đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș tony-gibson-delinquency-then-and-now.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 14:17:22. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Delinquency Then and Now Author: Tony Gibson Language: en Topics: children, crime, The Raven Source: Retrieved on 1 January 1999 from http://www.tao.ca/~freedom/crime.html Notes: The Raven 22 pp. 105â107
To ask what is the cause of juvenile delinquency is to pose the wrong
question. More realistically one might ask why such behaviour is
refrained from so often by so many people.
A boy wanders through a department store and sees many objects â which
he covets and which he could steal without much chance of detection, yet
he refrains. What is the cause of the inhibition of his action? One
cause is certainly a realistic fear of detection, but this cautiousness
alone does not fully account for the widespread practice of honesty.
Everyone will agree that there is also an inhibiting factor, an internal
restraint, which we call the conscience. Many boys will refrain from
gratifying their cupidity even when they are absolutely sure that they
would not get caught. But to label an inhibiting factor âconscienceâ is
not to explain it. Freud approached the phenomenon in terms of the
âsuper egoâ, but one does not have to assume all the complexities of his
system to study the workings of this form of built-in restraint which
governs so many of our actions, sometimes in an arbitrary and ludicrous
fashion.
The mechanism by which people normally refrain from forbidden acts may
be discussed, and it now remains to consider why this mechanism breaks
down with a certain frequency, particularly in boys of about the age of
fourteen. One reason is that the training they have received has not
been very effective. Many working class parents allow a degree of
latitude to their children which is very different from that allowed in
middle class families. The boy will learn that he may get clouted if mum
catches him filching money from her bag, but this is not the sort of
treatment which builds up a conditioned anxiety attached to stealing.
Most studies of methods of upbringing have indicated that what produces
a âstrong moral senseâ in children training by the threat of âwithdrawal
of loveâ. If the child grows up in a condition of affectionate emotional
dependence on his parents withdrawal of parental approval is a very
strong sanction. The child who is merely clouted when he is naughty
learns to avoid getting caught, or indeed to weigh up the pain of a
thick ear against the unlawful pleasure. The child who is made to feel
moral disapproval from adults who normally treat him tenderly is less
able to shrug of the penalty for wrongdoing; in order to put himself
back in a state of grace he has to strive actively to be a good boy, and
hence to introject the moral standards of his parents.
What has been described above is of course the extremes of two different
types af child management. Generally the regime is mixed If however, the
parental figures are unloving, indifferent or absent they cannot train
the child by âwithdrawal of loveâ, and the child is liable to grow up
with very little conscience. Again, if the parents are particularly
inconsistent in their behaviour, sometimes blaming and punishing the
child for wrongdoing and sometimes condoning such behaviour, the
training process will not work, and the child will not develop any
consistent moral standards.
Much of the above is open to misinterpretation by the careless reader.
It may be assumed erroneously that the present writer is advancing a
programme of strict moral training for the young by the effective
sanction of âwithdrawal of loveâ. This has certainly not been advocated
here. Again it might be assumed, equally erroneously, that the present
writer argues that the only reason we refrain from robbery and violence
is that we get a nasty kick from the rising tide of anxiety every time
we contemplate such actions. Such a model is altogether too crude. What
is really suggested here is that ordinary moral behaviour becomes
completely habitual with most people.
In a society based upon mutual aid, there would be little problem of
morality. But our society is one based upon aggressive competition and
unfairness The status quo is maintained by a combination of sheer
intimidation and ludicrously cock-eyed moral training. One of the most
sacred institutions in our society is property. If a boy were to steal
my car, I would be annoyed and call upon the police to recover it for
me. Yet I would feel no satisfaction if they caught him and placed him
in the lock-up. Nor do I believe that his act of theft is âimmoralâ As I
drive through the wet, cold streets in my warm and comfortable empty
car, and see the wretched mums of such boys queuing at bus stops, I
might wonder if my position is not immoral â far more immoral than that
of the underprivileged boys who occasionally steal a car. I am
comparatively clever and have been well educated therefore I am well
paid for interesting and varied work, whereas the are comparatively
stupid and have been appallingly miseducated and so they are poorly paid
for dull routine work. That is why I ride in the car while they queue in
the wet. This is a social fact, and makes nonsense of the moralistsâ
attempts to confuse crime with immorality.
Society gets the delinquency rate is deserves, yet this simple fact is
not recognised by many good people whose profession it is to study
criminology. The do-gooders vaguely hope that they will somehow reduce
the delinquency rate by preventive methods of a social nature or even by
âtherapyâ applied to those under lock and key â and always without
altering the essential structure of our society. In 1962 the
criminological division of the Council of Europe circulated countries
asking them what programmes of crime prvention has been inaugurated in
them. The resulting document reveals the utter poverty of imagination of
the majority of those who have contributed to it. In general the
response could be summed up in the honest reply nothingâ, but all too
often a good deal of humbug is resorted to as a cover for the fact that
no-one had any clear and practicable idea of how delinquancy could be
prevented.
Regarding âtherapyâ applied to prisoners in order to reform their
âcriminal tendenciesâ, most of it is a bad joke which reveals the
stupidity of the psychologists who confuse criminality with mental
illness. Now although certain men land up in prison because of
psychological disorders, e.g. the exposeur, the compulsive incendiary
any psychiatric sense. It is indeed a huge impertinence for any
do-gooders stand the hardened screws; the last thing they want to do is
to do the prisoners good â they want to do them evil, to humiliate,
crush and punish them. There is something terribly twisted in the
character of any man who freely elects to spend his working life in
prison when any other occupation, even the humblest, is open to him. Yet
I have read of a self-publicist called Hauser who claims to be showing
prison screws how to become âtherapistsâ: I do not know if the Nazi
movement produced any quacks who claimed to show SS men how to
ameliorate the jewishness of Jews, rather than give them standard
treatment.