to encourage an
interest in history per se, nor to revive an interest in the history of
revolutions or of the workersâ movement. We hope that in considering the
content of the struggles of the last century we will help to undermine
the illusion that this is somehow âourâ past, something to be protected
or preserved. Marxâs dictum reminds us of the need to shed the dead
weight of tradition. We would go so far as to say that with the
exception of the recognition of the historical break that separates us
from them, that we have nothing to learn from the failures of past
revolutions â no need to replay them to discover their âerrorsâ or
distil their âtruthsâ â for it would in any case be impossible to repeat
them. In drawing the balance of this history, in taking it to be over,
we are drawing a line that foregrounds the struggles of our own time.
The two parties to the exchange we are publishing, Troploin and Théorie
Communiste, both emerged from a tendency in the early 1970s that, on the
basis of new characteristics of the class struggle, critically
appropriated the historical ultra-left in both its German / Dutch
(council communist) and Italian (Bordigist) varieties as well the more
recent work of the Situationist International and Socialisme ou
Barbarie. Before we can introduce the texts themselves we must therefore
introduce this common background.
When Guy Debord wrote ânever workâ on the wall of a left-bank alleyway
in 1954, the slogan, appropriated from Rimbaud,[3] was still heavily
indebted to surrealism and its avant-garde progeny. That is to say, it
evoked at least in part a romanticised vision of late nineteenth century
bohemia â a world of dĂ©classĂ© artists and intellectuals who had become
caught between the traditional relations of patronage and the new
cultural marketplace in which they were obliged to vend their wares. The
bohemiansâ negative attitude towards work had been both a revolt
against, and an expression of, this polarized condition: caught between
an aristocratic disdain for the âprofessionalâ, and a petit-bourgeois
resentment of all other social classes, they came to see all work, their
own included, as debased. This posture of refusal was rendered political
by the surrealists, who transformed the nihilistic gestures of Rimbaud,
LautrĂ©amont, and the dadaists, into the revolutionary call for a âwar on
workâ.[4] Yet for the surrealists, along with other unorthodox
revolutionaries (e.g. Lafargue, elements of the IWW, as well as the
young Marx), the abolition of work was postponed to a utopian horizon on
the other side of a revolution defined in its immediacy by the socialist
programme of the liberation of work â the triumph of the workersâ
movement and the elevation of the working class to the position of a new
ruling class. The goal of the abolition of work would thus paradoxically
be achieved through first removing all of workâs limits (e.g. the
capitalist as a parasite upon labour, the relations of production as a
fetter to production) â thereby extending the condition of work to
everyone (âthose who donât work shall not eatâ) and rewarding labour
with its rightful share of the value it produces (through various
schemes of labour-accounting).
This apparent contradiction between means and ends, evinced in the
surrealistsâ troubled relationship with the French Communist Party, was
typical of revolutionary theories throughout the ascendant period of the
workersâ movement. From anarcho-syndicalists to Stalinists, the broad
swathe of this movement put their hopes for the overcoming of capitalism
and class society in general in the rising power of the working class
within capitalism. At a certain point this workersâ power was expected
to seize the means of production, ushering in a âperiod of transitionâ
to communism or anarchism, a period which would witness not the
abolition of the situation of the working class, but its generalisation.
Thus the final end of the elimination of class society coexisted with a
whole gamut of revolutionary means which were premised on its
perpetuation.
The Situationist International (SI) inherited the surrealistsâ
opposition between the concrete political means of the liberation of
work and the utopian end of its abolition. Their principle achievement
was to transpose it from an external opposition mediated by the
transition of the socialist programme into an internal one that
propelled their conception of revolutionary activity. This latter
consisted of a radical rethinking of the liberation of work, along lines
which emphasised the refusal of any separation between revolutionary
action and the total transformation of life â an idea expressed
implicitly in their original project of âcreating situationsâ. The
importance of this development should not be underestimated, for the
âcritique of separationâ here implied a negation of any temporal hiatus
between means and ends (thus of any period of transition), as well as a
refusal of any synchronic mediations â insisting on universal (direct
democratic) participation in revolutionary action. Yet in spite of this
ability to rethink the space and time of revolution, the SIâs
transcendence of the opposition between the liberation and abolition of
work would ultimately consist in collapsing its two poles into one
another, into an immediate contradictory unity, transposing the
opposition between means and ends into one between form and content.
After their encounter with the neo-councilist group Socialisme ou
Barbarie at the beginning of the sixties, the SI wholeheartedly adopted
the revolutionary programme of council communism, lauding the council â
the apparatus through which workers would self-manage their own
production and, together with other councils, grasp the entirety of
social power â as the âfinally achieved formâ of the proletarian
revolution. From then on all the potential and all the limits of the SI
were contained in the tension between their call to âabolish workâ and
their central slogan, âall power to the workersâ councils.â On the one
hand the content of the revolution was to involve a radical questioning
of work itself (and not merely its organisation), with the goal of
overcoming the separation between work and leisure; yet on the other
hand the form of this revolution was to be workers taking over their
workplaces and running them democratically.[5]
What prevented the SI from overcoming this contradiction was that the
polarities of content and form were both rooted in an affirmation of the
workersâ movement and the liberation of work. For although the SI
appropriated from the young Marx (and the sociological inquiries of
Socialisme ou Barbarie) a preoccupation with the alienation of labour,
they nonetheless saw the critique of this alienation as made possible by
the technological prosperity of modern capitalism (the âleisure societyâ
potentials of automation) and the battalions of the workersâ movement
who were capable of both compelling (in their day to day struggles) and
appropriating (in their revolutionary councils) these technical
advances. It was thus on the basis of an existing workersâ power at the
points of production that they saw the abolition of work as becoming
possible, both from a technical and organisational standpoint. In
transposing the techniques of the cyberneticians and the gestures of the
bohemian anti-artist into the trusted, calloused hands of the organised
working class, the situationists were able to imagine the abolition of
work as the direct result of its liberation; that is, to imagine the
overcoming of alienation as a result of an immediate technical-creative
restructuring of the workplace by the workers themselves.
In this sense the SIâs theory represents the last sincere gesture of
faith in a revolutionary conception of self-management integral to the
programme of the liberation of work. But its critique of work would be
taken up and transformed by those who sought to theorise the new
struggles that emerged when this programme had entered into irreversible
crisis in the 1970s. The latter would understand this critique as rooted
not in an affirmation of the workersâ movement, but in new forms of
struggles which coincided with its decomposition. However, in the
writings of Invariance, La Vielle Taupe, Mouvement Communiste and
others, the attempt to overcome the central contradiction of the SI
would first be expressed in a critique of âformalismâ, the privileging
of form over content, within the ideology of council communism.
Contrary to the instructions of the SI, the workers who took part in the
mass strike of May â68 in France did not seize the means of production,
form councils, or try to run the factories under workersâ control.[6] In
the vast majority of occupied workplaces workers were content to leave
all the organisation in the hands of their union delegates, and the
latter often had trouble in convincing workers to show up to the
occupation assemblies to vote for the continuation of the strike.[7] In
the most important class struggles of the ensuing years, most notably
those in Italy, the council form, consistently the epitome of
proletarian radicalism in the foregoing cycle (Germany â19, Italy â21,
Spain â36, Hungary â56), was absent. Yet these years paradoxically saw a
rise in the ideology of councilism, as the perception of an increasingly
unruly working class and the decreasing viability of the old
organisations seemed to suggest that the only thing missing was the form
most adequate to spontaneous and non-hierarchical struggles. In this
context groups like Informations Correspondance Ouvrieres (ICO) in
France, Solidarity in England, Root and Branch in the US, and to some
extent the operaisti current in Italy, managed to revive an interest in
the German/Dutch Left through blaming the old enemies of councilism â
all the left parties and unions, all the âbureaucratsâ in the language
of the SI â for the failure of each new insurgency.
It would not take long for this perspective to be challenged, and this
challenge would initially take the form of a revival of the other
left-communist tradition. Under the intellectual leadership of Amadeo
Bordiga, the Italian Left had long criticised council communism (which
in âLeft-wing Communism, an Infantile Disorderâ Lenin lumped together
with the Italian Left) for its championing of form over content, and its
uncritical conception of democracy.[8] It is this position, filtered
through the influence of the dissident Bordigist journal Invariance,
which underlies Gilles DauvĂ©âs critique of council communism in
âLeninism and the Ultraleftâ, one of the foundational texts of the
tendency we are describing.[9] Dauvé accuses council communism of
formalism on two counts: their approach to the question of organisation
sees the form of organisation as the decisive factor (an âinverted
Leninismâ), and their conception of post-revolutionary society
transforms the form (the councils) into the content of socialism,
through depicting the latter as fundamentally a question of management.
For Dauvé, as for Bordiga, this was a false question, for capitalism is
not a mode of management but a mode of production, in which âmanagersâ
of any sort (capitalists, bureaucrats, or even workers) are merely the
functionaries through which the law of value is articulated. As Pierre
Nashua (La Vielle Taupe) and Carsten Juhl (Invariance) would also later
argue, such a preoccupation with form over content effectively replaces
the communist goal of the destruction of the economy with a mere
opposition to its management by the bourgeoisie.[10]
In itself this critique of council communism could only lead to
reworking the canonical theses of the Italian Left, either through an
immanent critique (a la Invariance) or by developing a sort of
Italo-Germanic hybrid (a la Mouvement Communiste). What provided the
impetus for a new conception of revolution and communism (as
communisation) was not simply an understanding of the content of
communism derived from a close reading of Marx and Bordiga, but also the
influence of a whole wave of class struggles of the late sixties and
early seventies which would give a new meaning to âthe refusal of workâ
as a specific content of the revolution.
By the early 1970s journalists and sociologists began to speak of a
ârevolt against workâ afflicting an entire new generation of workers in
traditional industries, with rapidly rising rates of absenteeism and
sabotage, as well as a widespread disregard for the authority of the
union. Commentators variously blamed: the feeling of expendability and
insecurity brought about by automation; the increasing assertiveness of
traditionally oppressed minorities; the influence of an
anti-authoritarian counter-culture; the power and sense of entitlement
afforded by the prolonged post-war boom and its hard-won âsocial wageâ.
Whatever the reason for these developments, what seemed to characterize
the new struggles was a breakdown in the traditional forms through which
workers sought to gain control over the labour process, leaving only the
expression of an apparent desire to work less. For many of those who had
been influenced by the SI, this new proletarian âassaultâ was
characterized by a ârefusal of workâ shorn of the techno-utopian and
bohemian-artistic elements which the SI had never been able to abandon.
Groups like NĂ©gation and Intervention Communiste argued that it was not
only the power of the union which was being undermined in these
struggles, but the entire Marxist and Anarchist programme of the
liberation of work and the triumph of âworkersâ powerâ. Far from
liberating their work, bringing it under their own control, and using it
to seize control of society through self-managing their workplaces, in
the French May and the subsequent âcreeping Mayâ in Italy, the âcritique
of workâ took the form of hundreds of thousands of workers deserting
their workplaces. Rather than an indication that struggles hadnât gone
far enough, the absence of workersâ councils during this period was thus
understood as an expression of a rupture with what would come to be
known as âthe old workersâ movement.â
Just as it had been influential in spreading the above-mentioned
critique of councilism, the dissident Bordigist journal Invariance was
an important forerunner of critical reflection on the history and
function of the workersâ movement. For Invariance the old workersâ
movement was integral to a development of capitalism from a stage of
merely âformalâ to one of âreal domination.â The workersâ failures were
necessary since it was capital that constituted their organizing
principle:
âThe example of the German, and above all, of the Russian revolutions,
shows that the proletariat was fully capable of destroying a social
order which presented an obstacle to the development of the productive
forces, and thus to the development of capital, but that at the moment
that it became a matter of establishing a different community, it
remained a prisoner of the logic of the rationality of the development
of those productive forces, and confined itself within the problem of
managing them.â[11]
Thus a question that for Bordiga had been one of theoretical and
organisational error came for Camatte to define the historic function of
the workersâ movement within capitalism. The self-liberation of the
working class meant only the development of the productive forces, since
the principle productive force was the working class itself. One did not
need to follow Camatte into the wilderness[12] in order to agree with
this estimation. After all, by the 1970s it was clear that in the East
the workersâ movement had been integral, at least at the beginning, to
an unprecedented rise in the productive capacity of the socialist
states; whilst in the West workersâ struggles for better conditions had
played a key role in bringing about the post-war boom and the resulting
global expansion of the capitalist mode of production. Yet for many the
crisis of the institutions of the workersâ movement in the 1970s showed
that this purely capitalist function was itself coming into crisis, and
workers would be able to shed the burden of this history. For Mouvement
Communiste, NĂ©gation, Intervention Communiste, and others the breakdown
of the old workersâ movement was something to be celebrated, not because
the corrupt leadership of the workersâ organisations would no longer be
able to restrain the autonomy of the masses, but because such a shift
represented a transcendence of the historical function of the workersâ
movement, a transcendence that would mark the reemergence of the
communist movement, the âreal movement which abolishes the present state
of thingsâ.[13] And it did so in an immediate sense, for the riots and
wildcat strikes of that decade were read by these writers as a total
refusal of all the mediations of the workersâ movement, not in favour of
some other more âdemocraticâ mediation like that of workersâ councils,
but in a way that posed the immediate production of communist relations
as the only possible revolutionary horizon. Thus whereas communism had
previously been seen as something that needed to be created after the
revolution, the revolution was now seen as nothing other than the
production of communism (abolishing wage labour and the state). The
notion of a period of transition was jettisoned.[14]
In a recent text DauvĂ© sums up this estimation of the old workersâ
movement:
âThe workersâ movement that existed in 1900, or still in 1936, was
neither crushed by fascist repression nor bought off by transistors or
fridges: it destroyed itself as a force of change because it aimed at
preserving the proletarian condition, not superseding it. ⊠The purpose
of the old labour movement was to take over the same world and manage it
in a new way: putting the idle to work, developing production,
introducing workersâ democracy (in principle, at least). Only a tiny
minority, âanarchistâ as well as âmarxistâ, held that a different
society meant the destruction of State, commodity and wage labour,
although it rarely defined this as a process, rather as a programme to
put into practice after the seizure of powerâŠâ[15]
Against such a programmatic approach, groups like Mouvement Communiste,
NĂ©gation, and La Guerre Sociale advocated a conception of revolution as
the immediate destruction of capitalist relations of production, or
âcommunisationâ. As we shall see, the understanding of communisation
differed between different groups, but it essentially meant the
application of communist measures within the revolution â as the
condition of its survival and its principle weapon against capital. Any
âperiod of transitionâ was seen as inherently counter-revolutionary, not
just in so far as it entailed an alternative power structure which would
resist âwithering awayâ (c.f. anarchist critiques of âthe dictatorship
of the proletariatâ), nor simply because it always seemed to leave
unchallenged fundamental aspects of the relations of production, but
because the very basis of workersâ power on which such a transition was
to be erected was now seen to be fundamentally alien to the struggles
themselves. Workersâ power was just the other side of the power of
capital, the power of reproducing workers as workers; henceforth the
only available revolutionary perspective would be the abolition of this
reciprocal relation.[16]
Communiste
The milieu in which the idea of communisation emerged was never very
unified, and the divisions only grew as time went on. Some ended up
abandoning whatever was left of the councilist rejection of the party
and returned to what remained of the legacy of the Italian Left,
congregating around atavistic sects such as the International Communist
Current (ICC). Many others took the questioning of the old workersâ
movement and the ideal of workersâ councils to require a questioning of
the revolutionary potential of the working class. In its most extreme
form with the journal Invariance this led to an abandoning of âthe
theory of the proletariatâ, replacing it by a purely normative demand to
âleave this worldâ, a world in which the community of capital has,
through real domination, supplanted the human community. Yet even among
those who didnât go as far, there was an abiding sense that as long as
struggles remained attached to the workplace they could only express
themselves as a defence of the condition of the working class. In spite
of their different approaches, Mouvement Communiste, La Guerre Sociale,
NĂ©gation, and their descendants ended up affirming the workplace revolts
of the 1970s, and the growth of struggles around reproduction with which
they coincided, to the extent that they seemed to escape the constraints
of class identity, freeing the âclass for-itselfâ from the âclass
in-itselfâ, and thus revealing the potential for communisation as the
realisation of the true human community. A few people associated with
this tendency (notably Pierre Guillaume and Dominique Blanc) would take
the critique of anti-fascism (shared to some extent by all of those who
defended the communisation thesis) to an extreme and become entangled in
the âFaurisson Affairâ of the late-1970s.[17] Another tendency,
represented by Théorie Communiste (hereafter TC), attempted to
historicise the communisation thesis itself, understanding it in terms
of changes in class relations which were in the process of undermining
the institutions of the workersâ movement and working class identity in
general. They would go on to conceptualise this change as a fundamental
restructuring of the capitalist mode of production in accordance with
the termination of one cycle of struggle and the emergence, via a
successful counter-revolution, of a new cycle. The distinguishing
feature of this new cycle for TC is that it carries within it the
potential for communisation as the limit of a class contradiction newly
situated at the level of reproduction (see the afterword for a
clarification of TCâs theory in this respect).[18]
Whilst TC developed their theory of the restructuring at the end of the
1970s, others would follow suit in the 1980s and 90s, and the group
Troploin (consisting principally of Gilles Dauvé and Karl Nesic) has
recently attempted something of that order in âWither the Worldâ and âIn
for a Stormâ. The difference between these conceptions is marked, not
least because the latter seems to have been at least partly developed in
opposition to the former. The exchange between Théorie Communiste and
Troploin we are publishing here took place in the last ten years, and
underlying the assessment of the revolutionary history of the twentieth
century to be found in these texts, are different conceptions of
capitalist restructuring and opposed interpretations of the current
period.
The first text, When Insurrections Die, is based on an earlier
introduction by Gilles Dauvé to a collection of articles from the
Italian Left journal Bilan on the Spanish Civil War. In this text Dauvé
is concerned to show how the wave of proletarian revolts in the first
half of the twentieth century were crushed by the vicissitudes of war
and ideology. Thus in Russia the revolution is sacrificed to the civil
war, and destroyed by the consolidation of Bolshevik power; in Italy and
Germany the workers are betrayed by unions and parties, by the lie of
democracy; and in Spain it is again the march to war (to the tune of
anti-fascism) which seals the fate of the whole cycle, trapping the
proletarian revolution between two bourgeois fronts.
DauvĂ© doesnât address the later struggles of the 60s and 70s, but it is
obvious that judgements from this period, as to e.g. the nature of the
workersâ movement as a whole, inform his assessment of what was
âmissingâ in this earlier defeated wave of struggles. In their critique
of When Insurrections Die, TC attack what they consider to be DauvĂ©âs
ânormativeâ perspective, in which actual revolutions are counter-posed
to what they could and should have been â to a
never-completely-spelled-out formula of a genuine communist revolution.
TC broadly agree with DauvĂ©âs conception of revolution (i.e.
communisation) but criticise Dauvé for ahistorically imposing it on
previous revolutionary struggles as the measure of their success and
failure (and thus of failing to account for the historical emergence of
the communisation thesis itself). According to TC it follows that the
only explanation that Dauvé is capable of giving for the failure of past
revolutions is the ultimately tautological one that they didnât go far
enough â âthe proletarian revolutions failed because the proletarians
failed to make the revolution.â[19] In contrast they argue that their
own theory is able to give a robust account of the whole cycle of
revolution, counter-revolution and restructuring, in which revolutions
can be shown to have contained their own counter-revolutions within them
as the intrinsic limit of the cycles they emerge from and bring to
term.[20]
In the subsequent three texts in the exchange (two by Troploin and one
by TC) a number of controversies are explored, including the role of
âhumanismâ in Troploinâs conception of communisation, and the role of
âdeterminismâ in that of TC. Yet for us the most interesting aspect of
this exchange, the reason we are publishing it here, is that it
constitutes the most frank attempt we have come across to assess the
legacy of 20th century revolutionary movements in terms of a conception
of communism as neither an ideal or a programme, but a movement immanent
to the world of capital, that which abolishes capitalist social
relations on the basis of premises currently in existence. It is in
order to interrogate these premises, to return to the present â our
starting point â that we seek to analyse their conditions of emergence
in the foregoing cycles of struggle and revolution.
This version, translated by Loren Goldner and revised by the author,
first published by Antagonism Press, 1999.
âIf the Russian Revolution becomes the signal for a proletarian
revolution in the West, so that both complement each other, the present
Russian common ownership of land may serve as the starting point for a
communist development.â[21]
This perspective was not realised. The European proletariat missed its
rendezvous with a revitalised Russian peasant commune.[22]
Brest-Litovsk, Poland, December 1917: the Bolsheviks proposed peace
without annexations to a Germany intent on taking over a large swath of
the old Tsarist empire, stretching from Finland to the Caucasus. But in
February 1918, the German soldiers, âproletarians in uniformâ though
they were, obeyed their officers and resumed the offensive against a
soviet Russia as if they were still facing the Tsarist army. No
fraternisation occurred, and the revolutionary war advocated by the
Bolshevik Left proved impossible. In March, Trotsky had to sign a peace
treaty dictated by the Kaiserâs generals. âWeâre trading space for
timeâ, as Lenin put it, and in fact, in November, the German defeat
turned the treaty into a scrap of paper. Nevertheless, practical proof
of the international link-up of the exploited had failed to materialise.
A few months later, returning to civilian life with the warâs end, these
same proletarians confronted the alliance of the official workersâ
movement and the Freikorps. Defeat followed defeat: in Berlin, Bavaria
and Hungary in 1919; then the Red Army of the Ruhr in 1920; the March
Action in 1921âŠ
September 1939. Hitler and Stalin have just carved up Poland. At the
border bridge of Brest-Litovsk, several hundred members of the KPD,
refugees in the USSR subsequently arrested as âcounter-revolutionariesâ,
are taken from Stalinist prisons and handed over to the Gestapo. Years
later, one of them would explain the scars on her back â âGPU did itâ â
and her torn fingernails â âand thatâs the Gestapoâ. A fair account of
the first half of this century.
1917-37: twenty years that shook the world. The succession of horrors
represented by fascism, then World War II and the subsequent upheavals,
are the effect of a gigantic social crisis opening with the mutinies of
1917 and closed by the Spanish Civil War.
According to current left-wing wisdom, fascism is raw state power and
brutal capital unmasked, so the only way to do away with fascism is to
get rid of capitalism altogether.
So far, so good. Unfortunately, the analysis usually turns round on
itself: since fascism is capitalism at its worst, we ought to prevent it
from actually producing its worst, i.e. we ought to fight for a
ânormalâ, non-fascist capitalism, and even rally non-fascist
capitalists.
Moreover, as fascism is capital in its most reactionary forms, such a
vision means trying to promote capital in its most modern, non-feudal,
non-militarist, non-racist, non-repressive, non-reactionary forms, i.e.
a more liberal capitalism, in other words a more capitalist capitalism.
While it goes on at length to explain how fascism serves the interests
of âbig businessâ[23], anti-fascism maintains that fascism could have
been averted in 1922 or 1933 anyway, that is without destroying big
business, if the workersâ movement and/or the democrats had mounted
enough pressure to bar Mussolini and Hitler from power. Anti-fascism is
an endless comedy of sorrows: if only, in 1921, the Italian Socialist
Party and the newly-founded Italian Communist Party had allied with
Republican forces to stop Mussolini⊠if only, at the beginning of the
1930âs, the KPD had not launched a fratricidal struggle against the SPD,
Europe would have been spared one of the most ferocious dictatorships in
history, a second world war, a Nazi empire of almost continental
dimensions, the concentration camps, and the extermination of the Jews.
Above and beyond its very true observations about classes, the state,
and the ties between fascism and big industry, this vision fails to see
that fascism arose out of a two-fold failure: the failure of
revolutionaries after World War I, crushed as they were by
social-democracy and parliamentary democracy, and then, in the course of
the 1920âs, the failure of the democrats and social-democrats in
managing capital. Without a grasp of the preceding period as well as of
the earlier phase of class struggle and its limits, the coming to power,
and still more the nature of fascism, remain incomprehensible.
What is the real thrust of fascism, if not the economic and political
unification of capital, a tendency which has become general since 1914?
Fascism was a particular way of bringing about that unity in countries â
Italy and Germany â where, even though the revolution had been snuffed
out, the state was unable to impose order, including order in the ranks
of the bourgeoisie. Mussolini was no Thiers, with a solid base in power,
ordering regular forces to massacre the Communards. An essential aspect
of fascism is its birth in the streets, its use of disorder to impose
order, its mobilisation of the old middle classes crazed by their own
decline, and its regeneration, from without, of a state unable to deal
with the crisis of capitalism. Fascism was an effort of the bourgeoisie
to forcibly tame its own contradictions, to turn working class methods
of mobilisation to its own advantage, and to deploy all the resources of
the modern state, first against an internal enemy, then against an
external one.
This was indeed a crisis of the state, during the transition to the
total domination of capital over society. First, workersâ organisations
had been necessary to deal with the proletarian upsurge; then, fascism
was required to put an end to the ensuing disorder. This disorder was,
of course, not revolutionary, but it was paralysing, and stood in the
way of solutions which, as a result, could only be violent. This crisis
was only erratically overcome at the time: the fascist state was
efficient only in appearance, because it forcibly integrated the
wage-labour work force, and artificially buried conflicts by projecting
them into militarist adventure. But the crisis was overcome, relatively,
by the multi-tentacled democratic state established in 1945, which
potentially appropriated all of fascismâs methods, and added some of its
own, since it neutralises wage-worker organisations without destroying
them. Parliaments have lost control over the executive. With welfare or
with workfare, by modern techniques of surveillance or by state
assistance extended to millions of individuals, in short by a system
which makes everyone more and more dependent, social unification goes
beyond anything achieved by fascist terror, but fascism as a specific
movement has disappeared. It corresponded to the forced-march discipline
of the bourgeoisie, under the pressure of the state, in the particular
context of newly created states hard-pressed to constitute themselves as
nations.
The bourgeoisie even took the word âfascismâ from working class
organisations in Italy, which were often called fasci. It is significant
that fascism first defined itself as a form of organisation and not as a
programme. The word referred both to a symbol of state power (fasces, or
bundles, borne before high officials in Ancient Rome), and to a will to
get people together in bundles (groups). Fascismâs only programme is to
organise, to forcibly make the components of society converge.
Dictatorship is not a weapon of capital (as if capital could replace it
with other, less brutal weapons): dictatorship is one of its tendencies,
a tendency realised whenever it is deemed necessary. A âreturnâ to
parliamentary democracy, as it occurred in Germany after 1945, indicates
that dictatorship is useless for integrating the masses into the state
(at least until the next time). The problem is therefore not that
democracy ensures a more pliant domination than dictatorship: anyone
would prefer being exploited in the Swedish mode to being abducted by
the henchmen of Pinochet. But does one have the choice? Even the gentle
democracy of Scandinavia would be turned into a dictatorship if
circumstances demanded it. The state can only have one function, which
it fulfils democratically or dictatorially. The fact that the former is
less harsh does not mean that it is possible to reorient the state to
dispense with the latter. Capitalismâs forms depend no more on the
preferences of wage workers than they do on the intentions of the
bourgeoisie. Weimar capitulated to Hitler with open arms. LĂ©on Blumâs
Popular Front did not âavoid fascismâ, because in 1936 France required
neither an authoritarian unification of capital nor a shrinking of its
middle classes.
There is no political âchoiceâ to which proletarians could be enticed or
which could be forcibly imposed. Democracy is not dictatorship, but
democracy does prepare dictatorship, and prepares itself for
dictatorship.
The essence of anti-fascism consists in resisting fascism by defending
democracy: one no longer struggles against capitalism but seeks to
pressure capitalism into renouncing the totalitarian option. Since
socialism is identified with total democracy, and capitalism with an
accelerating tendency to fascism, the antagonisms between proletariat
and capital, communism and wage-labour, proletariat and state, are
rejected for a counter-position of democracy and fascism presented as
the quintessential revolutionary perspective. The official left and far
left tell us that a real change would be the realisation, at last, of
the ideals of 1789, endlessly betrayed by the bourgeoisie. The new
world? Why, it is already here, to some extent, in embryos to be
preserved, in little buds to be tended: already existing democratic
rights must be pushed further and further within an infinitely
perfectible society, with ever-greater daily doses of democracy, until
the achievement of complete democracy, or socialism.
Thus reduced to anti-fascist resistance, social critique is enlisted in
dithyrambs to everything it once denounced, and gives up nothing less
than that shop-worn affair, revolution, for gradualism, a variant on the
âpeaceful transition to socialismâ once advocated by the CPs, and
derided, thirty years ago, by anyone serious about changing the world.
The retrogression is palpable.
We wonât invite ridicule by accusing the left and far left of having
discarded a communist perspective which they knew in reality only when
opposing it. It is all too obvious that anti-fascism renounces
revolution. But anti-fascism fails exactly where its realism claims to
be effective: in preventing a possible dictatorial mutation of society.
Bourgeois democracy is a phase in capitalâs seizure of power, and its
extension in the 20th century completes capitalâs domination by
intensifying the isolation of individuals. Proposed as a remedy for the
separation between man and community, between human activity and
society, and between classes, democracy will never be able to solve the
problem of the most separated society in history. As a form forever
incapable of modifying its content, democracy is only a part of the
problem to which it claims to be the solution. Each time it claims to
strengthen the âsocial bondâ, democracy contributes to its dissolution.
Each time it papers over the contradictions of the commodity, it does so
by tightening the hold of the net which the state has placed over social
relations.
Even in their own desperately resigned terms, the anti-fascists, to be
credible, have to explain to us how local democracy is compatible with
the colonisation of the commodity which empties out public space, and
fills up the shopping malls. They have to explain how an omnipresent
state to which people turn for protection and help, this veritable
machine for producing social âgoodâ, will not commit âevilâ when
explosive contradictions require it to restore order. Fascism is the
adulation of the statist monster, while anti-fascism is its more subtle
apology. The fight for a democratic state is inevitably a fight to
consolidate the state, and far from crippling totalitarianism, such a
fight increases totalitarianismâs stranglehold on society.
Fascism triumphed in countries in which the revolutionary assault after
World War I matured into a series of armed insurrections. In Italy, an
important part of the proletariat, using its own methods and goals,
directly confronted fascism. There was nothing specifically anti-fascist
about its struggle: fighting capital compelled workers and the young CP
(created at Livorno, January 1921, and led by the âBordigistâ faction)
to fight both the Black Shirts and the cops of parliamentary
democracy.[24]
Fascism is unique in giving counter-revolution a mass base and in
mimicking revolution. Fascism turns the call to âtransform the
imperialist war into civil warâ against the workersâ movement, and it
appears as a reaction of demobilised veterans returning to civilian
life, where they are nothing, only held together by collective violence,
and bent on destroying everything they imagine to be a cause of their
dispossession: subversives, enemies of the nation, etc. In July 1918,
Mussoliniâs paper, Il Popolo dâItalia, added to its title âVeteransâ and
Producersâ Dailyâ.
Thus from the outset fascism became an auxiliary of the police in rural
areas, putting down the agricultural proletariat with bullets, but at
the same time developing a frenzied anti-capitalist demagogy. In 1919,
it represented nothing: in Milan, in the November general election, it
got less than 5000 votes, while the socialists got 170,000. Yet it
demanded the abolition of the monarchy, of the senate and all titles of
nobility, the vote for women, the confiscation of the property of the
clergy, and the expropriation of the big landowners and industrialists.
Fighting against the worker in the name of the âproducerâ, Mussolini
exalted the memory of the Red Week of 1914 (which had seen a wave a
riots, particularly in Ancona and Naples), and hailed the positive role
of unions in linking the worker to the nation. Fascismâs goal was the
authoritarian restoration of the state, in order to create a new state
structure capable (in contrast to democracy, Mussolini said) of limiting
big capital and of controlling the commodity logic which was eroding
values, social ties and work.
For decades, the bourgeoisie had denied the reality of social
contradictions. Fascism, on the contrary, proclaimed them with violence,
denying their existence between classes and transposing them to the
struggle between nations, denouncing Italyâs fate as a âproletarian
nationâ. Mussolini was archaic in so far as he upheld traditional values
ruined by capital, and modern in so far as he claimed to defend the
social rights of the people.
Fascist repression was unleashed after a proletarian failure engineered
mainly by democracy and its main fallback options: the parties and
unions, which alone can defeat the workers by employing direct and
indirect methods in tandem. Fascismâs arrival in power was not the
culmination of street battles. Italian and German proles had been
crushed before, by both ballots and bullets.
In 1919, federating pre-existing elements with others close to him,
Mussolini founded his fasci. To counter clubs and revolvers, while Italy
was exploding along with the rest of Europe, democracy called for⊠a
vote, from which a moderate and socialist majority emerged. Forty years
after these events Bordiga commented:
âEnthusiastic involvement in the 1919 electoral celebration was
tantamount to removing all obstacles on the path of fascism, which was
shooting ahead while the masses were put to sleep as they waited for the
big parliamentary showdown⊠Victory, the election of 150 socialist MPs,
was won at the cost of the ebb of the insurrectionary movement and of
the general political strike, and the rollback of the gains that had
already been won.â
At the time of the factory occupations of 1920, the state, holding back
from a head-on-assault, allowed the proletariat to exhaust itself, with
the support of the CGL (a majority-socialist union), which wore down the
strikes when it did not break them openly. The institutionalisation of
âworkersâ controlâ over the factories, under state supervision, was
approved by bosses and unions alike.
As soon as the fasciappeared, sacking the Case di Popolo, the police
either turned a blind eye or confiscated the workersâ guns. The courts
showed the fasci the greatest indulgence, and the army tolerated their
exactions when it did not actually assist them. This open but unofficial
support became quasi-official with the âBonomi circularâ. After being
expelled from the socialist party in 1912, with Mussoliniâs agreement,
for supporting Italyâs war against Libya, Ivanoe Bonomi held several
ministerial posts, and was head of government in 1921-22. His October
20, 1921 circular provided 60,000 demobilised officers to take command
of Mussoliniâs assault groups.
Meanwhile, what were the parties doing? Those liberals allied with the
right did not hesitate to form a ânational blocâ, including the
fascists, for the elections of May 1921. In June-July of the same year,
confronting an adversary without the slightest scruple, the PSI
concluded a meaningless âpacification pactâ whose only concrete effect
was to further disorient the workers.
Faced with an obvious political reaction, the CGL declared itself
a-political. Sensing that Mussolini had power within his grasp, the
union leaders dreamed of a tacit agreement of mutual tolerance with the
fascists, and called on the proletariat to stay out of the face-off
between the CP and the National Fascist Party.
Until August 1922, fascism rarely existed outside the agrarian regions,
mainly in the north, where it eradicated all traces of autonomous
agrarian worker unionism. In 1919, fascists did burn the headquarters of
the socialist daily paper, but they held back from any role as
strike-breakers in 1920, and even gave verbal support to worker demands:
Mussolini took great pains to stand behind the strikers and dissociate
himself from troublemakers, i.e. communists. In the urban areas, the
fasci were rarely dominant. Their âMarch on Ravennaâ (September 1921)
was easily routed. In Rome in November 1921 a general strike prevented a
fascist congress from taking place. In May 1922 the fascists tried
again, and were stopped again.
The scenario varied little. A localised fascist onslaught would be met
by a working-class counter-attack, which would then relent (following
calls for moderation from the reformist workersâ movement) as soon as
reactionary pressure tapered off: the proletarians trusted the democrats
to dismantle the armed bands. The fascist threat would pull back,
regroup and go elsewhere, over time making itself credible to the same
state from which the masses were expecting a solution. The proletarians
were quicker to recognise the enemy in the black shirt of the street
thug than in the ânormalâ uniform of a cop or soldier, draped in a
legality sanctioned by habit, law and universal suffrage. The workers
were militant, used guns, and turned many a Labour Exchange or Casa di
Popolo into a fortress, but stayed nearly always on the defensive,
waging a trench war against an ever mobile opponent.
At the beginning of July 1922, the CGL, by a two-thirds majority
(against the communist minorityâs one-third), declared its support for
âany government guaranteeing the restoration of basic freedomsâ. In the
same month, the fascists seriously stepped up their attempts to
penetrate the northern citiesâŠ
On August 1st, the Alliance of Labour, which included the railway
workersâ union, the CGL and the anarchist USI, called a general strike.
Despite broad success, the Alliance officially called off the strike on
the 3rd. In numerous cities, however, it continued in insurrectionary
form, which was finally contained only by a combined effort of the
police and the military, supported by naval cannon, and, of course,
reinforced by the fascists.
Who defeated this proletarian energy? The general strike was broken by
the state and the fasci, but it was also smothered by democracy, and its
failure opened the way to a fascist solution to the crisis.
What followed was less a coup dâĂ©tat than a transfer of power with the
support of a whole array of forces. The âMarch on Romeâ of the Duce (who
actually took the train) was less a showdown than a bit of theatre: the
fascists went through the motions of assaulting the state, the state
went through the motions of defending itself, and Mussolini took power.
His ultimatum of October 24 (âWe Want To Become the State!â) was not a
threat of civil war, but a signal to the ruling class that the National
Fascist Party represented the only force capable of restoring state
authority, and of assuring the political unity of the country. The army
could still have contained the fascist groups gathered in Rome, which
were badly equipped and notoriously inferior on the military level, and
the state could have withstood the seditious pressure. But the game was
not being played on the military level. Under the influence of Badoglio
in particular (the commander-in-chief in 1919-21) legitimate authority
caved in. The king refused to proclaim a state of emergency, and on the
30th he asked the Duce to form a new government.
The liberals â the same people anti-fascism counts on to stop fascism â
joined the government. With the exception of the socialists and the
communists, all parties sought a rapprochement with the PNF and voted
for Mussolini: the parliament, with only 35 fascist MPs, supported
Mussoliniâs investiture 306-116. Giolitti himself, the great liberal
icon of the time, an authoritarian reformer who had been head of state
many times before the war, and then again in 1920-21, whom fashionable
thought still fancies in retrospect as the sole politician capable of
opposing Mussolini, supported him up to 1924. Democracy not only
surrendered its powers to the dictator, but ratified them.
We might add that in the following months, several unions, including
those of the railway workers and the sailors, declared themselves
ânationalâ, patriotic, and therefore not hostile to the regime:
repression did not spare them.
If Italian democracy yielded to fascism without a fight, the latter
spawned democracy anew when it found itself no longer corresponding to
the balance of social and political forces.
The central question after 1943, as in 1919, was how to control the
working-class. In Italy more than in other countries, the end of World
War II shows the class dimension of international conflict, which can
never be explained by military logic alone. A general strike erupted at
FIAT in October 1942. In March 1943, a strike wave rocked Turin and
Milan, including attempts at forming workersâ councils. In 1943-45,
worker groups emerged, sometimes independent of the CP, sometimes
calling themselves âBordigistsâ, often simultaneously antifascist,
rossi, and armed. The regime could no longer maintain social
equilibrium, just as the German alliance was becoming untenable against
the rise of the Anglo-Americans, who were seen in every quarter as the
future masters of Western Europe. Changing sides meant allying with the
winners-to-be, but also meant rerouting worker revolts and partisan
groups into a patriotic objective with a social content. On July 10,
1943, the Allies landed in Sicily. On the 24th, finding himself in a
19-17 minority on the Grand Fascist Council, Mussolini resigned. Rarely
has a dictator had to step aside for a majority vote.
Marshal Badoglio, who had been a dignitary of the regime ever since his
support for the March on Rome, and who wanted to prevent, in his own
words, âthe collapse of the regime from swinging too far to the leftâ,
formed a government which was still fascist but which no longer included
the Duce, and turned to the democratic opposition. The democrats refused
to participate, making the departure of the king a condition. After a
second transitional government, Badoglio formed a third in April 1944,
which included the leader of the CP, Togliatti. Under the pressure of
the Allies and of the CP, the democrats agreed to accept the king (the
Republic would be proclaimed by referendum in 1946). But Badoglio
stirred up too many bad memories. In June, Bonomi, who 23 years earlier
had ordered the officers to join the fasci, formed the first ministry to
actually exclude the fascists. This is how Bonomi, ex-socialist,
ex-warmonger, ex-minister, ex-ânational blocâ (fascists included) MP,
ex-government leader from July 1921 to February 1922, ex-everything,
took office for six months as an anti-fascist. Later the situation was
reoriented around the tripartite formula (Stalinists + Socialists +
Christian Democrats) which would dominate both Italy and France in the
first years after the war.
This game of musical chairs, often played by the self-same political
class, was the theatre prop behind which democracy metamorphosed into
dictatorship, and vice-versa. The phases of equilibrium and
disequilibrium in class conflicts brought about a succession of
political forms aimed at maintaining the same state, underwriting the
same content. No one was more qualified to say it than the Spanish CP,
when it declared, out of cynicism or naivety, during the transition from
Francoism to democratic monarchy in the mid-70âs:
âSpanish society wants everything to be transformed so that the normal
functioning of the state can be assured, without detours or social
convulsions. The continuity of the state requires the non-continuity of
the regime.â
Counter-revolution inevitably triumphs on the terrain of revolution.
Through its âpeopleâs communityâ National Socialism would claim to have
eliminated the parliamentarism and bourgeois democracy against which the
proletariat revolted after 1917. But the conservative revolution also
took over old anti-capitalist tendencies (the return to nature, the
flight from citiesâŠ) that the workersâ parties, even the extremist ones,
had misestimated by their refusal to integrate the a-classist and
communitarian dimension of the proletariat, and their inability to think
of the future as anything but an extension of heavy industry. In the
first half of the 19th century, these themes were at the centre of the
socialist movementâs preoccupations, before Marxism abandoned them in
the name of progress and science, and they survived only in anarchism
and in sects.
Volksgemeinschaft vs. Gemeinwesen, peopleâs community or the human
community⊠1933 was not the defeat, only the consummation of the defeat.
Nazism arose and triumphed to defuse, resolve and to close a social
crisis so deep that we still donât appreciate its magnitude. Germany,
cradle of the largest Social Democracy in the world, also gave rise to
the strongest radical, anti-parliamentary, anti-union movement, one
aspiring to a âworkersââ world but also capable of attracting to itself
many other anti-bourgeois and anti-capitalist revolts. The presence of
avant-garde artists in the ranks of the âGerman Leftâ is no accident. It
was symptomatic of an attack on capital as âcivilisationâ in the way
Fourier criticised it. The loss of community, individualism and
gregariousness, sexual poverty, the family both undermined but affirmed
as a refuge, the estrangement from nature, industrialised food,
increasing artificiality, the prostheticisation of man, regimentation of
time, social relations increasingly mediated by money and technique: all
these alienations passed through the fire of a diffuse and multi-formed
critique. Only a superficial backward glance sees this ferment purely
through the prism of its inevitable recuperation.
The counter-revolution triumphed in the 1920âs only by laying the
foundations, in Germany and in the US, of a consumer society and of
Fordism, and by pulling millions of Germans, including workers, into
industrial, commodified modernity. Ten years of fragile rule, as the mad
hyperinflation of 1923 shows. This was followed in 1929 by an earthquake
in which not the proletariat but capitalist practice itself repudiated
the ideology of progress and an ever-increasing consumption of objects
and signs.
Capitalist modernity was questioned twice in ten years, first by
proletarians, then by capital. Nazi extremism and its violence were
adequate to the depth of the revolutionary movement National-Socialism
took over and negated. Like the radicals of 1919-21, Nazism proposed a
community of wage-workers, but one which was authoritarian, closed,
national, and racial, and for twelve years it succeeded in transforming
proletarians into wage-workers and into soldiers.
Fascism grew out of capital, but out of a capital which destroyed old
relationships without producing new stable ones brought about by
consumerism. Commodities failed to give birth to modern capitalist
community.
Dictatorship always comes after the defeat of social movements, once
they have been chloroformed and massacred by democracy, the leftist
parties and the unions. In Italy, several months separated the final
proletarian failures from the appointment of Mussolini as head of state.
In Germany, a gap of a dozen years broke the continuity and made January
30, 1933 appear as an essentially political or ideological phenomenon,
not as the effect of an earlier social earthquake. The popular basis of
National Socialism and the murderous energy it unleashed remain
mysteries if one ignores the question of the submission, revolt, and
control of labour.
The German defeat of 1918 and the fall of the empire set in motion a
proletarian assault strong enough to shake the foundations of society,
but impotent when it came to revolutionising it, thus bringing Social
Democracy and the unions to centre stage as the key to political
equilibrium. Their leaders emerged as men of order, and had no scruples
about calling in the Freikorps, fully fascist groupings with many future
Nazis in their ranks, to repress a radical worker minority in the name
of the interests of the reformist majority. First defeated by the rules
of bourgeois democracy, the communists were also defeated by
working-class democracy: the âworks councilsâ placed their trust in the
traditional organisations, not in the revolutionaries easily denounced
as anti-democrats.
In this juncture, democracy and Social Democracy were indispensable to
German capitalism for killing off the spirit of revolt in the polling
booth, winning a series of reforms from the bosses, and dispersing the
revolutionaries.[25]
After 1929, on the other hand, capitalism needed to eliminate part of
the middle classes, and to discipline the proletarians, and even the
bourgeoisie. The workersâ movement, defending as it did political
pluralism and immediate worker interests, had become an obstacle. As
mediators between capital and labour, working-class organisations derive
their function from both, but also try to remain autonomous from both,
and from the state. Social Democracy has meaning only as a force
contending with the employers and the state, not as an organ absorbed by
them. Its vocation is the management of an enormous political,
municipal, social, mutualist and cultural network. The KPD, moreover,
had quickly constituted its own empire, smaller but vast nonetheless.
But as capital becomes more and more organised, it tends to pull
together all its different strands, bringing a statist element to the
enterprise, a bourgeois element to the trade-union bureaucracy, and a
social element to public administration. The weight of working-class
reformism, which ultimately pervaded the state, and its existence as a
âcounter-societyâ made it a factor of social conservation which capital
in crisis had to eliminate. By their defence of wage-labour as a
component of capital, the SPD and the unions played an indispensable
anti-communist part in 1918-21, but this same function later led them to
put the interest of wage-labour ahead of everything else, to the
detriment of the reorganisation of capital as a whole.
A stable bourgeois state would have tried to solve this problem by
anti-union legislation, by recapturing the âworker fortressâ, and by
pitting the middle classes, in the name of modernity, against the
archaism of the proles, as Thatcherâs England did much later. Such an
offensive assumes that capital is relatively united under the control of
a few dominant factions. But the German bourgeoisie of 1930 was
profoundly divided, the middle classes had collapsed, and the
nation-state was in shambles.
By negotiation or by force, modern democracy represents and reconciles
antagonistic interests, to the extent that this is possible. Endless
parliamentary crises and real or imagined plots (for which Germany was
the stage after the fall of the last socialist chancellor in 1930) in a
democracy are the invariable sign of long-term disarray in ruling
circles. At the beginning of the 1930âs, the crisis whipsawed the
bourgeoisie between irreconcilable social and geopolitical strategies:
either the increased integration or the elimination of the workersâ
movement; international trade and pacifism, or autarchy laying the
foundations of a military expansion. The solution did not necessarily
imply a Hitler, but it did presuppose a concentration of force and
violence in the hands of central government. Once the centrist-reformist
compromise had exhausted itself, the only option left was statist,
protectionist and repressive.
A programme of this kind required the violent dismantling of Social
Democracy, which in its domestication of the workers had come to
exercise excessive influence, while still being incapable of unifying
all of Germany behind it. This unification was the task of Nazism, which
was able to appeal to all classes, from the unemployed to the industrial
tycoons, with a demagogy that even surpassed that of the bourgeois
politicians, and an anti-semitism intended to build cohesion through
exclusion.
How could the working-class parties have made themselves into an
obstacle to such xenophobic and racist madness, after having so often
been the fellow travellers of nationalism? For the SPD, this had been
clear since the turn of the century, obvious in 1914, and signed in
blood in the 1919 pact with the Freikorps, who were cast very much in
the same warrior mould as their contemporaries, the fasci.
Besides, socialists had not been immune to anti-semitism. Abraham
Berlauâs The German Social-Democratic Party 1914-1921 (Columbia 1949)
describes how many SPD or union leaders, and even the prestigious Neue
Zeit, openly raved against âforeignâ (i.e. Polish and Russian) Jews. In
March 1920 the Berlin police (under socialist supervision) raided the
Jewish district and sent about 1000 people to a concentration camp. All
were freed later, but the labour movement did contribute to the spread
of anti-semitism.
The KPD, for its part, had not hesitated to ally with the nationalists
against the French occupation of the Ruhr in 1923. No Comintern
theoretician opposed Radek when he stated that âonly the working-class
can save the nationâ. The KPD leader Thalheimer made it clear that the
party should fight alongside the German bourgeoisie, which played âan
objectively revolutionary role through its foreign policyâ. Later,
around 1930, the KPD demanded a ânational and social liberationâ and
denounced fascism as a âtraitor to the nationâ. Talk of ânational
revolutionâ was so common among German Stalinists that it inspired
Trotskyâs 1931 pamphlet Against National-Communism.
In January 1933, the die was cast. No one can deny that the Weimar
Republic willingly gave itself to Hitler. Both the right and the centre
had come round to seeing him as a viable solution to get the country out
of its impasse, or as a temporary lesser evil. âBig capitalâ, reticent
about any uncontrollable upheaval, had not, up to that time, been any
more generous with the NSDAP than with the other nationalist and
right-wing formations. Only in November 1932 did Schacht, an intimate
adviser of the bourgeoisie, convince business circles to support Hitler
(who had, moreover, just seen his electoral support slightly decline)
because he saw in Hitler a force capable of unifying the state and
society. The fact that industrial magnates did not foresee what then
ensued, leading to war and defeat, is another question, and in any event
they were not notable by their presence in the clandestine resistance to
the regime.
On January 30, 1933 Hitler was appointed chancellor in complete legality
by Hindenburg, who himself had been constitutionally elected president a
year earlier with the support of the socialists, who saw in him a
rampart against⊠Hitler. The Nazis were a minority in the first
government formed by the leader of the NSDAP.
In the following weeks, the masks were taken off: working-class
militants were hunted down, their offices were sacked, and a reign of
terror was launched. In the elections of March 1933, held against the
backdrop of violence by both the storm-troopers and the police, 288
NSDAP MPs were sent to the Reichstag (while the KPD still retained 80
and the SPD 120).
Naive people might express surprise at the docility with which the
repressive apparatus goes over to dictators, but the state machine obeys
the authority commanding it. Did the new leaders not enjoy full
legitimacy? Did eminent jurists not write their decrees in conformity
with the higher laws of the land? In the democratic state â and Weimar
was one â if there is conflict between the two components of the
binomial, it is not democracy which will win out. In a âstate founded on
lawâ â and Weimar was also one â if there is a contradiction, it is law
which must bend to serve the state, and never the opposite.
During these few months, what did the democrats do? Those on the right
accepted the new dispensation. The Zentrum, the Catholic party of the
centre, which had even seen its support increase in the March 1933
elections, voted to give four years of full emergency powers to Hitler,
powers which became the legal basis of Nazi dictatorship.
The socialists, for their part, attempted to avoid the fate of the KPD,
which had been outlawed on February 28 in the wake of the Reichstag
fire. On March 30, 1933, they left the Second International to prove
their national German character. On May 17 their parliamentary group
voted in support of Hitlerâs foreign policy.
On June 22, the SPD was dissolved as âan enemy of the people and the
stateâ. A few weeks later, the Zentrum was forced to dissolve itself.
The unions followed in the footsteps of the Italian CGL, and hoped to
salvage what they could by insisting that they were a-political. In
1932, the union leaders had proclaimed their independence from all
parties and their indifference to the form of the state. This did not
stop them from seeking an accord with Schleicher, who was chancellor
from November 1932 to January 1933, and who was looking for a base and
some credible pro-worker demagogy. Once the Nazis had formed a
government, the union leaders convinced themselves that if they
recognised National Socialism, the regime would leave them some small
space. This strategy culminated in the farce of union members marching
under the swastika on May Day 1933, which had been renamed âFestival of
German Labourâ. It was wasted effort. In the following days, the Nazis
liquidated the unions and arrested the militants.
Having been schooled to contain the masses and to negotiate in their
name or, that failing, to repress them, the working-class bureaucracy
was still fighting the previous war. The labour bureaucrats were not
being attacked for their lack of patriotism. What bothered the
bourgeoisie was not the bureaucratsâ lingering lip service to the old
pre-1914 internationalism, but rather the existence of trade-unions,
however servile, retaining a certain independence in an era in which
even an institution of class collaboration became superfluous if the
state did not completely control it.
In Italy and in Germany, fascism took over the state by legal means.
Democracy capitulated to dictatorship, or, worse still, greeted
dictatorship with open arms. But what about Spain? Far from being the
exceptional case of a resolute action that was nonetheless, and sadly,
defeated, Spain was the extreme case of armed confrontation between
democracy and fascism in which the nature of the struggle still remained
the same clash of two forms of capitalist development, two political
forms of the capitalist state, two state structures fighting for
legitimacy in the same country.
Objection!! â âSo, in your opinion, Franco and a working-class militia
are the same thing? The big landowners and impoverished peasants
collectivising land are in the same camp?!â
First of all, the confrontation happened only because the workers rose
up against fascism. All the contradictions of the movement were manifest
in its first weeks: an undeniable class war was transformed into a
capitalist civil war (though of course there was no assignment of roles
in which the two bourgeois factions orchestrated every act: history is
not a play).[26]
The dynamic of a class-divided society is ultimately shaped by the need
to unify those classes. When, as happened in Spain, a popular explosion
combines with the disarray of the ruling groups, a social crisis becomes
a crisis of the state. Mussolini and Hitler triumphed in countries with
weak, recently unified nation-states and powerful regionalist currents.
In Spain, from the Renaissance until modern times, the state was the
colonial armed might of a commercial society it ultimately ruined,
choking off one of the pre-conditions of industrial expansion: an
agrarian reform. In fact, Spanish industrialisation had to make its way
through monopolies, the misappropriation of public funds, and
parasitism.
Space is lacking here for a summary of the 19th century crazy quilt of
countless reforms and liberal impasses, dynastic squabbles, the Carlist
wars, the tragicomic succession of regimes and parties after World War
I, and the cycle of insurrections and repressions that followed the
establishment of the Republic in 1931. Beneath all these rumblings was
the weakness of the rising bourgeoisie, caught as it was between its
rivalry with the landed oligarchy and the absolute necessity of
containing peasant and worker revolts. In 1936, the land question had
not been resolved: unlike France after 1789, the mid-19th century
sell-off of the Spanish clergyâs lands wound up strengthening a
latifundist bourgeoisie. Even in the years after 1931, the Institute for
Agrarian Reform only used one-third of the funds at its disposal to buy
up large holdings. The conflagration of 1936-39 would never have reached
such political extremes, including the explosion of the state into two
factions fighting a three-year civil war, without the tremors which had
been rising from the social depths for a century.
Spain had no large centre-left bourgeois party like the âParti Radicalâ
which was the centre of gravity of French politics for over sixty years.
Before July 1936, Spanish Social Democracy kept a much more militant
outlook in a country where land was often occupied by wage-labourers,
where strikes were rampant, where Madrid tram workers tried to manage
the workplace, and where crowds stormed jails to free some of the 30,000
political prisoners. As a socialist leader put it: âThe possibilities of
stabilising a democratic republic in our country are decreasing every
day. Elections are but a variant of civil war.â (One might add: a
variant of how to keep it at bay.)
In the summer of 1936, it was an open secret that a military coup was
coming. After giving the rebels every chance to prepare themselves, the
Popular Front elected in February was willing to negotiate and perhaps
even to surrender. The politicians would have made their peace with the
rebels, as they had done during the dictatorship of Primo de Riveira
(1932-31), which was supported by eminent socialists (Caballero had
served it as a technical counsellor, before becoming Minister of Labour
in 1931, and then head of the Republican government from September 1936
to May 1937). Furthermore, the general who had obeyed Republican orders
two years earlier and crushed the Asturias insurrection â Franco â
couldnât be all that bad.
But the proletariat rose up, blocked the putsch in half of the country,
and hung on to its weapons. In so doing, the workers were obviously
fighting fascism, but they were not acting as anti-fascists, because
their actions were directed against Franco and against a democratic
state more unsettled by the massesâ initiative than by the military
revolt. Three prime ministers came and went in 24 hours before the fait
accompli of the arming of the people was accepted.
Once again, the unfolding of the insurrection showed that the problem of
violence is not primarily a technical one. Victory does not go to the
side with the advantage in weaponry (the military) or in numbers (the
people), but rather to who dares to take the initiative. Where workers
trusted the state, the state remained passive or promised the moon, as
happened in Zaragoza. When their struggle was focused and sharp (as in
Malaga) the workers won; if it was lacking in vigour, it was drowned in
blood (20,000 killed in Seville).
Thus the Spanish Civil War began with an authentic insurrection, but
such a characterisation is incomplete. It holds true only for the
opening moment: an effectively proletarian uprising. After defeating the
forces of reaction in a large number of cities, the workers had the
power. But what were they going to do with it? Should they give it back
to the republican state, or should they use it to go further in a
communist direction?
Created immediately after the insurrection, the Central Committee of
Antifascist Militias included delegates from the CNT, the FAI, the UGT
(socialist union), the POUM, the PSUC (product of the recent fusion of
the CP and the socialists in Catalonia), and four representatives of the
Generalitat, the Catalan regional government. As a veritable bridge
between the workersâ movement and the state, and, moreover, tied if not
integrated into the Generalitatâs Department of Defence by the presence
in its midst of the latterâs council of defence, the commissar of public
order, etc., the Central Committee of the Militias quickly began to
unravel.
Of course in giving up their autonomy most proletarians believed that
they were, in spite of everything, hanging onto real power and giving
the politicians only the facade of authority, which they mistrusted, and
which they could control and orient in a favourable direction. Were they
not armed?
This was a fatal error. The question is not: who has the guns? But
rather: what do the people with the guns do? 10,000 or 100,000
proletarians armed to the teeth are nothing if they place their trust in
anything beside their own power to change the world. Otherwise, the next
day, the next month or the next year, the power whose authority they
recognise will take away the guns which they failed to use against it.
âIn fact, the fight in Spain between âlegalâ government and ârebel
forcesâ is in no way a fight for ideals, but a struggle between
determined capitalist groups entrenched in the bourgeois Republic and
other capitalist groups ⊠The Spanish cabinet is no different in its
principles from the bloody Leroux regime which massacred thousands of
Spanish proletarians in 1934 ⊠Spanish workers are now being oppressed
with guns in their hands!â[27]
The insurgents did not take on the legal government, in other words the
state as it then existed, and all their subsequent actions took place
under its auspices. âA revolution had begun but never consolidatedâ, as
Orwell wrote. This is the main point which determined the course of an
increasingly losing armed struggle against Franco, as well as the
exhaustion and destruction by both camps of the collectivisations and
socialisations. After the summer of 1936, real power in Spain was
exercised by the state and not by organisations, unions, collectivities,
committees, etc. Even though Nin, the head of the POUM, was an adviser
to the Ministry of Justice, âThe POUM nowhere succeeded in having any
influence over the policeâ, as one defender of that party admitted.[28]
While the workersâ militias were indeed the flower of the Republican
army and paid a heavy price in combat, they carried no weight in the
decisions of the high command, which steadily integrated them into
regular units (a process completed by the beginning of 1937), preferring
to wear them down rather than tolerating their autonomy. As for the
powerful CNT, it ceded ground to a CP which had been very weak before
July 1936 (having 14 MPs in the Popular Front chamber in February, as
opposed to 85 socialists), but which was able to insinuate itself into
part of the state apparatus and turn the state increasingly to its own
advantage against the radicals, and particularly against the militants
of the CNT. The question was: who mastered the situation? And the answer
was: the state makes subtle and brutal use of its power when it has to.
If the Republican bourgeoisie and the Stalinists lost precious time
dismantling the peasant communes, disarming the POUM militias, and
hunting down Trotskyist âsaboteursâ and other âHitler agentsâ at the
very moment when anti-fascism was supposed to be throwing everything in
the struggle against Franco, they did not do so from a suicidal impulse.
For the state and the CP (which was becoming the backbone of the state
through the military and police) these operations were not a waste of
time. The head of the PSUC supposedly said: âBefore taking Zaragoza, we
have to take Barcelona.â Their main objective was never crushing Franco,
but retaining control of the masses, for this is what states are for,
and this is how Stalinism got its power. Barcelona was taken away from
the proletarians. Zaragoza remained in fascist hands.
On May 3, the police attempted to occupy the Telephone Exchange, which
was under the control of anarchist (and socialist) workers. In the
Catalan metropolis, heart and symbol of the revolution, legal authority
stopped at nothing in disarming whatever remained alive, spontaneous and
anti-bourgeois. The local police, moreover, was in the hands of the
PSUC. Confronted by an openly hostile power, the workers finally
understood that this power was not their own, that they had given it the
gift of their insurrection ten months earlier, and that their
insurrection had been turned against them. In reaction to the power grab
by the state, a general strike paralysed Barcelona. It was too late. The
workers still had the capacity to rise up against the state (this time
in its democratic form), but they could no longer push their struggle to
the point of an open break.
As always, the âsocialâ question predominated over the military one.
Legal authority could not impose itself by street battles. Within a few
hours, instead of urban guerrilla warfare, a war of position, a face-off
of apartment building against apartment building set in. It was a
defensive stalemate in which no one could win because no one was
attacking. With its own offensive bogged down, the police would not risk
its forces in attacks on buildings held by the anarchists. Broadly
speaking, the CP and the state held the centre of the city, while the
CNT and the POUM held the working-class districts.
The status quo ultimately won out by political means. The masses placed
their trust in the two organisations under attack, while the latter,
afraid of alienating the state, got people to go back to work (though
not without difficulty) and thereby undermined the only force capable of
saving them politically and⊠âphysicallyâ. As soon as the strike was
over, knowing that it henceforth controlled the situation, the
government brought in 6,000 Assault Guards â the elite of the police.
Because they accepted the mediation of ârepresentative organisationsâ
and counsels of moderation from the POUM and the CNT, the very same
masses who had defeated the fascist military in July 1936 surrendered
without a fight to the Republican police in May 1937.
At that point repression could begin. Only a few weeks were necessary to
outlaw the POUM, to arrest its leaders, to kill them legally or
otherwise, and to dispose of Nin. A parallel police was established,
organised by the NKVD and the secret apparatus of the Comintern, and
answering only to Moscow. Anyone showing the slightest opposition to the
Republican state and its main ally, the USSR, could be denounced and
hunted down as a âfascistâ, and all around the world an army of
well-meaning, gentle souls would repeat the slander, some from
ignorance, others from self-interest, but every one of them convinced
that no denunciation was too excessive when fascism was on the march.
The fury unleashed against the POUM was no aberration. By opposing the
Moscow Trials, the POUM condemned itself to be destroyed by a Stalinism
locked in a merciless world struggle against its rivals for the control
of the masses. At the time, not just CP fellow-travellers, but many
political parties, lawyers, reporters and even the French League for the
Rights of Man came out in endorsement of the guilt of the accused. Sixty
years later, mainstream ideology sees these trials as a sign of the
Kremlinâs mad will to power. As if Stalinist crimes had nothing to do
with anti-fascism! Anti-fascist logic will always align itself with the
most moderate forces and always turn against the most radical ones.
On the purely political level, May 1937 gave rise to what, a few months
before, would have been unthinkable: a Socialist even farther to the
right than Caballero: Negrin, heading a government which came down hard
on the side of law and order, including open repression against the
workers. Orwell â who almost lost his life in the events â realised that
the war âfor democracyâ was obviously over: âthat meant that the general
movement would be in the direction of some kind of fascism.â What
remained was a competition between two fascisms, Orwell wrote, with the
difference that one was less inhuman than its rival: he therefore clung
to the necessity of avoiding the âmore naked and developed fascism of
Hitler and Francoâ.[29] From then on, the only issue was fighting for a
fascism less bad than the opposing oneâŠ
Power does not come any more from the barrel of a gun than it comes from
a ballot box. No revolution is peaceful, but its âmilitaryâ dimension is
never central. The question is not whether the proles finally decide to
break into the armouries, but whether they unleash what they are:
commodified beings who no longer can and no longer want to exist as
commodities, and whose revolt explodes capitalist logic. Barricades and
machine guns flow from this âweaponâ. The greater the change in social
life, the less guns will be needed, and the less casualties there will
be. A communist revolution will never resemble a slaughter: not from any
nonviolent principle, but because revolution subverts more (soldiers
included) than it actually destroys.
To imagine a proletarian front facing off a bourgeois front is to
conceive the proletariat in bourgeois terms, on the model of a political
revolution or a war (seizing someoneâs power, occupying their
territory). In so doing, one reintroduces everything that the
insurrectionary movement had overwhelmed: hierarchy, a respect for
specialists, for knowledge that Knows, and for techniques to solve
problems â in short for everything that plays down the role of the
common man. In Spain, from the fall of 1936 onward, the revolution
dissolved into the war effort and into a kind of combat typical of
states: a war of fronts. Soon the working-class âmilitia manâ evolved
into a âsoldierâ.
Formed into âcolumnsâ, workers left Barcelona to defeat the fascists in
other cities, starting from Zaragoza. Taking the revolution beyond areas
under Republican control, however, would have meant completing the
revolution in the Republican areas as well. But even Durruti did not
seem to realise that the state was everywhere still intact. As his
column (70% of whose members were anarchists) advanced, it extended the
collectivisations: the militias helped the peasants and spread
revolutionary ideas. Yet however much Durruti declared that âthese
militias will never defend the bourgeoisieâ they did not attack it
either. Two weeks before his death he delivered a speech broadcast on
November 4, 1936:
âAt the front and in the trenches there is only one idea and one aim â
the destruction of fascism.
âWe call on the Catalan people to stop all internal conflicts and
intrigues, to forget all jealousy and politics and to think of the war
only. The politicians are only playing tricks to secure for themselves
an agreeable life. This dubious art must be replaced by the art to work.
The people of Catalonia must be worthy of their brothers fighting at the
front. If the workers of Catalonia have taken the supreme task to fight
at the different fronts, those living in towns and cities will also have
to be mobilised to do their share. Our heroic militia, ready to lie down
their lives on the battlefield want to be assured whom they have behind
them. They feel that no one should be deterred from their duty because
of lack of wage increase or shorter hours of work. Today all toilers and
especially those of the CNT must be ready for the utmost sacrifices. For
in that way alone can we hope to triumph over fascism.
âI address myself to all organisations, asking them to bury their
conflicts and grudgesâŠ
âThe militarisation of the militias has been decreed. If this has been
done to frighten us, to impose on us an iron discipline, this is a
mistaken policy. We challenge those who have issued this decree to come
to the front and see for themselves our moral and our discipline and
compare it with the moral and discipline in the rear. We will not accept
dictated discipline. We are doing our duty. Come to the front to see our
organisation! Later we shall come to Barcelona to examine your
discipline, your organisation and your control!
âThere is no chaos at the front, no lack of discipline. We all have a
strong sense of responsibility. We know what you have entrusted us with.
You can sleep quietly. But remember we have left Barcelona in your
hands. We demand responsibility and discipline from you too. Let us
prove our capacity to prevent the creation of new differences after our
war against fascism. Those who want their movement to be the strongest
are working in the wrong direction. Against tyranny there is only one
front possible, one organisation and only one sort of discipline.â[30]
Listeners would think that a revolution had actually taken place,
politically and socially, and just needed its military completion:
smashing the fascists. Durruti and his comrades embodied an energy which
had not waited for 1936 to storm the existing world. But all the
combative will in the world is not enough when workers aim all their
blows against one particular form of the state, and not against the
state as such. In mid-1936, accepting a war of fronts meant leaving
social and political weapons in the hands of the bourgeoisie behind the
lines, and moreover meant depriving military action itself of the
initial vigour it drew from another terrain, the only one where the
proletariat has the upper hand. As the âDutch Leftâ wrote:
âIf the workers really want to build up a defence front against the
Whites, they can only do so by taking over political power themselves,
instead of leaving it in the hands of a Popular Front government. In
other words, defending the revolution is only possible through the
dictatorship of the proletariat, and not through the collaboration of
all anti-fascist parties ⊠Proletarian revolution revolves around the
destruction of the old state machine, and the exercise of the central
functions of power by the workers themselves.â[31]
In the summer of 1936, far from having decisive military superiority,
the nationalists held no major city. Their main strength lay in the
Foreign Legion and in the Moroccan âMoorsâ. In 1912, Morocco had been
split by France and Spain into two protectorates, but had long since
rebelled against the colonial dreams of both countries. The Spanish
royal army had been badly defeated there in 1921, largely due to the
defection of Moroccan troops. Despite Franco-Spanish collaboration, the
Rif war (in which a general named Franco had distinguished himself)
ended only when Abd el-Krim surrendered in 1926. Ten years later, the
announcement of immediate and unconditional independence for Spanish
Morocco would, at minimum, have stirred up trouble among the shock
troops of reaction. The Republic obviously gave short shrift to this
solution, under a combined pressure from conservative milieus and from
the democracies of England and France, which had little enthusiasm for
the possible break-up of their own empires. At the very time, moreover,
the French Popular Front not only refused to grant any reform worthy of
any name to its colonial subjects, but dissolved the Etoile
Nord-Africaine, a proletarian movement in Algeria.
Everyone knows that the policy of ânon-interventionâ in Spain was a
farce. One week after the putsch London announced its opposition to any
arms shipment to what was then the legal Spanish government, and its
neutrality in the event that France would become drawn into a conflict.
Democratic England thus put the Republic and fascism on the same level.
As a result, the France of Blum and Thorez sent a few planes, while
Italy and Germany sent whole divisions with their supplies. As for the
International Brigades, controlled by the Soviet Union and the CPs,
their military value came at a heavy price, namely the elimination of
any opposition to Stalinism in working-class ranks. It was at the
beginning of 1937, after the first arms shipments, that Catalonia
removed Nin from his post as adviser to the Ministry of Justice.
Rarely has the narrow conception of history as a list of battles,
cannons and strategies been more inept in explaining the course of a
directly âsocialâ war, shaped as it was by the internal dynamic of
anti-fascism. Revolutionary Ă©lan initially broke the Ă©lan of the
nationalists. Then the workers accepted legality: the conflict was
stalemated and then institutionalised. From late 1936 onward, the
militia columns were bogged down in the siege of Zaragoza. The state
armed only the military units it trusted, i.e. the ones which would not
confiscate property. By early 1937, in the poorly equipped POUM militias
fighting the Francoists with old guns, a revolver was a luxury. In the
cities, militia men rubbed shoulders with perfectly outfitted regular
soldiers. The fronts got stuck, like the Barcelona proletarians against
the cops. The last burst of energy was the Republican victory at Madrid.
Soon hereafter, the government ordered private individuals to hand in
their weapons. The decree had little immediate effect, but it showed an
unabashed will to disarm the people. Disappointment and suspicions
undermined morale. The war was increasingly in the hands of specialists.
Finally, the Republic increasingly lost ground as all social content and
revolutionary appearances faded away in the anti-fascist camp.
Reducing the revolution to war simplifies and falsifies the social
question into the alternative of winning or losing, and in being âthe
strongestâ. The issue becomes one of having disciplined soldiers,
superior logistics, competent officers and the support of allies whose
own political nature gets as little scrutiny as possible. Curiously, all
this means taking the conflict further from daily life. It is a peculiar
quality of warfare that, even for its enthusiasts, no one wants to lose
but everyone wants it to end. In contrast to revolution, except in the
case of defeat, war does not cross my doorstep. Transformed into a
military conflict, the struggle against Franco ceased to be a personal
commitment, lost its immediate reality, and became a mobilisation from
above, like in any other war situation. After January 1937, voluntary
enlistments tapered off, and the civil war, in both camps, came to
depend mainly on compulsory military service. As a result a militia man
of July 1936 leaving his column a year later, disgusted with Republican
politics, could be arrested and shot as a âdeserterâ!
In different historical conditions, the military evolution from
insurrection to militias and then to a regular army is reminiscent of
the anti-Napoleonic âguerrillaâ warfare (the term was borrowed from
Spanish at the time) described by Marx:
âBy comparing the three periods of guerrilla warfare with the political
history of Spain, it is found that they represent the respective degrees
into which the counter-revolutionary spirit of the Government had
succeeded in cooling the spirit of the people. Beginning with the rise
of whole populations, the partisan war was next carried on by guerrilla
bands, of which whole districts formed the reserve, and terminated in
corps francs continually on the point of dwindling into banditti, or
sinking down to the level of standing regiments.â[32]
For 1936, as for 1808, the evolution of the military situation cannot be
explained exclusively or even mainly by the art of war, but flows from
the balance of political and social forces and its modification in an
anti-revolutionary direction. The compromise evoked by Durruti, the
necessity of unity at any cost, could only hand victory first to the
Republican state (over the proletariat) and then to the Francoist state
(over the Republic).
There was the beginning of a revolution in Spain, but it turned into its
opposite as the proletarians, convinced that they had effective power,
placed their trust in the state to fight against Franco. On that basis,
the multiplicity of subversive initiatives and measures taken in
production and in daily life were doomed by the simple and terrible fact
that they took place in the shadow of an intact state structure, which
had initially been put on hold, and then reinvigorated by the
necessities of the war against Franco, a paradox which remained opaque
to most revolutionary groups at the time. In order to be consolidated
and extended, the transformations without which revolution becomes an
empty word had to pose themselves as antagonistic to a state clearly
designed as the adversary.
The trouble was, after July 1936, dual power existed in appearance only.
Not only did the instruments of proletarian power which emerged from the
insurrection, and those which subsequently oversaw the socialisations,
tolerate the state, but they accorded the state a primacy in the
anti-Franco struggle, as if it were tactically necessary to pass through
the state in order to defeat Franco. In terms of ârealismâ, the recourse
to traditional military methods accepted by the far left (including the
POUM and the CNT) in the name of effectiveness almost invariably proved
ineffective. Sixty years later, people still deplore the fact. But the
democratic state is as little suited for armed struggle against fascism
as it is for stopping its peaceful accession to power. States are
normally loath to deal with social war, and normally fear rather than
encourage fraternisation. When, in Guadalajara, the anti-fascists
addressed themselves as workers to the Italian soldiers sent by
Mussolini, a group of Italians defected. Such an episode remained the
exception.
From the battle for Madrid (March â37) to the final fall of Catalonia
(February â39), the cadaver of the aborted revolution decomposed on the
battlefield. One can speak of war in Spain, not of revolution. This war
wound up having as its first function the resolution of a capitalist
problem: the constitution in Spain of a legitimate state which succeeded
in developing its national capital while keeping the popular masses in
check. In February 1939, the Surrealist and (then) Trotskyist Benjamin
PĂ©ret analysed the consummation of the defeat as follows:
âThe working class⊠having lost sight of its own goals, no longer sees
any urgent reason to be killed defending the bourgeois democratic clan
against the fascist clan, i.e. in the last analysis, for the defence of
Anglo-French capital against Italo-German imperialism. The civil war
increasingly became an imperialist war.â[33]
That same year, Bruno Rizzi made a similar comment in his essay on
âcollective bureaucratismâ in the USSR:
âThe old democracies play the game of anti-fascist politics in order to
let the sleeping dog lie. One must keep the proletarians quiet⊠at any
time, the old democracies feed the working class with anti-fascismâŠ
Spain had turned into a slaughter of proletarians of all nationalities,
in order to calm down unruly revolutionary workers, and to sell off the
products of heavy industry.â
The two camps undeniably had quite different sociological compositions.
If the bourgeoisie was present on both sides, the immense majority of
workers and poor peasants supported the Republic, whereas the archaic
and reactionary strata (landed property, small holders, clergy) lined up
behind Franco. This class polarisation gave a progressive aura to the
Republican state, but it did not disclose the historical meaning of the
conflict, any more than the large working-class membership of socialist
or Stalinist parties told us all about their nature. Such facts were
real, but secondary to the social function of these parties: in fact,
because they were grass-roots bodies, they were able to control or
oppose any proletarian upsurge. Likewise the Republican army had a large
number of workers, but for what, with whom and under whose orders were
they fighting? To ask the question is to answer it, unless one it
considers possible to fight the bourgeoisie in an alliance with the
bourgeoisie.
âCivil war is the supreme expression of the class struggleâ, Trotsky
wrote in Their Morals and Ours (1938). Quite⊠as long as one adds that,
from the âWars of Religionâ to the Irish or Lebanese convulsions of our
own time, civil war is also, and indeed most often, the form of an
impossible or failed social struggle: when class contradictions cannot
assert themselves as such, they erupt as ideological or ethnic blocs,
still further delaying any human emancipation.
Social Democracy did not âcapitulateâ in August 1914, like a fighter
throwing in the towel: it followed the normal trajectory of a powerful
movement which was internationalist in rhetoric and which, in reality,
had become profoundly national long before. The SPD may well have been
the leading electoral force in Germany in 1912, but it was powerful only
for the purpose of reform, within the framework of capitalism and
according to its laws, which included for example accepting colonialism,
and also war when the latter became the sole solution to social and
political contradictions.
In the same way, the integration of Spanish anarchism in the state in
1936 is only surprising if one forgets its nature: the CNT was a union,
an original union undoubtedly but a union all the same, and there is no
such thing as an anti-union union. Function transforms the organ.
Whatever its original ideals, every permanent organism for defending
wage labourers as such becomes a mediator, and then a conciliator. Even
when it is in the hands of radicals, even when it is repressed, the
institution is bound to escape control of the base and to turn into a
moderating instrument. Anarchist union though it may have been, the CNT
was a union before it was anarchist. A world separated the rank-and-file
from the leader seated at the bossesâ table, but the CNT as a whole was
little different from the UGT. Both of them worked to modernise and
rationally manage the economy: in a word, to socialise capitalism. A
single thread connects the socialist vote for war credits in August 1914
to the participation in the government of the anarchist leaders, first
in Catalonia (September â36) and then in the Spanish Republic (November
â36). As early as 1914, Malatesta had called those of his comrades
(including Kropotkin) who had accepted national defence âgovernment
anarchistsâ.
The CNT had long been both institutionalised and subversive. The
contradiction ended in the 1931 general election, when the CNT gave up
its anti-parliamentary stand, asking the masses to vote for Republican
candidates. The anarchist organisation was turning into âa union
aspiring to the conquest of powerâ, that would âinevitably lead to a
dictatorship over the proletariatâ.[34]
From one compromise to the next, the CNT wound up renouncing the
anti-statism which was its raison dâĂȘtre, even after the Republic and
its Russian ally or master had shown their real faces in May â37, not to
mention everything that followed, in the jails and secrets cellars. Like
the POUM, the CNT was effective in disarming proletarians, calling on
them to give up their struggle against the official and Stalinist police
bent on finishing them off. As the GIC put it,
ââŠthe CNT was among those chiefly responsible for the crushing of the
insurrection. It demoralised the proletariat at a time when the latter
was moving against democratic reactionaries.â[35]
Some radicals even had the bitter surprise of being locked up in a
prison administered by an old anarchist comrade, stripped of any real
power over what went on in his jail. Adding insult to injury, a CNT
delegation which had gone to the Soviet Union requesting material aid
did not even raise the issue of the Moscow Trials.
Everything for the anti-fascist struggle!
Everything for cannons and guns!
But even so, some people might object, anarchists by their very nature
are vaccinated against the statist virus. Isnât anarchism the arch-enemy
of the state? Yes, butâŠ
Some Marxists can recite whole pages of The Civil War in France on the
destruction of the state machine, and quote the passage from State and
Revolution where Lenin says that one day cooks will administer society
instead of politicians. But these same Marxists can practice the most
servile state idolatry, once they come to see the state as the agent of
progress or historical necessity. Because they imagine the future as a
capitalist socialisation without capitalists, as a world still based on
wage labour but egalitarian, democratised and planned, everything
prepares them to accept a state (transitional, to be sure) and to go off
to war for a capitalist state they see as bad, against another they see
as worse.
Anarchism overestimates state power by regarding authority as the main
enemy, and at the same time underestimates the stateâs force of inertia.
The state is the guarantor, but not the creator, of social
relationships. It represents and unifies capital, it is neither
capitalâs motor nor its centrepiece. From the undeniable fact that the
Spanish masses were armed after July 1936, anarchism deduced that the
state was losing its substance. But the substance of the state resides
not in institutional forms, but in its unifying function. The state
ensures the tie which human beings cannot and dare not create among
themselves, and creates a web of services which are both parasitic and
real.
In the summer of 1936, the state apparatus may have seemed derelict in
Republican Spain, because it only subsisted as a potential framework
capable of picking up the pieces of capitalist society and re-arranging
them one day. In the meantime, it continued to live, in social
hibernation. Then it gained new strength when the relations opened up by
subversion were loosened or torn apart. It revived its organs, and, the
occasion permitting, assumed control over those bodies which subversion
had caused to emerge. What had been seen as an empty shell showed itself
capable not only of revival, but of actually emptying out the parallel
forms of power in which the revolution thought it had best embodied
itself.
The CNTâs ultimate justification of its role comes down to the idea that
the government no longer really had power, because the workersâ movement
had taken power de facto.
ââŠthe government has ceased to be a force oppressing the working-class,
in the same way that the state is no longer the organism dividing
society into classes. And if CNT members work within the state and
government, the people will be less and less oppressed.â[36]
No less than Marxism, anarchism fetishizes the state and imagines it as
being incarnated in a place. Blanqui had already thrown his little armed
flock into attacks on city halls or on barracks, but he at least never
claimed to base his actions on the proletarian movement, only on a
minority that would awaken the people. A century later, the CNT declared
the Spanish state to be a phantom relative to the tangible reality of
the âsocial organisationsâ (i.e. militias, unions). But the existence of
the state, its raison dâĂȘtre, is to paper over the shortcomings of
âcivilâ society by a system of relations, of links, of a concentration
of forces, an administrative, police, judicial, and military network
which goes âon holdâ as a backup in times of crisis, awaiting the moment
when a police investigator can go sniffing into the files of the social
worker. The revolution has no Bastille, police station or governorâs
mansion to âtakeâ: its task is to render harmless or destroy everything
from which such places draw their substance.
The depth and breadth of the industrial and agrarian socialisations
after July 1936 was no historical fluke. Marx noted the Spanish
tradition of popular autonomy, and the gap between the people and the
state which made itself manifest in the anti-Napoleonic war, and then in
the revolutions of the 19th century, which renewed age-old communal
resistance to the power of the dynasty. The absolute monarchy, he
observed, did not shake up various strata to forge a modern state, but
rather left the living forces of the country intact. Napoleon could see
Spain as a âcadaver,
⊠but if the Spanish state was indeed dead, Spanish society was full of
lifeâ and âwhat we call the state in the modern sense of the word is
materialised, in reality, only in the army, in keeping with the
exclusive âprovincialâ life of the people.â[37]
In the Spain of 1936, the bourgeois revolution had been made, and it was
vain to dream of scenarios such as 1917, not to mention 1848 or 1789.
But if the bourgeoisie dominated politically, and capital dominated
economically, they were nowhere near the creation of a unified internal
market and a modern state apparatus, the subjugation of society as a
whole, and the domination of local life and its particularism. For Marx
in 1854 a âdespoticâ government coexisted with a lack of unity that
extended to the point of different currencies and different systems of
taxation: his observation still had some validity eighty years later.
The state was neither able to stimulate industry nor carry out agrarian
reform; it could neither extract from agriculture the profits necessary
for capital accumulation, nor unify the provinces, nor less keep down
the proletarians of the cities and the countryside.
It was thus almost naturally that the shock of July â36 gave rise, on
the margins of political power, to a social movement whose real
expressions, while containing communist potential, were later reabsorbed
by the state they allowed to remain intact. The first months of a
revolution already ebbing, but whose extent still concealed its failure,
looked like a splintering process: each region, commune, enterprise,
collective and municipality escaped the central authority without
actually attacking it, and set out to live differently. Anarchism, and
even the regionalism of the POUM, express this Spanish originality,
which is wrongly grasped if one sees only the negative side of this
âlateâ capitalist development. Even the ebb of 1937 did not eradicate
the Ă©lan of hundreds of thousands of workers and peasants who took over
land, factories, neighbourhoods, villages, seizing property and
socialising production with an autonomy and a solidarity in daily life
that struck both observers and participants.[38] Communism is also the
re-appropriation of the conditions of existence.
Sad to say, if these countless acts and deeds, sometimes extending over
several years, bear witness (as do, in their own way, the Russian and
German experience) to a communist movement remaking all of society, and
to its formidable subversive capacities when it emerges on a large
scale, it is equally true that its fate was sealed from the summer of
1936 onward. The Spanish Civil War proved both the revolutionary vigour
of communitarian bonds and forms which have been penetrated by capital
but which are not yet daily reproduced by capital, and also their
impotence, taken by themselves, in bringing off a revolution. The
absence of an assault against the state condemned the establishment of
different relationships to a fragmentary self-management preserving the
content and often the forms of capitalism, notably money and the
division of activities by individual enterprises. Any persistence of
wage-labour perpetuates the hierarchy of functions and incomes.
Communist measures could have undermined the social bases of the two
states (Republican and Nationalist), if only by solving the agrarian
question: in the 1930âs, more than half of the population went hungry. A
subversive force erupted, bringing to the fore the most oppressed
strata, those farthest from âpolitical lifeâ (e.g. women), but it could
not go all the way and eradicate the system root and branch.
At the time, the workersâ movement in the major industrial countries
corresponded to those regions of the world which had been socialised by
a total domination of capital over society, where communism was both
closer at hand as a result of this socialisation, and at the same time
farther away because of the dissolution of all relations into commodity
form. The new world, in these countries, was most commonly conceived as
a workerâs world, even as an industrial one.
The Spanish proletariat, on the contrary, continued to be shaped by a
capitalist penetration of society that was more quantitative than
qualitative. From this reality it drew both its strength and its
weakness, as attested by the tradition and demands for autonomy
represented by anarchism.
âIn the last hundred years, there has not been a single uprising in
Andalusia which has not resulted in the creation of communes, the
sharing out of land, the abolition of money and a declaration of
independence ⊠the anarchism of the workers is not very different. They
too demand, first of all, the possibility of managing their industrial
community or their union themselves, and then the reduction of working
hours and of the effort required from everyone âŠâ[39]
One of the main weaknesses was the attitude towards money. The
âdisappearance of moneyâ is meaningful only if it entails more than the
replacement of one instrument for measuring value with another one (such
as labour coupons). Like most radical groups, whether they called
themselves Marxist or anarchist, Spanish proletarians did not see money
as the expression and abstraction of real relationships, but as a tool
of measurement, an accounting device, and they reduced socialism to a
different management of the same categories and fundamental components
of capitalism.
The failure of the measures taken against commodity relations was not
due to the power of the UGT (which was opposed to the collectivisations)
over the banks. The closing of private banks and of the central bank
puts an end to mercantile relations only if production and life are
organised in a way no longer mediated by the commodity, and if such a
communal production and life gradually come to dominate the totality of
social relationships. Money is not the âevilâ to be removed from an
otherwise âgoodâ production, but the manifestation (today becoming
increasingly immaterial) of the commodity character of all aspects of
life. It cannot be destroyed by eliminating signs, but only when
exchange withers away as a social relationship.
In fact, only agrarian collectives managed to do without money, and they
often did so with the help of local currencies, with coupons often being
used as âinternal moneyâ. Sometimes money was handed over to the
collective. Sometimes workers were given vouchers according to the size
of their families, not to the amount of work done (âto each according to
their needâ). Sometimes money played no part: goods were shared. An
egalitarian spirit prevailed, as well as a rejection of âluxuryâ.[40]
However, unable to extend non-commodity production beyond different
autonomous zones with no scope for global action, the soviets,
collectives and liberated villages were transformed into precarious
communities, and sooner or later were either destroyed from within or
violently suppressed by the fascists⊠or the Republicans. In Aragon, the
column of the Stalinist Lister made this a speciality. Entering the
village of Calanda, his first act was to write on a wall:
âCollectivisations are theft.â
Ever since the First International, anarchism has counterposed the
collective appropriation of the means of production to Social Democratic
statism. Both visions, nonetheless, have the same starting point: the
need for collective management. The problem is: management of what? Of
course, what Social Democracy carried out from above, bureaucratically,
the Spanish proletarians practised at the base, armed, with each
individual responsible to everyone, thereby taking the land and the
factories away from a minority specialised in the organising and
exploitation of others. The opposite, in short, of the co-management of
the Coal Board by socialist or Stalinist union officials. Nevertheless,
the fact that a collectivity, rather than the state or a bureaucracy,
takes the production of its material life into its own hands does not,
by itself, do away with the capitalist character of that life.
Wage labour means the passage of an activity, whatever it might be,
ploughing a field or printing a newspaper, through the form of money.
This money, while it makes the activity possible, is expanded by it.
Equalising wages, deciding everything collectively, and replacing
currency by coupons has never been enough to do away with wage labour.
What money brings together cannot be free, and sooner or later money
becomes its master.
Substituting association for competition on a local basis was a
guaranteed recipe for disaster. Because if the collective did abolish
private property within itself, it also set itself up as a distinct
entity and as a particular element among others in the global economy,
and therefore as a private collective, compelled to buy and sell, to
trade with the outside world, thereby becoming in its turn an enterprise
which like it or not, had to play its part in regional, national and
world competition or else disappear.
One can only rejoice in the fact that half of Spain imploded: what
mainstream opinion calls âanarchyâ is a necessary condition for
revolution, as Marx wrote in his own time. But these movements made
their subversive impact on the basis of a centrifugal force. Rejuvenated
communitarian ties also locked everyone into their village and their
barrio, as if the point were to discover a lost world and a degraded
humanity, to counterpose the working-class neighbourhood to the
metropolis, the self-managed commune to the vast capitalist domain, the
countryside of the common folk to the commercialized city, in a word the
poor to the rich, the small to the large and the local to the
international, all the while forgetting that a co-operative is often the
longest road to capitalism.
There is no revolution without the destruction of the state. But how?
Beating off armed bands, getting rid of state structures and habits,
setting up new modes of debate and decision â all these tasks are
impossible if they do no go hand in hand with communisation. We donât
want âpowerâ, we want the power to change all of life. As an historical
process extending over generations, can one imagine over such a time
frame continuing to pay wages for food and lodging? If the revolution is
supposed to be political first and social later, it would create an
apparatus whose sole function would be the struggle against the
supporters of the old world, i.e. a negative function of repression, a
system of control resting on no other content than its âprogrammeâ and
its will to realise communism the day that conditions finally allow for
it. This is how a revolution ideologises itself and legitimises the
birth of a specialised stratum assigned to oversee the maturation and
the expectation of the ever-radiant day after tomorrow. The very stuff
of politics is not being able, and not wanting, to change anything: it
brings together what is separated without going any further. Power is
there, it manages, it administers, it oversees, it calms, it represses:
it is.
Political domination (in which a whole school of thought sees problem
number one) flows from the incapacity of human beings to take charge of
themselves, and to organise their lives and their activity. This
domination persists only through the radical dispossession which
characterises the proletarian. When everyone participates in the
production of their existence, the capacity for pressure and oppression
now in the hands of the state will cease to be operative. It is because
wage-labour society deprives us of our means of living, producing and
communicating, not stopping short of the invasion of once-private space
and of our emotional lives, that the state is all-powerful. The best
guarantee against the reappearance of a new structure of power over us
is the deepest possible appropriation of the conditions of existence, at
every level. For example, even if we donât want everyone generating
their own electricity in their basements, the domination of the
Leviathan also comes from the fact that energy (a significant term,
another word for which is power) makes us dependent on industrial
complexes which, nuclear or not, inevitably remain external to us and
escape any control.
To conceive the destruction of the state as an armed struggle against
the police and the armed forces is to mistake the part for the whole.
Communism is first of all activity. A mode of life in which men and
women produce their social existence paralyses or reabsorbs the
emergence of separate powers.
The alternative upheld by Bordiga: âShall we take over the factory, or
take over power?â (Il Soviet, February 20, 1920) can and must be
superseded. We donât say: it does not matter who manages production,
whether an executive or a council, because what counts is to have
production without value. We say: as long as production for value
continues, as long as it is separated from the rest of life, as long as
humankind does not collectively produce its ways and means of existence,
as long as there is an âeconomyâ, any council is bound to lose its power
to an executive. This is where we differ both from âcouncilistsâ and
âBordigistsâ, and why we are likely to be called Bordigists by the
former, and councilists by the latter.
The Spanish failure of 1936-37 is symmetrical to the Russian failure of
1917-21. The Russian workers were able to seize power, not to use it for
a communist transformation. Backwardness, economic ruin and
international isolation by themselves do not explain the involution. The
perspective set out by Marx, and perhaps applicable in a different way
after 1917, of a renaissance in a new form of communal agrarian
structures, was at the time not even thinkable. Leaving aside Leninâs
eulogy for Taylorism, and Trotskyâs justification of military labour,
for almost all the Bolsheviks and the overwhelming majority of the Third
International, including the Communist Left, socialism meant a
capitalist socialisation plus soviets, and the agriculture of the future
was conceived as democratically managed large landholdings. (The
difference â and it is a major one! â between the German-Dutch left and
the Comintern was that the Left took soviets and worker democracy
seriously, whereas the Russian communists, as their practice proved, saw
in them nothing but tactical formulas.)
The Bolsheviks are the best illustration of what happens to a power
which is only a power, and which has to hold on without changing real
conditions very much.
What distinguishes reform from revolution is not that revolution is
violent, but that it links insurrection and communisation. The Russian
civil war was won in 1919, but sealed the fate of the revolution, as the
victory over the Whites was achieved without communising society, and
ended in a new state power. In his 1939 Brown Fascism, Red Fascism, Otto
RĂŒhle pointed out how the French Revolution had given birth to a
military structure and strategy adequate to its social content. It
unified the bourgeoisie with the people, while the Russian revolution
failed to create an army based on proletarian principles. The Red Army
that Poland defeated in 1920 hardly kept any revolutionary significance.
As early as mid-1918, Trotsky summed it up in three words: âwork,
discipline, orderâ.
Very logically and, at least in the beginning, in perfectly good faith,
the soviet state perpetuated itself at any cost, first in the
perspective of world revolution, then for itself, with the absolute
priority being to preserve the unity of a society coming apart at the
seams. This explains, on one hand, the concessions to small peasant
property, followed by requisitions, both of which resulted in a further
unravelling of any communal life or production. On the other hand, it
also explains the repression against workers and against any opposition
within the party.
In January 1921, the wheel had come full circle. The 1917 revolutionary
wave set in motion by mutinies and basic democratic demands ended in the
same way â except this time proles were being repressed by a
âproletarianâ state. A power which gets to the point of massacring the
Kronstadt mutineers in the name of a socialism it could not realise, and
which goes on to justify its action with lies and calumny, is only
demonstrating that it no longer has any communist character. Lenin died
his physical death in 1924, but the revolutionary Lenin had died as head
of state in 1921, if not earlier. Bolshevism was left with no option but
to become the manager of capitalism.
As the hypertrophy of a political perspective hell bent on eliminating
the obstacles which it could not subvert, the October Revolution
dissolved in a self-cannibalising civil war. Its pathos was that of a
power which, unable to transform society, degenerated into a
counter-revolutionary force.
In the Spanish tragedy, the proletarians, because they had left their
own terrain, wound up prisoners of a conflict in which the bourgeoisie
and its state were present behind the front lines on both sides. In
1936-37, the proletarians of Spain were not fighting against Franco
alone, but also against the fascist countries, against the democracies
and the farce of ânon-interventionâ, against their own state, against
the Soviet Union, against...
The âItalianâ and âGerman-Dutchâ communist Left (including Mattick in
the US) were among the very few who defined the post-1933 period as
utterly anti-revolutionary, whereas many groups (Trotskyists, for
example) were prompt to foresee subversive potentials in France, in
Spain, in America, etc.
1937 closed the historical moment opened by 1917. From then on, capital
would not accept any other community but its own, which meant there
could no longer be permanent radical proletarian groups of any
significant size. The demise of the POUM was tantamount to the end of
the former workersâ movement.
In a future revolutionary period, the most subtle and most dangerous
defenders of capitalism will not be the people shouting pro-capitalist
and pro-statist slogans, but those who have understood the possible
point of a total rupture. Far from eulogising TV commercials and social
submission, they will propose to change life⊠but, to that end, call for
building a true democratic power first. If they succeed in dominating
the situation, the creation of this new political form will use up
peopleâs energy, fritter away radical aspirations and, with the means
becoming the end, will once again turn revolution into an ideology.
Against them, and of course against overtly capitalist reaction, the
proletariansâ only path to success will be the multiplication of
concrete communist initiatives, which will naturally often be denounced
as anti-democratic or even as⊠âfascistâ. The struggle to establish
places and moments for deliberation and decision, making possible the
autonomy of the movement, will prove inseparable from practical measures
aimed at changing life.
ââŠin all past revolutions, the mode of activity has always remained
intact and the only issue has been a different distribution of this
activity and a redistribution of work among different persons; whereas
the communist revolution is directed against the mode of activity as it
has existed up till now and abolishes work and the domination of all
classes by abolishing classes themselves, because it is carried out by
the class which no longer counts as a class in society, which is not
recognised as a class, and is in itself the expression of the
dissolution of all classes, nationalities, etc. within present
societyâŠâ[41]
prolétariat. Théorie Communiste , no. 16, 2000 A critique of Gilles
Dauvé's When Insurrections Die Translated by Endnotes .
In When Insurrections Die we find the normative conception of the
history of class struggle in its purity. On the first page Dauvé puts in
place the vocabulary of this problematic: a vocabulary of âmissedâ
chances and âfailedâ materialisations. Throughout the text fascism and
Nazism are described as the result of the limits of the class struggles
of the preceding period, but these limits are defined in relation to
Communism (with a big âCâ) rather than in relation to the struggles of
that period. Meanwhile the history of capital is referred to a
contradiction which overreaches it, a general contradiction of history:
the separation between man and community, between human activity and
society:
âDemocracy will never be able to solve the problem of the most separated
society in history.â[42]
But this was never its intention. Only the society in which the
relations between people are the strongest and most developed produces
the fiction of the isolated individual. The question is never to know
how individuals, determined by a mode of production, are linked together
by a political form, but why these social bonds take the form of
politics. A certain type of individual corresponds to a certain type of
community; individuals form communities as limited as themselves.
Democracy (the state in general) is the form of this community at the
political level; it does not respond to a general separation â such a
separation does not exist. To say that democracy responds âbadlyâ to
separation is to say that this general separation is the general dynamic
of history (an idea broadly developed in La Banquise).
We are told that the workers were defeated by democracy (with the aid of
the parties and unions); but the objectives â the content â of these
workersâ struggles (in Italy, Spain, Germany) always remains unspoken.
We are thus plunged into the problematic of âbetrayalâ by the parties
and unions.[43] That the workers obeyed reformist movements â it is
precisely this that ought to have been explained â and on the basis of
the nature of those struggles themselves, rather than letting the
nebulous shadows of manipulation and trickery pass for explanation.
âProletarians trusted the democratsâ[44], the very same proletariat
which fought capital âusing its own methods and goalsâ[45]; methods and
goals which are never defined. Dauvé goes so far as to ask the question,
âWho defeated this proletarian energy?â[46] but nothing is ever said of
the content, the forms and the limits proper to this energy. It is
proletarian energy and that is all. For Dauvé the central question was
âhow to control the working class?â[47] but before asking this question
we need to ask another one: âWhat does the working class do?â This
always seems self-evident in the text, just a matter of âproletarian
energyâ. Why then did the âcontrolâ succeed in â21 and in â43 (in
Italy)? These are the questions to which the text only responds
anecdotally; or else in the profound manner weâll see later on: the
workers failed and were beaten because they didnât make the revolution â
a collapse into tautology.
We find this same indeterminate ârevolutionary energyâ in the analysis
of the working class defeat and subsequent victory of Nazism in Germany:
âThe German defeat of 1918 and the fall of the empire set in motion a
proletarian assault [we must be dealing with a manifestation of
âproletarian energyâ] strong enough to shake the foundations of society,
but impotent to revolutionize it, thus bringing Social Democracy and the
unions to centre stage as the key to political equilibriumâ.[48]
We are not told anything else about this âproletarian assaultâ. Why is
it not powerful enough to revolutionise society? Thatâs the question,
however, and the only one we need answer. Things seem so obvious to the
author, itâs enough to say âproletariatâ and ârevolutionâ. At one moment
he fleetingly gives us an indication: the German radical movement is
described as âaspiring to a workersâ worldâ.[48] But this comment of
fundamental import isnât developed; here it serves only as a sort of
detail which does not resolve the question of defeat, and it is
immediately downplayed by the generality of the âproletarian assaultâ.
The key to the problematic is given to us in an incidental remark:
âBut the conservative revolution also took over old anti-capitalist
tendencies (the return to nature, the flight to citiesâŠ) that the
workersâ parties, even the extremist ones, had misestimated by their
refusal to integrate the a-classist and communitarian dimension of the
proletariat, and their inability to think of the future as anything but
an extension of heavy industry.â[49]
Weâll leave aside the struggles of the Nazi regime against heavy
industry; itâs the âproletarian energyâ which interests us. This energy
resides in this âa-classist and communitarian dimensionâ. If this is so,
once this dimension is proclaimed, everything else â that is the real
history of class struggles â can be nothing more than a succession of
forms more or less adequate to it. The general pattern of the argument
is then as follows: man and society are separate and this is the
foundation of all history; all the historic forms of human society are
built on this separation and try to resolve them but only through
alienated forms. Capital is the society in which the contradiction is
pushed to its limits, but simultaneously (Hegel to the rescue!) it is
the society which gives birth to a class with this communal dimension,
an a-classist class. As for capital, it is forced to respond to the same
question of separation (which, letâs not forget, is just a form of
social bond), with the state, democracy, politics. We have arrived at
the simple opposition of two answers to the same question. It is no
longer proletariat and capital which are the terms of the contradiction
within the capitalist mode of production, but the human community
carried by the proletariat and politics (the state) which confront each
other, the only connection between them being that they are opposing
solutions to the trans-historical problem of the separation of man and
society, individual and community. We can find this problematic in
developed form in La Banquiseâs âThe Story of Our Originsâ (LB no. 2).
This whole problematic ignores the basic axiom of materialism: that a
certain type of individual corresponds to a certain type of community.
The proletariat does not have an a-classist or communitarian dimension:
it has, in its contradiction with capital, the ability to abolish
capital and class society and to produce community (the social immediacy
of the individual). This is not a dimension that it carries within
itself â neither as a nature that comes to it from its situation in the
capitalist mode of production, nor as the finally discovered subject of
the general tendency of history towards community.
Unable, in such a problematic, to consider class struggle as the real
history of its immediate forms and to understand that its particular
historical content exhausts the totality of what transpires in the
struggle (and not as a historical form of something else), Dauvé never
tells us why the revolution failed, or why it is that every time the
state, the parties, the unions want to destroy the revolutionary
movement, it works. âCounter-revolution inevitably triumphs on the
terrain of revolutionâ[50] â exactly, but we never find out why the
counter-revolution wins out in relation to the historical
characteristics of the revolution. The author describes how it happens,
but leaves it at that. Given the general problematic, the only
explanation has to be tautological: the revolution failed because it
didnât go further. In saying this weâve said nothing on the actually
existing failure of the actually existing revolution. âIn this juncture,
democracy and Social Democracy were indispensable to German capitalism
for killing off the spirit of revolt in the polling booth, winning a
series of reforms from the bosses, and dispersing the
revolutionaries.â[51] But the relation of this activity of the
capitalist class and social democracy to the historical content of the
revolution itself, which alone would tell us why âit worksâ, has not
been explained; herein lies the necessary blind spot of this
problematic.
The chapter on Spain takes the impasses of this problematic to an
extreme. Dauvé describes precisely the counter-revolution (we have no
disagreement on this), but he only talks about the revolution on the
basis of what it didnât do, in relation to what it should have done and
as a succession of âfatal errorsâ:
âAfter defeating the forces of reaction in a large number of cities, the
workers had the power. But what were they going to do with it? Should
they give it back to the republican state, or should they use it to go
further in a communist direction?â[52]
We know the answer, and DauvĂ© explains to us in great detail the âfatal
errorâ of the Spanish revolutionaries who failed to take on the legal
government, the State. But why did they make this error, was this error
not bound up with the very nature of the âproletarian assaultâ? (It was
certainly fatal, but whether we can talk of an error is less sure).
These are the real questions which this problematic cannot address. âIn
May ÂŽ37, workers still had the capacity to rise up against the state
(this time in its democratic form), but they could no longer push their
struggle to the point of an open breakâ[53]â so this capacity did exist
in July 1936. For DauvĂ© the masses are âdeceivedâ by the CNT and the
POUM who are afraid of alienating the State:
âBecause they accepted the mediation of ârepresentative organisationsâ
and counsels of moderation from the POUM and the CNT, the very same
masses who had defeated the fascist military in July 1936 surrendered
without a fight to the Republican police in May 1937.â[54]
If we follow this interpretation, Spanish proletarians are idiots. It is
extraordinary to write such expressions as: âthe masses placed their
trustâ, âfatal errorâ, âthe proletarians, convinced that they had
effective powerâ, âbecause they accepted the mediationâŠ,â without a
single moment of doubt, or a question such as: but why does it work? Why
did they give their trust? Why did this error happen? Why this
conviction? If these questions donât even momentarily occur, we should
nonetheless ask ourselves why not.
The point is that in the text the proletariat is by nature
revolutionary, and, even better, communist. It is a given that history
is the history of the separation of man and society; as for
proletarians, they are âcommodified beings who no longer can and no
longer want to exist as commodities, and whose revolt explodes
capitalist logicâ. Proletarians are, in themselves, contradictory
beings, and as such they carry the community â communism â within
themselves. It follows that when they fail to make the revolution, itâs
that they are wrong, or have been deceived. Thus it is that which failed
to happen which becomes the explanation for what actually happened.
The formula âcommodified beings, etc.â leaves shrouded in darkness
theoretical questions which could not be more arduous or decisive. The
proletarians are here the crux of an internal contradiction, one of
whose terms is left unsaid and is taken as given: on the one hand they
are commodities, but in the name of what, on the other, do they no
longer want to be this? Elementary: they are men. The social definition
of the proletariat in a specific mode of production gives way to a
hybrid definition: commodity and man. But who then is this man who is
not the ensemble of his social relations through which he is merely a
commodity?
From the moment that the revolutionary nature of the proletariat is
constructed as this contradictory hybridisation of man and commodity,
the history of the class struggle â and more precisely of revolution and
communism â disappears. Communism is inscribed once and for all in the
nature of the proletariat. That the proletariat canât and doesnât want
to remain what it is, is not a contradiction internal to its nature,
intrinsic to its being, but rather the actuality of its contradictory
relation to capital in a historically specific mode of production. It is
the relation to capital of that particular commodity which is labour
power, as a relation of exploitation, which is the revolutionary
relation. Posed in this way, it is necessarily a history: that of this
contradiction. The class struggle in Barcelona in May â37 was not the
movement of communism in general (even in these particular conditions)
which fell short for reasons which can never be given; it was rather the
revolution as it really existed, that is to say, as affirmation of the
proletariat drawing its force and the content of its autonomy from its
very condition inside the capitalist mode of production. âErrorsâ now
appear as what they are, inherent limits, to the extent that the
revolution implies its own counter-revolution. The affirmation of the
autonomy of the proletariat implies the affirmation of what it is in
capital; that is where it finds its power and the raison dÂŽĂȘtre for its
action, at the same time as the essential link between this action and
the counter-revolution is produced.
The affirmation of an âa-classistâ, âcommunitarianâ dimension of the
proletariat merely derives from a poor understanding of an era of the
class struggle (up to the 1840s) and not from the revolutionary nature
of the proletariat. However, this allows the proletariat to be
constructed as figure of humanity, as representation of a pre-existing
contradiction. Communism is presupposed as tension, as tendency, which
opposes itself to capital from the outset of the capitalist mode of
production and aims to explode it. This is different from affirming that
communism is the movement which abolishes existing conditions, that is
to say the movement of the internal contradiction of these conditions.
Moreover, if the proletariat is invested with this dimension, the
historical process of the class struggle is no longer really necessary
in relation to the revolution: it is merely a process of realisation.
This causes the slippage in the analysis whereby the contradiction
between communism and capital comes to replace the contradiction between
the proletariat and capital.
If we come back to the course of the Spanish civil war as described in
the text, what is striking is the use of the subjunctive and the
conditional: âTaking the revolution beyond areas under republican
control, however, would have meant completing the revolution in the
republican areas as wellâ.[55] What failed to happen is always the
explanation for what actually happened: âbut even Durruti did not seem
to realize that the state was everywhere still intact.â Everything
happens as if there were a huge thermometer with a scale up to Communist
Revolution (human community): you stick it into a sensitive point of
events and see how far the mercury rises, then you explain that the
mercury only rose that far because it failed to rise any further.
However âDurruti and his comrades embodied an energy which had not
waited for 1936 to storm the existing worldâ.[56] âProletarian energyâ
plays a starring role in this vision of history: it is what makes the
mercury rise in the thermometer. It is, like in the old physics, one of
those ineffable forces destined to wrap up all tautologies. We note in
passing that âenergyâ is embodied, just like âmomentumâ.[57] Ultimately,
without explaining why the Spanish revolution fails to go further and
what its essential relation to the counter-revolution is, Dauvé
accumulates all the perfectly pertinent âhowsâ, but without ever
providing us with the beginnings of an explanation; unless it is in the
conditional, with the condition being what should have been done:
âthe announcement of immediate and unconditional independence for
Spanish Morocco would, at minimum, have stirred up trouble among the
shock troops of reaction.â[58]
âIn order to be consolidated and extended, the transformations without
which revolution becomes an empty word had to pose themselves as
antagonistic to a state clearly designed as the adversary. The trouble
was, after July 1936, dual power existed in appearance only. Not only
did the instruments of proletarian power which emerged from the
insurrection, and those which subsequently oversaw the socialisations,
tolerate the state, but they accorded the state a primacy in the
anti-Franco struggle, as if it were tactically necessary to pass through
the state in order to defeat Franco.â[59]
âCommunist measures could have undermined the social bases of the two
states (republican and nationalist), if only by solving the agrarian
question: in the 1930âs, more than half of the population went hungry. A
subversive force erupted, bringing to the fore the most oppressed
strata, those farthest from âpolitical lifeâ (e.g. women), but it could
not go all the way and eradicate the system root and branch.â[60]
Why? To answer that question the revolution must be defined other than
as ârevolutionary Ă©lanâ, âcommunist potentialâ or âaborted
revolutionâ.[61] The contradiction between the proletariat and capital
must be considered as a relation of reciprocal implication, and
revolution and communism as historical products â not as the result of
the nature of the revolutionary class defined as such once and for all.
For Dauvé the German revolution, like the Russian and Spanish ones,
testifies to âa communist movement remaking all of societyâ.[62] But it
is precisely the nature of this communist movement, at this particular
juncture in the history of the contradiction between the proletariat and
capital, that must be defined if we want to understand its limits and
its relation to the counter-revolution without reducing it to what it
should have done and what it wasnât. Nevertheless the author furnishes
us with an explanation of the limits of the revolution, albeit without
seeming to attribute much importance to it:
âThe Spanish Civil War proved both the revolutionary vigour of
communitarian bonds and forms which have been penetrated by capital but
which are not yet daily reproduced by capital, and also their impotence,
taken by themselves, in bringing off a revolution. The absence of an
assault against the state condemned the establishment of different
relationships to a fragmentary self-management preserving the content
and often the forms of capitalism, notably money and the division of
activities by individual enterprises.â[63]
And what if it was precisely these bonds and these forms which prevented
the âassaultâ? And what if this were just a particular form of the
affirmation of the proletariat? Dauvé does not ask himself this type of
question, because for him the particular conditions are always merely
the conditions in relation to what the revolution must do, and not the
very form of the revolution at a given moment. In this brief but very
interesting passage he does not escape a problematic of objective
conditions / revolutionary nature. These particular conditions which he
calls to our attention should have been those which nonetheless should
have produced an assault against the state. In consequence this
explanation of the limits is given but doesnât intervene in the general
reasoning. If it had intervened, Dauvé would have been forced to
historically specify the ârevolutionary vigourâ, the ârevolutionary
Ă©lanâ, and could no longer have spoken of âaborted revolutionâ or
âcommunist potentialitiesâ. He would no longer have been able to explain
what had happened by what hadnât, and all the âwould-have-beensâ would
have had no sense. As it is he is content to juxtapose an ahistorical
vision of the revolution and of communism with the conditions which will
give it form, which will model it. The history of class struggle is here
always double: on the one hand the communist principle, the Ă©lan or
revolutionary energy which animates the proletariat, a transcendent
history, and on the other, the limited manifestation of this energy, an
anecdotal history. Between these two aspects there exists a hierarchy.
Transcendent history is ârealâ history, and real history with all its
limits is only the accidental form of the former, so much so that the
former is constantly the judgment of the latter.
One can hardly question DauvĂ©âs remark on the condition of social
relations in 1930âs Spain, but either it was possible to do what he says
it would have been necessary to do, and thus the conditions could have
been overcome, or it was not possible and in that case the conditionals
of Dauvé lose all rational signification. Such a situation would have
been overcome if the revolutionary Ă©lan was that which he presupposes in
his analysis. But if it was a matter of a programmatic struggle, such a
situation (communal bonds) is a material that it reworks according to
its own nature.
One could consider that the whole of this historical text is a work of
reflection on what the revolution must and can be today. But the problem
with Dauvé is that he presents this in an eternal, atemporal, fashion;
so much so that if we finish more knowledgeable we have nonetheless made
no advance on the essential question: question: why could the revolution
be today what it wasnât in the past?
We should make it clear: we are absolutely in agreement with the
sequence of facts that Dauvé presents, as much for Germany as for Spain
(with some reservations in regard to Russia). His conception of the
communist revolution is entirely our own as far as its content and
communist measures are concerned, its comprehension as communisation and
not as prior to this communisation. Where we differ profoundly is on the
comprehension of the course of class struggle as the juxtaposition of a
given, known, communist principle within the being of the proletariat,
and a history which contents itself with expressing this principle in a
partial, confused or aborted fashion. Its not a question of the method
of historical analysis; this isnât a quarrel between philosophers of
history. As always, what is at stake is the comprehension of the current
period. DauvĂ©âs method renders impossible the comprehension of the
overcoming of programmatism, of the revolution as affirmation of the
proletariat.[64] The communist revolution as we can currently conceive
it, as it presents itself in this cycle of struggle, is for him already
there (limited, aborted, with errors and illusions, etc.) in the
Russian, German and Spanish revolutions. Thus even when we say that we
are in agreement with the conception of the revolution that he presents
at the end of his brochure, this is because he does not see that this
revolution is not â is no longer â that of Russia etc. They were
revolutions of the cycle of struggle in which the proletariat was
affirmed; this is no longer the case today. The confusion is not without
consequences for any theory based on the current situation of the
relation between the proletariat and capital, on the comprehension of
current struggles and on the revolution as produced overcoming of this
cycle of struggle. That is to say, on the way one takes these struggles
as really productive of their overcoming (practically and theoretically)
and not as to be judged in relation to this overcoming already posed as
a norm. The history of class struggle is production and not realisation.
[48]p. 38
Proletariatâ by ThĂ©orie Communiste. Originally published as âHumain,
Trop Humain?â, appendix to Quand Meurent Les Insurrections (When
Insurrections Die ), (La Sociale, Montreal 2000), pp. 69â77. Translated
by Endnotes .
It is for the reader to judge whether, as Théorie Communiste think, When
Insurrections Die explains what happened by what didnât happen. We
believe that in that article we set out first what proletarians actually
did, and then what they werenât able or didnât want to do. âYet no
lessons but negative ones can be drawn from all these undertakings [the
struggles of the German proletariat from 1919 to 1923]⊠The lesson
learned was how not to proceed.â[65] To jump back and forth between
yesterday and tomorrow has its dangers, but is more illuminating than
the explanation according to which every social movement ineluctably
ends up where it is driven by its epoch.
âMankind thus inevitably sets itself only such tasks as it is able to
solve, since closer examination will always show that the problem itself
arises only when the material conditions for its solution are already
present or at least in the course of formation.â[66]
So be it. It remains for us to determine these conditions, and which
goal they correspond to. Otherwise we limit ourselves to demonstrating
how what had to happen happened. To reconstruct two hundred years of
class struggles from the knowledge which we now have of them is not
without interest. But what privilege permits the observer in the year
2000 to know that his standpoint is ultimately the right one? Nothing
can guarantee that in 2050, after 50 more years of capitalism, an even
more broad-ranging overview wonât establish for x + y reasons the ways
in which the proletarians of the year 2000 (and with them TC along with
G. Dauvé) remained historically constrained by the limits of their
times, and thus that communism wasnât actually in the offing in the year
2000 any more than it was in 1970 or 1919, but that now a new period is
ushering itself in, allowing us to genuinely grasp the past from the
new, proper viewpoint. Nothing guarantees it, except the certainty of
the opening of a totally different historical epoch towards the end of
the 20th century. To be sure, the conviction of TC is well buttressed
and argued. Despite everything, however, it is not a caricature to read
a new version of the âfinal crisisâ in this vision of a phase in which
proletariat and capital are supposedly from now on face to face,
enabling proletarians to call into question their own existence as
class, thus posing the question of communism in all its nakedness.
More than a mere theoretical position, it is this way of situating
oneself in relation to the world, this ultimatism, which is
questionable.[67]
Capitalism will only be non-reproducible the day when proletarians cease
producing it. There is no objective limit to a social system.
Proletarians only give themselves tasks that they are able to and want
to resolve.
Théorie Communiste steers clear of the conditional and subjunctive
modes. However, just as one of the traits of language is projection into
the future, man is also characterised by his capacity to think what
could be, to reinterpret the past on the basis of the collective choices
made by social groups, and thus to consider what could have been.
History is a conjunction of possibilities and wills. Freedom consists
not in being able to do anything one wants, but in wanting what one can
do. Which is another way of saying âMen make their own history ⊠but
under circumstances directly encountered, given and transmitted from the
pastâ[68], circumstances which they donât invent, but which it is within
their power to modify.
âWillâ, âfreedomâ, âManâ: these are all words which disturb the
theoretical rigour of TC. Unfortunately, to refuse all concepts which
are exterior to capitalism is to condemn oneself to thinking nothing but
capitalism. The fate of capitalism is not intelligible on the basis of
capitalism alone. To reject all concepts which refer to an outside of
the capital/wage-labour structure amounts to building a model that is
irrefutable because it refers only to itself. What would be the use in a
proletarian structuralism?
We donât postulate an irreducible, ahistorical human nature which ends
up bursting the capitalist fetter.
âUnderneath labour lies activityâ, stated an article in La Banquise.[69]
Idealism? Everything depends on the underneath. It is false to conceive
of capitalism as a prison from which, one glorious dawn, will emerge a
virtuality which today is enclosed. That would presuppose an always
already existing positivity, constrained by capital and waiting to
escape.
What exists, on the contrary, neither anterior nor exterior to capital,
but consubstantial with it, and as indispensable condition of its
functioning, is the universal scope of living labour, from which it
feeds every day.
Not in the sense in which labour is presumed as the essential
characteristic of Man defined as homo faber.
More simply, proletarians are not bovines. A man is not put to work like
an animal is. The most manual occupation demands more than mere
expenditure of muscle: a grasp, an anticipation of the gesture, a
savoir-faire not eliminated by Taylorism, an acquired skill which the
worker can then transmit. This faculty includes the representation of
what other workers do and are, including if they live 10,000km away. The
horse can refuse the work demanded of it, kill its master, escape and
finish its days free, but it cannot initiate another form of life which
reorganises the life of the former master as well. Capital is only
capital because it exploits not only the product of labour but that
which is human: a power to work, an energy which is always collective,
which capital manages but can never completely dominate, which it
depends on and which can put it into crisis â or even a revolution.
Proletarianisation is not the loss of some prior existing thing, but the
exploitation of a human capacity. Alienation is only transhistorical to
the extent that capitalism recapitulates a multi-millenarian past.
Something becomes other: this is certainly one of the characteristics of
wage-labour. The latter effects a dispossession, not of an undefinable
humanity, but of time constrained, energy used, acts forced by capital
which is thereby valorised. What the proletarian loses every day is not
a strip of some eternal nature, but a force of life, a social capacity
which the beast of burden does not have at its disposal, and which is
thus a reality internal to the wage relation. Itâs not a question of
introducing a human dimension into the analysis, but of seeing that it
is to be found there.
A fundamental contribution of the German-Dutch Left, and its
descendents, is to have emphasised this.
âIf the worker is, even from the economic point of view, more than a
machine, it is because he produces for the capitalist more than he costs
him, and above all because in the course of his labour he manifests the
creativity, the capacity to produce ever more and ever better, than any
productive class of previous periods ever possessed. When the capitalist
treats the proletariat as livestock, he learns quickly to his expense
that livestock cannot fulfil the function of the worker, because the
productivity of over-exploited workers decreases rapidly. This is the
deep root of the contradictions of the modern system of exploitation and
the historical reason of its failure, of its incapacity to stabilise
itself.â[70]
Socialisme ou Barbarie, like councilism, reduced the generic character
which is the foundation of wage-labour to the dimension of its
management. This fact, however, cannot blind us to that which these
currents, which reflect the struggles for self-activity and autonomy
against the bosses, bureaucracy and the State, brought to light: it is
the proletariat which capitalism places in a situation of universality.
The important thing is not that proletarians produce riches (which for
the most part impoverish us), but that they themselves are the ever more
totalising but never total commodification of activity and life. Since
the proletarian is the commodity which produces all the others, he
contains them all, holds the key to his own exploitation, and in
negating himself as commodified-being, can revolutionise the world of
the commodity. No previous exploited class lived a similar potentiality.
In fact, even if they died from overwork, the slave, the serf, the
peasant under the yoke of the corvée and tax, the artisan and the worker
before the industrial revolution, were only ferociously exploited in one
part of their existence, a large portion of which remained outside the
control of the dominant class. The serfâs vegetable garden wasnât of
interest to the lord. Modern proletarians produce the totality of
material life, they lose it, then they receive it back in the form of
the commodity and the spectacle, and this takes the form of the global
circulation of goods and labour. Itâs for this reason that capitalism
was theorised a hundred and fifty years ago as the realisation, if not
the completion, of a double tendency of the universalisation of humanity
and its alienation.
Between 1830 and 1848, a minority perceived society at a limit-point:
proletarians can only reappropriate the totality of the conditions of
life, ânot only to achieve self-activity, but, also, merely to safeguard
their very existence.â[71] The announced revolution will use productive
forces, but wonât be a revolution of the producers. Technology is only
valid as a flowering of individuals, with the supersession of
professional capacities: ânow the isolation of individuals and each
personâs particular way of gaining his livelihood have themselves become
accidental.â[72]
âThus, while the fugitive serfs only wished to have full scope to
develop and assert those conditions of existence which were already
there, and hence, in the end, only arrived at free labour, the
proletarians, if they are to assert themselves as individuals, have to
abolish hitherto prevailing condition of their existence (which has,
moreover, been that of all society up to then), namely, labour. Thus
they find themselves directly opposed to the form in which, hitherto,
the individuals, of which society consists, have given themselves
collective expression, that is, the state; in order, therefore, to
assert themselves as individuals, they must overthrow the State.â[73]
Beyond the glaring contradiction between an increasing production of
wealth which impoverishes its producers, the more radical perceived a
historic opening, through the contradiction of labour, âwhich is now the
only possible but, as we see, negative form of self-activity.â[74]
From the clash between artisans a new figure could emerge beyond the
creator-artist and the proletarian-servant of the machine. Thanks to
commodified labour, which was unattached and indifferent to its content,
but collective, it became possible to envisage association, and the
supersession of the wage form (still too recent to appear ânaturalâ).
The âProletariatâ is thus conceived as that which will compose another
society. It already configures a kind of society, since classes dissolve
themselves in it. It sucks in artisans and peasants, attracts a
proportion of âintellectualsâ, and doesnât form a bloc or entity, but
expresses a social decomposition (or a recomposition as revolutionaries
hope). Proletarians experience unemployment, poverty, uprooting, the
breakdown of the family, of customs, of identities, of values, and at
the same time act collectively (as seen in insurrections, chartism,
trade-unions, Tristanâs Union OuvriĂšre, Luddism too, of which the later
trade unions gave the falsified image of a brute force, spontaneous but
limited). The proletariat of before 1848 is an ensemble disaggregated
enough to criticise itself, but still communitarian enough to want to
struggle, and by the breaking-down of barriers between
worker/non-worker, artisan/labourer, manual/intellectual⊠accede to a
free association. The organised workersâ movement subsequently both took
on and denied this heritage, and the communist horizon has been fixed on
sociology for more than a century.
Under the weight of the epoch, Marx himself, although aiming for âa
description of the characteristics of communist societyâ[75] considered
it increasingly on the basis of capitalism, and by dint of criticising
political economy became enclosed within it. What is the interest in
scientifically âprovingâ exploitation, instead of exposing how
exploitation exploits that which can produce communism?
Itâs not a case of opting for the âyoungâ Marx against the âoldâ Marx,
but of understanding that the âyoungâ Marx contains the âoldâ Marx a lot
more than the âoldâ Marx contains the âyoungâ Marx. Thus the
intellectual involution echoes a historical stabilisation. The
perspective is impoverished in the International Workingmenâs
Association or the Commune when compared to that of the middle of the
century, which the author of the 1844 Manuscripts synthesised the best,
but which others had also expressed.[76]
The revolution didnât occur around 1848, and it would be vain to expect
that computerisation will finally render âhistorically necessaryâ in the
year 2000 that which large-scale mechanised industry was supposed to
achieve before 1914 or nascent automation after 1960.
What is true is that every profound reorganisation of the productive
system materially impoverishes the workers, but also dispossesses them
of a relative mastery over their work, and unleashes resistance and
revolts, often conservative, but revolutionary perhaps. The calling into
question by capitalism of the forms of wage-labour opens up a path of
rupture with the wage condition. Each time, nothing guarantees that a
communist movement will be able or want to take advantage of it, but the
possibility is there, which makes of the proletariat the âoverthrowing
classâ.[77]
A hypothesis: we are living in a new charnel-epoch in which capitalism
is able to create poles of profit for itself, technically innovate and
multiply consumer goods, create employment and/or income, calm riots,
but not unify the global society of generalised labour at the very
moment in which the latter becomes inessential. From the fetid cellars
of Lille or Manchester in 1840 to the living-rooms of council
tower-blocks where the VCR has pride of place, the problem remains: how
to put wage-earners to work if they are profitable, and what to do with
them when they are not? At one extreme, in China, 100 million uprooted
ex-rurals which the capitalist city wonât be able to integrate. At the
other end of the chain, in Seine-Saint-Denis (TN: Parisian suburb ):
school until 22 years old; training schemes; insignificant, precarious
jobs; benefits. Between the two, the United States. For Emmanuel Todd
(Lâillusion Ă©conomique), âthe biggest success of the American system of
production is anti-economicâ. The question isnât whether there is no way
out of the situation for capital, but whether it reopens a way out for
the proletariat as a class not of workers, but of the critique of work.
The limit of capital is that it is unable to do without labour, which it
indeed generalises, making millions of beings enter into wage labour, at
the same time as it reduces labour to a negligible role. To remedy this,
thinkers such as Andre Gorz propose the delinking of money from labour,
in order to accord to everybody a share in consumption, whether they
have participated in production or not. Such a society is impossible:
even if it were ten times more automated, our world would still rest
upon labour. Proletarians will remain the necessary evil of capitalism.
A question: is it possible to pass from the moment where capital refuses
many proletarians (in particular young ones) to the refusal of this
world and its labour by proletarians (particularly lots of young ones)?
What will be done by these âmasses resulting from the drastic
dissolution of society, mainly of the middle estate, that form the
proletariatâŠâ
â⊠By proclaiming the dissolution of the hereto existing world order,
the proletariat merely proclaims the secret of its own existence, for it
is in fact the dissolution of that world order. By demanding the
negation of private property, the proletariat merely raises to the rank
of a principle of society what society has made the principle of the
proletariat, what without its own co-operation, is already incorporated
in it as the negative result of society.â[78]
On the basis of what he had in front of his eyes â i.e. nascent
industrialisation, Marx theorised a period (to come) of dislocation of
classes, which was simultaneously the effect of a profound social crisis
and the conscious action of proletarians. For him, the proletariat of
1844, but also one hundred or two hundred years later, is the ensemble
of categories having in common that they live only from the sale of
their labour-power, whether they are in work or without it, partially
employed, precarious or protected by a statute but susceptible (if not,
a brother, or a daughterâŠ) to falling into a fragile category. The
proletariat exists as dissolution of classes in the sense that it is and
effects this dissolution. It is both the product and the process of this
dissolution, by a revolution âin which, further, the proletariat rids
itself of everything that still clings to it from its previous position
in society.â[79] It is not a question of it forming a bloc like an army
against another, but that it puts into practice the negation which it is
already, going beyond individualism as well as massification.
ââŠstanding over against these productive forces, we have the majority of
the individuals from whom these forces have been wrested away, and who,
robbed thus of all real life-content, have become abstract individuals,
but who are, however, only by this fact put into a position to enter
into relation with one another as individuals.â[80]
ââŠthe communal relationship into which the individuals of a class
entered, and which was determined by their common interests over against
a third party, was always a community to which these individuals
belonged only as average individuals, only insofar as they lived within
the conditions of existence of their class â a relationship in which
they participated not as individuals but as members of a class. With the
community of revolutionary proletarians, on the other hand, who take
their conditions of existence and those of all members of society under
their control, it is just the reverse; it is as individuals that the
individuals participate in it. It is just this combination of
individuals (assuming the advanced stage of modern productive forces, of
course) which puts the conditions of the free development and movement
of individuals under their control â conditions which were previously
abandoned to chance and had won an independent existence over against
the separate individuals just because of their separation as
individuals, and because of the necessity of their combination.â[81]
According to ThĂ©orie Communiste, âthe proletarian of the young Marx is
the personal individual for whom the previous social determinations have
become a matter of contingency, and it is this situation in itself which
is posed as revolutionary.â[82] However this proletarian evoked by Marx
is more than an individual, as he shares (in his head and his actions)
his fate with millions of others. Is he so individual, this individual
who is weighed down by a historical constraint, this being who is
endlessly âexcludedâ from production then coercively re-included, and by
the same token who, because his condition doesnât enclose him in a
factory, an occupation or a particular place, is able to do what the CGT
metalworker proved himself to be incapable of: to pass from one category
to another, not to think of himself one-sidedly as âworkerâ or âout of
workâ, to manifest a certain fluidity, a freedomâŠ
Proletarians can fight exploitation, either to merely impose some limits
upon it, or to bring an end to it by producing communist social
relations. How does the link between the two operate? Even the most
resolved and most autonomous movement will only challenge society if it
manifests the practical demand for another life, in a word if its acts
contain or acquire a universal dimension. The communist revolution is
precisely the moment of fusion between the struggle against exploitation
and the struggle against alienation. No historical dialectic can deliver
the key to this in advance.
dâamour?â, Lettre de Troploin no. 2, 2002. This version, translated by
the authors, first published as âTo Work or not to Work? Is that the
Question?â, (Troploin Newsletter no. 3, 2002). Some passages from the
original which were removed have been reinserted for the sake of
continuity with the text that follows. Published in Endnotes #1.
A historical failure: 154 years after Marxâs and Engelsâ Manifesto, that
could be a blunt but not too unfair summary of the communist movement.
One interpretation of such a miscarriage centres on the importance or
prevalence given to work. From the 1960s onwards, a more and more
visible resistance to work, sometimes to the point of open rebellion,
has led quite a few revolutionaries to revisit the past from the point
of view of the acceptance or rejection of work. Former social movements
are said to have failed because the labourers tried to have labour rule
society, i.e. tried to liberate themselves by using the very medium of
their enslavement: work. In contrast, true emancipation would be based
on the refusal of work, seen as the only effective subversion of
bourgeois and bureaucratic domination alike. Only work refusal would
have a universal dimension able to transcend quantitative claims, and to
put forward a qualitative demand for an altogether different life.
The Situationists were among the most articulate proponents of this
view: âNever work!â[83] Later, in Italy particularly, a number of formal
and informal groups, often called autonomous, attempted to develop and
systematise spontaneous anti-work activities.[84]
The refusal of work has become the underlying theme of many a theory on
past and present struggles. Defeats are explained by the acceptance of
work, partial successes by active shop-floor insubordination, and a
revolution to come is equated with a complete rejection of work.
According to this analysis, in the past, workers shared the cult of
production. Now they can free themselves of the delusion of work,
because capitalism is depriving it of interest or human content, while
making hundreds of millions of people jobless.
In Germany, Krisis recently gave an excellent illustration of the
transformation of the anti-work stand into the philosopherâs stone of
revolution.[85]
But since the 70s, mainly in France, the role of work has also been
reinterpreted in a different light: up to now the labouring classes have
only tried to assert themselves as the class of labour and to socialise
work, not to do away with it, because up to now capitalist development
prevented communist prospects from emerging. Whatever the proletarians
(or radical minorities) may have thought, they were fighting for a
capitalism without capitalists, for a worker led capitalism. A real
critique of work was impossible in the 60s-70s, and the â68 period is
analysed as the last possible effort of labour to pose itself as the
dominant pole within the capital/wage labour couple. Now things are
completely different, because a restructured capital no longer leaves
any scope for a workersâ capitalism. ThĂ©orie Communiste has been the
main exponent of this perspective.[86]
Weâre not lumping together people as different from each other as the SI
and ThĂ©orie Communiste. Weâre only dealing with one important point they
have in common: the belief that asserting the importance of labour was a
major obstacle to revolution, and that this obstacle has been removed
more by capitalist development than by the proletarians themselves. It
seems to us that these views are false in regard to the facts, and even
more so in regard to the method, the attitude in relation to the world
to be transformed. However, their defenders clearly uphold revolution as
communisation, destruction of the State and abolition of classes. So
this essay will be less of a refutation than an attempt to think twice
about work.
A profusion of data shows that for centuries the workers used their
professional ability and dignity as justifications for what they
regarded as their due. They acted as if their right to a fair wage (and
to fair prices, in the âmoral economyâ described by E.P. Thompson)
derived from their toil and competence.
But, if they claimed and rebelled in the name of work, were they
fighting for a world where they would take their mastersâ place?
Answering the question implies distinguishing between workersâ practice
and workersâ ideology.
Old time social movements are depicted as endeavours to achieve a utopia
where labour would be king. This certainly was one of their dimensions,
but not the only one, nor the one that gave coherence to all the others.
Otherwise, how do we account for the frequent demand to work less? In
1539, in Lyons, printing workers went on a four months strike for
shorter hours and longer public holidays. In the 18th century, French
paper-makers used to take âillegalâ holidays. Marx mentions how English
bourgeois were shocked by workers who, chose to work (and earn) less, by
only coming to the factory four days a week instead of six.
âTo live as a worker, or die as a fighter.â The famous Lyons
silk-workersâ motto of the 1830s of course signifies a claim for work,
but less for work as a positive reality than as a means of resisting
deteriorating pay. The 1834 silk-workersâ insurrection was not prompted
by machines that would have deprived them of their jobs â the machines
were already there. The workers actually fought the power of the
merchants who allocated work at their own discretion and paid very
little. When the silk-worker spoke highly of the quality of his silk, he
was not talking like a medieval master craftsman â his life was the
subject-matter.
In June 1848, it is true that the closure of the National Workshops by
the government led to the Paris insurrection. But these workshops were
no social model, only a means to keep the jobless busy. The actual work
done was socially unprofitable, and of no interest to the recipients.
The insurgents rose to survive, not to defend a guaranteed nationalised
or socialised form of work that they would have regarded as an embryo of
socialism.
At the time, many strikes and riots took place against mechanization.
They expressed the resistance of craftsmen anxious to save the (real and
imagined) rich human content of their skills, but equally they tried to
curb further exploitation. When Rouen textile workers managed to prevent
more efficient machinery being installed, they were not fighting for a
trade, they were putting a (temporary) stop to worsening living
conditions. Meanwhile, other Normandy textile hands were asking for a
10-hour day, and construction workers for the end of overtime, which
they regarded as a cause of accidents and unemployment.
As for the Paris Commune, when it took over a few firms, imposed a wage
rate or forced owners to re-open the plants, its main purpose was to
provide these wage-earners with an income. Taking charge of production
was no priority for the Communards.
This short survey of the 19th century points to a juxtaposition of
struggles. Some could be labelled modern. In that they aimed at higher
wages and sometimes rejected work (in a nutshell, less working hours and
more pay). Others aimed through producer and consumer cooperatives at a
working class take over of industrialisation by which the working
classes would put an end to capital and become a sort of total capital.
Association was then a keyword that summed up the ambiguity of the time:
it conveyed the ideas both of mercantile links and of fraternal unity.
Many workers hoped that co-ops would be more competitive than private
business, would eliminate capitalists from the market and from their
social function, and maybe force them to join the associated workers.
United labour would have beaten the bourgeois at their own game.
1848 tolled the death knell of the utopia of a wage-labour capital, of a
working class that would become the ruling class and then the unique or
universal class through the absorption of capital in associated labour.
From then on, via a growing union movement, the workers will only be
concerned with their share of the wage system, they wonât try to compete
with the monopoly of capital owned by the bourgeoisie, but to constitute
themselves as a monopoly of labour power. The programme of a popular
capitalism was on the wane. At the same time, the ruling classes gave up
any attempt at the âdifferentâ capitalism imagined and sometimes
practised by innovative and generous industrialists like Owen. At both
ends of the wage system, capital and labour knew their place.
This explains the paradox of a social movement that was so keen on
separating labour from capital, but which finally created so few
producersâ cooperatives. The ones that existed were born out of the will
of enlightened bourgeois, or, if they had a worker origin, soon turned
into business as usual.
The Albi Workersâ Glassworks in the south of France illustrates this
tendency. The highly skilled glass workers, still organised on a
pre-1789 guild model, had kept their control over apprenticeship. It
took 15 years to be a fully-fledged glass-blower. Those labour
aristocrats were paid twice as much as miners. In 1891, a strike of
several months against the introduction of new technology only resulted
in the creation of a union, which the management then tried to smash,
thereby provoking another strike. The bosses locked-out and refused to
reintegrate the most militant strikers. Out of this deadlock rose the
idea of a co-op. This came into existence in 1892, after a national
subscription with some bourgeois help, and the labour force contributing
by investing 50% of their wages (and 5% more in 1912). To be profitable,
a cooperative had to combine high skills and income, popular support and
outside financing. Self-management soon lost any reality. The plant went
through a series of industrial disputes directly against the CGT, which
stood in the dual position of the single union and the boss (it was the
biggest shareholder): a several monthsâ strike in 1912, 4 months in
1921, stoppages for 7 months in 1924, and so on. The co-op still existed
in 1968.
Since the mid-19th century, cooperatives have lost their social impetus
and all ambition for historical change. When today the Welsh miners of
Towers Colliery buy out a workplace that the owners wanted to get rid
of, and then manage it collectively, even those who support and praise
them do not consider their market and human success as a solution that
could be generalised.
Between February and October 1917, âworkersâ controlâ did little to
restart production.[87] Later, though they were stimulated by a
political power that owed to them its existence and strength, the
proletarians hardly manifested any productive enthusiasm. They often
lacked respect for what was supposed to be theirs: Victor Serge recalls
how Petrograd workers would take machines apart and cut the belts to
make slippers or soles that they sold on the market.
Leninâs party did not get to (and stay in) power through bureaucratic
intrigues. It was built on proletarian struggles. But, for lack of
social change, the Bolsheviks whoâd become the new State remained at its
head like any power does, promising a lot, promoting some and repressing
others. The mass of the workers, who initially had not been able or
willing to run the factories in their own interests, were faced with new
bosses who told them they now worked for themselves and for world
socialism. They reacted as they usually do, by individual and collective
resistance, active and passive. Even before 1921 and Kronstadt, some
strikes, at the famous workersâ bastion of the huge Putilov plant for
instance, were suppressed in a bloodbath (as documented in the now
available Cheka archives).
The inversion we are describing did not take place in a month or a year.
A contradictory process, it allowed for the coexistence (often in the
same person) of a revolutionary dynamic and a crystalisation of power
looking to maintain itself at any price. The historical tragedy was that
one part of the working class, organised in a party and in State power,
forced the other part to work for a revolution⊠that by this very
situation ceased to exist. That contradiction was perceived at once by
the anarchists, soon by the German-Dutch Communist Left, and much later
â if ever â by the Italian Left. In any case, it surely closed the door
on any workersâ capitalism.
The recurrent opposition to the Bolshevik majority â the Left
Communists, the Makhnovshchina (which included industrial collectives),
the Workersâ Opposition, the Workersâ Group â was an expression of that
impossibility. Itâs no accident the debate on who should run the
factories reached its climax in 1920, at the backward surge of the
revolutionary wave. Then everything had been said and done, and the
split between the masses and the party was complete: but it was only a
negative split, as the proletarians didnât come up with an alternative
to Bolshevik policy. If Miasnikovâs Workersâ Group was a small but
genuine emanation of the rank and file, Kollontaiâs Workersâ Opposition
was the unionsâ voice â one bureaucracy against another.
But the party had the merit of coherence. As early as 1917, Lozovsky
stated: âThe workers must not figure the factories belong to them.â
Still, at that time, the decree on workersâ control expressed a balance
of power â shop-floor militancy maintained some collective rank and file
management, directly or through union channels. But the leaders had made
no secret of their objectives. Trotskyâs Terrorism and Communism defined
man as a âlazy animalâ that must be forced to work. For the Bolsheviks,
workersâ control only served to curb bourgeois power, help wage-earners
to discipline themselves, and teach management to a handful of future
executives.
The oppositionsâ platforms (even the radical one by the Miasnikov group)
might appear as an attempt to assert the value of work and socialise it,
but after 1920 with a world balance of power that was unfavourable to
wage labour such an attempt was even less feasible. Those proletarian
expropriations and re-organisations of production that took place were
emergency measures. It would have been impossible to turn these partial
spontaneous efforts into something systematic, and the proletarians did
not bother to. Labour kept away from the programmes that wished to make
it (and not the Bolshevik party) the real ruler.
In 1921, the toiling masses stood outside such a debate. The Workersâ
Oppositionâs proposals, like those of Leninâs and Trotskyâs, dealt with
the best way to put people to work in a society the workers had lost
control of. The Russian proletarians werenât keen to discuss the ways
and means of their own exploitation. The debate that ensued did not
oppose socialisation of labour unbound, to labour under constraint, it
was about a rearrangement of power at the top.
The Russian revolutionary crisis shows that as long as capital reigns,
labour canât be liberated and must be imposed upon the wage-earners, and
that its persistence in one form or another is an unmistakable sign of a
failed revolution. In 1917â21, the alternative was between abolishing
wage labour or perpetuating exploitation, with no possible third option.
Russia was to experience the charms of material incentives, elite
workers, hard and forced labour camps, and âcommunist Sundaysâ. But
letâs not turn history upside down. The Russian proles did not fail
because of a misguided belief in the myth of liberation through work:
itâs their failure that gave a free rein to an unprecedented
glorification of work. Who truly believed in a âcommunist Sundayâ,
except those who could expect some symbolic or material reward out of
it? Stakhanovism was to be the ultimate argument in that debate, and
caused quite a few reactions, including the murder of some elite workers
by their mates. As for Alexei Stakhanov, he died more addicted to vodka
than to coal.
Reading Gramsci and the Ordine Nuovo on the Italian workers that took
over the factories in 1920 is like going through the impressive yet
contradictory saga of a movement that was both formidable and tame.
Violent means (including the use of guns to guard the plants) mixed with
a definite moderation in the actual demands. The Fiat proletarian is
described thus: âintelligent, human, proud of his professional dignityâ;
âhe doesnât bow before the bossâ; âHe is the socialist worker, the
protagonist of a new mankindâŠâ; âThe Italian workers⊠have never opposed
the innovations that bring about lower costs, work rationalisation and
the introduction of a more sophisticated automatismâ. (Gramsci, Notes on
Machiavelli)
At the metalworkersâ union conference (November, 1919), Tasca, one of
the editors of Ordine Nuovo, called for the shop stewards to study, the
bourgeois system of production and work processes to achieve the maximum
technical capacities necessary to manage the factory in a communist
society. One last quote from Ordine Nuovo in September 1920: âThe
workers wish ⊠to prove that they can do without the boss. Today the
working class is moving forward with discipline and obeying its
organisation. Tomorrow, in a system that it will have created itself, it
will achieve everything.â
Reality proved different. The workers showed no desire to increase the
quantity or quality of work. The absence of significant production
during the occupation movement reveals the weakness of the ideology of a
producer proud of his labour, and the impossibility of liberated and
socialised work. Buozzi, general secretary of the Metalworkersâ union,
admitted it: âEveryone knew that the workers interrupted work on the
most futile pretext.â In a week, between August 21st and 28th, 1920, the
15,000 workers of Fiat-Centre decreased production by 60%.
At Fiat-Rome, a banner proclaimed: âThe man who will not work shall not
eatâ (a statement borrowed from Saint-Paul). Other banners at
Fiat-Centre repeated: âWork elevates manâ. Yet the succession of
stoppages at Fiat-Brevetti led the workersâ council to force the
personnel back to work, and to create a âworkersâ prisonâ to deal with
theft and laziness. Because of âthe extravagant number of people taking
days offâ, Fiatâs central council threatened to fire all those whoâd
been away for more than two days.
Caught up between the desire of union and party activists to reorganise
work in a socialist manner, and their own reluctance to work, the
workers had not hesitated long.
Letâs rewind the course of history a little. Weâd be mistaken to think
no-one cared about a theoretical critique of work before the 1960s. In
the 1840s, Marx and others (Stirner for example) defined communism as
the abolition of classes, of the State and of work.[88]
Later, in his Right to be Lazy (1880), Lafargue was thinking ahead of
his time when he attacked the 1848 âRight to Workâ: work degrades, he
says, and industrial civilisation is inferior to so-called primitive
societies. A âstrange folly â pushed the modern masses into a life of
work. But Marxâs son-in-law also belonged to his time because he partook
of the myth of technical liberation: âthe machine is the redeemer of
mankindâ. He did not advocate the suppression of work, but its reduction
to 3 hours daily. Though pressing a few buttons is usually less
destructive than sweating from morning till night, it does not put an
end to the separation between the productive act and the rest of life.
(Itâs this separation which defines work. It was unknown in primitive
communities, uncommon or incomplete in the pre-industrial world, and it
took centuries to turn it into a habit and norm in Western Europe.)
Lafargueâs provocative insight was a critique of work within work.
Interestingly, this pamphlet (with the Manifesto) long remained among
the most popular classics of the SFIO, the old French socialist party.
The Right to be Lazy helped present work as a boon and an evil, as a
blessing and a curse, but in any case as an inescapable reality, as
unavoidable as the economy.
The labour movement wished (in opposing ways, of course, according to
its organisations being reformist or revolutionary) the workers to prove
their ability to manage the economy and the whole society. But thereâs a
discrepancy between these sets of ideas and the behaviour of
wage-earners who did their best to get away from the âimplacable
imposition of workâ (point 8 of the KAPD programme). That phrase isnât
trivial. Itâs significant it should come from the KAPD, a party whose
programme included the generalisation of grassroots workersâ democracy,
but came up against the reality of work and its role in a socialist
society. The KAPD did not deny the alienation inherent to work, yet
wanted it imposed on everyone for a transition period to develop the
bases of communism to come. That contradiction calls for an explanation.
The aspiration to set up the workers as the ruling class and to build a
workersâ world was at its highest in the heyday of the labour movement,
when the Second and Third Internationals were more than big parties and
unions: they were a way of life, a counter-society. That aspiration was
carried by Marxism as well as by anarchism (particularly in its
revolutionary syndicalist form). It coincided with the growth of large
scale industry (as opposed to manufacture earlier, and Scientific
Management later).[89]
âLet the miners run the mine, the workers run the factoryâŠâ â this only
makes sense when the people involved can identify with what they do, and
when they collectively produce what they are. Although railwaymen do not
manufacture train engines, they are entitled to say: We run the railway
lines, we are the railway system. This was not the case of the craftsmen
pushed together in the manufacture: they could dream of an
industrialisation that would turn its back on the big factory and return
to the small workshop, and to a private independent property freed of
money fetters (for example, thanks to free credit Ă la Proudhon, or to
Louis Blancâs Peopleâs Bank).
In contrast, for the skilled electricity or metal worker, for the miner,
railwayman or docker, there was no going back. His Golden Age was not to
be found in the past, but in a future based on giant factories⊠without
bosses. His experience in a relatively autonomous work team made it
logical for him to think he could collectively manage the factory, and
on the same model the whole society, which was conceived of as an
inter-connection of firms that had to be democratically re â unified to
do away with bourgeois anarchy. The workers perform tasks that the boss
merely organises â so the boss could be dispensed with. Workersâ or
âindustrialâ democracy was an extension of a community (both myth and
reality) that existed in the union meeting, in the strike, in the
workersâ district, in the pub or the cafĂ©, in a specific language, and
in a powerful network of institutions that shaped working class life
from the aftermath of the Paris Commune to the 1950s or 60s.
This was no longer the case for the industrial or service sector
unskilled worker. One cannot envisage managing a labour process that has
been as fragmented inside the plant as between geographically separate
production units. When a car or a toothbrush comprises components from
two or three continents, no collective worker is able to regard it as
his own. Totality is split. Work loses its unity. Workers are no longer
unified by the content of tasks, nor by the globality of production. One
can only wish to (self-)manage what one masters.
Taylorised workers (like those in the US in the 1930s) did not form
councils. The collective organ of struggle was not at the same time a
potential collective management organ. The strike and occupation
committee was only an aggregate instrument of solidarity, and provided
the leadership of that specific movement: it was not a body that would
represent or incarnate labour for other tasks (particularly the running
of the firm). The Taylorised workplace leaves little room for managerial
aspirations.
Itâs interesting to observe that after 1945, workersâ councils
re-emerged in State capitalist countries that remained mainly in the
large scale mechanised industry stage, and were hardly penetrated by
Scientific Management: East Germany, 1953; Poland, 1955 and 1971;
Hungary, 1956; Czechoslovakia, 1968.
âThe future world must be a workersâ worldâ, as a Chinese communist put
it around 1920. This was the dreamland of skilled labour. However, after
1914â18, even where in Europe the movement was at its most radical, in
Germany, where a sizeable minority attacked unions and parliamentary
democracy, and where groups like the KAPD would implement a workersâ
programme, there were hardly any attempts to take over production in
order to manage it. Whatever plans they may have nurtured, in practice
neither the Essen and Berlin workers nor those in Turin put work at the
centre of society, even of a socialist one. Factories were used as
strongholds in which the proletarians would entrench themselves, not as
levers of social reorganisation. Even in Italy, the plant was not a
bastion to be defended at all costs. Many Turin workers would occupy
their workplace in the daytime, leave at night and come back in the
morning. (Such behaviour will re-occur in Italyâs Hot Autumn, 1969.)
This is no sign of extreme radicality. Those proletarians abstained from
changing the world as much as from promoting work, and âonlyâ snatched
from capital what they could get. That unformulated refusal of work
contrasted with thousands of pro-work posters and speeches. It just
showed that these proletarians werenât totally caught in the framework
where theyâd been trapped, and where theyâd trapped themselves.
well-researched Workers Against Work during the Popular Front (UCLA,
1991).
Much has been written about the transformation of factories into
closed-in workersâ fortresses. But the June â36 sit-downs never aimed to
re-start production. Their objective was less to protect the machinery
(which no saboteur threatened) than to use it to put pressure on the
boss and to have a good time. The conscious festive dimension was far
more important than an alleged will to prove productive abilities
superior to those of the bourgeois. Very few even contemplated worker
management of the occupied plants. A harsh and alienating place was
turned into liberated space, if only for a few weeks. It certainly was
no revolution, nor its dawning, but a transgression, a place and time to
enjoy a somewhat illegal yet fully legitimate holiday, while winning
substantial reforms. The striker was proud to show his family round the
premises, but his long collective meals, his dancing and singing
signalled his joy not to be at work. As in the US a little later, the
sit-down was a re-appropriation of the present, a (short) capture of
time for oneself.
The vast majority of the strikers understood the situation better than
Trotsky (âThe French revolution has begunâ) or Marceau Pivert
(âEverythingâs possible nowâ).[90] They realised that 1936 did not
herald social upheaval, and they were neither ready nor willing to make
it happen. They grabbed what they could, especially in terms of labour
time: the 40-hour week and paid holiday stand as symbols of that period.
They also preserved the possibility of selling their labour power to
capital as it existed, not to a collective capitalism that would have
been run by the labour movement. The CGT kept a low profile on a
possible new society based on socialised work. June â36 had a more
humble and more realistic purpose â to enable the worker to sell himself
without being treated as an animated thing. This was also the period
when recreational and educational activities organised for and sometimes
by the masses became popular: culture brought to the factories,
âqualityâ theatre for the common people, youth hostels, etc.
Resistance to work went on for a long while after the sit-downs, in a
more and more hostile environment. Bosses and Popular Front spokesmen
kept insisting on a âpauseâ in demands, and on the necessity to rearm
France. But the proletarians took advantage of the slackening of the
military style factory discipline that had been enforced since the 1929
crash. In the Spring of 1936, theyâd got into the habit of coming in
late, leaving early, not coming at all, slowing down work and disobeying
orders. Some would walk in drunk. Many refused piece rates. At Renault,
stoppages and go-slows resulted in a productivity that was lower in 1938
than two years before. In the aircraft industry, piece rates were
virtually abandoned. That trend did not prevail only in big factories,
but also in construction work and plumbing. Itâs after the failure of
the November â38 general strike (which aimed to defend the 40 hour
week), and after the government had called in the police and army to
intimidate and beat up strikers (Paris lived in an undeclared state of
siege for 24 hours) that discipline was restored and working hours
greatly extended, with a resulting increase in production and
productivity. The centre-right leader Daladier (formerly one of the
leaders of the Popular Front) rightly boasted he was âputting France
back to workâ.
Apart from farming estates, many companies were collectivised and
production re-started by the personnel. This was often because the boss
had fled, but sometimes to âpunishâ one whoâd stayed but sabotaged
production to harm the Popular Front. That period gave birth to a
multitude of meaningful experiences, like waiters refusing tips on the
basis that they werenât servants. Other endeavours tried to suppress
money circulation and develop non-mercantile relationships between
production and between people.
Another future was in search of itself, and it carried with it the
superseding of work as a separate activity. The main objective was to
organise social life without the ruling classes, or âoutsideâ them. The
Spanish proletarians, in the factories as well as in the fields, did not
aim at developing production, but at living free. They werenât
liberating production from bourgeois fetters, they were more plainly
doing their best to liberate themselves from bourgeois domination.[91]
In practice, the democratic management of the company usually meant its
union management by CNT and UGT (the socialist union) activists or
officials. Itâs they who described self-governance of production as the
road to socialism, but it does not seem that the rank and file
identified itself with such a prospect.
Loathing work had long been a permanent feature of Spanish working class
life. It continued under the Popular Front. This resistance was in
contradiction with the programme (particularly upheld by the
anarcho-syndicalists) calling the proles to get fully involved in the
running of the workplace. The workers showed little interest in factory
meetings which discussed the organising of production. Some
collectivised companies had to change the meeting day from Sunday (when
nobody cared to turn up) to Thursday. Workers also rejected piece rates,
neglected working schedules, or deserted the place. When piecework was
legally abolished, productivity fell. In February 1937, the CNT
metalworkersâ union regretted that too many workers took advantage of
industrial injuries. In November, some railwaymen refused to come on
Saturday afternoon.
Union officials, trying to bridge the gap between government and
shop-floor, retaliated by reintroducing piece rates and keeping a
careful eye on working hours, in order to fight absenteeism and theft.
Some went as far as forbidding singing at work. Unauthorized leaving of
oneâs work station could lead to a 3-day dismissal, with a 3 to 5 day
wage cut. To get rid of the immorality adverse to maximum efficiency,
the CNT suggested closing bars, concert and dance halls at 10 p.m. There
was talk of putting prostitutes back on the straight and narrow path
thanks to the therapy of work. Laziness was stigmatised as
individualistic, bourgeois and (needless to say) fascist. In January
1938, the CNT daily, Solidaridad Obrera, published an article â âWe
Impose Strict Discipline in the Workplaceâ â that was to be reproduced
several times in the CNT and UGT press, pressing the workers not to
behave as they used to, i.e. not to sabotage production, and not to work
as little as possible. âNow everything (was) completely differentâ
because industry was laying âthe foundations of a communist societyâ.
With the exception of the anarchist rank and file (and dissidents like
the Friends of Durruti) and the POUM, the parties and unions who stood
for a reign of labour were the same who did everything to prevent that
ideology from becoming a reality, and to make work remain nothing but
work. In 1937, the debate was over, and the contradiction soon brought
to a close â by force.
As early as 1944, a number of French companies went under union control,
sometimes under union management, as in the Berliet heavy vehicle plant.
Throughout the country, several hundred factories were supervised by
workersâ committees. With assistance from the administrative staff, they
took care of production, pay, canteens and some social benefits, and
asked for a say over hiring and firing. As a CGT official declared in
1944: âThe workers are human beings, they want to know who theyâre
working for⊠The worker must feel at home in the factory ⊠and through
the union get involved in the management of the economyâ.
But the haze of self-management assertions could not cloud a capitalist
functioning that soon reappeared in its down-to-earth banality. Letâs
just take the example of the miner. Much has been made of his pride and
his eagerness to mine coal. Weâve seen newsreels of Thorez (the CP
leader) exhorting thousands of miners in their work clothes to do what
he called their class and national duty â to produce⊠and produce more
and more.
Thereâs no point in denying the minerâs pride, but we have to assess its
scope and limits. Every social group develops an image of itself and
feels proud of what it does and of what it thinks it is. The colliersâ
self-esteem was socially conditioned. The official Minerâs Status (which
dates back to that period) granted quite a few advantages, like free
medical care and heating, but also put the mining areas under a
paternalistic supervision. The CGT controlled labour and daily life.
Being regarded as a loafer was close to being treated as a saboteur, or
even as a pro-Nazi. It was up to the foreman to decide how much coal was
to be mined. Piecework ruled. To put it mildly, what productive
eagerness there was lacked spontaneity.
Real minersâ pride had more to do with the community of labour
(festivals, rituals, solidarityâŠ) than with the content of work, and
even less with its alleged purpose (to produce for the renaissance of
France). In the 30s and 40s, the diary of a radical miner like Constant
Malva never mentions the beauty or the greatness of his craft. To him,
work was work and nothing else.[92]
Productivist practices and speeches also filled a gap. Everyone,
including the common man, claimed to be a patriot and accused the
bourgeoisie as a whole of collaboration with the Germans. Coal was also
the prime energy source, and a precious one in a devastated economy.
Letâs add a direct political cause to this near fusion between
patriotism and productivism: it helped people forget the support given
to the Hitler-Stalin pact by the French CP, its denunciation of the war
in 1939â41 as âimperialistâ, and its late involvement in the anti-German
Resistance.
Putting the proletarians back to work meant reintegrating them into the
national community, and punishing those bosses whoâd been overtly
collaborationist. This is why Renault was nationalised in 1945.
Branding the bourgeoisie as anti-labour and un-French was one and the
same thing, and it went along with self-managerial appearances. But this
was all the more possible because in France the CP did not really aspire
to power. Wherever it did (in Eastern Europe for instance), it did not
bother with such slogans. In fact, the average French (or Italian, or
AmericanâŠ) Stalinist was convinced that socialist countries did their
best for the welfare of the masses, but certainly not that the Russian
or Polish workers ran the factories â everything for the peopleâs good,
nothing by the people themselvesâŠ
The whole post-war story looks like a shadow theatre. No more than the
bosses, did unions and workersâ parties ever try to promote labour as a
class, or develop a wage-earnersâ democracy (even a superficial one)
inside the firms. After the troubled 1920s, after the persistent
rejection of work of the 1930s, the prime objective was now to force the
proletarians into reconstructing the economy. The workers were too
preoccupied with bread and butter demands to put their minds and energy
into a âreign of labourâ nobody really cared for, nor sought to
establish. The 1947â48 strikes offer an excellent illustration of this:
they proved the ability of the French CP (and of its Italian neighbour)
to recuperate and streamline the class struggle potentials it had been
repressing since the end of the war.
As early as 1942, Italy was shaken by a strike wave that culminated in
the April 25, 1943 insurrection that drove the Germans out of Turin
after five days of street fighting. A national union of all parties was
set up, dominated by the Stalinists (at Fiat-Mirafiori, 7,000 workers
out of 17,000 belonged to the CP). Economic recovery was given top
priority. In September 1945, the Metalworkersâ union stated that âthe
toiling masses are willing to accept more sacrifices [lower wages,
transfers, firing of those who have other incomes, partial redundancy]
so that Italy can be born again ⊠We must increase production and
develop labour: there lies the unique road to salvation.â
In December, the National Liberation Committees turned into Company
Management Committees, or rather they took over those bodies created
under Mussoliniâs corporatism. The main role of every CMC was to help
put people back to work and enhance hierarchy. Its method was a mixture
of Taylorism and Stakhanovism: youth brigades, volunteersâ groups,
material incentives, bonuses for cleaning and maintaining machines⊠The
idea was to arouse âthe enthusiasm of the working classes for the
productive effortâ.
Reality stood in stark contrast to propaganda. The struggle for better
work conditions remained strong, and enthusiasm for production quite
low. A CMC official admitted that the party had to resort to much
persuasion because people took a nap in the afternoon. According to a
Mirafiori shop steward, the union activists were labelled âfascistsâ
when they tried to convince the workers that it was their duty as
comrades to work: âthey interpreted freedom as the right to do nothingâ.
The workers would come in at 8.30 in the morning and have breakfast. An
ex-partisan then employed at Mirafiori sadly told how the workers
misused their own freedom, how they loitered in the toilets. They
werenât suitable material for building socialism, he regretted, they
went on strike to play games â âwe were more seriousâ. The personnel
kept resisting anything that came close to a control over time, to the
reintroduction of material incentives. On factory walls, writings like
âDown with timingâ were a rejection of the pro-Taylor quotes by Lenin
which the Stalinists were most fond of.
If the CMCs eventually proved relatively efficient in restoring
discipline and hierarchy, they failed to raise productivity: in 1946, it
only increased by 10%, which wasnât much, owing to its low level at the
end of the war. Above all, they failed to create a ânewâ proletarian â
the one that would manage his own exploitation. The CMCs composed only
of workers never got off the ground. The proles had more trust in their
direct delegates, the shop-floor commissars, who were more inclined to
go on strike than to produce.
This multiform unrest went on until 1948, which was the last outburst
against a worsening repression and deteriorating living conditions. A
partial wage freeze was imposed in April 1947, and maintained until
1954. For about 15 years, the Fiat workers underwent unrestrained
exploitation and were nearly deprived of union protection. In other
words, in 1944â47, the Italian proletarians were not defeated because
they had tried to establish a domination of labour over capital while
remaining within capital. They got crushed by the bourgeoisie in a more
conventional way â with the help of union and party bureaucracies.
This time, the festive element that characterised the June 36 sit-downs
was fairly absent in France, but quite widespread in Italy. In many
French factories dominated by the CGT, the place was practically locked
up, for fear restless workers and âoutsidersâ would upset the orderly
running of the strike by the union. â68 was in many respects harsher
than â36, as a small but determined proletarian minority challenged the
hegemony of the Stalinists over the industrial workers.
The festive dimension moved from the factory to the street, which
indicated that demands were breaking the workplace barrier and that the
heart of the matter was encompassing the whole of daily life. In France,
the most radical wage-earners would often leave the factory. There was
no Chinese Wall between âworkersâ and âstudentsâ (a lot of whom were not
students at all). Many workers, often young ones, would share their time
between their work mates inside the factory, and discussion (and
sometimes action) groups outside, where they met with minority workers
from other factories.[93] Moreover, during the Italian Hot Autumn of 69,
it was quite common for workers to occupy the premises in the daytime,
leave at night and be back the following morning, even after theyâd been
violently fighting the police and company guards to occupy the plant.
They felt that the essential was not happening just within the confines
of the workplace. As passive reaction (absenteeism) turned active
(collective sabotage, permanent meeting and wild partying on the
assembly line, etc.), it burst outside the factory walls.
The aftermath of â68 brought forth an experience that set itself up (and
that many people accepted) as exemplary, but which remained on the
fringe of the movement: in 1973, LIP, a watchmaker company that went
bankrupt, was taken over by the personnel and became a symbol of
self-managed capitalism. But its principles (âWe produce, we sell, we
pay ourselvesâ) were little more than an ingenious yet desperate attempt
to avoid unemployment and to continue to get an income. LIPâs
wage-earners self-managed distribution more than production (they sold a
lot of watches and manufactured few), until they had to close down. In
the mid-1970s, radicals were perfectly justified to analyse the LIP
adventure as an experiment in self-exploitation, but quite wrong to
interpret it as a feasible form of counter-revolution. Clearly, this was
neither a viable option for the capitalists, nor a popular one among
workers.
Similar attempts with a partial restarting of manufacturing and some
selling of stock were to follow, particularly in the engineering
industry, However, these were more a way to react to a programmed
closure, than a blueprint for the future. Whatever theories may have
been elaborated by leftists, these self-management embryos were grounded
on nothing solid, nothing able to mobilise the workers. Such practices
appeared at the crossroads of an endemic critique of work that led to
nothing else, and the beginning of a capitalist restructuring about to
dispose of excess labour.
(Solidarity, 1977). A lively account and thorough analysis.
The âRevolution of the Carnationsâ set in motion factory sit-ins and
self-management practices. These occurred generally in small or medium
size firms, mostly in poor industries, employing simple technology and
unskilled labour such as textiles, furniture-making and agro-industry.
These occupations were usually in response to (real or fraudulent)
bankruptcy, or to a closure of the plant by the owner. Sometimes, they
got rid of a boss who had been too visibly supporting the Salazar
regime. One of the objectives was to counter economic sabotage by the
opponents of the Revolution of the Carnations. It was also a means to
impose specific demands such as the reintegration of fired militant
workers, to apply government decisions regarding wages and work
conditions, or to prevent planned redundancies.
This social surge (Ă©lan) never questioned the circulation of money, nor
the existence and function of the State. Self-managers would turn to the
State for capital, and more often than not Stalinist â influenced
agencies would logically reserve investment funds for their political
friends or allies. They also asked the State to impose exchanges between
self-managed firms and those that werenât. Wages were still being paid,
often with a narrowed wage differential, or none. Hierarchy was
frequently dismantled, and the rank and file had a democratic say in
most decisions. Still, the movement did not go beyond workersâ control
over production, wage scales, and hiring and firing. It was a kind of
LIP extended to an entire relatively poor capitalist country. The
Portuguese experience was a replay of all the dead-ends revived by the
60s-70s era: populism, syndicalism, Leninism, Stalinism,
self-managementâŠ
Short as it is, our historical scan casts the shadow of doubt on the
thesis that the (undeniable) self-identification of the proletarian as
producer has been the decisive cause of our defeats. When did the
workers really try to shoulder economic growth? When did they compete
with old time bourgeois owners or modern directors for the management of
the companies? In that matter at least, thereâs no coincidence between
political platforms and proletarian practices. Workersâ movements donât
boil down to an affirmation of labour. The attempts to resume production
were often enough a makeshift solution, an effort to fill a gap caused
by the absence or incompetence of the boss. In that case, occupying the
premises and restarting the work process did not mean an affirmation of
the workers as workers â as in other circumstances when a bankrupt
company is bought out of by its personnel, it was a means of survival.
When, in Argentina at the end of 2001, the workers took over the
Bruckman textile factory which was threatened with closure, and kept it
going, they did so with no prospect of transforming capitalism into
socialism, even within the limits of a single firm. This then became the
case with dozens of Argentinian companies. Such behaviour occurs when
proletarians think they have no chance of changing the world.
An essential point here is how far we are determined by history. If the
âbeingâ of the proletariat theorised by Marx is not just a metaphysics,
its content is independent of the forms taken by capitalist domination.
The tension between the submission to work and the critique of work has
been active since the dawn of capitalism. Of course the realisation of
communism depends on the historical moment, but its deep content remains
invariant in 1796 and in 2002. Otherwise, we would not understand how,
as early as the 1840âs, some people were able to define communism as the
abolition of wage-labour, classes, the State and work. If everything is
determined by a historical necessity that was logically immature in
1845, how could we explain the genesis of communist theory at that time?
In the 20th century it was the failure of the rich post-1917
revolutionary process that gave full scope to the social-democratic and
Stalinist cult of the productive forces.[94] To afterwards interpret
that process as the cause of the cult, is tantamount to analysing
something from its contrary. Marx and Stalin both talked of the
dictatorship of the proletariat, but Stalin does not explain Marx. To
say that the KPD programme in 1930 (or the SPD programme in 1945) would
reveal the true nature of the KAPD programme in 1920, is to turn history
upside down.
Once the counter-revolution was there to stay, work (in the US as in the
USSR) could only exist under constraint: the workers werenât put to work
as a pseudo ruling class, but as a really ruled one, and according to
proven capitalist methods. The ideology of workersâ management was
flatly denied by unions and labour parties of all kinds. Now they had a
share in power (in corporate boardrooms as in ministries) they could
only promote the economy by resorting to the good old devices that had
been beneficial to the bourgeois for centuries.
In the most acute social crises, whatever they may have thought or said,
the proletarians did not try to assert themselves through asserting the
value of work. Since the origins of the class struggle, they have kept
fighting for less working hours and more pay. Letâs also bear in mind
the stuff daily workshop or office life is made of: absenteeism, petty
thefts, go-slows, non-genuine illness or faked injuries, even sabotage
or assault on supervisors, all of which only decrease in times of severe
unemployment. If freebie strikes (for instance, when transportation
workers permit free rides, or postal employees allow free postage and
phone calls) are so rare, itâs a sign that strikes offer a pleasant
opportunity to dodge work.
Weâre not suggesting that proletarian reality is a permanent underground
rebellion. The contradictory role of the wage-earner in the productive
process entails a contradictory attitude to work. The proletarian puts a
lot into work, among other reasons because no-one can stand a job for
hours and years without a minimum of interest, and because work both
stultifies our ability and know-how and allows us to at least partially
express them â the anthropological dimension of work has been
sufficiently exposed elsewhere that we donât have to go into it
here.[95]
In periods of social turmoil, either the workers show a deep
indifference to work (sometimes running away from it); or work is
re-imposed on them. During such periods, proletarians initiate a
critique of their condition, because refusing work is a first move
toward negating oneself as a proletarian.
Itâs true, however, that so far they have not gone past that critique,
or its early steps. There lies the problem.
Itâs not the critique of work thatâs been lacking, like an essential
dimension up to now neglected. How many men and women are happy to wear
themselves out for the sake of churning out alarm clocks or pencils, or
of processing files for the NHS? The worker is well aware that work
stands as his enemy and, as far as he can, he does his best to get away
from it. What is more difficult for him to imagine (and even more to put
into deeds) is that he could do away with both work and capital. Isnât
it the critique of capital thatâs been lacking, and still is? People are
prone to lay the blame on the reign of money, and they also denounce the
alienation of work: what is much less common is the understanding of the
unity that binds the two, the critique of selling oneâs activity in
exchange for an income, i.e. the critique of wage-labour, of capital.
The failure of the proletarian movement up to now is to be related to
its own activity, not to its specific formatting by capital at specific
historical moments. Formatting provides the conditions: it does not give
nor ever will give the means to use them. And weâll only have a true
answer once the transformation of the world is achieved.
In any case, a revolutionary period weakens (rather than strengthens)
the ideology of emancipating labour through labour. Then the ebb of the
radical wave brings about self-managerial practices that leave bourgeois
power intact, and which this power sooner or later will sweep away.
The ideal of a wage-labour capitalism, and the attempt to realise it,
are not remains from the past that a real domination of capital (or some
form of it more real than previously) would at last be able to
undermine.[96] The adhesion to work is neither (as Situationists tend to
think) a delusion which the proles should or now can grow out of, nor
(as Théorie Communiste tends to think) a historical phase formerly
inevitable but now gone. It is neither an ideology nor a stage in
history (though both aspects play their part). Wage-labour is not a
phenomenon imposed from outside, but the social relationship that
structures our society: practical and collective adherence to work is
built into the framework of that relationship.
Some have interpreted contemporary capitalism as a production of value
without work, of a value so diffused that its productive agents and
moments would be scattered throughout the whole social fabric.
Neither theory (Marxâs Grundrisse, in particular[97]) nor hard facts
validate this thesis. Itâs true that today valorisation depends much
less on the direct intervention of every single producer than on a
collective effort. It is a lot more difficult to isolate each productive
wage-earnerâs contribution to value than in 1867. Nevertheless, it is
not an undifferentiated social whole that valorises capital. The
assembler, the lorry-driver, the computer expert, the firm researcherâŠ
do not add value to the company to the same extent. The âsocial factoryâ
theory is relevant as far as it takes into account unpaid productive
labour (e.g., that of housewives). It gets irrelevant when it regards
value as the result of a uniform totality. Managers know their Marx
better than Toni Negri â they keep tracing and measuring productive
places and moments to try and rationalise them more and more. They even
locate and develop âprofit centresâ within the company. Work is not
diffuse, it is separated from the rest. If manual labour is evidently
not the unique or main source of value, if immaterial labour is on the
increase, work remains vital to our societies. It is strange to speak of
an âend of workâ when temp agencies are among the largest employers in
the US.
In a country like France, though sociologists and statisticians tell us
that there are more office than factory workers (now reduced to 1â4 of
the working population), the latter â 80% of whom are male â are often
married to the former. As a consequence, 40% of kids are living in a
household where one of their parents is a âblue collarâ worker, often
employed in the service sector. Instead of walking through factory gates
every morning, he is in charge of maintenance, drives a heavy vehicle,
moves goods in a warehouse, etc. Half of French workers arenât
âindustrialâ any more. Still, thus defined, workers are the most
numerous groups. Whether theyâre old style factory operatives, service
sector manual wage-earners, Taylorised clerks, cashiers, etc., underling
wage-earners compose over half of the French working population. (It
would be interesting to have the exact figures for a would-be city of
the future like Los Angeles.) These facts do not change anything in the
validity or vanity of a communist perspective, their only merit is
precisely to show that nothing fundamental has changed since the 19th
century. According to Marxâs own figures in Capital volume I, there were
more servants than industrial workers in mid-Victorian England. Should
the theory of the proletariat be wrong, it was already so in 1867, and
it isnât wrong in 2002 because there arenât enough workers left.
Capitalism is the first universal exploitation system. Surplus-labour is
no longer extorted from someone who organises and therefore controls his
production to a large extent, as was the case of the peasant under
Asiatic despotism, the serf pressurized by his lord and by the taxman,
or the craftsman dominated by the merchant. These werenât exploited
within their work: part of the fruit of their labour was taken away from
them from outside and after it had been produced. Buying and selling
labour power introduces exploitation, not on the edge of human activity,
but in its heart.
But, because of that very process â because the wage-earner sells his
labour power â he makes capital as much as he is made by it, he lives
inside capital to a far higher degree than the peasant depended on his
master and the craftsman on the merchant. Because he lives (and resists,
and fights) inside capital, he produces and shares its essentials,
including consumption and democracy. Because selling his life force is
necessary to him, he can only despise and reject his work, in reality
and in his mind, by rejecting what makes him exist as a wage-earner,
i.e. by rejecting capital. In other words, if itâs got to be more than
everyday resistance, refusal of work is only possible through an acute
social crisis.
In pre-industrial times, the Peasantsâ wars in the 15th and 16th
centuries, the Tai-Ping in 19th century China, and many others, managed
to build up self-sufficient liberated areas that sometimes survived for
over ten years. In the West Indies, Black slaves could take to the hills
and live on their own outside âcivilisationâ. The industrial world
leaves no such space for an alternative. If the 1919 Petrograd worker
fled to the countryside, capitalism caught up with him within a few
years. The Spanish collectivities of 1936â38 never âliberatedâ large
areas. More recently, Bolivian miners self-managed their villages, with
armed militia, radio stations, co-ops, etc. But it stopped when the
mines were closed down. Their social dynamism depended on the function
that international capital gave them. Only peasant communities, in so
much as they stood outside the world economy, could go on living on
their own for a long while. Modern workers have been unable to set up
any reorganised social life that would rival normal or purely capitalist
capitalism for a durable length of time. No room for a Third Way any
more.
Every reader of Marx knows that he never completed what he regarded as
his master work, and that he rewrote the beginning several times. Why
does Marx linger on the commodity, why does he start with the way
capitalism presents itself, instead of giving its definition right away?
If he insists first on representation and not on capitalâs nature, it
may well be that he thinks its nature is related to its representation,
which is no psychological process, but has to do with social
representation at its deepest.
The author of Das Kapital keeps talking about a mystery, a secret to
penetrate. Which one? It is hard to believe Marx is only concerned with
proving to the worker that he is exploited⊠Itâs more logical Marx would
be circling the various facets of capital to focus on a contradiction
more crucial to the communist movement than the mechanics of
surplus-value.[98] He is targeting the amazing dynamics of a social
system that is based more than any other on those it enslaves and
provides them with weapons to dismantle it, but â because of that â
manages to integrate them into its triumphant and destructive march, and
(at least until now) uses social crises to regenerate itself. The
contradiction of the proletarian is to be the bearer of a commodity that
contains the possibility of all others, and can transform everything,
while having to sell this commodity, and therefore to act and picture
himself as a valorizer. The potential gravedigger of the system is the
same one who feeds it.
Only with commodity exchange do relationships between humans appear as
relations between things. The 19th century worker tended to see in
capital only the capitalist. The 21st century wage-earner often
perceives capital as just⊠capital, and not his own activity that
(re)produces it. Fetishism still rules, albeit depersonalised, but it
still veils the social relations producing capital. The denunciation of
exploitation usually misses what economy is â the domination of
everything and everyone by production for value. Actually, whatâs at
stake from a communist point of view is not what capital hides and what
most proletarians have the intuition of: the extraction of
surplus-value. Whatâs at stake is what capitalism imposes daily in real
life and impresses on our minds: the economy as something obvious and
inevitable, the necessity of exchanging commodities, of buying and
selling labour, if we wish to avoid want, misery and dictatorship.
True, contemporary work does not socialise well because it tends to
become a pure means of earning a living. Still, that socialisation does
not vanish. (The emergence of radical reformism has to do with its
persistence.) As a Moulinex laid-off worker said in 2001: âThe hardest
thing now is to be alone.â The ideology of labour power is the necessary
ideology of the proletarian within capital. That commodity is the prime
reality of billions of men and women. The proletarian is never reduced
to what capital turns him into, yet he feels a need to be recognised and
socially enhanced, and that need is based on his only asset: work. He
has to have this positive image of himself, if only to be able to sell
himself on good terms. In an interview, the job seeker will not devalue
himself. If he did, he would submit to the common prejudice that debases
the competence of a simple order-taker.
On the other hand, non-adherence to work is not enough to guarantee the
possibility of revolution, let alone its success. A proletarian who
regards himself as nothing will never question anything. The unskilled
worker of 1970 was convinced he was doing a stupid job, not that he was
stupid himself: his critique addressed precisely the emptiness of an
activity unworthy of what he claimed to be. A purely negative vision of
the world and of oneself is synonymous with resignation or acceptance of
anything. The proletarian only starts acting as a revolutionary when he
goes beyond the negative of his condition and begins to create something
positive out of it, i.e. something that subverts the existing order.
Itâs not for lack of a critique of work that the proletarians have not
made the revolution, but because they stayed within a negative critique
of work.
The affirmation of labour has not been the principal factor of
counter-revolution, only (and this is important!) one of its main
expressions. But unions conveyed this ideology through what remains
their essential function: the bargaining of labour power. Organisations
like the Knights of Labour at the end of the 19th century played a minor
part, and withered with the generalisation of large scale industry.
If the promotion of labour was as central as weâre sometimes told,
Fordism would have taken it up. But Scientific Management did not defeat
the skilled workers by bestowing more professional dignity on the
shop-floor, but by deskilling and breaking down trades. Generous schemes
for job enrichment and re-empowerment are only implemented to disrupt
the autonomy of the work team â then these reforms gradually fade away
because the rank and file does not really care.
The ideas that rule are those of the ruling class. The ideology of work,
whatever form it takes, is the capitalist ideology of work. There canât
be any other. When the social consensus is shattered, that
representation goes down with the others. It would be paradoxical that a
severe crisis, instead of shaking it, should develop it even further.
The first part of this essay was mainly historical. What follows could
be called methodological. Our critique of determinism focuses on a
general tendency among revolutionaries to treat capitalist civilisation
as if it were a one-way street to revolution.
From the omnipresence of capital, one can conclude with the possibility
â or even necessity â of revolution. One could also deduct from it the
impossibility of a revolution. That type of reasoning may be repeated
indefinitely, and still be used in a hundred years if capitalism is
still here. A theoretical model explains nothing but itself. Yesterday
and tomorrow, as many reasons point to the continuity of capitalism as
to its abolition. (As we wrote earlier, only when accomplished will the
destruction of the old world throw a full light on past failures.)
Some comrades postulate the coming of an ultimate stage when the inner
working of the system wonât just upset it, but destroy it. They believe
that whatever has happened before that final stage has been necessary,
because up to now the workers have only been able to reform capitalism.
Now there comes a threshold when reform becomes utterly pointless, a
threshold that leaves no other option except revolution. Past radical
proletarian activity has only contributed to bring about the historical
moment that makes revolution possible â or necessary, rather. Until
then, the class struggle has provided the required sequence of phases
preparing the final phase.
By the way, this would justify what has been called Marxâs and Engelsâ
revolutionary reformism â urging the bourgeoisie to develop capitalism
and create the conditions of communism. Among other things, Marx
supported the German national bourgeoisie, praised Lincoln, sided with
quite a few reformist parties and unions while relentlessly targeting
anarchistsâŠ[99] Shall we also have to agree with Lenin (because he acted
like a new revolutionary bourgeois) against Gorter and Bordiga? And was
Roosevelt a better (though unconscious) contributor to human
emancipation than Rosa Luxemburg?
Anyway, from now on, all ambiguity is said to have been cleared up. We
should be entering the final stage in the history of wage-labour: work
is said to be now less and less available, more and more deskilled,
devoid of any other meaning but to provide an income, thereby preventing
the wage-earner from adhering to capital, and to the plan of a
capitalism without capitalists. Reaching this threshold has made it
impossible once and for all for labour to assert itself as labour within
capital.
The underlying logic to this approach is to search for an un-mediated
class relationship that would leave no other solution for the
proletariat but a direct (class against class) confrontation with
capital.
Determinism revisits history to locate the obstacle to revolution, and
discovers it in the form of the social space that the workers supposedly
wished to occupy inside capitalism. Then that option is said to be now
closed â such a social space does not exist any more because in fully
real domination capitalism is everywhere. The reasons for past failures
give the reasons for tomorrowâs success, and provide the inevitability
of communist revolution, as the obstacle is cleared away by the
completion of what is described as capitalâs quasi natural life cycle.
In other words, the revolutionary crisis is no longer perceived as a
breaking up and superseding of the social conditions that create it. It
is only conceived of as the conclusion of a pre-ordained evolution.
The methodological flaw is to believe in a privileged vantage point that
enables the observer to grasp the totality (and the whole meaning) of
past, present and near future human history.
In short, the causes of our previous shortcomings are not sought in the
practical deeds of the proletarians. Instead of a labour-power
overcoming its condition and rising to its historic task of freeing
itself from its chains, and thus freeing humanity, the dynamic element
is no longer proletarian action, but the movement of capital. The mutual
involvement of capital and labour is reduced to a one-way relation of
cause and effect. History gets frozen.
We would prefer to say that there is no other limit to the life-span of
capital than the conscious activity of the proletarians. Otherwise, no
crisis, however deep it might be, will be enough to produce such a
result. And any deep crisis (a crisis of the system, not just in it)
could be the last if the proletarians took advantage of it. But thereâll
never be a day of reckoning, a final un-mediated showdown, as if at long
last the proletarians were directly facing capital and therefore
attacking it.
âThe self-emancipation of the proletariat is the breakdown of
capitalismâ, as Pannekoek wrote in the last sentence of his essay on The
Theory of the Breakdown of Capitalism (1934). It is significant this
should come as the conclusion of a discussion on capitalâs cycles and
reproduction models (Marxâs, Luxemburgâs and Henrik Grossmannâs). The
communist movement cannot be understood through models similar to those
of the reproduction of capital â unless we regard communism as the last
logical ( = as inevitable as any previous crisis) step in the course of
capital. If this were the case, the communist revolution would be as
ânaturalâ as the growing up and ageing of living beings, the succession
of seasons and the gravitation of planets, and just like them
scientifically predictable.
1789 might have happened forty years later or sooner, without a
Robespierre and a Bonaparte, but a bourgeois revolution was bound to
happen in France in the 18th or 19th century.
Who could argue that communism is bound to happen? The communist
revolution is not the ultimate stage of capitalism.
âWith the psychology of a trade unionist who will not stay off his work
on May Day unless he is assured in advance of a definite amount of
support in the event of his being victimised, neither revolution nor
mass strike can be made. But in the storm of the revolutionary period
even the proletarian is transformed from a provident pater familas
demanding support, into a ârevolutionary romanticistâ, for whom even the
highest good, life itself, to say nothing of material well-being,
possesses but little in comparison with the ideals of the
struggle.â[100]
Finally, whoever believes that 1848, 1917, 1968⊠were compelled to end
up as they ended up, should be requested to prophesy the future â for
once. No-one had foreseen May â68. Those who explain that its failure
was inevitable only knew this afterwards. Determinism would gain
credibility if it gave us useful forecasts.[101]
Revolution is not a problem, and no theory is the solution of that
problem. (Two centuries of modern revolutionary movement demonstrate
that communist theory does not anticipate the doings of the
proletarians.)
History does not prove any direct causal link between a degree of
capitalist development, and specific proletarian behaviour. It is
improvable that at a given historical moment the essential contradiction
of a whole system would bear upon the reproduction of its fundamental
classes and therefore of the system itself. The error does not lie in
the answer but in the question. Looking for what would force the
proletarian, in his confrontation with capital, to attack his own
existence as a wage-earner, is tantamount to trying to solve in advance
and through theory a problem which can only be solved â if it ever is â
in practice. We cannot exclude the possibility of a new project of
social reorganisation similar to that which had workersâ identity as its
core. The rail-worker of 2002 canât live like his predecessor of 1950.
This is not enough for us to conclude that he would only be left with
the alternative of resignation or revolution.
When the proletariat seems absent from the scene, it is quite logical to
wonder about its reality and its ability to change the world. Each
counter-revolutionary period has the dual singularity of dragging along
while never looking like the previous ones. That causes either a
renunciation of critical activity, or the rejection of a revolutionary
âsubjectâ, or its replacement by other solutions, or a theoretical
elaboration supposed to account for past defeats in order to guarantee
future success. This is asking for unobtainable certainties, which only
serve to reassure. On the basis of historical experience, it seems more
to the point to state that the proletariat remains the only subject of a
revolution (otherwise there wonât be any), that communist revolution is
a possibility but not a certainty, and that nothing ensures its coming
and success but proletarian activity.
The fundamental contradiction of our society (proletariat-capital) is
only potentially deadly to capitalism if the worker confronts his work,
and therefore takes on not just the capitalist, but what capital makes
of him, i.e. if he takes on what he does and is. Itâs no use hoping for
a time when capital, like a worn out mechanism, would find it impossible
to function, because of declining profits, market saturation, exclusion
of too many proletarians from work, or the inability of the class
structure to reproduce itself.
A current subtext runs through much of revolutionary thinking: the more
capitalism we have, the nearer we get to communism. To which people like
Jacques Camatte retort: no, the more capitalism we have, the more
capitalist we become. At the risk of shocking some readers, weâd say
that the evolution of capital does not take us closer to or farther from
communism. From a communist point of view, nothing is positive in itself
in the march of capital, as is shown by the fate of classism.
In practice, âclassismâ was the forward drive of the working class as a
class within capitalist society, where its organisations came to occupy
as much social space as possible. Labour set up collective bodies that
rivalled with those of the bourgeoisie, and conquered positions inside
the State. That took â and still takes â many forms (social-democracy,
CPs, the AFL-CIOâŠ), and also existed in South America, in Asia and parts
of Africa.
In theory, classism is the vindication of class difference (and
opposition) as an end in itself, as if class war was the same as the
emancipation of the workers and of mankind. So itâs based exactly on
what has to be criticised, as classes are basic constituents of
capitalist society. Whether itâs peaceful or violent, the mere
opposition of one class to the other leaves both facing each other.
Naturally any ruling class denies the existence of class antagonisms.
Still, in the early 19th century, the first to emphasise class
confrontation werenât socialists, but bourgeois historians of the French
revolution. What is revolutionary is not to uphold class struggle, but
to affirm that such a struggle can end through a communist revolution.
Nowadays, the decay of classism and of the labour movement is visible
and documented enough for us not to dwell upon it. Some revolutionaries
have rejoiced over the demise of workerâs identity and of the
glorification of the working class as the class of labour, and theyâve
interpreted that demise as the elimination of a major obstacle to
revolution â which the labour institutions and that ideology no doubt
were. But what has the critique of the world really gained by their
withering away? Weâd be tempted to say â not much, because of the rise
of even softer practices and ideas. Just being freed of their workersâ
role and hopes didnât turn wage-earners into radical proletarians. So
far, the crisis of the working class and of classism has not favoured
subversion. The past twenty years have brought about neo-liberal,
neo-social-democratic, neo-reactionary, neo-everything ideologies, the
emergence of which has coincided with the symbolic annihilation of the
working class. This wiping out is a product of capital class
recomposition (unemployment, de-industrialisation, proletarianisation of
office work, casualisation, etc.). It also results from the rejection by
the wage-earners themselves of the most rigid forms of worker identity.
But this rejection remains mainly negative. The proletarians have
shattered the control of parties and unions over labour. (In 1960,
anyone handing out an anti-union leaflet at a French factory gate risked
being beaten up by the Stalinists.) But they havenât gone much further.
The decline of workerism was accompanied by the loss of a point of view
allowing a perspective on the whole of this society, gauging and judging
it from the outside in order to conceive and propose another.
Proletarian autonomy has not taken advantage of bureaucratic decline.
We are experiencing a dislocation of class struggle. In the 60s-70s, the
unskilled workers stood at the centre of the reproduction of the whole
system, and other categories recognised themselves in the âmass workerâ.
No social symbolical figure plays such a pivotal role â yet.
19th century and early 20th century communists often shared the
progressivism of their time, and believed that a new industry and a new
labour would emancipate humankind.[102] A hundred years later, weâd be
naive to espouse the exact opposite views just because they happen to be
fashionable. In fifty years, the praise of toil and sacrifice has become
as outdated as the belief in the liberating Horn of Plenty of the
economy.[103] This evolution is as much the result of the radical
critique of the 1960s-70s, as of a deepening of capital â making labour
productive today is achieved more through the work process itself than
by outright discipline. The computer screen is now the immediate
supervisor of millions of industrial and service sector wage-earners. In
its most advanced sectors, capital has already gone beyond authoritarian
hierarchy and work as a curse. âAutonomyâ and âbottom-upâ are the in
words. The macho, muscle-bound, national (= white) worker image is
giving way to a more open, multi-ethnic, male and female figure.
In 1900, you had to produce before consuming, and labour parties told
the worker he had to develop the productive forces first, in order to
enjoy the fruits of socialism later. Instead of a single Redeemer dying
on a cross, millions of sufferers (âthe salt of the earthâ) would create
the conditions of a better world. The consumer and credit society has
done away with that: painful self-exertion is no longer said to come
before pleasure. True, this goes together with the multiplication of
sweatshops, of forced, unpaid or ill-paid labour, and of a renaissance
of slavery. Such forms complement but do not contradict the general
trend toward a de-consecration of work. (In 1965, unskilled mass workers
werenât the majority of wage-earners either.)
Work is an idol, albeit a fallen one. Its imposition is no longer of a
moral or religious kind (âYou shall gain your bread by the sweat of your
browâ), but profane and down-to-earth. In some Asian countries, labour
is now being disciplined better by the pressure of consumerism than by
an appeal to Confucianism. In Tai-Peh as in Berlin, public concern is
about creating and getting jobs, not suffering to enter some earthly or
heavenly paradise. So work now calls for a critique different from the
time when an aura of self-inflicted pain surrounded it. Mobility and
self-empowerment are the present slogans of capital. We cannot be
content with anti-work statements such as the ones that the surrealists
were rightly making eighty years ago.[104]
In 2002, work rules, but the work ethic is no longer sacrificial: it
calls upon us to realise our potentials as human beings. Nowadays, we
donât work for a transcendent goal (our salvation, a sacred duty,
progress, a better future, etc.). The consecration of work was
two-sided: any object of worship is a taboo to be broken. But our age is
one of universal de-consecration. Transcendence is out. The pragmatic
pursuit of happiness is todayâs motive: we are Americans.
This, however, does not lead to a growing subterranean rejection of
work. A de-Christianized society substitutes the desire to feel good for
the fear of sin. Religion gives way to a body and health cult: the âme
generationâ is more concerned with keeping fit than saving souls. So
work is no longer worshipped because it does not need to be: itâs enough
for it to simply be there. Itâs more an overwhelming reality than an
ideology. Its pressure is more direct and open, close to what Marx
described as the American attitude: âtotal indifference to the specific
content of work and easily moving from one job to anotherâ.[105] In a
modern and âpurerâ capitalism, de-consecrated work still structures our
lives and minds. And the current moral backlash in the US is proof of
how reactionary attitudes complement permissiveness.
Not much revolutionary clarification has grown out of these changes,
because not everything has the same value in capitalist evolution. The
critical potential completely differs if itâs the workers that attack
worker identity and the worship of work, or if capital is sweeping them
aside. For the last thirty years, as work identification was being
disrupted, the possibility of an utterly different world has also
vanished from individual and collective thinking. In the past, Stalinist
and bureaucratic shackles did not prevent such a utopia, and minorities
debated the content of communism. If a working class entangled in its
identification with work did not make a revolution, nothing yet proves
that the proletarians now liberated from it will act in a revolutionary
way.
We find it hard to share the optimism of those who see the present
period as entirely dissimilar from the 60s-70s or from any previous
period, with a capitalism that would systematically downgrade the living
conditions of wage-earners, thereby creating a situation that would soon
enough be intolerable and lead to a revolutionary crisis. The limits of
proletarian upsurges from Algeria to Argentina, and the rise of radical
reformism in Europe and the US, rather suggest that itâs reform â not
revolution â that is becoming topical again.[106]
The eagerness to celebrate the twilight of worker identity has led some
comrades to forget that this identity also expressed an understanding of
the irreconcilable antagonism between labour and capital. The
proletarians had at least grasped that they lived in a world that was
not theirs and could never be. Weâre not calling for a return to a
Golden Age. Weâre saying that the disappearance of this identification
owes as much to counter-revolution as to radical critique. Revolution
will only be possible when the proletarians act as if they were
strangers to this world, its outsiders, and will relate to a universal
dimension, that of a classless society, of a human community.
This implies the social subjectivity indispensable to any real critique.
We are well aware of the interrogations raised by the word subjectivity,
and we surely do not wish to invent a new magical recipe. For the
moment, let us just say that weâre not bestowing any privilege on
subjectivity against objective conditions which would then be secondary
or negligible.
Weâve often emphasised that thereâs no point in trying to arouse a
consciousness prior to action: but any real breakthrough implies some
minimal belief in the ability of the people involved to change the
world. This is a big difference with the 60s-70s. Thirty years ago, many
proletarians were not just dissatisfied with this society: they thought
of themselves as agents of historical change, and acted accordingly, or
at least tried to.
The subject/object couple is one of those philosophical expressions that
a human community would supersede. The declared definitive opposition
between individual and society, soul and body, spirit and matter, theory
and praxis, art and economy, ideals and reality, morals and politicsâŠ
all relate to the dissolution of communities into classes through the
combined action of property, money and State power. Though not
synonymous with perfect harmony, communism would try and live beyond
such tragic splits in human life.[107] âSubjectâ and âobjectâ donât
exist separate from each other. A crisis is not something exterior to
us, that happens and forces us to react. Historical situations (and
opportunities) are also made of beliefs and initiatives, of our actions
â or inaction.
Vaneigemâs âradical subjectivityâ[108] had its qualities (and its
purpose at the time) and one major weakness: it appealed to the free
will, to the self-awareness of an individual rising against his social
role and conditioning. This is clearly not what we suggest. Capitalism
is not based on necessity, and communism (or a communist revolution) on
liberty. The abolition of their condition by the proletarians cannot be
separated from concrete struggles against capital. And capital exists
through social groups and institutions. Objective realities, notably the
succession of âsystems of productionâ rooted in and dependent on the
class struggle, are the inevitable framework of the communist movement.
What we do and will do with it remains to be seen.
The subject which Dauvé and Nesic seek to reflect upon in this text is
nothing less than the âhistorical failureâ of the communist movement
over the 154 years following the publication of Marx and Engelsâ
Manifesto.[109] They approach this subject by way of a critique of the
concept of programmatism developed primarily by the journal Théorie
Communiste. However, programmatism could only serve as an explanation of
the âfailure of the communist movementâ if we imagine, as DauvĂ© and
Nesic do, that communism is a norm, a substance, something invariable in
âits deep contentâ.[110] For without this assumption programmatism is
only the explanation of its own failure. We will thus begin by
explicating the theory of programmatism which Dauvé and Nesic have so
misunderstood. But it should be noted that what is actually at stake
here is the definition of the present period and, even more, the fact
that a âpresent periodâ may even exist. That is ultimately to say,
something called history.
Generally speaking we could say that programmatism is defined as a
theory and practice of class struggle in which the proletariat finds, in
its drive toward liberation, the fundamental elements of a future social
organisation which become the programme to be realised. This revolution
is thus the affirmation of the proletariat, whether as a dictatorship of
the proletariat, workersâ councils, the liberation of work, a period of
transition, the withering of the state, generalised self-management, or
a âsociety of associated producersâ. Programmatism is not simply a
theory â it is above all the practice of the proletariat, in which the
rising strength of the class (in unions and parliaments,
organisationally, in terms of the relations of social forces or of a
certain level of consciousness regarding âthe lessons of historyâ) is
positively conceived of as a stepping-stone toward revolution and
communism. Programmatism is intrinsically linked to the contradiction
between the proletariat and capital as it is constituted by the formal
subsumption of labour under capital.
At this point capital, in its relation to labour, poses itself as an
external force. For the proletariat, to liberate itself from capitalist
domination is to turn labour into the basis of social relations between
all individuals, to liberate productive labour, take up the means of
production, and abolish the anarchy of capitalism and private property.
The proletariatâs liberation is to be founded in a mode of production
based upon abstract labour, i.e. upon value.
The revolutionary process of the affirmation of the class is two-fold.
It is on the one hand conceived of as the rising strength of the
proletariat in the capitalist mode of production and, on the other hand,
its affirmation as a particular class and thus the preservation of its
autonomy. In the necessity of its own mediations (parties, unions,
cooperatives, societies, parliaments), the revolution as autonomous
affirmation of the class (as a particular existence for itself in
relation to capital) loses its way, not so much in relation to
revolution per se, but in relation to this very affirmation. The
proletariatâs rising strength is confused with the development of
capital, and comes to contradict that which was nevertheless its own
specific purpose: its autonomous affirmation.
In the revolutionary period after World War I, of which the Communist
Lefts in their practice and theory are the substantial expression, the
proletariat finds itself ambushed by a novel situation: in its
autonomous affirmation it confronts what it is in capital, what it has
become, its own strength as a class in so far as it is a class of the
capitalist mode of production. The revolution as affirmation of the
class confronts its own failure, because the counter-revolution is
intrinsically linked to this affirmation in its very motivations (and
not because there was any âerrorâ, or because it was impossible in terms
of some ahistorical definition of the revolution). From this point on,
the workersâ parties become the content of the counter-revolution
closest to the revolution.
With the transition of capital to a period of real subsumption of labour
(at the end of the 19th, and beginning of the 20th century), the rising
strength of the class, in which labour presents itself as the essence of
capital, is confused with the development of capital itself. All the
organisations which formalise this rising strength, are able from the
First World War onwards, to present themselves as the managers of
capital â they become as such the most acute form of the
counter-revolution.
In the years after 1917 revolution is still an affirmation of the class,
and the proletariat seeks to liberate against capital its social
strength which exists in capital â a social strength on which it bases
its organisation and founds its revolutionary practice. The very
situation which gave it the capacity to engage in the broad affirmation
underlying the ârevolutionary Ă©lanâ of the post-war period became its
limit. The specificity of this period in relation to classical
programmatism, represented by pre-1914 social democracy, resides in the
fact that the autonomous affirmation of the class against capital
entered into contradiction with its rising strength within capital. At
the same time, this affirmation found its raison dâĂȘtre and its
foundation in this integration. What the class is in the capitalist mode
of production is the negation of its own autonomy, whilst at the same
time being the reason and power behind its drive for autonomous
affirmation. The counter-revolutions are administered by the workersâ
organisations. The impetuous history between the wars, from the Russian
revolution to the Spanish civil war, is that of the liquidation of this
question.
The concept of programmatism historicises the terms of class struggle,
revolution and communism. This enables us to understand class struggle
and revolution in their real historical characteristics and not in
relation to a norm; to overcome the opposition which is made between
revolution, communism, and its conditions (those famous conditions which
are never ripe); to abandon the dichotomy between a proletariat always
revolutionary in its substance (revolutionary, in fact, as the
subsequent period understands the term) and a revolution which it never
produces; to construct the diverse elements of an epoch as a totality
producing its own internal connections at the same time as its
diversities and conflicts (between Marx and Bakunin, Luxembourg and
Bernstein, etc.); and finally, to avoid ending up with a ârevolutionary
beingâ of the proletariat, whose every âmanifestationâ results in a
restructuring of capital.
One can always search out evidence to the contrary in isolated actions
and events which appear at first sight to oppose themselves to the
general movement, and seek to detach such moments from the movement and
consider them in isolation. In this way Dauvé and Nesic only show how
the incomparably larger part of the movement contradicts their
affirmations. By failing to integrate these moments into a totality they
limit themselves to opposing isolated activities to each other without
grasping their unity.
With the real subsumption of labour under capital, the defining
characteristic of which is the extraction of relative surplus value,
that which disappears is everything which allowed the proletarian
condition to be turned against capital â this is the decomposition of
programmatism. From the 20s to the end of the 70s, this decomposition is
not an exhaustion of the previous period, but a new structure and a new
cycle of struggle. The basis of the decomposition of programmatism as an
historical period is the existence of a workersâ identity stabilised in
the aftermath of the second world war: a workersâ identity confirmed in
the reproduction of capital â labour legitimised as the rival of capital
within the capitalist mode of production. This workersâ identity is
founded on all the characteristics of the immediate process of
production (i.e. assembly-line work, cooperation, the collective worker,
the continuity of the process of production, sub-contracting, the
segmentation of labour power) and all those of reproduction (work,
unemployment, training and welfare). As such it is an identity founded
on all the elements which make of the class a determination of the
reproduction of capital itself (i.e. public services, the national
delimitation of accumulation, creeping inflation and âthe sharing of
productivity gainsâ); all these elements which positioned the
proletariat, socially and politically, as a national interlocutor formed
a workersâ identity which challenged the hegemonic control and
management of the whole of society. This workersâ identity which
constituted the workersâ movement and structured class struggle, even
integrating âreally existing socialismâ within the global division of
accumulation, rested on the contradiction between, on the one hand, the
creation and development of labour power put to work by capital in an
increasingly collective and social manner, and on the other, the
(increasingly) limited forms of appropriation by capital of this labour
power in the immediate process of production and reproduction.
This is the conflictual situation which developed as workersâ identity â
an identity which found its distinction and its immediate modalities of
recognition (its confirmation) in the âlarge factoryâ, in the dichotomy
between employment and unemployment, work and training, in the
submission of the labour process to the collectivity of workers, in the
link between wages, growth and productivity on a national level, in the
institutional representations that all this implied, as much in the
factory as at the level of the state, and, last but not least, in the
social and cultural legitimacy and pride in being a worker. There was a
self-presupposition of capital, in accordance with the concept of
capital, but the contradiction between the proletariat and capital
couldnât situate itself at this level, in so far as within this
self-presupposition there was a production and confirmation of a
workersâ identity through which the class struggle structured itself as
the workersâ movement.
The decomposition of programmatism contains the increasingly obvious
impossibility of conceiving the revolution as a âgrowing-overâ[111] of
that which the proletariat is in capitalist society, of its rising power
as a workersâ movement. The process of revolution is practically and
theoretically posed in terms of class autonomy, as so many ruptures with
its integration, and of the defence of its reproduction.
Self-organisation and autonomy become the revolution, to such an extent
that the form suffices for the content.
Self-organisation, strong unions and the workersâ movement, all appeared
in the same world of the revolution as affirmation of the class. The
affirmation of the truly revolutionary being of the class which
manifests itself in autonomy could not have the slightest basis in
reality if it werenât for the good de-alienated side of this world which
was experienced as a strong workersâ movement âframingâ the class.
Self-organisation entails the self-organisation of struggle, thus the
self-organisation of producers. In a word â liberated labour; in another
word â value. This cycle of struggle culminated between the end of the
60s and the first half of the 70s. Practically and theoretically,
autonomy was unleashed in every possible manner, from self-organised
unions to insurrectionary autonomy. This world is now obsolete.
There is no restructuring of the capitalist mode of production without a
workersâ defeat. This defeat was that of workersâ identity, of communist
parties, of unionism; of self-management, self-organisation and
autonomy. The restructuring is essentially counter-revolution. Through
the defeat of a particular cycle of struggle â the one which opened in
the aftermath of World War I â it is the whole programmatic cycle which
reached its conclusion.
We have just briefly outlined the âthesis of programmatism.â For DauvĂ©
and Nesic this thesis is âfalse in regard to the facts, and even more so
in regard to the method, the attitude in relation to the world to be
transformed.â[112] Nevertheless, DauvĂ© and Nesic have understood it
neither in regard to the facts nor the âmethod.â And as for the
âattitudeââŠ
The starting point for their refutation of the âthesis of programmatismâ
is a misunderstanding:
âFrom the 1960s onwards, a more and more visible resistance to work,
sometimes to the point of open rebellion, has led quite a few
revolutionaries to revisit the past from the point of view of the
acceptance or rejection of work.â[113]
âA real critique of work was impossible in the 60s ⊠Now things are
completely different.â[114]
This observation is historically correct, but the misunderstanding
resides in the fact that to understand the breakdown of programmatism as
a crisis of work and its overcoming formulated as a âcritique of workâ
is to remain within programmatism.
Given that the proletariat presented itself as a revolutionary class in
the critique of all that which âarticulatesâ it as a class of the
capitalist mode of production, in the councilist and
self-organisationalist vision the worm was already in the fruit. It
popped its head out at the beginning of the 70s, with the ideology of
self-negation of the proletariat and the critique of work. It was only
by opposing itself to that which could define it as a class of the
capitalist mode of production that the proletariat could be
revolutionary. The ârefusal of workâ, the riots, lootings and strikes
without demands, naturally became the supreme activity on the basis of
which self-negation could take place. All that was needed was to
self-organise, set up The Councils whilst no longer remaining
âlabourersâ and âworkersâ: i.e. to square the circle.
Theoretical humanism allowed that which appeared as negation and refusal
to be seen as overcoming. Dauvé and Nesic are examples of theoreticians
blocked at this stage of theoretical production, not only because they
understand neither the restructuring nor the new cycle of struggle, but
most importantly because they are waiting for such things to resurface â
the resurrection of a schema which was already in its own day an
ideology of the failure of a cycle of struggle coming to an end. Just as
the relation between the rising strength of the class and its autonomous
affirmation expresses, in its own terms, the failure of programmatism,
this same relation, in the form of the relation between
self-organisation and self-negation, expresses the impossibility of the
revolution, in its own terms, in the cycle of the decomposition of
programmatism. Communism is not principally the abolition of work, it is
only such within a theoretical system founded on the analysis of labour,
that is to say on the relation between man and nature as the starting
point of communist theory. What matters in reality are the social
relations which determine human activity as labour â the point is thus
the abolition of these relations and not the abolition of work. The
âcritique of workâ is not able to positively address the restructuring
as a transformation of the contradictory relation between classes. It
can only address it negatively in terms of the âliquidationâ or
de-essentialisation of work.
For DauvĂ© and Nesic we are free of the âold workersâ movementâ based on
the âconsecration of workâ and âworkersâ identityâ etc., but this has
resulted in no ârevolutionary clarificationâ â in short we are no
further down the road. It is obvious that âproletarian autonomy has not
taken advantage of bureaucratic decline,â for they both belong to the
same world of workersâ identity. DauvĂ© and Nesic attribute this
liquidation exclusively to capital, as if the âstruggles of â68â had no
role to play. Trapped in their normative problematic of the revolution
(in fact an ideological result of the failure of the previous cycle)
they see only the disappearance of the old and not the appearance of the
new.
Today, the overcoming of revindicative struggles[115] as revolutionary
struggle â i.e. as communisation â is presaged whenever, in these
struggles, it is its own existence as a class that the proletariat
confronts. This confrontation takes place within revindicative struggles
and is first and foremost only a means of waging these struggles
further, but this means of waging them further implicitly contains a
conflict with that which defines the proletariat. This is the whole
originality of this new cycle of struggle. Revindicative struggles have
today a characteristic that would have been inconceivable thirty years
ago.
The proletariat is confronted by its own determination as a class which
becomes autonomous in relation to it, becomes alien to it. The
objectifications in capital of the unity of the class have become
palpable in the multiplication of collectives and the recurrence of
discontinuous strikes (the strikes of spring 2003 in France, the strike
of the English postmen). When it appears that autonomy and
self-organisation are no longer the perspective of anything, as with the
transport strike in Italy or that of the workers at FIAT Melfi, it is
precisely there that the dynamic of this cycle is constituted and the
overcoming of revindicative struggles is presaged through a tension
within revindicative struggles themselves.
To put unemployment and precarity at the heart of the wage relation
today; to define clandestinity (TN: undocumented, black-market work) as
the general situation of labour power; to pose â as in the direct-action
movement â the social immediacy of individuals as the already existing
foundation of the opposition to capital, even if this opposition
describes the whole limit of this movement; to lead suicidal struggles
like those of Cellatex and others of Spring and Summer of 2000;[116] to
refer class unity back to an objectivity constituted by capital, as in
all the collectives and discontinuous strikes; to target all that
defines us, all that we are, as in the riots in the French suburbs of
2005; to find in the extension of revindicative struggles the
questioning of revindication itself, as in the struggles against the
CPE; are contents, for all of these particular struggles, which
determine the dynamic of this cycle within and through these struggles.
The revolutionary dynamic of this cycle of struggle, which consists in
the class producing and confronting in capital its own existence, that
is to say putting itself in question as a class, appears in the majority
of struggles today. This dynamic has its intrinsic limit in that which
defines it as a dynamic: action as a class.
In Argentina, in the productive activities which were developed,
principally within the Piquetero movement, something occurred which was
at first glance disconcerting: autonomy appeared clearly for what it is
â the management and reproduction by the working class of its situation
in capital. The defenders of ârevolutionaryâ autonomy would say that
this is due to the fact that it didnât triumph, although its triumph is
precisely there. But at the moment within productive activity when
autonomy appeared as it is, everything on which autonomy and
self-organisation are founded was upset: the proletariat cannot find in
itself the capacity to create other inter-individual relations (we
deliberately do not speak of social relations) without overturning and
negating what it is in this society, that is to say without entering
into contradiction with autonomy and its dynamic. In the way that these
productive activities were put into place â in the effective modalities
of their realisation, in the conflicts between self-organised sectors â
the determinations of the proletariat as a class of this society
(property, exchange, division of labour) were effectively upset.
Self-organisation was not superseded in Argentina, but the social
struggles pointed beyond themselves to such a supersession; it is in
this way that the revolution becomes credible as communisation. The
generalisation of the movement was suspended, its continuation
conditioned upon the ability of every fraction of the proletariat to
overcome its own situation, that is to say the self-organisation of its
situation.
To act as a class today means, on the one hand, to no longer have as a
horizon anything other than capital and the categories of its
reproduction, and on the other, for the same reason, to be in
contradiction with oneâs own reproduction as a class, to put it into
question. These are two faces of the same action as a class. This
conflict, this divergence[117] in the action of the class (to reproduce
itself as a class of this mode of production / to put itself into
question) exists in the course of the majority of conflicts. To act as a
class is the limit of the action of the proletariat as a class. This
contradiction will be a practical question in need of resolution, a
question much more difficult, risky and conflict laden than the limits
of programmatism.
Revolutionary activity is the rupture and overcoming that Dauvé and
Nesic are looking for, but a produced rupture and overcoming â it has
nothing to do with the immediate and above all presuppositionless
transformation of the âpater familiasâ into a ârevolutionary
romanticist.â[118]
The alliance between the autonomy of the proletariat and the negation of
classes, the worker and man, which is an emergent ideology from a
particular historical situation (that of May â68 and its failure) has
been presented by Dauvé and Nesic as the invariant substance of a
âtensionâ within the proletariat âbetween the submission to work and the
critique of work.â[119] Their essentialist and invariant problematic of
the proletariat and communism prevents them from having a historical
conception of revolution and communism. The concept of programmatism is
the basis of such a conception â a conception that they declare âfalse
in regard to the facts, and even more so in regard to the methodâ.
Dauvé and Nesic make seven objections to the concept of programmatism:
for âotherwise, how do we account for the frequent demand to work less?â
The workers couldnât have had the liberation of labour as their
perspective because they didnât want to work more for the boss. The
argument is simply dumbfounding. DauvĂ© and Nesic donât understand the
âaffirmation of labourâ as the âliberation of labourâ, that is to say
the abolition of its situation of subordination. The âliberation of
labourâ is precisely the reverse of wanting to work more (for less
money) for the boss. It is precisely not to consider wage labour as a
positive reality, but as that which is to be abolished. This objection
wouldnât be worth citing if we didnât find it repeated in inverted form
in the ideology of the âsocial bondâ or âadhesionâ which is supposed to
be one of the terms of the âtensionâ within the being of the
proletariat.
the workersâ movement and not of the workers themselves
This is passing a little rapidly over the fact that the workers
themselves had founded these organisations and adhered to them in
sometimes massive numbers. Besides, it was indeed the workers who, even
if to defend their existence as workers (but how else could it be when
one sets up workersâ councils?), created councils, soviets, occasionally
experimented with self-management, took control of factories,
participated in factory committees, set up cooperatives and founded
organisations, parties and unions which had the dictatorship of the
proletariat and the liberation of labour as their programme. If we say
that the liberation of labour is the theory of the organisations and not
the working class, first it is false, but even if it were true it would
be necessary to explain the relation between the two.
The history of the Commune is supposed to show that all of the
aforementioned rigmarole didnât actually interest the workers. In his
preface to Bilan, Dauvé says that during the Commune the communists,
âbeing few in number,â were âcautiousâ.[120] But it is the content of
their programme that explains these âcautionsâ: the presentation of the
affirmation of labour as âthe final end of the movementâ which must
integrate âa long historical processâ;[121] the fact that in their own
programme the communists recognised the historical necessity of those
(the bourgeois republicans) who were about to eliminate them. There was
a lot to be âcautiousâ about.
The re-appropriation of production by the workers was in reality such a
small priority for the Commune that its central committee announced as
early as 21st of March 1871 (between the 18th and the 26th, thus before
the re-appropriation by the republicans) in its Journal official: âThe
workmen, who produce everything and enjoy nothing, who suffer from
misery in the midst of their accumulated products, the fruit of their
work and their sweat⊠shall they never be allowed to work for their
emancipation?â[122] Commenting on this citation Marx writes: âit is
proclaimed as a war of labour upon the monopolists of the means of
labour, upon capital;â[123] and a little bit further, âwhat the Commune
wants is the social property which makes property the attribute of
labour.â[124]
Leaving aside these overt calls for re-appropriation, the number of
enterprises and workshops taken over by the workers is far from being
insignificant, nor was the system the Commune employed of handing out
contracts to the most âsocially progressiveâ bid. In the end it is the
nature of the struggle for the liberation of work that explains the
small number of measures of the kind Dauvé and Nesic are looking for.
This struggle of the working class is moulded by all the historical
mediations of capitalist development. Marx attacks the âpatronizing
friends of the working classâ who congratulate themselves that âafter
all, workmen are rational men and whenever in power always resolutely
turn their back upon socialist enterprises! They do in fact neither try
to establish in Paris a phalanstĂšre nor an Icarieâ.[125] In a word,
those who seek the immediate realisation of the liberation of labour
which is, for Marx, merely âa tendencyâ in the measures taken by the
Commune, remain at the stage of utopian socialism and have not
understood that these objectives have now become real through their
submission to the âhistorical conditions of the movement.â[126]
Although âthe working class did not expect miracles from the
Commune,â[127] this working class knew that to âwork out their own
emancipationâ they would have to âpass through long struggles,â a
âseries of historic processes,â in order for them to be recognised as
âthe only class capable of social initiativeâ[128]â and recognised as
such by the middle class, which was supposed to line up, with the
Commune, on the side of the workers.
The âhesitantâ and timid character of these measures has also another
root. Toward the end of March, within the Commune, the workers were
beaten in their own camp. If Marx doesnât speak of the social
significance of the transformation of the Communeâs organs of
management, and if he pretends that the Commune is exclusively a
workersâ government (âthe finally achieved form of the dictatorship of
the proletariatâ) it is because, for him, the revolution is not where
we, today, look for it â that is to say in the independence of
proletarian action and in its capacity to abolish itself in abolishing
the capitalist mode of production â but in the capacity of the
proletariat to represent the whole of society and its future. Looked at
closely, this other reason for âhesitancyâ is not that different than
the first. The historical development of working class practice implies
its defeat as an autonomous class.
As with the Commune, the Russian Revolution of 1917 is supposed to
confirm that âthe proletarians hardly manifested any productive
enthusiasm.â And nevertheless in an earlier text by DauvĂ© we find:
ââŠthe movement of factory and workshop Committees saw a remarkable surge
between February and October. These committees were most often created
with the aim of obtaining the eight-hour day and wage increases. In
April the provisional government recognized their right to represent the
workers in their negotiations with bosses and the government, but little
by little the committees tried to influence the direction of the
factories which they took over in several cases.â[129]
âDuring this time [after October 1917, the Bolshevik leadership having
inaugurated and structured workersâ control in Russia âin the interests
of a planned direction for the national economyâ] the Russian workers
continued to animate the Committees which often tried to seize
factories. As the January 1918 number of the Voice of the Metal Workers
states: âthe working class, from its nature, must occupy the central
place in production and especially its organisationâŠâ But these efforts
often lead to failure.â[130]
Of course one can change oneâs opinion, but thatâs not on the issue here
â rather than the opinion about them, it is the historical facts
themselves that have changed: that which existed exists no more.
One can equally refer to more âclassicalâ historians:
âThe natural consequence of the [February 1917] revolution was to
exacerbate the economic struggles. In this context the factory
committees became the veritable protagonists of the confrontation
between Capital and Labour. They regulated the unions from behind. âŠ
Moreover, their leaders [the unions], mostly Mensheviks, took care to
avoid intervening directly in the domain of production. It was thus the
factory committees which immediately took this up, without a thought to
the limits to which they were assigned by law. The workers of many
factories had started to interrogate the questions of administration and
technical direction, even to the point of chasing bosses and engineers
out of the factory. When the employer decided to leave the key under the
door it was common to the find the factory committee taking over the
management of the establishment. ⊠By launching the slogan of âworkersâ
controlâ, which constituted an essential aspect of their programme, the
Bolsheviks fanned the flames of the spontaneous movement which grew from
the radicalisation of the working masses. They thus encouraged â for
tactical reasons which we will return to later â the libertarian and
anarcho-syndicalist tendencies which appeared in the factory committees
and which sought to establish a workersâ power in each separate
enterprise, without making use of a centralised direction or taking into
account the whole economic reality, thus a singularly confused
programme. While the Mensheviks and the union leaders foresaw a state
control of production, conforming to the generally accepted socialist
principles, the factory committees generally stood up for the direct
seizure of the enterprise and the self-management of the
factories.â[131]
âWorkersâ committees rapidly formed in the factories and a decree for
the provisional government of the 22nd April 1917 gave them a legal
existence in recognising their right to represent the workers in
relation to the employers and the government. Their first demands were
for the 8 hour day and a wage rise. But these demands didnât delay in
arriving at more or less organised attempts on the part of workers, at
first sporadic, but soon more and more frequent, to intervene in the
management and to take possession themselves of the factories âŠ
Nonetheless, that which no one foresaw, was that the seizure of the
factories by the workers would be in the long term even less compatible
with the establishment of a socialist order than the seizure of land by
the peasants.â[132]
The last phrase by Carr contains the solution to the next question.
place under workersâ control, the leaders of âworkersââ organisations
had a very hard time imposing discipline on workers who showed little
productive enthusiasm.
The first thing would be to explain why such âoccasionsâ existed. But
letâs let this pass and come to the objection itself. The emancipation
of labour is here conceived as the measurement of value by labour time,
the preservation of the notion of the product, and the framework of the
enterprise and exchange. At those rare moments when an autonomous
affirmation of the proletariat as liberation of labour arrives at its
realisation (necessarily under the control of organisations of the
workersâ movement), as in Russia, Italy and Spain, it immediately
inverts itself into the only thing it can become: a new form of the
mobilisation of labour under the constraint of value and thus of
âmaximum outputâ (as the CNT demanded of the workers of Barcelona in
1936) provoking ipso facto, though marginally, all the reactions of
disengagement or workersâ resistance (cf. Seidman, M., Workers Against
Work in Barcelona and Paris).
According to Dauvé the Russian Revolution of 1917 showed two
fundamentally related things: firstly the workers âdid little to restart
productionâ[133] and lacked productive enthusiasm, and secondly these
workers found themselves âfaced with new bosses,â and responded âas they
usually do, by individual and collective resistance, active and
passive.â[134] We have dealt with the first point, letâs pass to the
second. Why were the workers confronted with new bosses? Why was the
revolution a failure? What is this ârevolutionary dynamicâ which,
coexisting with the âcrystallization of powerâ would define the Russian
Revolution as a âcontradictory processâ which went through an
involution?[135] In all the texts of Dauvé and Nesic there is never a
response to these questions. To respond to them they would have to
qualify their ârevolutionary dynamicâ, specify it historically, along
with its counter-revolution. Yet it is here that we discover the
forbidden dimension of their theory. For it presupposes that though the
development of capital can be historically specified, the revolution,
just like the counter-revolution, must be as it is in itself for all
eternity. This hiatus prevents them from arriving at any synthesis.
DauvĂ© and Nesic donât want to see the self-management and the seizure of
the factories in the ascendant phase of the Russian Revolution (February
to October 1917). They donât completely deny the facts, but class them
in the range of activities subject to necessity (i.e. poverty). In their
conception, given that the revolution must â by definition â be free,
that which arises from necessity cannot be revolutionary. Thus there was
never any revolutionary emancipation of labour because everything that
could be seen as close to it in fact depends on the sordid activity of
necessity. âWhat would be the worth of a revolution into which we were
pushed against our wills?â ask DauvĂ© and Nesic in an earlier text.[136]
There is a ârevolutionary Ă©lanâ[137], a ârevolutionary dynamicâ, but
these must remain undefined: everything else is ânecessityâ. To define
them would be to see the essential relation between the revolution and
the Bolshevik counter-revolution, it would be to define the failure of
revolution in terms of its very nature as liberation of labour, in terms
of the seizing of production by the âassociated producersâ. In effect it
would mean having to deal with that which is described by Anweiler, Carr
or Voline; and even DauvĂ© and Nesic themselvesâŠ
These latter two report all the trouble that the Bolsheviks had in
returning the factories to a state of order. In this way they contradict
their previous assertion about the infrequency of workers seizing
factories and taking over the management of production. The Bolshevik
counter-revolution finds its source and flows naturally (which doesnât
mean without confrontation) from the course of the workersâ revolution.
It is as Trotsky said âthe seizure of power by the whole of the
proletariatâ, and simultaneously âworkersâ control initiated in the
interests of a planned regulation of the national economyâ (Decree on
Workersâ Control of 14-27 November 1917). If revolution is the control
and management of the factories, the organisation of their relations,
the circulation and exchange of the products of labour, it has nothing
to oppose to the state, to value, to the plan and a renewed capitalist
management, other than its rank and file soviet democracy â that is to
say nothing, a pure form â or else resistance to the re-imposition of
work.
Yet this is not without importance. The proletariat does not simply find
itself once more in an ordinary capitalist enterprise. Its refusal of
work is situated at the heart of programmatism. In its manifestation of
what, on its own terms, is an internal contradiction and impossibility
of the programmatic revolution, the refusal of re-imposed work
anticipates that which will spell the death of programmatism at the end
of the 1960s.
In the most general sense, in its internal contradiction and the
practical process of its own impossibility, programmatism produces the
terms of its overcoming. It is through all that which, practically and
theoretically, exists for us today as this impossibility that we can
relate ourselves to the history of past struggles and to the continuity
of theoretical production. We donât attribute to these struggles and
theoretical productions the consciousness or the possibility to see
another perspective, because we can only relate to them through the
mediation of a restructuring of the capitalist mode of production which
was their defeat. We donât relate to these elements genealogically, but
reproduce them in a problematic constituting a new paradigm of the
contradiction between proletariat and capital.
It is true, there was never any âscope for a workersâ capitalismâ, but
that simply means that there was scope for a capitalist
counter-revolution articulated within a workersâ revolution based upon
the seizing of factories, liberating labour, and erecting the
proletariat as ruling class; a counter-revolution that was able to turn
the latterâs content back against it. If âthe proletarians didnât come
up with an alternative to Bolshevik policy,â[138] it is because
Bolshevik policy was the accomplishment against them of their
revolution.
Just as in Spain against the CNT, the UGT or the POUM, the workers have
nothing to oppose to the management of enterprises by their
organisations, because the programme that they apply is their own. The
revolution as affirmation of the class implacably transforms into the
management of capital, smoothly reverts into the counter-revolution to
which it provides its own content. Faced with this ineluctable reversal
of their own movement, overseen by their own organisations, the workers
are thrown back to resisting work. The revolution as affirmation of the
class finds itself confronted by a counter-revolution which has for its
content that which justified the revolution itself: the rising power of
the class in the capitalist mode of production, its recognition and
integration in the reproduction of the capitalist mode of production. We
could even call it the âdictatorship of the proletariatâ.
We can only agree with DauvĂ© and Nesic when they write that âthe Russian
revolutionary crisis shows that as long as capital reigns, labour canât
be liberated and must be imposed upon the wage-earners.â[139] And yet
the social and historical mechanism of this dynamic must be made clear:
the liberation of labour is impossible because it calls forth its own
counter-revolution as capitalist organisation of work. Dauvé and Nesic
dispel the problem saying: no revolution ever presented itself as such
(except in the programme of the organisations). We have very briefly
seen that this is false. Being unable to explain by what mechanism this
impossibility imposes itself, they prefer to say that things didnât
happen. Anyone can proclaim that âin 1917-21, the alternative was
between abolishing wage labour or perpetuating exploitation, with no
possible third optionâ[140] â itâs a nice phrase, but it expresses
absolutely nothing; says nothing about the period of ârevolutionary
crisisâ. In the sense that nobody â not a single social movement â posed
such an opposition other than as the liberation of labour and the
opening of a period of transition; the radical alternative, as Dauvé and
Nesic present it, simply didnât exist.
In Italy, as in Russia, being unable to explain what happened, Dauvé and
Nesic decide that nothing happened. For the whole period one must start
from two principal facts: (1) there was a powerful organised workersâ
movement, which (2) had as a programme the affirmation/emancipation of
labour (the workersâ creating factory councils, etc.). These two major
elements define the periodâs content. Faced with the reversal that they
suffer, the workers are disarmed in the sense that that which is taken
over by the organisations is in fact the perspective, now turned against
them, that they themselves advance from their own ranks.
It is difficult to regard the articles and reports of Malatesta on the
situation in Italy as merely a series of militant lies. On the 28th of
June 1922, in lâUmanitĂ Nova, Malatesta writes: âThe metal workers
started the movement over the question of wages. It turned out to be a
strike of a new kind. Instead of abandoning the factories, they stayed
in them without working, guarding them night and day against any
lockout. But we were in 1920. All of proletarian Italy was trembling
with revolutionary fever, and the movement rapidly changed character.
The workers thought it was the moment to definitively take over the
means of production. They armed themselves for defence, transformed
numerous factories into veritable fortresses, and began to organise
production for themselves.â[141]
In Italy once more it is the revolutionary perspective of emancipation,
of âseizing the factoriesâ, which allowed the state and the bourgeoisie
to retake control of the situation (with the violent intervention of the
fascists). The number of occupations decline after the 25th of September
1920 with the signing of the accord between Aragonna, chief of the CGL,
and the government of Giolitti:
âthe famous decree on the control of the factories is a joke, because it
gives birth to a new band of bureaucrats who, although they come from
your ranks, will not defend your interests, but only their position,
because they seek to combine your interests with those of the
bourgeoisie, which is to try to set a wolf to tend a goat.â[142]
In lâUmanitĂ Nova of the 10th September 1920, under the title To the
Metal Workers, Malatesta writes:
âEnter into relations between factories and with the railway workers for
the provision of raw materials; come to agreements with cooperatives and
with the people. Sell and exchange your products without dealing with
ex-bosses.â[143]
âSell and exchange your productsâ: in the very injunction of Malatesta
to pursue and deepen revolutionary combat resides its failure and
reversal into counter-revolution. The same worker who would applaud
Malatesta will the very next day press for slowing down the work rate in
âthe enterprise in the hands of the workersâ. To take over the
factories, emancipate productive labour, to make labour-time the measure
of exchange, is value, is capital. As long as the revolution will have
no other object than to liberate that which necessarily makes the
proletariat a class of the capitalist mode of production, workersâ
organisations which are the expression of this necessity will employ
themselves to make it respected. Being unable to hold onto the
articulation of these elements, Dauvé and Nesic have decided, against
all the evidence, that the workersâ never had the perspective or
practice of the emancipation of labour. What is more, although for Dauvé
and Nesic it was indeed the case that all of that was true of the
organisations â to deny this would be very difficult â it is still
necessary to explain who could have put such ideas into the heads of the
organisations. The facts which were still visible in When Insurrections
Die, and even more in the Preface to Bilan, have here disappeared.
Nothing happened, move on, there is nothing to see.
Dauvé and Nesic see the problem without being able to connect the terms.
In their argumentation they ceaselessly confuse the effective
impossibility of the liberation of labour with its non-existence, just
as they confuse the âliberation of labourâ with âthe liberating power of
labour.â
further exploitationâ
It is contentious to try to separate revindicative struggles in a given
period from revolution and communism as they are defined in that same
period. It is hardly credible to say that in 1848 the workers only
struggled against the worsening of their conditions, that the insurgents
only ârose to surviveâ[144], and that the struggles betrayed no
perspective of the reorganisation of society around the âorganisation of
labourâ and its generalisation, that is to say liberation, by the
working class. Such incredibility is amply demonstrated by a glance at
the political expressions of the Parisian working class in that year:
âMarche, a worker, dictated the decree [decree on the right to work, 25
February 1848] by which the newly formed Provisional Government pledged
itself to guarantee the workers a livelihood by means of labour, to
provide work for all citizens, etc. And when a few days later it forgot
its promises and seemed to have lost sight of the proletariat, a mass of
20,000 workers marched on the HĂŽtel de Ville with the cry: Organise
labour! Form a special Ministry of Labour.â[145]
To ârise up in order to surviveâ is an expression as lacking in meaning
in 1848 as it is in 2007. Every insurrection and even every strike,
however âmodestâ, always exists in a certain period of the contradiction
between the proletariat and capital. To this degree, the defence of
physical survival has no more existence in itself, is no more an
ahistorical invariant, than is communism âin its deep contentâ.
In the form of the National Workshops the âdefence of survivalâ becomes
a question of social regime: âThe right to work is, in the bourgeois
sense, an absurdity, a miserable, pious wish. But behind the right to
work stands the power over capital; behind the power over capital, the
appropriation of the means of production, their subjection to the
associated working class, and therefore the abolition of wage labour, of
capital, and of their mutual relations. Behind the âright to workâ stood
the June insurrection.â[146]The Parisian workers ârose up to surviveâ
and this insurrection for survival contained: âthe organisation of
labour,â and the âsubmission of the means of production to the
associated working classâ. A precise study of the insurrection of June
shows that it was substantially supported by the unemployed workers of
the National Workshops. Yet one finds in far greater number those who
were not directly touched by the closure of the National Workshops: the
local workers and the professions who had also been the most virulent
during the quasi general strike which hit Paris in 1840.
On this connection between immediate struggles, political reform and
social revolution, the most important movement of the period is without
doubt Chartism. About this Dauvé and Nesic say not a word. For doing so
would make it difficult to suggest that the aspiration to re-appropriate
the means of production by the associated workers was only an ideology
which had no correspondence in the practice or mobilisation of the
workers, and that the resistance to the worsening of exploitation is a
neutral and purely quantitative activity.
For Dauvé and Nesic 1848 marks a turning point in the history of
workersâ struggles:
â1848 tolled the knell of the utopia of a wage-labour capital, of a
working class that would become the ruling class and then the unique or
universal class through the absorption of capital in associated labour.
From then on, via a growing union movement, the workers will only be
concerned with their share of the wage system, they wonât try to compete
with the monopoly of capital owned by the bourgeoisie, but to constitute
themselves as a monopoly of labour power. The programme of a popular
capitalism was on the wane.â[147]
Thus that which never existed nonetheless had an existence prior to
1848. The peculiarity of eclecticism is to fail to perceive that the
elements which one juxtaposes may contradict each other. This
consideration of the pre-1848 period is all the more surprising given
that this period of âwage-labour capitalâ is for them, in another
respect, essentially that of the expression of communism in âits deep
contentâ: the proletariat of the human community, not yet bogged down in
the defence of the wage (see below).
Thus the proletariat no longer attempted, after 1848, to become a ruling
class. With a wave of the theoretical wand, Dauvé and Nesic manage to
make the Commune vanish; they imply that all the post-1848 texts of Marx
are apocryphal; they convince us that revolutionary syndicalism never
existed. Even German Social Democracy, with its rising power of the
class and the theory of the spontaneous socialization of capital leading
to socialism, fails to fit with the need of Dauvé and Nesic to flatten
class struggle in the extreme for fear of recognizing the infamous
programmatism; even Bernstein and Hilferding disappear. The project of
âa working class take over of industrializationâ is over in 1848, just
as that of âa working class that would become the ruling class.â[148] Of
course! If it didnât come from such good authors one would suspect
simply ignorance, here one must also suspect the theoretical impasse of
a discourse which after being tempted by an indeterminate ârevolutionary
Ă©lanâ has to silence itself from fear of allowing it to be determined.
Once again: move on, there is nothing to see!
If we can consider that 1848 is a break, it is only in the measure that
that which was an alternative project, that is to say, able to coexist
with bourgeois society (cooperatives etc.), became after â48 a political
project presupposing the reversal of bourgeois society. Far from
âtolling the knellâ of workersâ emancipation and the liberation of
labour (articulated, of course, with the revindicative struggles of the
working class), 1848 marked the generalisation of this project in a
struggle of class against class.
half-hearted
And once again we find an epoch where that which never existed attained
its apogee. Dauvé and Nesic concede that there might have been a period
of the workersâ composition of a world of free labour:
âthe aspiration to set up the workers as the ruling class and to build a
workersâ world was at its highest in the heyday of the labour movement,
when the Second and Third Internationals were more than big parties and
unions: they were a way of life, a counter-society⊠Workersâ or
âindustrialâ democracy was an extension of a community (both myth and
reality) ⊠that shaped working class life from the aftermath of the
Paris Commune to the 1950s or 60s.â[149]
Here is a remarkable concession, but one which doesnât recognize that
this organised workersâ movement was also a counter-revolutionary force.
DauvĂ© and Nesic want to insist that this âworkersâ worldâ which shaped
the life of the working class was just a âutopia of skilled
labourâ.[150] Yet even in Germany between 1919 and 1921, where for DauvĂ©
and Nesic this movement of skilled workers had gone the furthest, âthere
were hardly any attempts to take over production in order to manage it.
Whatever plans they may have nurtured, in practice neither the Essen and
Berlin workers nor those in Turin put work at the centre of society,
even of a socialist one.â[151]
Weâve already seen in the case of Italy and Russia that if we shouldnât
confuse the activity of workers with the activity of organisations and
their programmes, it is completely insufficient to satisfy oneself with
the distinction. When the principle factory organisations are grouped
into two unions (AAUD and AAUDE) that together counted several hundred
thousand members (not counting those adhering to the revolutionary
unions) the programme of the KAPD is not an invention of the
theoreticians of the KAPD. It is the only perspective that the struggle
itself allows. In the period about which Dauvé and Nesic speak (in fact
since 1848), the struggle for the emancipation of labour passes by a
political struggle; that is, the abolition of existing society (whatever
form this takes, seizure of power or abolition of the state) and
establishment of the proletariat as a ruling class (which cannot fail to
turn back on itself in the very course of its success as
counter-revolution). The workers of Essen, Berlin and Turin âput work at
the centre of societyâ by their very uprising. What else is the power of
the councils where it momentarily establishes itself other than the
power of workers as workers? Are we supposed to believe that the workers
sought power for its own sake?
The seizure of state power, the political victory, is the necessary
preamble, even the first act, of the emancipation of labour, the
proletariat becoming a ruling class. In Germany between 1918 and 1923,
in Italy in 1920, the political struggles for the power of the working
class, the dictatorship of the proletariat, had for their content the
affirmation of the proletariat as a ruling class and through this the
generalization of its condition. Under the pretext that they see no (or
very few) self-managed factories, Dauvé and Nesic deny that the
political struggle had the affirmation of the proletariat as a ruling
class for its object, that is to say, the emancipation of labour.
We canât help but note that in these pages on the âutopia of skilled
labourâ, DauvĂ© and Nesic, for the second time, and contrary to their
official religion, link a certain practice of the proletariat to a
certain level of development of capital, that which they condemn in the
theoretical conclusion of their text. This link is made several times in
their text, with the artisan, the manufacturing worker, the skilled
worker, the mass worker. That which Dauvé and Nesic refuse to attribute
to the contradiction between the proletariat and capital and its
overcoming â to be a history â they accord to the action of historically
existing workers. In a kind of impoverished Operaismo, they confer to
âclass compositionâ that which they canât allow for revolution and
communism.
The seventh objection is not exactly of the same nature as the others.
It applies to the struggles at the end of the 1960s and the beginning of
the 1970s. That is to say, to the period when programmatism is at the
end of its course, the period in which we are ready to recognise that
the affirmation of the proletariat and the liberation of labour are no
longer the content and perspective of the class struggle. As a
consequence, we could, to an extent, agree with the comments on these
struggles, and at a push this objection would not be one at all. Yet
only to an extent⊠and for two reasons. Firstly, Dauvé and Nesic
recognise no historical break, for history is the looming absence in
their whole normative horizon; the examples only succeed one another in
a chronological order by the simple habit of thought and presentation â
they could be presented in any other order without having the slightest
influence on the âdemonstrationâ. Secondly, in accordance with their
permanent denial of the reality of anything which could be seen as
affirmation of labour, they fail to see that the overcoming of
programmatism, very real in the struggles of this period, still takes
place within programmatism.
The turn at the end of the sixties and the beginning of the seventies
was simply the breakdown of programmatism. âMay â68â was the liquidation
of all the old forms of the workersâ movement. The revolution was no
longer a question of the establishment of the proletariat as a ruling
class which generalises its situation, universalises labour as a social
relation, and the economy as the objectivity of a society founded on
value. But the âMay â68â period doesnât simply remain in this
impossibility of being a programmatic revolution.
On the one hand we had a strong workersâ movement with solid roots, the
confirmation by capital of a workersâ identity, a recognised strength of
the class but a radical impossibility to transform this strength into an
autonomous force and into a revolutionary affirmation of the class of
labour. On the other, this impossibility was positively the extension of
a revolt against all social reproduction, a revolt through which âthe
proletariat negated itselfâ.
The revolution could only be the negation of the workerâs condition, but
it was necessary to seek it, not in the relation between proletariat and
capital, but in the universality of alienation. Universal, and to this
extent human, alienation. Through real subsumption capital had subjected
all social reproduction, all aspects of life. In encompassing the whole
of everyday life, the revolution was the negation of the proletarian
condition. Through the universality of its negation the revolt became
autonomised from its real conditions, it appeared to no longer flow
directly from the situation of the working class, but from the universal
alienation of which this situation was the consummation, the
condensation.
The revolt against the condition of the working class, revolt against
every aspect of life, was caught in a divergence. It could only express
itself, only become effective, in turning against its own foundations,
the workersâ conditions, but not in order to suppress them, for it
didnât find in itself the relation to capital which could have been that
suppression, but in order to separate itself from them. âMay â68â thus
remained on the level of a revolt.
The workers fled the factories occupied by the unions, the youngest
among them joined the student struggle, May â68 was the critique in acts
and often âwith the feetâ of the revolution as the rising strength and
affirmation of the class. The workers only entered the factories at the
moment of the return to work, often to oppose themselves violently to
it. Here we are in agreement with the few remarks of Dauvé and Nesic on
May â68. Where we diverge is in the fact that for them such a thing is
not a historical product, but merely fits into the long list of examples
that they evoke. It is supposed to have always been this way, from the
simple fact of what the proletariat is and what the revolution must be.
For Dauvé and Nesic the end of the sixties is prosperity and the
critique of prosperity (consumer society, everyday life, alienation), it
is the workersâ movement and the âcritique of workâ â the enigma is
solved. The revolution must be both a workersâ revolution and a human
revolution, but only âworkersââ because in the worker it is the human
that is negated. As a worker the proletarian has the possibility to
smash this society, as a human, to construct the new one. To remain at
this position is to remain within an ideology born of the failure of
â68. During that whole period, in Italy, France and elsewhere, class
struggles expressed but failed to overcome the limits and impasses of
the previous cycle, that of workersâ identity, of autonomy, of
self-organisation, that which formed the very definition of the
revolutionary dynamic, whilst today they form its limit.
This contradiction internal to class struggle appeared in Italy, from
the mid-sixties, in a very concrete manner, in the extension of
struggles beyond the factories. On the one hand the central figure of
the Italian working class, that through which all class struggle was
structured, is that of the industrial triangle MilanâTurinâGenoa, and,
in this triangle, principally the productive workers of the big
manufacturers. On the other hand, such a concentration implies, and only
exists through, the socialisation and massification of the working class
beyond the immediate process of production. The workersâ struggle is
also the town, transport, housing, all of social life. By encompassing
all of everyday life, class struggle becomes a refusal of the workerâs
condition, but it only encompasses all social life from the basis of the
factory, the very extension only exists under the leadership, the
tutorship, of the worker of the large factory: Turin is FIAT. This
movement contains a contradiction between, on the one hand, the central
figure of workersâ identity, still dominating and structuring class
struggle, on the basis of which this movement exists, and, on the other
hand, the struggle over the entirety of reproduction which can thus not
give everything that it contains, cannot put into question the condition
of the worker itself. The struggle over the wage is the place of this
contradiction, the place it becomes concrete. That which the workerists,
in a programmatic perspective, theorised as âpolitical wageâ or
âself-valorisation of the working classâ was, as a practice, as a
particular struggle, the contradiction in which, on the basis of the
very situation of the worker and within this, the reproduction of the
worker as such was put into question. The slogan of workersâ power in
the factories coexisted with the refusal to live outside as a worker and
to be employed as a worker in that very factory. The class struggle
developed within that highly contradictory and unstable configuration in
which it is labour which refuses to function, in capitalism, as labour
power.
Autonomy can only be programmatic, because it is by its very nature
workersâ autonomy. The movement of â69 is still a movement of the
affirmation of the proletariat and the emancipation of labour, it is its
dominant characteristic. It is only on the basis of this dominant
characteristic that one can understand that it contains within it that
which subsequently puts it into question, renders it impossible. It was
the same workers who committed sabotage and organised the marches in the
factories who regrouped in the CUB as in Pirelli, or who found
themselves in the student-worker assemblies in Turin. It is in this
situation that all the originality and importance, as much historical as
theoretical, of this period lay.
Today every revindicative struggle of whatever size or intensity is
self-organised and autonomous; self-organisation and autonomy can be
opposed to the unions, but always remain merely a moment of unionism. We
have passed from one cycle of struggle to another.
But for Dauvé and Nesic it is not enough to say that nothing happened,
it is necessary to add that those for whom what happened was the
revolution, as defined historically in its strength and its failure in
its own terms, commit a methodological error: determinism. Any
historical critique which fails to acknowledge the invariant substance
and says that revolution and communism are historical is branded with
the infamous epithet.
The âmethodological errorâ of ThĂ©orie Communiste (not named) is supposed
to consist in believing that there is a âsituationâ or a âperiodâ in the
history of the capitalist mode of production, and therefore of class
struggle (but this âthereforeâ is, as we shall see, for DauvĂ© and Nesic
another methodological error), which will assure the victory of the
communist revolution. We finally confront the famous determinist devil.
DauvĂ© and Nesic do not see that the âerrorâ they denounce is only an
âerrorâ if we accept all their presuppositions. Only if we suppose that
the communist revolution is a given and known substance since the
beginning of the class struggle within capitalism.[152] If we accept
that the proletariat would have been able to do in 1968 what it did in
1848, in the Paris of 1830 what it did in Bologna in 1977, that the
insurgents of the Commune failed because they didnât do what the SI had
said nonetheless had to be done, it is obvious that TC is wrong.
The principle âerrorâ is necessarily accompanied by an accessory error.
We are supposed to have looked to capital and its development to resolve
our problems in our place. This is to assume that it is capital alone
which suppressed workersâ identity, the âold workersâ movementâ, and, as
a consequence, that which we call programmatism. As if the struggles at
the end of the sixties and the beginning of the seventies had nothing to
do with it; as if the re-appropriation of the themes of workersâ
identity in the radical democratic movement and the practical critique
of this radical democratism by the direct action movement are all for
nothing. Even if we accepted that capital suppressed workersâ identity,
it could only be as a counter-revolution, that is to say against the
preceding revolution and not as an objective tendency which would âgiveâ
us ready-made new âconditionsâ, without us participating in their
emergence.
We will develop all these questions around the three synthetic themes
that Dauvé and Nesic expose: there is no direct link between proletarian
action and the degree of the development of capital; the âbeingâ of the
proletariat; and the âreasons for past failuresâ.
of the development of capital
âIf the âbeingâ of the proletariat theorized by Marx is not just a
metaphysics, its content is independent of the forms taken by capitalist
domination. The tension between the submission to work and the critique
of work has been active since the dawn of capitalism. Of course the
realization of communism depends on the historical moment, but its deep
content remains invariant in 1796 and in 2002.â[153]
If there is a âbeingâ of the proletariat, and moreover a being on which
the ârealization of communismâ depends, the revolution is inevitable. No
amount of theoretical tinkering around the âhistorical momentâ as the
conjunctural condition of the becoming actual of this âbeingâ will
change anything. The âbeingâ will always find its way through
contingency and circumstance. Communism âin its deep contentâ will
remain invariant in 1796 and 2002. All that remains is to name that
âdeep contentâ, and, in passing, indicate a little contingent dross due
to the âhistorical momentâ of 1796 or 2002. But how do we separate the
dross from the âinvariantâ?
Contrary to what DauvĂ© and Nesic say, if this âbeingâ is ânot just a
metaphysicsâ then it is not âindependent of the forms taken by
capitalist dominationâ. How could its âbeingâ be independent when the
proletariat is only a class of the capitalist mode of production? The
âbeingâ is held to be independent of the forms taken by capitalist
evolution, but apparently the ârealization of communismâ is âof courseâ
dependent on the âhistorical momentâ. Here we are knee-deep in the
metaphysical relation par excellence: that of the essence and its
conditions, of the tendency and its realisation. Dauvé and Nesic are
careful to avoid explaining the relation between this âbeingâ and the
âhistorical momentâ. It goes without saying, just like the spontaneous
idealism with which we think unawares. It is a case of the ideology of
the launch window. They believe themselves to have overcome determinism
because, as DauvĂ© writes in Human, all too Human: ânothing guarantees
that a communist movement will be able or want to take advantage of it,
but the possibility is there.â[154] A âpossibilityâ which may or may not
be actualised⊠in other words: objective conditions.
âHistory does not prove any direct causal link between a degree of
capitalist development, and specific proletarian behaviour.â[155] The
âMetropolitan Indiansâ of Bologna could have taken the Winter Palace,
and the unemployed of the National Workshops could have set up workersâ
councils. Dauvé and Nesic have conserved the entire theoretical
structure of determinism, but the key element has become impossible to
maintain: the identification of the âdevelopment of capitalâ with
ârevolutionary activityâ, that is, the rising strength of the class in
the capitalist mode of production. As a result, they find themselves
with a class activity which floats in the void, condemned to
self-determination, that is to say indetermination. Such a conclusion
cannot be expressed as such; one thus needs determination, but not too
much, âinvarianceâ and the âhistorical momentâ. And above all lots of
âfreedomâ, because the development of capitalism has been paradoxically
maintained in its objective density.
The development of capitalism is nothing more than the contradiction
between the proletariat and capital; there is no âlinkâ, neither rigid,
nor fluid, nor direct. In the end Dauvé and Nesic tinker between
determinism and liberty, necessity and possibility, invariance and
contingency, freedom with a little determinacy and determinism with a
little freedom. One must allow the proletariat the âfreedomâ to rise to
its âhistoric taskâ.[156] What a strange freedom, and a strange critique
of determinism, which can speak of an âhistoric taskâ. In the end it is
their own determinism that Dauvé and Nesic are seeking to exorcize.
To look for the cause of revolutions and their failures in the relation
between the proletariat and capital as they existed, is that to do
anything other than to look for them in the practice of proletarians?
What would this practice be if not the relation to capital? What would
this development of capital be if not this relation? To demand that we
search for the causes of âour failuresâ only in the âactivity of
proletariansâ is to see the development of capital as a frame to which
we attribute more or less effectivity, but always as a sum of
conditions. Dauvé and Nesic have conserved all the fundamental
separations of objectivism and determinism, their only âoriginalityâ is
to have refused the causal link which unites the elements. This renders
their production incoherent and eclectic, and their writing full of
hesitation and oscillation (yes/but, it is such and such/but of course
we know that nonethelessâŠ). And yet it is we, for whom the âsolutionâ is
neither a presupposition nor ineffable, but a real historical
production, and of the only history that exists, that of the capitalist
mode of production, who are supposed to be âdeterministsâ.
When we define exploitation as the contradiction between the proletariat
and capital, we define that contradiction as a history. The stage of the
cycle of accumulation is not an external condition of victories or
defeats, a conjuncture. Accumulation is part of the definition of the
proletariat and its contradiction with capital. The proletariat is
defined in the totality of the moments of exploitation, in the sense
that it implies its reproduction and produces the conditions of the
latter. To define the proletariat in the three moments of exploitation
(the coming together of labour power and capital and the buying and
selling of labour power, the absorption of living labour by objectified
labour in the immediate process of production where surplus value is
formed, the transformation of surplus value into additional capital) is
to understand that the development of capital is not the realisation or
the condition of the class contradiction which opposes the proletariat
to capital, it is the real history of this contradiction. The
contradiction does not dress itself in different forms, because it is
nothing other than these forms. Those who would take umbrage at that,
assuming it means capital would be doing the work in our (the
revolutionary proletariansâ) place, have understood nothing of what a
social relation means. All this also implies the historicity of the
content of communism. Communism is historical in that it is in relation
with the immediate course of each cycle of struggle. When we say that
the revolution and communism can only be immediate communisation, that
doesnât mean that communism has finally presented itself today as it
always really was or as it always should have been.
To all those who say that 1848, 1917, 1968 etc. ended up in a way that
could have been averted, we have a right to demand that just for once
they tell us what made them end up where they did other than by saying
that they ended up where they did because they didnât end up where they
could have. Could anything else have happened? We donât know and we
donât care. The question is meaningless. That which didnât happen leaves
the domain of thought to enter the domain of faith and madness. The
ideology of the possible looks to the past and says âthis could have
been or not beenâ, it consists in considering as contingent, on the
basis of the subsequent period, that which was essential to the previous
period. From this substitution is born the belief in the invariant as
the substantial core which results from the movement.
If the restructuring of the contradiction between the proletariat and
capital resolves to a large extent the contradictions and limits of
programmatism (not without the participation of workersâ struggles), it
neither gets us closer to a purity of this contradiction, nor a purity
of capital. What creates this illusion is the fact that the capitalist
mode of production always restructures itself according to what it is,
and overcomes the limits which had been its own (its own conditions of
valorisation and reproduction in a given moment). The restructuring is a
supersession which, though unforeseeable (constituted along the
tempestuous flow of struggles), cannot infringe upon the nature of
capital. Once the restructuring is accomplished, the previous
characteristics of capital appear for the next period as contingent,
non-indispensable in relation to the nature of capital, but they were
certainly not contingent for the previous period. It is in this way that
the becoming appears predetermined as a march towards purity. This is
the trap into which fall all the ideologues who, not being able to
conceive of history beyond teleology, choose to suppress it.
What is more, the question as to the âultimateâ character of this cycle
of struggle has no solution, for strictly speaking it cannot be posed
theoretically (and it never has been, for any cycle of struggle). Does
that mean that the revolution and communisation are now the only future?
Again this is a question without meaning, without reality. The only
inevitability is the class struggle though which we can only conceive of
the revolution of this cycle of struggle, and not as a collapse of
capital leaving a space open, but as an historically specific practice
of the proletariat in the crisis of this period of capital. It is thus
this practice which renders the capitalist mode of production
irreproducible. The outcome of the struggle is never given beforehand.
It is self-evident that revolution cannot be reduced to a sum of its
conditions, because it is an overcoming and not a fulfilment. It is
communisation which renders the contradiction between the proletariat
and capital irreproducible.
In the last resort, the independence of communism âin its deep contentâ
in relation to the development of the contradiction between the
proletariat and capital has its ontological argument: that of the
philosophical communism of 1843-46.
Philosophical communism, which invokes Man and Species, characterises
the quasi totality of theoretical production in the first half of the
1840s. For the âGermansâ its point of departure is the critique of
religion. This critique, as Marx himself applied it, is the matrix of
the critique of all alienations (as Marx affirms in the first sentence
of the Introduction of 1843). It follows that manâs rediscovery of his
essence in the critique and abolition/overcoming of religion is,
according to him, the matrix of all abolitions (money, work etc.): the
return of the subject to itself as Community, Species Being, Man.
Stirner was right to say that Man had replaced God and that it is the
worst of all religions.
Man externalises his own powers, he objectifies them. It was thus
necessary to rediscover the anthropological nature of religion in order
to abolish it. Of course what was found there was the mechanism of every
alienation, abolition, and overcoming for philosophical communism,
including the abolition of labour which, in becoming
âself-manifestationâ, was intended to reconcile the essence of the
proletariat as a person with his immediate being. The abolition of
money, of the state, followed the same logical mechanism. The
Feuerbachian critical apparatus was generalised. The result of the
abolition/overcoming is merely the true form of the essence of man.
There is only a historical development and contradiction as an inverted
form of the true community, which is already the truth of this inverted
form. Alienation is merely its own becoming for itself.
âLabour is manâs coming to be for himself within alienation or as an
alienated man.â[157] Alienated labour or alienation of the essence of
man are thus only moments of the identity in-itself of labour and its
objects, of man and his externalised forces, in the process of becoming
an identity for-itself. The loss is only a form of the identity, its
necessary becoming in order to rediscover itself (here lies all the
limits of the concept of alienation). Against all the analysis of
Capital or the Grundrisse in which we rediscover these expressions of
the alienation of labour or its product, here the point of departure is
not a social relation, but a subject (man) which divides itself in its
identity with itself. Itâs in this sense that labour is destined to be
abolished, because labour exists here only to produce its abolition.
In The German Ideology the abolition of labour is deduced from two
themes: the virtual universality of the proletariat in relation to the
history of the division of labour as universalisation of productive
life; the contradiction in the life of the individual between its
existence as a person and its existence as a member of a class. This
second theme can be seen as derived from the first. Potentially
universal, labour can no longer be a âmeansâ.
Those who think that Marx and Engels, between 1843 and 1846, with the
abolition of labour and the other abolitions, grasped what we are now
able to conceive of communist revolution donât realise that it is the
very fact of conceiving the revolution as abolition of labour which
distinguished their vision from ours. The abolition of labour, for Marx
and many others, was the emancipation of the proletariat not, of course,
as an affirmation of labour, but as a movement of the affirmation of a
class which, because in the old world it is ârid of the old worldâ[158],
represents the movement which abolishes existing conditions: communism.
But since simultaneously, as action, communism exists as the definition
of a class of this society, it follows that it is its independent
organisation, its reinforcement and its pursuit of its own ends, the
defence of its interests in this society which becomes identified with
communism itself. Less than a year after The German Ideology, the
abolition of labour explicitly becomes the âliberation of labourâ[159],
because the âabolition of labourâ was the emancipation of the
proletariat and the emancipation of the proletariat was its actual
existence as action in the present society. At the moment when the old
theory became coherent and concrete it flies into pieces.
The years 46-47 do not mark the passage between two theories of
communism or revolution: a âradicalâ theory which, from the moment of
its entry on the historical stage, is supposed to have announced, thanks
to a particular situation of the proletariat, the quintessence of
Communism, and a theory of the proletariat as class of the capitalist
mode of production destined to defend its interests within it, a theory
of the defence of the wage. It marks a passage from a philosophy of the
proletariat, the revolution and communism, to a theory of the
proletariat, the revolution and communism. This latter is not our own,
but the former still less so. In this philosophical communism, under the
same words, the concepts are absolutely different from our own, are
inscribed in a completely different problematic. It is illusory to try
to use some formulas as if they could be applied to class struggle as it
exists today.
The revolutionary humanism of the âyoungâ Marx, which he shares with all
the theoreticians of the epoch, amounts, in the period which comes to a
close in 1848, to the belief that capitalism and the domination of the
bourgeoisie is only an ephemeral state (Marx broke from this position
before â48). The proletariat is only a class of transition, an unstable
social form resulting from the decomposition of society.
From the moment the contradiction was posed, its overcoming was supposed
to be imminent. What escaped Marx and Engels at that early point was
that capital could be the development of the contradictions which give
rise to it, that they could be its raison dâĂȘtre, that which nourishes
it, that they could be the principle of its accumulation. They didnât
see development as part of the contradiction, it was only anecdotal in
relation to it, and could well not be from the moment that The
Contradiction is. But it is thus the contradiction itself which is
purely formal because its development is unnecessary.
We could treat the history of capital as unimportant because in 1845 (or
1867) and in 2007 it is identical in itself, and conclude that what was
said of communism at its beginning is fixed in stone. But those who
believe that the history of capital is without importance in the sense
that, from the beginning, it is as it is in itself, have not yet managed
to become Hegelian. Parmenides suffices. They leave the development
alongside being as something which doesnât form part of it, something
accidental. Contrary to the Marx of 1843-46, if we can and must speak of
revolution today as the abolition of work (and all the rest) we do it on
the basis of the internal contradictions of the capitalist mode of
production, of exploitation, of the situation of the proletariat,
without any reference to the âpersonâ of the proletariat, to a âhuman
essenceâ, to âman as communityâ. We are in contradiction with capital on
the basis of what we are, that is to say of what capital is, and not
from what we could be, a potential which would somehow already exist as
suffering. It is the breakdown of programmatism which, at the end of the
sixties and beginning of the seventies, momentarily resurrected the very
conditions of its emergence as if they could also be those of its
overcoming. We momentarily all became Feuerbachians again, âŠsome of us
remained so. They have thus made of an ideology born of the failure of
â68, the eternal formula of the communist revolution.
The question of the âbeingâ of the proletariat was raised and criticised
at the beginning of the previous section. Here we consider more closely
the central role given to labour in the âtensionâ within this âbeingâ.
âThe tension between the submission to work and the critique of work has
been active since the dawn of capitalismâ. There we have it: the âbeingâ
of the proletariat. On the one side: the âadherenceâ and âinvestmentâ
which come with the wage relation, yet also the famous âanthropological
dimensionâ of work;[160] but the first wouldnât be able to function
without the second, the other side: the desire for âevasionâ and
âcritiqueâ of work. But can one oppose an âanthropological dimensionâ?
No. In the âtensionâ defined by DauvĂ© and Nesic the âanthropological
dimensionâ effectively possesses the status of a mediation. It is that
which permits the âadherenceâ of the worker to his work, but
simultaneously, combined this time with the ârejectionâ of this work,
that which opens other social horizons.
As always, if we have a ârevolutionary beingâ this means that something
in this being is the seed of its overcoming. In the revolution, the
evasion and critique of work must be combined with adherence in so far
as the former is also anthropological.
DauvĂ© and Nesic have uncovered the âsecretâ and the âmysteryâ over which
Marx slaved away all his life: the âintegrationâ of the proletariat with
the âtriumphant and destructive march of capitalâ.[161] Such
âenslavementâ and âintegrationâ is supposed to be founded on the
anthropological nature of work which is prevented from rejecting its
enslavement by the fetishism of commodities which âveils the social
relations producing capitalâ.[162] For DauvĂ© and Nesic capital is not a
relation or production which defines us, but something which makes us
adhere. The social relation explains why we enter it, but then the whole
problem is there: we no more enter a social relation than we adhere to
it. Fetishism and its veil are necessary to a problematic for which the
social definition of classes, or more trivially individuals, is a matter
of adherence. However, it isnât as exchangers that proletarians and
capitalists confront each other, but as poles of a social relation, as
classes.
It is the relation of exploitation and its reproduction, the capital
relation, which includes exchange, and not the other way around. It is
because it is a relation of exploitation that, if we want to put it like
that, âcapitalism imposes daily in real life and impresses on our minds:
the economy as something obvious and inevitable, the necessity of
exchanging commodities, of buying and selling labour.â[163] But then
itâs not a kind of blackmail, an imposition we must obey ââŠif we wish to
avoid want, misery and dictatorship,â that intergrates us into the
âdestructive march of capital.â We are not intergrated by the fetishism
of commodities (which is different to that of capital, i.e. the
autonomisation of the elements of production in their relation to
profit) but by the very structure of the social relation which is our
own, exploitation â a relation which has turned exchange into an
immanent moment of the domination of living labour by objectified
labour. The possibility of tearing away the âmystifying appearance of
the transactionâ is situated within the contradictions of exploitation,
the abolition of exploitation is not dependent on the tearing of the
veil. If we read DauvĂ© and Nesic closely it seems that the âsocial bondâ
is for them what authorises the reproduction of capital.[164] Everything
is inverted and appears as if the actors of capitalist society imagine
their belonging to society as an environment. The âsocial systemâ is
based on those it enslaves because the fetishism of commodity exchange
veils the social relation productive of capital. The point is to
overcome âthe economy as something obvious and inevitable.â
The âsocial bondâ is always the reproduction of the capitalist social
relation, always the self-presupposition as result of the contradiction
between the classes in the sense that capital is always the dominant
pole, assuring and constraining reproduction. In reality capitalism is
only âbased on those it enslavesâ to the extent that âthose it enslavesâ
exist only in the âenslavementâ which defines them. They wonât get out
of this slavery by tearing away a âveilâ, but only by abolishing this
slavery, by abolishing themselves. This is only possible due to the
contradictory process of this enslavement for capital itself. The
contradiction between the proletariat and capital is a contradiction for
the very thing for which it is the dynamic: the capitalist mode of
production. Itâs in this sense that it is a contradiction which can lead
to its own abolition. Capitalism is not only âbased on those it
enslavesâ, but it is also in the very nature of this enslavement that
the capacity for the latter to become revolutionary resides. It is the
object as totality â the capitalist mode of production â that is in
contradiction with itself in the contradiction of its elements, because
this contradiction with the other is for every element, to the extent
that is its other, a contradiction with itself. The overcoming of the
contradiction of exploitation is provided by its non-symmetrical aspect
(subsumption of labour under capital). The situation of the proletariat
is the self-contradiction of the reproduction of capital. When we say
that exploitation is a contradiction for itself we define the situation
and revolutionary activity of the proletariat.
Dauvé and Nesic expressly say:
âThe proletarian only starts acting as a revolutionary when he goes
beyond the negative of his condition and begins to create something
positive out of it, i.e. something that subverts the existing order.
Itâs not for lack of a critique of work that the proletarians have not
âmade the revolutionâ, but because they stayed within a negative
critique of work.â[165]
We are still waiting for them to define âa positive critique of work.â
They avoid doing this because it would require them also to define this
anthropological work which capital imperfectly subsumes to itself and
which, in relation to the refusal of this subsumption, gives us the
revolution. Dauvé and Nesic want the liberation of true labour. Such
âliving labour with universal graspâ only exists as such, that is, as
abstraction, to the extent that capital nourishes it; it is nothing more
that its relation to capital.
âLabour power overcoming its condition and rising to its historic task
of freeing itself from its chains, and thus freeing humanity.â[166] What
an unfortunate and truly determinist formula. Doubly unfortunate, for
not only does it take up that dominical determinism of the âold daysâ
soapbox discourse, it indicates all the hidden discourse of Dauvé and
Nesic â that of the liberation of labour. Labour power âfreeing itself
from its chainsâ is a contradiction in terms. Itâs true that it has
already âovercome its conditionâ, but this just renders everything more
confused. If it âovercomes its conditionâ it is no longer labour-power,
there is nothing left which can be called by that name.
The conclusion of DauvĂ© and Nesicâs text is given the authoritative
stamp of a quote from Babeuf: âwe are not of this world.â Sylvain
Maréchal took the hospice as the model of communist organisation, Babeuf
took the army. To call proletarians at the turn of the 19th century âmen
from nowhereâ is to cast around phrases without consideration. We would
recommend, on this subject, the reading of E.P. Thompsonâs The Making of
the English Working Class, of which Gilles Dauvé was one of the
translators, to understand all the historical, cultural and geographical
rootedness which formed this class and on the basis of which it formed
itself. Dauvé and Nesic do not conceive of the overcoming of the
capitalist mode of production on the basis of the contemporary situation
and practice of the working class in this mode of production, within it,
as its contradictory process; they write: âthe decline of workerism was
accompanied by the loss of a point of view allowing a perspective on the
whole of this society, gauging and judging it from the outside in order
to conceive and propose anotherâ.[167]
After regretting not being able to âjudgeâ and âgaugeâ society âfrom the
outsideâ in order to propose another, they wait for the proletarians to
act as if they were outside: âRevolution will only be possible when the
proletarians act as if they were strangers to this world, its outsiders,
and will relate to a universal dimension, that of a classless society,
of a human community.â[168] What does it mean to act as if one was
outside? Note the circumlocutions of the formula. Already how to act
âoutsideâ is hardly obvious, but to act âas ifâ one was outside⊠The
outside connects to the universal dimension: we are in total conceptual
phantasmagoria. One of the most difficult things to understand is the
nature of contradiction: that the capitalist social relation can be on
the one hand totally ours and we can only be it, and, on the other, that
we could in that very respect abolish it.
The abolition of the proletarian condition is the self-transformation of
proletarians into immediately social individuals, it is the struggle
against capital which will make us such, because this struggle is a
relation that implies us with it. The production of communism is
effectuated by a class which finds the content of communism in its own
class situation, without having to attach itself to any âuniversal
dimensionâ. Communisation is carried out in the struggle of the
proletariat against capital. Abolishing exchange, the division of
labour, the structure of the corporation, the stateâŠ, are measures which
are necessarily taken up in the course of struggle, with their retreats
and their sudden stops they are just as much tactical measures through
which communisation is constructed as the strategy of the revolution. It
is thus, through the struggle of a class against capital, that the
immediately social individual is produced. It is produced by the
proletariat in the abolition of capital (the final relation between
capital and the proletariat), and not by proletarians who will no longer
be completely proletarians acting âas if they were outsideâ. But then,
protest the delicate souls, âwe would be forcedâŠâ
Proletarian activity does not determine itself because it has no âdirect
link with capital,â it determines itself because it is its relation to
capital and nothing more and this relation is a contradiction. That can
only be seen as determinism if one wants to define a subject prior to
its relations in which alone it exists, which define it, and in which it
acts. If we separate the subject and its action from its âframeâ we can
only conceive of their relation in the alternative of determinism and
freedom.
Why the failure? In a certain way Dauvé and Nesic give an answer: the
revolution failed because the proletariat failed to make the revolution.
They never get beyond that tautology and they cannot. It is inevitable
because to get beyond that tautology would be to determine the
historical action of proletarians, it would be to establish a link
between the development of capital and proletarian activity. The
tautology is structural to their thought. If you mess with the tautology
you mess with freedom.
DauvĂ© and Nesic can only accuse TC of âdeterminismâ by supposing that TC
shares their own fixed, normative and invariant conception of the
revolution. It is obvious that in such a problematic the revolution
cannot âresult from a particular stageâ, for it is âinvariant in its
deep contentâ.
For us, the revolution of which we speak today is, if you will, the
product of the current situation; it is not The Revolution rendered at
last possible by the current situation. In the problematic of Dauvé and
Nesic TC is determinist, what DauvĂ© and Nesic havenât noticed is that TC
abandoned that problematic thirty years ago. They critique TC as if TC
was just giving another response to the same problematic.
After 18 pages intended to show that it never (and could never have)
existed, Dauvé and Nesic allow the supposition that the working class
was âentangled in its identification with workâ.[169] We wouldnât say
the class was ever âentangledâ, we would rather say strengthened by its
identification with work. We donât share DauvĂ© and Nesicâs normative
view of the revolution. Until a recent period there was no revolution
without this âidentification with workâ (or else there has never been a
revolutionary movement). If the proletariat is defined through
accumulation and acts accordingly, its failure is not interior to its
practice; it lies in its relation to the counter-revolution. This
practice is a determinant practice and not a communist practice
inherently propelled towards an internal impossibility. This practice is
directed at the community of labour, and it has really been rendered
impossible in the class struggle through its relation to the
counter-revolution.
If we say today that the revolutions were beaten on the basis of what
they were, that their intimate relationship to the counter revolution
was found within them (as certain left communist tendencies perceived),
if we do not replay history supposing that the revolutions could have
been anything else, we nonetheless donât say that they lacked anything,
we donât attribute to them the consciousness which results precisely
from their failures and counter-revolutions. The Russian proletarians of
1917, German of 1919, or Spanish of 1936, acted as such, they carried
out the revolutionary movement which was theirs in all consciousness and
all contradiction. The limits of their movement were imposed on them by
the counter-revolution that they had to fight. What we can say now of
these movements, we say now, and if we say why they failed we owe it to
the combats as they were waged. Our analysis is a result; the result
doesnât pre-exist the thing. Anyone is free to explain what was on the
basis of what ought to have been, and to imagine the latter; that isnât
our method.
âWhat privilege permits the observer in the year 2000 to know that his
standpoint is ultimately the right one? Nothing can guarantee that in
2050, after 50 more years of capitalism, a even more broad-ranging
overview wonât establish for x + y reasons the ways in which the
proletarians of the year 2000 ⊠remained historically constrained by the
limits of their times, and thus that communism wasnât actually in the
offing in the year 2000 any more than it was in 1970 or 1919, but that
now a new period is ushering itself in, allowing us to genuinely grasp
the past from the new, proper viewpoint.â[170]
The point of view is a good one because, today, itâs the only one we
have, because it is ours. We donât aspire to an eternal grasp of
communism because such a thing doesnât exist. Of course we may be
âconstrained by our limitsâ, but for as long as the combat continues
these limits are what we are, our force which will perhaps become our
undoing. We know that if, in the current cycle, the limit of the class
activity of the proletariat is to act as a class, then nothing is
determined in advance, and overcoming this contradiction will be
arduous. But we also know that for us, now, communism is the abolition
of all classes and that it is the overcoming of all previous limits of
class struggle.
We donât believe in the unchanging being of the proletariat or in the
invariant need of the human community since time immemorial. We think
the situation in which we find ourselves: our cycle of struggle carries
such a content and such a structure of the confrontation between capital
and the proletariat, and for us it is the communist revolution, because
for us it is rigorously impossible to envisage other forms and other
contents.
The debate between Théorie Communiste (TC) and Troploin (Dauvé & Nesic)
that we have reproduced revolves around the fundamental question of how
to theorise the history and actuality of class struggle and revolution
in the capitalist epoch. As we have stressed in our introduction, both
sides of the debate were products of the same political milieu in France
in the aftermath of the events of 1968; both groups share, to this day,
an understanding of the movement which abolishes capitalist social
relations as a movement of communisation. According to this shared view,
the transition to communism is not something that happens after the
revolution. Rather, the revolution as communisation is itself the
dissolution of capitalist social relations through communist measures
taken by the proletariat, abolishing the enterprise form, the commodity
form, exchange, money, wage labour and value, and destroying the state.
Communisation, then, is the immediate production of communism: the
self-abolition of the proletariat through its abolition of capital and
state.
What sharply differentiates TC's position from that of Troploin,
however, is the way in which the two groups theorise the production, or
the historical production, of this movement of communisation. Neither
grounds the possibility of successful communist revolution on an
âobjectiveâ decadence of capitalism; however, Troploin's conception of
the history of class struggle, in common with much of the wider
ultra-left, is of a fluctuating antagonism between classes, an ebb and
flow of class struggle, according to the contingencies of each
historical conjuncture. In this wider conception, the revolutionary
struggle of the proletariat appears to be or is submerged at some points
in history, only to re-emerge at other âhigh pointsâ (e.g. 1848, 1871,
1917-21, 1936, 1968-9). On this view, we are currently experiencing a
prolonged downturn in class struggle (at least in the advanced
capitalist countries), and it is a case of waiting for the next
re-emergence of the communist movement, or for the revolutionary
proletariat to carry out its subversive work: âWell burrowed, old
Mole!â[171]
Thus for Troploin, communism as communisation is an ever-present (if at
times submerged) possibility, one which, even if there is no guarantee
that it will be realised, is an invariant in the capitalist epoch. By
contrast, for TC communisation is the specific form which the communist
revolution must take in the current cycle of struggle. In distinction
from Troploin, then, TC are able to self-reflexively ground their
conception of communisation in an understanding of capitalist history as
cycles of struggle.
TC historicise the contradictory relation between capital and
proletariat on the basis of a periodisation of the subsumption of labour
under capital; this periodisation distinguishes cycles of struggle
corresponding to the qualitative shifts in the relation of exploitation.
This history for TC comprises three broadly identifiable periods: (1)
formal subsumption â ending around 1900; (2) the first phase of real
subsumption â from 1900 to the 1970s; (3) the second phase of real
subsumption â from the 1970s to the present.
Importantly for TC, the subsumption of labour under capital is not
merely a question of the technical organisation of labour in the
immediate production process, in which formal subsumption would be
paired with the extraction of absolute surplus value (through the
lengthening of the working day) and real subsumption with the extraction
of relative surplus value (through increasing productivity by the
introduction of new production techniques, allowing workers to reproduce
the value of their wages in less time thus performing more surplus
labour in a working day of a given length). In TC's conception, the
character and extent or degree of subsumption of labour under capital is
also, and perhaps fundamentally, determined by the way in which the two
poles of the capital-labour relation, i.e. capital and proletariat,
relate to each other as classes of capitalist society. Thus for TC, the
key to the history of capital is the changing mode of reproduction of
capitalist social relations as a whole according to the dialectical
development of the relation between classes. Of course this development
is itself intrinsically bound up with the exigencies of surplus-value
extraction. In short, for TC the subsumption of labour under capital
mediates, and is mediated by the specific historical character of the
class relation at the level of society as a whole.
There is something problematic both in the way TC use the concept of
subsumption to periodise capitalism, and in the way this usage partially
obscures one of the most significant aspects of the development of the
class relation which their theory otherwise brings into focus. Strictly
speaking, formal and real subsumption of labour under capital only apply
to the immediate process of production. In what sense, for example, can
anything beyond the labour-process ever be said to be actually subsumed
by capital rather than merely dominated or transformed by it?[172] TC,
however, attempt to theorise under the rubric of these categories of
subsumption the character of the capitalist class relation per se rather
than simply the mode in which the labour-process actually becomes the
valorisation-process of capital. Yet it is through their questionable
theoretical deployment of the categories of subsumption that TC are able
to advance a new conception of the historical development of the class
relation. Within this periodisation the degree of integration of the
circuits of reproduction of capital and labour-power is of decisive
importance. The key to the historical periodisation of the class
relation is the extent to which the reproduction of labour-power, and
hence of the proletariat as class, is integrated with the circuit of
self-presupposition of capital.[173]
TC's âperiod of formal subsumptionâ is characterised by an un-mediated,
external relation between capital and proletariat: the reproduction of
the working-class is not fully integrated into the cycle of valorisation
of capital. In this period, the proletariat constitutes a positive pole
of the relation, and is able to assert its autonomy vis-Ă -vis capital at
the same time as it finds itself empowered by capitalist development.
However the rising power of the class within capitalist society and its
autonomous affirmation steadily come into contradiction with each other.
In the crushing of workersâ autonomy in the revolutions and
counter-revolutions at the end of the First World War this contradiction
is resolved in an empowerment of the class which reveals itself as
nothing more than capitalist development itself. This qualitative shift
in the class relation marks the end of the transition from the period of
formal subsumption to the first phase of real subsumption. From this
point on the reproduction of labour-power becomes fully integrated,
albeit in a heavily mediated fashion, into the capitalist economy, and
the process of production is transformed in accordance with the
requirements of the valorisation of capital. The relation between
capital and proletariat in this phase of subsumption is one which is
becoming internal, but mediated through the state, the division of the
world economy into national areas and Eastern or Western zones of
accumulation (each with their accompanying models of âthird worldâ
development), collective bargaining within the framework of the national
labour-market and the Fordist deals linking productivity and wage
increases
The positivity of the proletarian pole within the class relation during
the phase of formal subsumption and the first phase of real subsumption
is expressed in what TC term the âprogrammatismâ of the workersâ
movement, whose organisations, parties and trade unions (whether social
democratic or communist, anarchist or syndicalist) represented the
rising power of the proletariat and upheld the programme of the
liberation of labour and the self-affirmation of the working class. The
character of the class relation in the period of the programmatic
workersâ movement thus determines the communist revolution in this cycle
of struggle as the self-affirmation of one pole within the
capital-labour relation. As such the communist revolution does not do
away with the relation itself, but merely alters its terms, and hence
carries within it the counter-revolution in the shape of workersâ
management of the economy and the continued accumulation of capital.
Decentralised management of production through factory councils on the
one hand and central-planning by the workersâ state on the other are two
sides of the same coin, two forms of the same content: workersâ power as
both revolution and counter-revolution.
For TC this cycle of struggle is brought to a close by the movements of
1968â73, which mark the obsolescence of the programme of the liberation
of labour and the self-affirmation of the proletariat; the capitalist
restructuring in the aftermath of these struggles and the crisis in the
relation between capital and proletariat sweeps away or hollows out the
institutions of the old workersâ movement. The conflicts of 1968â73 thus
usher in a new cycle of accumulation and struggle, which TC term the
second phase of real subsumption, characterised by the capitalist
restructuring or counter-revolution from 1974â95 which fundamentally
alters the character of the relation between capital and proletariat.
Gone now are all the constraints to accumulation â all impediments to
the fluidity and international mobility of capital â represented by
rigidities of national labour-markets, welfare, the division of the
world economy into Cold War blocs and the protected national development
these allowed on the âperipheryâ of the world economy.
The crisis of the social compact based on the Fordist productive model
and the Keynesian Welfare State issues in financialisation, the
dismantling and relocation of industrial production, the breaking of
workersâ power, de-regulation, the ending of collective bargaining,
privatisation, the move to temporary, flexibilised labour and the
proliferation of new service industries. The global capitalist
restructuring â the formation of an increasingly unified global labour
market, the implementation of neo-liberal policies, the liberalisation
of markets, and international downward pressure on wages and conditions
â represents a counter-revolution whose result is that capital and the
proletariat now confront each other directly on a global scale. The
circuits of reproduction of capital and labour-power â circuits through
which the class relation itself is reproduced â are now fully
integrated: these circuits are now immediately internally related. The
contradiction between capital and proletariat is now displaced to the
level of their reproduction as classes; from this moment on, what is at
stake is the reproduction of the class relation itself.
With the restructuring of capital (which is the dissolution of all the
mediations in the class relation) arises the impossibility of the
proletariat to relate to itself positively against capital: the
impossibility of proletarian autonomy. From being a positive pole of the
relation as interlocutor with, or antagonist to, the capitalist class,
the proletariat is transformed into a negative pole. Its very being qua
proletariat, whose reproduction is fully integrated within the circuit
of capital, becomes external to itself. What defines the current cycle
of struggle in contradistinction to the previous one is the character of
the proletariat's self-relation which is now immediately its relation to
capital. As TC put it, in the current cycle the proletariat's own class
belonging is objectified against it as exterior constraint, as
capital.[174]
This fundamental transformation in the character of the class relation,
which produces this inversion in the proletariat's self-relation as pole
of the relation of exploitation, alters the character of class
struggles, and causes the proletariat to call into question its own
existence as class of the capitalist mode of production. Thus for TC the
revolution as communisation is an historically specific production: it
is the horizon of this cycle of struggle.[175]
For TC, the relation between capital and proletariat is not one between
two separate subjects, but one of reciprocal implication in which both
poles of the relation are constituted as moments of a
self-differentiating totality. It is this totality itself â this moving
contradiction â which produces its own supersession in the revolutionary
action of the proletariat against its own class-being, against capital.
This immanent, dialectical conception of the historical course of the
capitalist class relation supersedes the related dualisms of
objectivism/ subjectivism and spontaneism/ voluntarism which
characterised most Marxist theory in the 20th Century and indeed up to
the present. The dynamism and changing character of this relation is
thus grasped as a unified process and not simply in terms of waves of
proletarian offensive and capitalist counter-offensive.
According to TC, it is the qualitative transformations within the
capitalist class relation that determine the revolutionary horizon of
the current cycle of struggle as communisation. For us, it is also true
at a more general level of abstraction that the contradictory relation
between capital and proletariat has always pointed beyond itself, to the
extent that â from its very origins â it has produced its own overcoming
as the immanent horizon of actual struggles. This horizon, however, is
inextricable from the real, historical forms that the moving
contradiction takes. It is thus only in this qualified sense that we can
talk of communism transhistorically (i.e. throughout the history of the
capitalist mode of production). As we see it, the communist movement,
understood not as a particularisation of the totality â neither as a
movement of communists nor of the class â but rather as the totality
itself, is both transhistorical and variant according to the
historically specific configurations of the capitalist class relation.
What determines the communist movement â the communist revolution â to
take the specific form of communisation in the current cycle is the very
dialectic of integration of the circuits of reproduction of capital and
labour-power.[176] It is this which produces the radical negativity of
the proletariat's self-relation vis-Ă -vis capital. In this period, in
throwing off its âradical chainsâ the proletariat does not generalise
its condition to the whole of society, but dissolves its own being
immediately through the abolition of capitalist social relations.
[1] Karl Marx, The 18th Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte, 1852 (MECW 11), pp.
103â106. All references to the works of Marx and Engels are to the
Lawrence & Wishhart Marx-Engels Collected Works (MECW).
[2] âNow, The SIâ (IS no. 9, 1964). Christopher Gray, Leaving the
Twentieth Century: the Incomplete Works of the Situationist
International (Rebel Press 1998).
[3] âWe shall never work, oh waves of fire!â Arthur Rimbaud, Quâest-ce
pour nous, mon cĆur (1872) in: Ćuvres complĂštes (RenĂ©ville & Mouquet,
1954), p. 124.
[4] La RĂ©volution SurrĂ©aliste no. 4 (1925). In practice the surrealistsâ
refusal of work was often restricted to artists, with denunciations of
the influence of wage-labour on creativity and demands for public
subsidies to pay for their living costs. Even the text co-written by
Breton and Trotsky, Towards a Free Revolutionary Art, seems to
distinguish between two revolutionary regimes, one for artists/
intellectuals and one for workers: âif, for a better development of the
forces of material production, the revolution must build a socialist
regime with centralized control, to develop intellectual creation an
anarchist regime of individual liberty should from the first be
established.â Thus one reason the surrealists neglected the
contradiction between the liberation and abolition of labour may have
been that they saw the former as a matter for others.
[5] The situationists were aware of this potential critique and tried to
deflect it. In âPreliminaries on Councils and Councilist Organisationâ
(IS no. 12, 1969) Riesel writes âit is known that we have no inclination
towards workerism of any form whatsoeverâ, but goes on to describe how
workers remain the âcentral forceâ within the councils and the
revolution. Where they get closest to questioning the affirmation of the
proletariat, in the theory of âgeneralized self-managementâ, they are at
their most incoherent â e.g.: âonly the proletariat, by negating itself,
gives clear shape to the project of generalized self-management, because
it bears the project within itself subjectively and objectivelyâ
(Vaneigem, âNotice to the Civilized Concerning Generalised
Self-Managementâ ibid.). If the proletariat bears the project of
self-management âwithin itselfâ then it follows that it must negate this
project in ânegating itselfâ.
[6] The SI would later reveal the extent of their self-delusion by
retrospectively claiming that workers had been âobjectively at several
moments only an hour awayâ from setting up councils during the May
events. âThe Beginning of an Eraâ (IS no. 12, 1969).
[7] Bruno Astarian, Les grĂšves en France en mai-juin 1968, (Echanges et
Mouvement 2003).
[8] e.g.: â[T]he formulae âworkersâ controlâ and âworkersâ managementâ
are lacking in any content. ⊠The âcontentâ [of socialism] wonât be
proletarian autonomy, control, and management of production, but the
disappearance of the proletarian class; of the wage system; of exchange
â even in its last surviving form as the exchange of money for
labour-power; and, finally, the individual enterprise will disappear as
well. There will be nothing to control and manage, and nobody to demand
autonomy from.â Amadeo Bordiga, The Fundamentals of Revolutionary
Communism (1957) (ICP, 1972).
[9] First published in English in Eclipse and Re-Emergence of the
Communist Movement (Black and Red, 1974).
[10] Pierre Nashua (Pierre Guillaume), Perspectives on Councils,
Workersâ Management and the German Left (La Vielle Taupe 1974). Carsten
Juhl, âThe German Revolution and the Spectre of the proletariatâ
(Invariance Series II no. 5, 1974).
[11] Jacques Camatte, âProletariat and Revolutionâ (Invariance Series II
no. 6, 1975).
[12] Camatte, particularly through his influence on Fredy Perlman, would
go on to become a principle inspiration for primitivist thought â see
This World We Must Leave: and Other Essays (Autonomedia, 1995).
[13] Marx & Engels, The German Ideology (MECW 5), p. 49.
[14] The idea of a âperiod of transitionâ, found notably in the
political writings of Marx and Engels, had been shared by almost every
tendency of the workersâ movement. During such a period workers were
supposed to seize control of the political (Leninist) or economic
(syndicalist) apparatuses and run them in their own interests. This
corresponded to a generally held assumption that workers could run their
workplaces better than their bosses, and thus that to take over
production would equally be to develop it (resolving inefficiencies,
irrationalities and injustices). In displacing the communist question
(the practical question of the abolition of wage-labour, exchange, and
the state) to after the transition, the immediate goal, the revolution,
became a matter of overcoming certain âbadâ aspects of capitalism
(inequality, the tyranny of a parasitical class, the âanarchyâ of the
market, the âirrationalityâ of âunproductiveâ pursuitsâŠ) whilst
preserving aspects of capitalist production in a more ârationalâ and
less âunjustâ form (equality of the wage and of the obligation to work,
the entitlement to the full value of oneâs product after deductions for
âsocial costsââŠ).
[15] Gilles DauvĂ©, âOut of the Futureâ in Eclipse and Reemergence of the
Communist Movement (1997) pp. 12â13.
[16] It should be noted that something like a communisation thesis was
arrived at independently by Alfredo Bonanno and other âinsurrectionary
anarchistsâ in the 1980s. Yet they tended to understand it as a lesson
to be applied to every particular struggle. As Debord says of anarchism
in general, such an idealist and normative methodology âabandons the
historical terrainâ in assuming that the adequate forms of practice have
all been found (Debord, Society of the Spectacle (Rebel Press, 1992), §
93 p.49). Like a broken clock, such anarchism is always capable of
telling the right time, but only at a single instant, so that when the
time finally comes it will make little difference that it is finally
right.
[17] Robert Faurisson is a bourgeois historian who attracted attention
to himself in the late 70s by denying the existence of gas chambers at
Auschwitz (though not the Naziâs systematic mass murder of civilians).
For this Faurisson was put on trial. For reasons only really known to
himself, Pierre Guillaume became a prominent defender of Faurisson and
managed to attract several affiliates of La Vielle Taupe and La Guerre
Sociale (notably Dominique Blanc) to his cause. This created an
internecine polemic within the Parisian ultra-left which lasted more
than a decade.
[18] Other groups which trace their descent from this (loosely defined)
tendency in the 1970s: La Banquise, LâInsecuritĂ© Sociale, Le Brise
Glace, Le Voyou, Crise Communiste, Hic Salta, La Materielle, Temps
Critiques.
[19] see below p. 207.
[20] For a more detailed discussion of the differing assumptions at work
in this exchange see the Afterword at the end of this issue.
[21] Marx & Engels, Preface to Russian Edition 1882, Communist Manifesto
(MECW 24), p. 426.
[22] Originally published as Quand Meurent les Insurrections, ADEL,
Paris, 1998. This version was translated by Loren Goldner, revised by
the author, and first published by Antagonism Press, 1999. An earlier
version was published in 1979 as a preface to the selection of articles
from Bilan on Spain 1936-39. Chapters of this preface have been
translated in English as Fascism and Anti-Fascism by several publishers,
for instance Unpopular Books.
[23] For example, Daniel Guérin, Fascism and Big Business (New
International vol. 4 no. 10, 1938)
[24] Angelo Tasca, The Rise of Italian Fascism 1918-1922 (Gordon 1976).
Phillip Bourrinet, The Italian Communist Left 1927-45 (ICC 1992).
[25] See Serge Bricianer, Anton Pannekoek and the Workersâ Councils
(Telos 1978) and Phillip Bourrinet, The German/Dutch Left (NZW 2003).
[26] Vernon Richards, Lessons of the Spanish Revolution 1936-1939
(Freedom Press 1953). Michael Seidman, Workers Against Work during the
Popular Front (UCLA 1993).
[27] Proletariër, published by the councilist group in The Hague, July
27, 1936.
[28] Victor Alba, Spanish Marxism versus Soviet Communism: a History of
the POUM (Transaction Press, 1988).
[29] Homage to Catalonia, April 1938. In 1951, it had sold less than
1,500 copies. It was first published in the US in 1952.
[30] BoletĂn de InformaciĂłn, CNT-ait-FAI, Via Layetana, 32 y 34,
Barcelona, November 11, 1936.
[31] P.I.C., published by the GIC, Amsterdam, October 1936
[32] Marx, Revolutionary Spain, 1854 (MECW 13), p. 422.
[33] Clé, 2nd issue.
[34] P.I.C., German edition, December 1931.
[35] RĂ€te-Korrespondenz, June 1937.
[36] Solidaridad Obrera, November 1936.
[37] Marx, cited by Marie Laffranque, âMarx et lâEspagneâ (Cahiers de
lâISEA, sĂ©rie S. n°15).
[38] Among others: Orwell, and Low & Brea, Red Spanish Notebook, (City
Lights, 1979).
[39] Gerald Brenan, The Spanish Labyrinth (Cambridge, 1990).
[40] Franz Borkenau, The Spanish Cockpit (Faber & Faber, 1937).
[41] Marx & Engels, The German Ideology (MECW 5), p. 52.
[42] Gilles Dauvé, When Insurrections Die, p. 27 (all page references
are to the text in the published copy of Endnotes #1, unless otherwise
noted, a PDF of Endnotes #1 can be found here)
[43]
p. 29
[44]
p. 31
[45]
p. 28
[46]
p. 32
[47]
p. 34
[48]
p. 36. Our emphasis
[49]
p. 36
[50]
p. 36
[51]
p. 38. Translatorâs note (TN): In the French version of the text to
which Théorie Communiste refer, democracy and Social Democracy
were also indispensable for containing/integrating (encadrer)
workers. This phrase is omitted from the English version.
[52]
p. 34
[53]
p. 50
[54]
p. 51
[55]
p. 53
[56]
p. 55
[57] TN: âĂ©lanâ â a play on DauvĂ©âs ârevolutionary Ă©lanâ (pp. 57, 67)
which in other texts by DauvĂ© is translated as ârevolutionary waveâ
ââŠsurgeâ or ââŠmomentumâ. Here it corresponds to one of the ineffable
forces of a defunct physics.
[58]
p. 56
[59]
p. 59
[60]
p. 68
[61] pp. 57, 66, 59 respectively
[62]
p. 67
[63]
p. 67
[64] For an explanation of TCâs concept of âprogrammatismâ see below pp.
155-161 and Afterword p. 215.
[65] Paul Mattick, âOtto RĂŒhle and the German Labour Movementâ, 1935, in
Anti-Bolshevik Communism (Merlin Press, 1978).
[66] Marx, Preface, A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy,
1859 (MECW 29), p. 263.
[67] TN: Ultimatism â the confidence that one is in a position to grasp
the ultimate truth.
[68] Marx, 18th Brumaire (MECW 11), p. 103.
[69] âSous Le Travail: lâActivitĂ©â, La Banquise no. 4, 1986.
[70] Socialisme ou Barbarie no. 1, 1949.
[71] Marx & Engels, The German Ideology (MECW 5), p. 87.
[72] ibid. p. 88
[73] ibid. p. 80
[74] ibid. p. 87
[75] Amadeo Bordiga, âTrajectoire et catastrophe de la forme capitaliste
dans la classique et monolithique construction marxisteâ, RĂ©union de
Piombino, September 1957. (French translation of the article which
appeared in Il Programma Communista in 1957).
[76] cf. Alain Maillard, La Communauté des égaux (éd. Kimé, 1999).
[77] Marx, The German Ideology (MECW 5), p. 53.
[78] Marx, Introduction, A Contribution to the Critique of Hegelâs
Philosophy of Right, 1843 (MECW 3), p. 187.
[79] Marx, The German Ideology (MECW 5), p. 88.
[80] ibid. p. 87.
[81] ibid. p. 80.
[82] Théorie Communiste no. 14, 1997 p. 19.
[83] âNe travaillez jamaisâ: writing on a Paris wall, photographed in
the IS no. 8, 1963. That same issue defined âthe centre of the
revolutionary projectâ as ânothing less than the suppression of work in
the usual sense (as well as the suppression of the proletariat) and of
all justifications of old style workâ.
[84] âAutonomyâ is a misleading term, because it mixes activities and
theories that vastly differed, though they were often present within the
same groups. A large part of the âautonomousâ movement was involved in
grassroots anti-work action. On the other hand, Operaismo was using the
critique of work as a unifying theme on which some organisation
(sometimes genuinely democratic, sometimes similar to a party) could be
built. Operaismo found the common element to all categories of
proletarians in the fact that they were all at work, whether formal or
unofficial, waged or un-waged, permanent or casual. So, even when it did
promote shop-floor rebellion, Operaismoâs purpose was to have everyoneâs
work acknowledged, through the supposedly unifying slogan of the
âpolitical wageâ. Instead of contributing to a dissolution of work into
the whole of human activity, it wanted everyone to be treated as a
worker (women, the jobless, immigrants, students, etc.). The critique of
work was used as a tool to claim the generalisation of paid productive
activity, i.e. of⊠wage-labour. Operaismo was fighting for the
recognition of the centrality of labour, that is for something which is
the opposite of the abolition of work. See for example Zerowork no. 1,
1975. This contradiction was expressed in Potere Operaioâs slogan: âFrom
the fight for the wage to the abolition of wage-labourâ. Lack of space
prevents us from going into details. Cf. the two very informative
collections of articles and documents by Red Notes in the 70âs: Italy
1977â78. Living with an Earthquake, and Working Class Autonomy and the
Crisis. Just to show that the critique of work exceeds the borders of
so-called rich countries: A Ballad Against Work, A Publication for
Collectivities, 1997, Majdoor Library, Autopin Jhuggi, NIT, Faridabad
121001, India.
[85] Krisis, Manifesto Against Work (1999), now translated into French
and English.
[86] Théorie Communiste, BP 17, 84300. Les VignÚres. Also the two books
by Roland Simon published by Senonevero.
[87] Stephen Smith, Red Petrograd: Revolution in the Factories 1917â18
(Cambridge UP, 1983)
[88] ââLabourâ by its very nature is unfree, unhuman, unsocial activity,
determined by private property and creating private property. Hence the
abolition of private property will become a reality only when it is
conceived as the abolition of âlabourâ.â Marx, Notes on Frederich List,
1845 (MECW 4), p. 279.
[89] Though Marx does not speak of âsystems of productionâ, the concept
is clearly in his writings. cf. Marx, Capital vol. 1 (MECW 35), pp.
341â509.
[90] Pivert was the leader of a left opposition in the socialist party
(which later formed the psop in 1938).
[91] Similar experiences took place in other countries and continents.
In 1945, in the north of Vietnam, 30,000 miners elected councils, ran
the mines for a while, controlled the public services, the railways, the
post office, imposed equal pay for all, and taught people to read, until
the Vietminh put its foot down. As a Vietnamese revolutionary recalled
later, they wished to live âwithout bosses, without copsâ. Promoting
work was far from being their prime motive or concern.
[92] Constant Malva, Ma nuit au jour le jour (Labour, 2001). At the same
time, Belgium had to import thousands of Italians because the local
workers were reluctant to go down the mine.
[93] Richard Grégoire & Freddy Perlman, Worker-Student Action Committees
(Black & Red, 1969). Also Francois Martin, âThe Class Struggle and Its
Most Characteristics Aspects in Recent YearsâŠâ in Eclipse and
Re-Emergence⊠(Antagonism Press, 1998).
[94] On how both Stalinism and Nazism glorified work and social
egalitarianism, see Communism, ICG, no. 13, 2002, âOn the Praise of
Workâ.
[95] La Banquise âSous le travail: lâactivitĂ©â (La Banquise no. 4, 1986)
[96] On formal and real domination see: Marx, Results of the Immediate
Process of Production (MECW 34), pp. 355, 471.
[97] Also the beginning of Capital vol. 1, chap.16 (MECW 35), p. 509ff.
[98] At the time, various people had the intuition of the origin of
surplus-value, and some came close to formulating it, for example Flora
Tristan in 1843.
[99] Any good biography of Marx describes his political activity, for
instance Franz Mehringâs and more recently Francis Wheenâs. In his
introduction to Capital volume I, Marx paid tribute to his time when he
compared himself to a scientist who discovers ânaturalâ laws.
Fortunately, and in contradiction to Engelsâs funeral speech on his
friendâs grave, Marx was not the Darwin of the proletariat. Nor did he
think history was foretold. To him, only a teleological mind would have
the course of human history move to a pre-ordained end. There was no
single line of evolution, as shown by the âlateâ Marx. See note 22
below.
[100] Rosa Luxemburg The Mass Strike, the Political Party and the Trade
Unions (1906)
[101] The reader will understand that weâre not preaching indeterminism.
By and large, the 19th century was the epic of a conquering bourgeoisie
with a faith in the iron logic of progress that left no alternative but
final abundance and peace. 1914 opened an era of doubt and
anti-determinism, as is evident in the popular appeal of the
âuncertainty principleâ. There is no need for us to swap the scientific
fashion of one age for another.
[102] Marxâs progressivism is both real and contradictory. He certainly
worked out a linear sequence: primitive community â slavery â feudalism
â capitalism â communism, with the side option of the âAsiatic mode of
productionâ. But his deep, longstanding interest in the Russian mir and
in so-called primitive societies (cf. his notebooks published in 1972)
prove that he thought it possible for some (vast) areas to avoid the
capitalist phase. If Marx had been the herald of industrialisation he is
often depicted as, he would have completed the six volumes heâd planned
for Das Kapital, instead of accumulating notes on Russia, the East, etc.
See âKarl Marx & the Iroquoisâ, Arsenal/Surrealist Subversion, no. 4
(Black Swan Press 1989) and our Re-Visiting the East and Popping in at
Marxâs Grave, available on the Troploin site.
[103] Similarly, in 1900, it was âobviousâ to ask for more technology. A
hundred years later, itâs the opposite that goes without saying: we
âobviouslyâ need lessâŠ
[104] The cover of the 4th issue of La Révolution Surréaliste (1925)
proclaimed: âand war on workâ. See also Bretonâs article âThe Last
Strikeâ in no. 2 (1925), and Aragonâs Cahier Noir (1926).
[105] Results of the Immediate Process of Production (MECW 34), pp.
419â424.⊠See also the General Introduction to the Critique of Political
Economy, 1857 (MECW 28), p. 41.
[106] On the difficulty for capital to fully achieve a new
(post-Fordist) system of production, and the consequences of this
situation for the proletarians, see our 2nd Newsletter in English,
Whither the World?, 2002.
[107] Rigorous Marxists often dismiss notions like âsubjectivityâ,
âmankindâ, âfreedomâ, âaspirationâ⊠because of their association with
idealism and psychology. Strangely enough, the same rigor does not apply
to set of concepts borrowed from economics, philosophy or sociology.
(Primitivists would prefer anthropology.) All those vocabularies (and
the visions of the world they convey) belong to specialised fields of
knowledge, all of them inadequate for human emancipation, and therefore
to be superseded. Until then, we have to compose a âunitaryâ critique
from them and against them.
[108] The Revolution of Everyday Life (1967).
[109] Gilles DauvĂ© & Karl Nesic, âLove of Labour? Love of Labour LostâŠâ
p. 107 (all page references are to DauvĂ© and Nesicâs texts in the
published version of Endnotes #1 unless otherwise noted, the PDF of
Endnotes #1 is available here).
[110]
p. 134
[111] TN: Transcroissance â Trotsky used this term to describe the
âgrowing overâ from the bourgeois to the proletarian revolution. TC
employ the term more generally, using it to signify the belief that
class struggle is not a part of capitalism but a stage in the
progressive liberation of the class; in particular the idea that
struggles over the wage may become revolutionary through being
generalised.
[112]
p. 108
[113]
p. 107
[114]
p. 108
[115] TN: Luttes revendicatives â from ârevindicateâ: to demand. Luttes
revendicatives is a common French term meaning struggles over wages and
conditions, or struggles over immediate demands (as opposed to
insurrectionary or political struggles). We use the archaic
ârevindicativeâ because there is no simple equivalent in English.
[116] The struggle against capital, according to the advocates of
self-organisation, becomes âsuicidalâ, yet this never led them to
question the âpreservation of the tools of labourâ which the proletariat
was supposed to take over. They donât see what this suicide contains for
the proletariat in its contradiction with capital: the evidence of its
own disappearance.
[117] Ă©cart â could also be translated as âswerveâ or âgapâ. See note 5
to the Afterword for an explanation of this concept.
[118]
p. 147
[119]
p. 134
[120] Jean Barrot (Gilles Dauvé) Fascism/Anti-fascism (Black Cat Press
1982). This text is a partial translation of DauvĂ©âs preface to Bilan:
Contre-rĂ©volution en Espagne 1936â1939 (10/18 1979), which was also the
basis for When Insurrections Die.
[121] Marx. The Civil War in France. (MECW 22), p. 504.
[122] Cited by Marx in Draft of The Civil War in France (MECW 22), p.
500.
[123] ibid. p. 501
[124] ibid. p. 505.
[125] ibid. p. 499.
[126] ibid.
[127] ibid. p. 335.
[128] ibid. p. 336.
[129] Jean Barrot / Gilles Dauvé, Notes pour une analyse de la
rĂ©volution russe â 1967 â in Communisme et question russe (TĂȘte de
feuilles, 1972) pp.47-48. Emphasis added.
[130] ibid. p. 51
[131] Oskar Anweiler, The Russian Soviets. Translated from the French:
Les Soviets en Russie, (Gallimard 1972), pp.157-158. Emphasis added.
[132]
E. H. Carr, The Bolschevik Revolution. Translated from the French: La
Révolution bolchévique, vol.II (Ed. de Minuit 1969), p.66.
[133]
p. 113
[134] ibid.
[135] ibid.
[136] âque vaudrait une rĂ©volution oĂč nous serions poussĂ©s quasi malgrĂ©
nous?â Gillles DauvĂ© & Karl Nesic, Il va falloir attendre (Troploin
Newsletter no. 2 2002), p.4. TN: this passage was removed from the
English version of this text â Whither the World?
[137] see note 18 to p. 87 above.
[138]
p. 114
[139]
p. 115
[140] ibid.
[141] Cited in Pier Carlo Masini, Anarchistes et Communistes dans le
mouvement des Conseils Ă Turin, (Nautilus 1983), p. 63.
[142] Errico Malatesta, UmanitĂ Nova, 23 September 1920. Emphasis added.
[143] in Errico Malatesta, Articles politiques (10/18 1979), p.274.
[144]
p. 110
[145] Marx, The Class Struggles in France (MECW 10), p. 55.
[146] ibid. p. 78
[147]
p. 111
[148] ibid.
[149]
p. 120
[150]
p. 119
[151]
p. 121
[152] Dating this conception of the invariance of communism to the
emergence of capitalism is to give a charitable interpretation, because
for Nesic (in Call of the Void) it seemed to go back much further, and
for Dauvé in the Banquise it seemed inherent to the (unfortunately
misguided) communal nature of humanity.
[153]
p. 134
[154] DauvĂ©, âHuman, All Too Human?â p. 100 above.
[155]
p. 147
[156]
p. 145
[157] Marx, 1844 Manuscripts (MECW 3), p. 333.
[158] Marx, The German Ideology (MECW 5), p. 73.
[159] The text to which TC refer, Engelsâ Principles of Communism, an
early draft of the Communist Manifesto, has in its English translation
the âliberation of the proletariatâ rather than âlabourâ (MECW 6), p.
341.
[160]
p. 135
[161]
p. 141
[162] ibid.
[163] ibid.
[164] The term âsocial bondâ or âsocial linkâ (lien social), is employed
by DauvĂ© alongside others such as âadhesionâ âcohesionâ and
âintegrationâ to describe the means by which capital commands the
allegiance of those it exploits. See e.g. Gilles Dauvé & Karl Nesic.
Whither The World (Troploin Newsletter no. 2 2002) p. 13 and 28.
[165]
p. 142
[166]
p. 145
[167] pp. 150-151
[168]
p. 154
[169]
p. 153
[170] DauvĂ©, âHuman, All Too Human?â p. 93 above.
[171] Marx, 18th Brumaire, (MECW 11), p.105.
[172] We will explore these issues further in the next issue of
Endnotes.
[173] By "self-presupposition of capital" TC mean the sense in which
capital establishes itself both as condition and result of its own
process. This is expressed in TC's use (following the French edition of
Capital) of the term double
moulinet, signifying two intersecting cycles.
[174] This fundamental negativity in the proletariat's self-relation
vis-a-vis capital is expressed by TC's use of the term Ă©cart, which may
be translated as "divergence", "swerve" or "gap". For TC this concept
expresses the idea that the proletariat's action as a class is the limit
of this cycle of struggle; for its struggles have no other horizon apart
from its own reproduction as a class, yet it is incapable of affirming
this as such.
[175] For a discussion of this problematic in relation to concrete
struggles, see TC's 'Self-organization is the first act of the
revolution; it then becomes an obstacle which the revolution has to
overcome.' Available on libcom.org.
[176] We will explore these issues further in the next issue of
Endnotes.