đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș david-graeber-beyond-power-knowledge.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 09:04:36. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Beyond Power/Knowledge Author: David Graeber Date: 25th May 2006 Language: en Topics: power, anthropology, social anarchism, bureaucracy Source: Retrieved on 4th September 2020 from https://libcom.org/library/beyond-powerknowledge-exploration-power-ignorance-stupidity
Let me begin with a brief story about bureaucracy.
Over the last year my mother had a series of strokes. It soon became
obvious that she would eventually be incapable of living at home without
assistance; since her insurance would not cover home care, a series of
social workers advised us to put in for Medicaid. To qualify for
Medicaid however, oneâs total worth can only amount to six thousand
dollars. We arranged to transfer her savingsâthis was, I suppose,
technically a scam, though itâs a peculiar sort of scam since the
government employs thousands of social workers whose main work seems to
be telling citizens how to do itâbut shortly thereafter, she had
another, very serious stroke, and found herself in a nursing home
undergoing long-term rehabilitation. When she emerged from there she
would definitely need home care, but there was a problem: her social
security check was being deposited directly, she was barely able to sign
her name, so unless I acquired power of attorney over her account and
was thus able to pay her monthly rent bills for her, the money would
immediately build up and disqualify her, even after I filled out the
enormous raft of Medicaid documents I needed to file to qualify her for
pending status.
I went to her bank, picked up the requisite forms, and brought them to
the nursing home. The documents needed to be notarized. The nurse on the
floor informed me there was an in-house notary, but I needed to make an
appointment; she picked up the phone and put me through to a disembodied
voice, who then transferred me to the notary. The notary proceeded to
inform me I first had to get authorization from the head of social work,
and hung up. So I acquired his name and room number and duly took the
elevator downstairs, appeared at his officeâonly to discover he was, in
fact, the disembodied voice on the phone. The head of social work picked
up the phone, said âMarjorie, that was me, youâre driving this man crazy
with this nonsense and youâre driving me crazy tooâ, and proceeded to
secure me an appointment for early the next week.
The next week the notary duly appeared, accompanied me upstairs, made
sure Iâd filled out my side of the form (as had been repeatedly
emphasized to me), and then, in my motherâs presence, proceeded to fill
out her own. I was a little puzzled that she didnât ask my mother to
sign anything, only me, but I figured she must know what she was doing.
The next day I took it to the bank, where the woman at the desk took one
look, asked why my mother hadnât signed it, and showed it to her
manager, who told me to take it back and do it right. Apparently the
notary had no idea what she was doing. So I got new forms, filled out my
side of each, and made a new appointment. On the appointed day the
notary duly appeared, and after some awkward remarks about the
difficulties caused by each bank having its own, completely different
power of attorney form, we proceeded upstairs. I signed, my mother
signedâwith some difficultyâand the next day I returned to the bank.
Another woman at a different desk examined the forms and asked why I had
signed the line where it said to write my name and printed my name on
the line where it said to sign.
âI did? Well, I just did exactly what the notary told me to do.â
âBut it says clearly âsignatureâ here.â
âOh, yes, it does, doesnât it? I guess she told me wrong. Again. WellâŠ
all the information is still there, isnât it? Itâs just those two bits
that are reversed. So is it really a problem? Itâs kind of pressing and
Iâd really rather not have to wait to make another appointment.â
âWell, normally we donât even accept these forms without all the
signatories being here in person.â
âMy mother had a stroke. Sheâs bedridden. Thatâs why I need power of
attorney in the first place.â
She said sheâd check with the manager, and after ten minutes returned,
saying the bank could not accept the forms in their present state, and
in addition, even if they were filled out correctly, I would still need
a letter from my motherâs doctor certifying that she was mentally
competent to sign such a document. I pointed out that no one had
mentioned any such letter previously.
âWhat?â asked the manager, who was listening in. âWho gave you those
forms and didnât tell you about the letter?â
Since the apparent culprit was actually one of the nicer bank employees,
I changed the subject, noting that in the bankbook it was printed, quite
clearly, âin trust for David Graeberâ. He of course replied that would
only matter if she was dead.
As it happened, the whole problem soon became academic: my mother did
indeed die a few weeks later.
At the time, I found this experience extremely disconcerting. Having led
an existence comparatively insulated from this sort of thing, I found
myself continually asking my friends: is this what ordinary life, for
most people, is really like? Most were inclined to suspect it was.
Obviously, the notary was unusually incompetent. Still, I had to spend
over a month not long after dealing with the consequences of some
anonymous clerk in the New York Department of Motor Vehicles who decided
my given name was
âDaidâ, not to mention the Verizon clerk who spelled my surname
âGrueberâ.
Bureaucracies public and private appearâfor whatever historical
reasonsâto be organized in such a way as to guarantee that a significant
proportion of actors will not be able to perform their tasks as
expected. It also exemplifies what I have come to think of the defining
feature of a utopian form of practice, in that, on discovering this,
those maintaining the system conclude that the problem is not with the
system itself but with the inadequacy of the human beings involved.
As an intellectual, probably the most disturbing thing was how dealing
with these forms somehow rendered me stupid too. How could I not have
noticed that I was printing my name on the line that said âsignatureâ?
This despite the fact that I had been investing a great deal of mental
and emotional energy in the whole affair. The problem, I think, was that
most of this energy was going into a continual attempt to try to
understand and influence whoever, at any moment, seemed to have some
kind of bureaucratic power over meâwhen what was required was the
correct interpretation of one or two Latin words, and correct
performance of purely mechanical functions. Spending so much of my time
worrying about how not to seem like I was rubbing the notaryâs face in
her incompetence, or imagining what might make me seem sympathetic to
various bank officials, made me less inclined to notice when they told
me to do something foolish. It was an obviously misplaced strategy,
since insofar as anyone had the power to bend the rules they were
usually not the people I was talking to; moreover, if I did encounter
them, I was constantly being reminded that if I did complain, even about
a purely structural absurdity, the only possible result would be to get
some junior functionary in trouble.
As an anthropologist, probably the most curious thing for me was how
little trace any of this tends to leave in the ethnographic literature.
After all, we anthropologists have made something of a specialty out of
dealing with the ritual surrounding birth, marriage, death, and similar
rites of passage. We are particularly concerned with ritual gestures
that are socially efficacious: where the mere act of saying or doing
something makes it socially true. Yet in most existing societies at this
point, it is precisely paperwork, not other forms of ritual, that is
socially efficacious. My mother, for example, wished to be cremated
without ceremony; my main memory of the funeral home though was of the
plump, good-natured clerk who walked me through a 14-page document he
had to file in order to obtain a death certificate, written in ballpoint
on carbon paper so it came out in triplicate. âHow many hours a day do
you spend filling out forms like that?â I asked. He sighed. âItâs all I
do,â holding up a hand bandaged from some kind of incipient carpal
tunnel syndrome. Without those forms, my mother would not be,
legallyâsociallyâdead.
Why, then, are there not vast ethnographic tomes about American or
British rites of passage, with long chapters about forms and paperwork?
The obvious answer is that paperwork is boring. There really arenât many
interesting things one can say about it.
Anthropologists are drawn to areas of density. The interpretative tools
we have at our disposal are best suited to unpack complex webs of
meaning or signification: intricate ritual symbolism, social dramas,
poetic forms, kinship networks⊠What all these have in common is that
they tend to be both infinitely rich, and at the same time, open-ended;
if oneâs intention was to exhaust every meaning, motives, or association
packed in to a single Ncwala ritual, Balinese cockfight, witchcraft
accusation, or family saga, one could potentially go on forever: all the
more of so if one also wished to trace its relations with other elements
in the larger social or symbolic fields they invariably open up. Forms
in contrast are designed to be maximally simple and self-contained.
There just isnât much there to interpret. Literature, of course, has the
same problem with bureaucracy. At best it can become the object of some
kind of bleak Kafkaesque comedy. But even here there, itâs probably
significant that Kafka has remained pretty much the only author to have
made great literature of any sort out of bureaucracy: thereâs so little
there that once youâve done it, thereâs nothing left for anyone to add.
Still, social theory abhors a vacuum. Nowhere is this more obvious than
in the literature on bureaucracy itself. Insofar as ethnographies of
bureaucracy existâthe paradigm here is Herzfeldâs âThe Social Production
of Indifferenceâ (1992)âthe
âbureaucracy as idiocyâ perspective tends to be represented at best as
the naĂŻve folk model whose existence any sophisticated, cultural
understanding of the phenomenon must start by being able to explain.
This is not to say such works necessarily deny that immersion in
bureaucratic codes and regulations does, in fact, regularly cause people
to act in ways that in any other context would be considered idiotic.
Just about anyone is aware from personal experiences that they do. Yet
for purposes of cultural analysis, truth is rarely considered an
adequate explanation. At best one can expect a âyes, butâŠââwith the
assumption that the âbutâ introduces everything thatâs really important.
When we pass to the more rarified domains of theory, even that âyes,
butâ usually disappears. Consider the hegemonic role, in US social
theory, of Max Weber in the â50s and â60s, and of Michel Foucault ever
since. Their popularity, no doubt, had much to do with the ease with
which each could be adopted as a kind of anti-Marx, their theories put
forth (usually in crudely simplified form) to argue that power is not
simply or primarily a matter of the control of production but rather a
pervasive, multifaceted, and unavoidable feature of any social life. I
also think itâs no coincidence that these sometimes appear to be the
only two intelligent people in human history who honestly believed that
bureaucracies work. Weber saw bureaucratic forms of organization as the
very embodiment of rationality, so obviously superior to any alternative
that they threatened to lock humanity in a joyless âiron cageâ, bereft
of spirit and charisma. Foucault was far more subversive, but in a way
that made bureaucratic power more effective, not less.
Bodies, subjects, truth itself, all become the products of
administrative discourses; through concepts like governmentality and
biopower, state bureaucracies end up shaping the terms of human
existence in ways far more intimate than anything Weber would have
possibly imagined.
Itâs hard to avoid the conclusion that, in either case, their popularity
owed much to the fact that the American university system during this
period had itself become increasingly an institution dedicated to
producing functionaries for an imperial administrative apparatus on a
global scale. The current ascendancy of Foucault seems trace back to
â60s radicalsâ rejection of Talcott Parsonâs version of Weber for
precisely this reason; the ultimate result however was a kind of
division of labor, with the optimistic side of Weber reinvented in even
more simplified form for the actual training of bureaucrats under the
name of ârational choice theoryâ, while of the pessimistic side was
relegated to the Foucauldians. Foucaultâs ascendancy in turn was
precisely within those fields of academic endeavor that both became the
haven for former radicals, but that were themselves most completely
divorced from any access to political power, or increasingly, even to
real social movementsâwhich gave Foucaultâs emphasis on the
âpower/knowledgeâ nexus, the assertion that forms of knowledge are
always also forms of social power, indeed, the most important forms of
social power, a particular appeal.
No doubt any such historical argument is a bit caricaturish and unfair;
but I think there is a profound truth here. It is not just that we are
drawn to areas of density, where our skills at interpretation are best
deployed. We also have an increasing tendency to identify whatâs
interesting and whatâs important, to assume places of density are also
places of power. The power of bureaucracy shows just how much this is
often not the case.
This essay is not, however, primarily about bureaucracyâor even about
the reasons for its neglect in anthropology and related disciplines. It
is really about violence.
What I would like to argue is that situations created by
violenceâparticularly structural violence, by which I mean forms of
pervasive social inequality that are ultimately backed up by the threat
of physical harmâinvariably tend to create the kinds of willful
blindness we normally associate with bureaucratic procedures. To put it
crudely: it is not so much that bureaucratic procedures are inherently
stupid, or even that they tend to produce behavior that they themselves
define as stupid, but rather, that are invariably ways of managing
social situations that are already stupid because they are founded on
structural violence. I think this approach allows potential insights
into matters that are, in fact, both interesting and important: for
instance, the actual relationship between those forms of simplification
typical of social theory, and those typical of administrative
procedures.
We are not used to thinking of nursing homes or banks or even HMOs as
violent institutionsâexcept perhaps in the most abstract and
metaphorical sense. But the violence Iâm referring to here is not
epistemic. Itâs quite concrete. All of these are institutions involved
in the allocation of resources within a system of property rights
regulated and guaranteed by governments in a system that ultimately
rests on the threat of force. âForceâ in turn is just a euphemistic way
to refer to violence.
All of this is obvious enough. Whatâs of ethnographic interest, perhaps,
is how rarely citizens in industrial democracies actually think about
this fact, or how instinctively we try to discount its importance. This
is what makes it possible, for example, for graduate students to be able
to spend days in the stacks of university libraries poring over
theoretical tracts about the declining importance of coercion as a
factor in modern life, without ever reflecting on that fact that, had
they insisted on their right to enter the stacks without showing a
properly stamped and validated ID, armed men would have been summoned to
physically remove them. Itâs almost as the more we allow aspects of our
everyday existence to fall under the purview of bureaucratic
regulations, the more everyone concerned colludes to downplay the fact
(perfectly obvious to those actually running the system) that all of it
ultimately depends on the threat of violence.
In many of the rural communities that anthropologists are most familiar
with, where modern administrative techniques are explicitly seen as
alien impositions, many of these connections are much easier to see. In
the part of rural Madagascar where I did my fieldwork, for example, that
governments operate primarily by inspiring fear was seen as obvious. At
the same time, in the absence of any significant government interference
in the minutiae of daily life (via building codes, open container laws,
the mandatory insuring of vehicles and so on), it became all the more
apparent that the main business of government bureaucracy was the
registration of taxable property. One curious result was that it was
precisely the sort of information that was available from the Malagasy
archives for the 19^(th) and early 20^(th) centuries for the community I
was studyingâprecise figures about the size of each family and its
holdings in land and cattle (and in the earlier period, slaves)âthat I
was least able to attain for the time I was there, simply because that
was precisely what most people assumed an outsider coming from the
capital would be likely to be asking about, and therefore, which they
were least inclined to tell them.
Whatâs more, one result of the colonial experience was that what might
be called relations of commandâbasically, any ongoing relationship in
which one adult renders another an extension of his or her willâhad
become identified with slavery, and slavery, with the essential nature
of the state. In the community I studied, such associations were most
likely to come to the fore when people were talking about the great
slave-holding families of the 19^(th) century whose children went on to
become the core of the colonial-era administration, largely (it was
always remarked) by dint of their devotion to education and skill with
paperwork. In other contexts, relations of command, particularly in
bureaucratic contexts, were linguistically coded: they were firmly
identified with French; Malagasy, in contrast, was seen as the language
appropriate to deliberation, explanation, and consensus decision-making.
Minor functionaries, when they wished to impose arbitrary dictates,
would almost invariably switch to French. I particularly remember one
occasion when an official who had had many conversations with me in
Malagasy, and had no idea I even understood French, was flustered one
day to discover me dropping by at exactly the moment everyone had
decided to go home early. âThe office is closed,â he announced, in
French, âif you have any business you must return tomorrow at 8AM.â When
I pretended confusion and claimed, in Malagasy, not to understand
French, he proved utterly incapable of repeating the sentence in the
vernacular, but just kept repeating the French over and over. Others
later confirmed what I suspected: that if he had switched to Malagasy,
he would at the very least have had to explain why the office had closed
at such an unusual time. French is actually referred to in Malagasy as
âthe language of commandâ; it was characteristic of contexts where
explanations, deliberation, ultimately, consent, was not really
required, since they were ultimately premised on the threat of violence.
In Madagascar, bureaucratic power was somewhat redeemed in most peopleâs
minds by its tie to education. Comparative analysis suggests there is a
direct relation however between the level of violence employed in a
bureaucratic system, and the level of absurdity it is seen to produce.
Keith Breckenridge, for example, has documented at some length the
regimes of âpower without knowledgeâ typical of colonial South Africa
(2003), where coercion and paperwork largely substituted for the need
for understanding African subjects. The actual installation of apartheid
beginning in the 1950s, for example, was heralded by a new pass system
that was designed to simplify earlier rules that obliged African workers
to carry extensive documentation of labor contracts, substituting a
single identity booklet, marked with their ânames, locale, fingerprints,
tax status, and their officially prescribed ârightsâ to live and work in
the towns and citiesâ (2005:84), and nothing else. Government
functionaries appreciated it for streamlining administration, police for
relieving them of the responsibility of having to actually talk to
African workers; the latter universally referred to as the âdompasâ, or
âstupid passâ, for precisely that reason.
There are traces of the link between coercion and absurdity even in the
way we talk about bureaucracy in English: note for example, how most of
the colloquial terms that specifically refer to bureaucratic
foolishness, SNAFU, Catch-22 and the likeâderive from military slang.
More generally, political scientists have long observed a ânegative
correlationâ, as David Apter put it (1965, 1971) between coercion and
information: that is, while relatively democratic regimes tend to be
awash in too much information, the more authoritarian and repressive a
regime, the less reason people have to tell it anythingâwhich is why
such regimes are forced to rely so heavily on spies, intelligence
agencies, and secret police.
Violenceâs capacity to allow arbitrary decisions, and thus to avoid the
kind of debate, clarification and renegotiation typical of more
egalitarian social relations, is obviously what allows its victims to
see procedures created on the basis of violence as stupid or
unreasonable. One might say, those relying on the fear of force are not
obliged to engage in a lot of interpretative labor, and thus, generally
speaking, do not.
This is not an aspect of violence that has received much attention in
the anthropological literature on the subject The latter has tended
instead to emphasize the ways that acts of violence are meaningful and
communicative. It seems to me this is an area where we are particularly
prone to fall victim to the confusion of interpretive depth and social
significance: that is, to assume that the most interesting aspect of
violence is also the most important. This is not to say that acts of
violence are not, generally speaking, also acts of communication.
Clearly they are. But this is true of any other form of human action as
well. It strikes me that what is really important about violence is that
it is perhaps the only form of human action that holds out even the
possibility of having social effects without being communicative. To be
more precise: violence may well be the only form of human action by
which it is possible to have relatively predictable effects on the
actions of a person about whom you understand nothing. Pretty much any
other way one might try to influence anotherâs actions, one at least has
to have some idea who they think they are, who they think you are, what
they might want out of the situation, their aversions and proclivities,
and so forth. Hit them over the head hard enough, all of this becomes
irrelevant.
It is true that the effects one can have by disabling or killing someone
are very limited, but they are real enough, and critically, they are
predictable. Any alternative form of action cannot, without some sort of
appeal to shared meanings or understandings, have any predictable
effects at all. Whatâs more, while attempts to influence others by the
threat of violence do require some level of shared understandings, these
can be pretty minimal. Itâs important to bear in mind that most human
relationsâparticularly ongoing ones, whether between longstanding
friends or longstanding enemiesâare extremely complicated, dense with
experience and meaning. Maintaining them requires a constant and often
subtle work of interpretation, of endlessly imagining othersâ points of
view.
Threatening others with physical harm allows the possibility of cutting
through all this. It makes possible relations of a far more schematic
kind (i.e., âcross this line and I will shoot youâ). This is of course
why violence is so often the preferred weapon of the stupid: indeed, one
might say it is one of the tragedies of human existence that this is the
one form of stupidity to which it is most difficult to come up with an
intelligent response.
I do need to introduce one crucial qualification here. If two parties
engaged in a contest of violenceâsay, generals commanding opposing
armiesâthey have good reason to try to get inside each otherâs heads. It
is really only when one side has an overwhelming advantage in their
capacity to cause physical harm that they no longer need to do so. But
this has very profound effects, because it means that the most
characteristic effect of violenceâits ability to obviate the need for
interpretive laborâbecomes most salient when the violence itself is
least visible, in fact, where acts of spectacular physical violence are
least likely to occur. These are situations of what Iâve referred to as
structural violence, on the assumption that systematic inequalities
backed up by the threat of force can be treated as forms of violence in
themselves. For this reason, situations of structural violence
invariably produce extreme lopsided structures of imaginative
identification.
These effects are often most visible when the structures of inequality
take the most deeply internalized forms. A constant staple of 1950s
American situation comedies, for example, was jokes about the
impossibility of understanding women. The jokes (always of course told
by men) always represented womenâs logic as fundamentally alien and
incomprehensible. One never had the impression the women in question had
any trouble understanding men. The reasons are obvious: women had no
choice but to understand men; this was the heyday of a certain image of
the patriarchal family, and women with no access to their own income or
resources had little choice but to spend a great deal of time and energy
understanding what their menfolk thought was going on.
Patriarchal families of this sort are, as generations of feminists have
emphasized, most certainly forms of structural violence; their norms are
indeed sanctioned by threat of physical harm in endless subtle and
not-so-subtle ways. And this kind of rhetoric about the mysteries of
womankind appears to be a perennial feature of them. Generations of
women novelistsâVirginia Woolf comes most immediately to mindâhave also
documented the other side of such arrangements: the constant efforts
women end up having to expend in managing, maintaining, and adjusting
the egos of oblivious and self-important men, involving an continual
work of imaginative identification or what Iâve called interpretive
labor. This carries over on every level. Women are always expected to
imagine what things look like from a male point of view. Men are almost
never expected to reciprocate. So deeply internalized is this pattern of
behavior that many men react to the suggestion that they might do
otherwise as if it were an act of violence in itself. A popular exercise
among High School creative writing teachers in America, for example, is
to ask students to imagining they have been transformed, for a day, into
someone of the opposite sex, and describe what that day might be like.
The results, apparently, are uncannily uniform. The girls all write long
and detailed essays that clearly show they have spent a great deal of
time thinking about the subject. Half of the boys usually refuse to
write the essay entirely. Those who do make it clear they have not the
slightest conception what being a teenage girl might be like, and deeply
resent having to think about it.
There are two critical elements here that, while linked, should probably
be formally distinguished. The first is the process of imaginative
identification as a form of knowledge, the fact that within relations of
domination, it is generally the subordinates who are effectively
relegated the work of understanding how the social relations in question
really work. Anyone who has ever worked in a restaurant kitchen, for
example, knows that if something goes terribly wrong and an angry boss
appears to size things up, he is unlikely to carry out a detailed
investigation, or even, to pay serious attention to the workers all
scrambling to explain their version of what happened. He is much more
likely to tell them all to shut up and arbitrarily impose a story that
allows instant judgment: i.e., âyouâre the new guy, you messed upâif you
do it again, youâre fired.â Itâs those who do not have the power to hire
and fire who are left with the work of figuring out what actually did go
wrong so as to make sure it doesnât happen again. The same thing usually
happens with ongoing relations: everyone knows that servants tend to
know a great deal about their employersâ families, but the opposite
almost never occurs. The second element is that of sympathetic
identification. Interestingly, it was Adam Smith, in his Theory of Moral
Sentiments (XXX), who first observed the phenomenon we now refer to as
âcompassion fatigueâ. Human beings, he proposed, are normally inclined
not only to imaginatively identify with their fellows, but as a result,
to spontaneously feel one anotherâs joys and sorrows. The poor, however,
are so consistently miserable that otherwise sympathetic observers face
a tacit choice between being entirely overwhelmed, or simply blotting
out their existence. The result is that while those on the bottom of a
social ladder spend a great deal of time imagining the perspectives of,
and actually caring about, those on the top, it almost never happens the
other way around.
Whether one is dealing with masters and servants, men and women,
employers and employees, rich and poor, structural inequalityâwhat Iâve
been calling structural violenceâinvariably creates highly lopsided
structures of the imagination. Since I think Smith was right to observe
that imagination tends to bring with it sympathy: the result is that
victims of structural violence tend to care about its beneficiaries far
more than those beneficiaries care about them. This might well be, after
the violence itself, the single most powerful force preserving such
relations.
All this I think has some interesting theoretical implications.
Now, in contemporary industrialized democracies, the legitimate
administration of violence is turned over to what is euphemistically
referred to as âlaw enforcementââparticularly, to police officers, whose
real role, as police sociologists have repeatedly demonstrated, has much
less to do with enforcing criminal law than with the scientific
application of physical force to aid in the resolution of administrative
problems. Police are, essentially, bureaucrats with weapons. At the same
time, they have, significantly, over the last fifty years or so become
the almost obsessive objects of imaginative identification in popular
culture. It has come to the point that itâs not at all unusual for a
citizen in a contemporary industrialized democracy to spend several
hours a day reading books, watching movies, or viewing TV shows that
invite them to look at the world from a police point of view, and to
vicariously participate in their exploits. If nothing else, all this
throws an odd wrinkle in Weberâs dire prophecies about the iron cage: as
it turns out, faceless bureaucracies do seem inclined to throw up
charismatic heroes of a sort, in the form of an endless assortment of
mythic detectives, spies, and police officersâall, significantly,
figures whose job is to operate precisely where the bureaucratic
structures for ordering information encounter, and appeal to, genuine
physical violence.
Even more striking, it seems to me, are the implications for the status
of theory itself.
Bureaucratic knowledge is all about schematization. In practice,
bureaucratic procedure invariably means ignoring all the subtleties of
real social existence and reducing everything to preconceived mechanical
or statistical formulae. Whether itâs a matter of forms, rules,
statistics, or questionnaires, it is always a matter of simplification.
Usually itâs not so different than the boss who walks into the kitchen
to make arbitrary snap decisions as to what went wrong: in either case
it is a matter of applying very simple pre-existing templates to complex
and often ambiguous situations. The result often leaves those forced to
deal with bureaucratic administration with the impression that they are
dealing with people who have for some arbitrary reason decided to put on
a set of glasses that only allows them to see only 2% of whatâs in front
of them. Admittedly, something very similar happens in social theory. An
ethnographic description, even a very good one, captures at best 2% of
whatâs happening in any particular Nuer feud or Balinese cockfight. A
theoretical work will normally focus on only a tiny part of that,
plucking perhaps one or two strands out of an endlessly complex tissue
of human circumstance, and using it as the basis on which to make
generalizations: say, about the nature of social conflict or about the
nature of performance. I am certainly not trying to say thereâs anything
wrong in this kind of theoretical reduction (Iâm arguably doing it right
now).
Actually, I suspect some such process is necessary if one wishes to say
something dramatically new about the world.
Consider the role of structural analysis, so famously endorsed by Edmund
Leach in the first Malinowski Memorial Lecture almost half a century ago
(1959). Nowadays structural analysis is considered definitively passé;
Claude Levi-Straussâ theoretical corpus, vaguely ridiculous. It seems to
me this is unfortunate. The great merit of structural analysis is that
it provides an well-nigh foolproof technique for doing what any good
theory should do: simplifying and schematizing complex material in such
a way as to be able to say something unexpected. This is incidentally
how I actually came up with the point about Weber just above:
I prefer to see someone like Levi-Strauss as a heroic figure, a man with
the sheer intellectual courage to pursue his model as far as it would
go, no matter how obviously absurd the results could sometimes beâor, if
you prefer, how much violence he thus did to reality.
As long as one remains within the domain of theory, then, I would argue
that simplification can be a form of intelligence. The problems arise
when the violence is no longer metaphorical. Here let me turn from
imaginary cops to real ones. A former LAPD officer turned sociologist
(Cooper 1991) observed that the overwhelming majority of those beaten by
police turn out not to be guilty of any crime. âCops donât beat up
burglarsâ, he observed. The reason, he explained, is simple: the one
thing most guaranteed to evoke a violent reaction from police is to
challenge their right to âdefine the situation.â If what Iâve been
saying is true this is just what weâd expect. The police truncheon is
precisely the point where the stateâs bureaucratic imperative for
imposing simple administrative schema, and its monopoly of coercive
force, come together. It only makes sense then that bureaucratic
violence should consist first and foremost of attacks on those who
insist on alternative schemas or interpretations. At the same time, if
one accepts Piagetâs famous definition of mature intelligence as the
ability to coordinate between multiple perspectives (or possible
perspectives) one can see, here, precisely how bureaucratic power, at
the moment it turns to violence, becomes literally a form of infantile
stupidity.
If I had more time I would suggest why I feel this approach could
suggest new ways to consider old problems. From a Marxian perspective,
for example, one might note that my notion of âinterpretive laborâ that
keeps social life running smoothly implies a fundamental distinction
between the domain of social production (the production of persons and
social relations) where the imaginative labor is relegated to those on
the bottom, and a domain of commodity production where the imaginative
aspects of work are relegated to those on the top. In either case,
though, structures of inequality produce lopsided structures of the
imagination. I would also propose that what we are used to calling
âalienationâ is largely the subjective experience of living inside such
lopsided structures. This in turn has implications for any liberatory
politics. For present purposes, though, let me just draw attention to
some of the implications for anthropology.
One is that many of the interpretive techniques we employ have,
historically, served as weapons of the weak far more often than as
instruments of power. Renato Rosaldo (1986) made a famous argument that
when Evans-Pritchard, annoyed that no one would speak to him, ended up
gazing at a Nuer camp of Muot Dit âfrom the door of his tentâ, he
rendered it equivalent to a Foucauldian panopticon. The logic seems to
be that any knowledge gathered under unequal conditions serves a
disciplinary function. To me, this is absurd. The panopticon was a
prison. Prisoners endured the gaze, and internalized its dictates,
because if they tried to escape, or resist, they could be killed. Absent
the apparatus of coercion, such an observer is reduced to the equivalent
of a neighborhood gossip, deprived even of the sanction of public
opinion.
Underlying the analogy, I think, is the assumption that comprehensive
knowledge of this sort is an inherent part of any imperial project. Even
the briefest examination of the historical record though makes clear
that empires tend to have little or no interest in documenting
ethnographic material. They tend to be interested instead in questions
of law and administration. For information on exotic marriage customs or
mortuary ritual, one almost invariably has to fall back on travelers
accountsâon the likes of Herodotus, Ibn Battuta, or Zhang Qianâthat is,
on descriptions of those lands which fell outside the jurisdiction of
whatever state the traveler belonged to.
Historical research reveals that the inhabitants of Muot Dit were, in
fact, largely former follows of a prophet named Gwek who had been
victims of RAF bombing and forced displacement the year before (Johnson
1979, 1982, 1994), the whole affair being occasioned by fairly typical
bureaucratic foolishness (basic misunderstandings about the nature of
power in Nuer society, attempts to separate Nuer and Dinka populations
that had been entangled for generations). When Evans-Pritchard was there
they were still subject to punitive raids from the British authorities.
Evans-Pritchard was asked to go to Nuerland basically as a spy, at first
refused, then finally agreed, he later said because he
âfelt sorry for themâ. He appears to have carefully avoided gathering
the specific information the authorities really wanted, while, at the
same time, doing his best to use his more general insights into the
workings of Nuer society to discourage some of their more idiotic
abuses, as he put it, to âhumanizeâ the authorities (Johnson 1982:245).
As an ethnographer, then, he ended up doing something very much like
traditional womenâs work: keeping the system from disaster by tactful
interventions meant to protect the oblivious and self-important men in
charge from the consequences of their own blindness.
Would it have been better to have kept oneâs hands clean? These strike
me as questions of personal conscience. I suspect the greater moral
dangers lie on an entirely different level. The question for me is
whether our theoretical work is ultimately directed at undoing,
dismantling, some of the effects of these lopsided structures of
imagination, or whetherâas can so easily happen when even our best ideas
come to be backed up by bureaucratically administered violenceâwe end up
reinforcing them.
Iâd like to thank David Apter, Keith Breckenridge, Kryzstina Fevervary,
Andrej Grubacic, Matthew Hull, Lauren Leve, Christina Moon, Stuart
Rockefeller, Marina Sitrin, Steve Cupid Theodore, and Hylton White for
advice and suggestions and encouragement on this project. The essay is
dedicated to my mother, in honor of her moral political commitment,
irreverence, and common sense.
Apter, David
1965 The Politics of Modernization. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
1971 Choice and the Politics of Allocation: a developmental theory. New
Haven: Yale University Press.
Breckenridge, Keith
2003 âPower Without Knowledge: Three Colonialisms in South Africa.â
http://www.history.und.ac.za/Sempapers/Breckenridge2003.pdf.
2005 âVerwoerdâs Bureau of Proof: Total Information in the Making of
Apartheid.â History Workshop Journal 59: 83â108
Cooper, Marc
1991 âDum Da Dum-Dumâ. Village Voice April 16, 1991, pp.28â33.
Graeber, David
2006 On the Nature of Politics: Magic and the Legacy of Slavery in
Madagascar. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Herzfeld, Michael
13
1994 The Social Production of Indifference: Exploring the Symbolic Roots
of Western Bureaucracy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Johnson, Douglas H.
1979 âColonial Policy and Prophecy: the âNuer Settlementâ 1929â20â in
Journal of the Anthropological Society of Oxford, X/1.
1982 âEvans-Pritchard, the Nuer, and the Sudan Political Service.â
African Affairs, Vol. 81, No. 323. (Apr., 1982), pp. 231â246
1994 Nuer Prophets. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Leach, Edmund
1959 âRethinking Anthropology.â Man:
Rosaldo, Renato
1986 âFrom the Door of His Tent: the Fieldworker and the Inquisitor.â In
Writing Culture: The Poetics and Politics of Ethnography (James Clifford
and George Marcus, eds.), Berkeley: University of California Press, pp.
77â97.
Smith, Adam
XXX Theory of Moral Sentiments