đŸ’Ÿ Archived View for library.inu.red â€ș file â€ș tony-gibson-delinquency-then-and-now.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 14:17:22. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

âžĄïž Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Delinquency Then and Now
Author: Tony Gibson
Language: en
Topics: children, crime, The Raven
Source: Retrieved on 1 January 1999 from http://www.tao.ca/~freedom/crime.html
Notes: The Raven 22 pp. 105–107

Tony Gibson

Delinquency Then and Now

To ask what is the cause of juvenile delinquency is to pose the wrong

question. More realistically one might ask why such behaviour is

refrained from so often by so many people.

A boy wanders through a department store and sees many objects — which

he covets and which he could steal without much chance of detection, yet

he refrains. What is the cause of the inhibition of his action? One

cause is certainly a realistic fear of detection, but this cautiousness

alone does not fully account for the widespread practice of honesty.

Everyone will agree that there is also an inhibiting factor, an internal

restraint, which we call the conscience. Many boys will refrain from

gratifying their cupidity even when they are absolutely sure that they

would not get caught. But to label an inhibiting factor ‘conscience’ is

not to explain it. Freud approached the phenomenon in terms of the

‘super ego’, but one does not have to assume all the complexities of his

system to study the workings of this form of built-in restraint which

governs so many of our actions, sometimes in an arbitrary and ludicrous

fashion.

The mechanism by which people normally refrain from forbidden acts may

be discussed, and it now remains to consider why this mechanism breaks

down with a certain frequency, particularly in boys of about the age of

fourteen. One reason is that the training they have received has not

been very effective. Many working class parents allow a degree of

latitude to their children which is very different from that allowed in

middle class families. The boy will learn that he may get clouted if mum

catches him filching money from her bag, but this is not the sort of

treatment which builds up a conditioned anxiety attached to stealing.

Most studies of methods of upbringing have indicated that what produces

a ‘strong moral sense’ in children training by the threat of ‘withdrawal

of love’. If the child grows up in a condition of affectionate emotional

dependence on his parents withdrawal of parental approval is a very

strong sanction. The child who is merely clouted when he is naughty

learns to avoid getting caught, or indeed to weigh up the pain of a

thick ear against the unlawful pleasure. The child who is made to feel

moral disapproval from adults who normally treat him tenderly is less

able to shrug of the penalty for wrongdoing; in order to put himself

back in a state of grace he has to strive actively to be a good boy, and

hence to introject the moral standards of his parents.

What has been described above is of course the extremes of two different

types af child management. Generally the regime is mixed If however, the

parental figures are unloving, indifferent or absent they cannot train

the child by ‘withdrawal of love’, and the child is liable to grow up

with very little conscience. Again, if the parents are particularly

inconsistent in their behaviour, sometimes blaming and punishing the

child for wrongdoing and sometimes condoning such behaviour, the

training process will not work, and the child will not develop any

consistent moral standards.

Much of the above is open to misinterpretation by the careless reader.

It may be assumed erroneously that the present writer is advancing a

programme of strict moral training for the young by the effective

sanction of ‘withdrawal of love’. This has certainly not been advocated

here. Again it might be assumed, equally erroneously, that the present

writer argues that the only reason we refrain from robbery and violence

is that we get a nasty kick from the rising tide of anxiety every time

we contemplate such actions. Such a model is altogether too crude. What

is really suggested here is that ordinary moral behaviour becomes

completely habitual with most people.

In a society based upon mutual aid, there would be little problem of

morality. But our society is one based upon aggressive competition and

unfairness The status quo is maintained by a combination of sheer

intimidation and ludicrously cock-eyed moral training. One of the most

sacred institutions in our society is property. If a boy were to steal

my car, I would be annoyed and call upon the police to recover it for

me. Yet I would feel no satisfaction if they caught him and placed him

in the lock-up. Nor do I believe that his act of theft is ‘immoral’ As I

drive through the wet, cold streets in my warm and comfortable empty

car, and see the wretched mums of such boys queuing at bus stops, I

might wonder if my position is not immoral — far more immoral than that

of the underprivileged boys who occasionally steal a car. I am

comparatively clever and have been well educated therefore I am well

paid for interesting and varied work, whereas the are comparatively

stupid and have been appallingly miseducated and so they are poorly paid

for dull routine work. That is why I ride in the car while they queue in

the wet. This is a social fact, and makes nonsense of the moralists’

attempts to confuse crime with immorality.

Society gets the delinquency rate is deserves, yet this simple fact is

not recognised by many good people whose profession it is to study

criminology. The do-gooders vaguely hope that they will somehow reduce

the delinquency rate by preventive methods of a social nature or even by

‘therapy’ applied to those under lock and key — and always without

altering the essential structure of our society. In 1962 the

criminological division of the Council of Europe circulated countries

asking them what programmes of crime prvention has been inaugurated in

them. The resulting document reveals the utter poverty of imagination of

the majority of those who have contributed to it. In general the

response could be summed up in the honest reply nothing’, but all too

often a good deal of humbug is resorted to as a cover for the fact that

no-one had any clear and practicable idea of how delinquancy could be

prevented.

Regarding ‘therapy’ applied to prisoners in order to reform their

‘criminal tendencies’, most of it is a bad joke which reveals the

stupidity of the psychologists who confuse criminality with mental

illness. Now although certain men land up in prison because of

psychological disorders, e.g. the exposeur, the compulsive incendiary

any psychiatric sense. It is indeed a huge impertinence for any

do-gooders stand the hardened screws; the last thing they want to do is

to do the prisoners good — they want to do them evil, to humiliate,

crush and punish them. There is something terribly twisted in the

character of any man who freely elects to spend his working life in

prison when any other occupation, even the humblest, is open to him. Yet

I have read of a self-publicist called Hauser who claims to be showing

prison screws how to become ‘therapists’: I do not know if the Nazi

movement produced any quacks who claimed to show SS men how to

ameliorate the jewishness of Jews, rather than give them standard

treatment.