💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › wayne-price-the-alternative-to-capitalism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 14:50:07. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: The Alternative to Capitalism?
Author: Wayne Price
Date: November 2013
Language: en
Topics: review, marxism, capital, the state
Source: Retrieved on July 2, 2014 from http://anarkismo.net/article/26446?search_text=wayne%20price&print_page=true

Wayne Price

The Alternative to Capitalism?

In my last book, I provided an anarchist introduction to Marx’s economic

thought, from the viewpoint of a “Marxist-informed anarchist.” Peter

Hudis’ volume (2013) is written as if to disprove part of the dual

assertion I make in my book’s opening. I had claimed: “When it comes to

an analysis of capitalist economy, Marx’s economic theories are superior

to others, including what there is of anarchist economic

thinking….However, when it comes to presenting a post-capitalist vision,

a socialist goal, then anarchism…is superior to Marxism” (price, 2013;

p. 2). Instead of my second assertion, Hudis declares the virtues of

Marx’s vision of a post-capitalist, post-revolutionary, economy. This is

even though, in practice, movements calling themselves “Marxist” have

created totalitarian, state-capitalist, mass murdering regimes, before

eventually collapsing back into traditional capitalism—as Hudis

acknowledges.

Hudis should be in an excellent position to carry out an analysis of

Marxism’s humanistic and working class goals. He comes out of the

“Marxist-Humanist” theoretical school established by Raya Dunayevskaya

(which itself evolved out of the “Johnson-Forrest Tendency”). He is

general editor of “The Complete Works of Rosa Luxemburg.” This history

situates him in the libertarian-democratic trend within Marxism, a

minority trend which rejects social democracy and Stalinism (and

Trotskyism).

The first problem Hudis, or anyone else focusing on Marx’s vision, must

face is that Marx did not emphasize his vision or his goals. In a

multi-volume analysis of Marx’s politics, Hal Draper (who shares with

Hudis a view of Marx as radically democratic) writes:

“…From early on, Marx and Engels habitually stated their political aim

not in terms of a desired change in social system (socialism) but in

terms of a change in class power (proletarian rule)….Marx and Engels

took as their governing aims not the aspirations for a certain type of

future society, but the position of a social class as an embodiment of

humanity’s interests…. It is not the form of organization of future

society that is at the center of his theory of revolution” (Draper,

1978; pp. 24 & 27).

Therefore we should not be surprised that Marx’s comments on a future

society are few and far between, scattered among his writings, which

have to be scoured to find the references. As anarchists see it, there

is a problem with focusing on the workers and other oppressed people

taking power, unless we also hold a clear vision of what they will do

with that power. Will they establish a radically democratized,

decentralized federation of self-governing communities and industries,

becoming the self-organization of the producers? Or will they set up a

centralized, bureaucratic, socially-alienated military machine to rule

over the rest of the population? That is, will they create a new state

(even a “workers’ state,” whatever that means)? Anarchists do not accept

the counterposition of workers’ revolution to the need for programmatic

vision. Lacking such a libertarian and humanistic vision, it is not

surprising that most revolutionary Marxists have accepted Stalinist

tyrannies, once they appear, as “really existing socialism.”

Hegelianism?

Hudis’ solution to this problem is to make his argument fairly abstract,

with a hefty dose of Hegelian terminology. He states his agreement with

Dunayevskaya “that the realities of our era make it imperative to return

directly to Hegel’s Absolutes in working out a conception of the

alternative to capitalism” (p. 33). He criticizes Draper for his “scant

attention to [Marx’s] Hegelian inheritance…” (p. 59).

He asserts that Marx wanted a post-capitalist society to be free of

alienation, commodity fetishism, and the law of value. But these

assertions (undoubtedly true) require Hudis to make explanations about

what alienation, fetishism, and the law of value actually

are—explanations which are not always of the clearest. It does not occur

to him that, while a knowledge of Hegel’s work may conceivably help

Hudis himself to understand Marx, it does not necessarily lead him to be

better able to explain Marx to others.

Hudis declares, “There is little doubt that Marx’s critique of

capitalism centers upon a critique of value-production. What is less

clear, however, is exactly what is needed, in Marx’s view, to surmount

value-production. My aim is to discover the elements, however implicit,

that he thought are needed to overcome value-production” (p. 8). So

Hudis admits that Marx’s vision is “implicit” at best and “less clear”

(or unclear or even murky) about what social changes are necessary “to

overcome value-production.” (“Value-production” refers to an economy

dominated by the market, with the buying and selling of commodities,

including the “commodity labor power,” the ability of workers to work

for wages—the ultimate controlling factor of commodity exchange being

the amount of socially necessary labor it takes to produce each

commodity.)

Therefore most of Hudis’ book is not directly about alternatives to

capitalism but about how capitalism works in Marx’s theory. Some of this

I found interesting, such as the comparisons among schools of Marxist

theory, particularly the “objectivists” versus the “subjectivists” or

“autonomists.” He also denies the “socialism” of the “Bolivarian”

program of the late Hugo Chavez and claims that state planning as such

was not a “Marxist” goal. But this does not really advance us very far

into the nature of a possible post-capitalist society.

Marxism and Anarchism

Marxism and anarchism both developed out of the socialist and working

class movements of the early nineteenth century. Yet Hudis rately

contrasts the two trends (or other libertarian socialist conceptions,

such as guild socialism or Parecon). The closest he gets is a discussion

about “time-chits or labor vouchers.” Marx expected such labor credits

to be used as to pay workers during the “lower phase” of communism.

Hudis argues that this is very different from the proposals for labor

credit payments made by Proudhon (the first person to call himself an

anarchist). I do not find his arguments persuasive (like most Marxists

who write about Proudhon, he seems to have studied what Marx wrote about

Proudhon, but not what Proudhon actual wrote). But in any case, he does

not go on to contrast Marx’s “higher phase of communism” with the

anarchist-communist program of Kropotkin and others. Yet anarchists have

written much more clearly and specifically on the methods by which a

stateless, moneyless, economy might be organized.

Oddly, Hudis does not mention Marx’s view of a post-capitalist society

as going beyond the capitalist division of labor, a view shared with

anarchist-communists. In particular, Marx foresaw the end of the split

between mental and manual labor, between order-giving and order-taking

in the process of production. Marx and Engels expected this to result in

a classless society, with new relations between men and women. They saw

it as ending the division between “town” and “country,” which they felt

was a cause of pollution and ecological crises.

Hudis claims that Marx advocated “a communal network of associations in

which value-production has been superseded…” (p. 110). “Marx now

conceives of an association of freely-associated cooperatives as the

most effective form for making a transition to a new society” (p. 186).

Did Marx hold such views, which are fully in agreement with socialist

anarchists? There are numerous passages in which he briefly makes such

remarks. This was particularly true when he discussed workers’

cooperatives or the extreme democracy of the 1871 Paris Commune. But

there are also numerous passages in which he appears to imply the value

of centralized planning by a state. As Hudis recognizes, the heritage is

often unclear.

State Capitalism

In Marx and Engels’ post-capitalist vision, their biggest failing was

their failure to consider the possibility that the stock-owning

bourgeoisie might be replaced by a class other than the working class.

This is unmentioned by Hudis. From Bakunin on, anarchists have warned

that the Marxist program might result in a new, collectivized, ruling

class of intellectuals, bureaucrats, and the “aristocracy of labor.”

Marx denied it.

Yet there were undeveloped aspects of his theory which might have led to

such a prediction. For example, in the studies of so-called “Oriental

Despotism” in Asia, Africa, and the Americas, Marx and Engels described

societies with collectivized economies and bureaucratic ruling classes.

(These were not capitalist, because they were generally stagnant and

non-dynamic.) And they analyzed the tendency of modern capitalism to

become ever more centralized, bureaucratized, and statified. (These

would be managed by “salaried employees,” with stock-owning bourgeoisie

hanging on as parasites.) But the founding Marxists did not foresee the

danger that a centralized, planned, economy might evolve into a fully

state capitalist regime with a totally collectivized ruling class—at

least for an extended period.

Peter Hudis concludes his book, “…The realities of our time…call on us

to develop a much more explicit and articulate alternative to capitalism

than appeared necessary in Marx’s time, and even to Marx himself” (p.

215). I fully agree on the need for a more “explicit and articulate

alternative to capitalism” than was developed by Marx—without abandoning

the insights of Marx. But there were others at the time who also began

to work out a participatory, cooperative, humanistic, and freedom-loving

“alternative to capitalism,” namely the revolutionary anarchists. To

ignore this is to abandon a great tradition.

References

Draper, Hal (1978). Karl Marx’s Theory of Revolution; Vol. II: The

Politics of Social Classes. NY: Monthly Review Press.

Hudis, Peter (2013). Marx’s Concept of the Alternative to Capitalism.

Chicago IL: Haymarket Books.

price, wayne (2013). The Value of Radical Theory: An Anarchist

Introduction to Marx’s Critique of Political Economy. Oakland CA: AK

Press.