💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › caspar-rasp-lesser-known-individualism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 08:45:39. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Lesser known individualism Author: Caspar Rasp Date: March 2021 Language: en Topics: individualism, individual, unique, anti-humanism, definitions, being, abstraction Source: Retrieved on May 12, 2021 from https://chi.st/to-kick-as-a-horse-would/lesser-known-individualism
As an exercise in rendering down a bare-bones definition of anarchist
practice, Ive come up with: the tension between resisting (anti-) and/or
avoiding (a-) being controlled on the one hand, and letting go of
control on the other.
I find a collectivist foundation incompatible with this definition. Ill
define collectivism as a logic that prioritizes the goals of an abstract
we over those of unique beings.[1] The abstract we can be given an
endless number of names: group, community, the people, hairdressers,
Italians, zoomers, etc. Or it can be simply we, with the speaker
assuming that they and their audience are all a we. This abstract we
lives in the realm of the ideal, as something external to the beings it
claims to be. The collectivist logic uses categorization to make all
sorts of determinations based on singular beings as units of
measurement, or numbers on papers and screens. While fundamental to
politics (strategies and tactics to manage large numbers of people), I
find this logic detrimental to a liberatory anarchist practice that isnt
willing to deny the unique contingencies of beings, and desires to let
go of control.
Regarding the individualist perspective, I think there are two
conceptions to grapple with. The first is the more commonly known
individualism found in liberalism.[2] I find it individualistic in name
only: conflating an atomistic separateness with individualism. This
perspective insists on independent self interest as a foundational
principal, yet depends on abstractions to motivate interests:
rationalism, humanism, progressive teleology through technology, and
perhaps the most emphasized–economic relationality. This creates a
conflicting existence for the atomized: wanting, but never fully able to
own themselves. The ideals of this perspective also alienate beings from
the ecology they find themselves in, leading to metaphysical extremes
such as hard materialism (the denial of mind). The result is endless
civilizational growth through resource extraction and servitude through
work. Individuals are understood as economic agents and rational
subjects: not in service of themselves, but economics and rationalist
philosophy. I see this form of individualism not as individualist as it
claims to be, and more collectivist than it admits.
The second understanding is the lesser known radical ownness of
individualist anarchism. I find this to be truer to the name in that it
also emphasizes self interest as a foundational principle,[3] but seeks
to shed the abstract demands that liberal individualism clings to. In
the text,
The Individualist Anarchist Discourse of Early Interwar Germany
, Constantin Parvulescu puts it this way:
“the power void [left by revolution] brought to the fore a disoriented
being, one frightened by freedom and addicted to transcendent guidance.
Stirner’s predictions proved to be true: liberalism had failed to
produce a free subject; instead it created a monad that conceived of
itself as incomplete, as part of something bigger than him or her: an
order, a body politic or a mission.”
In contrast to this monad, the unique being (or individualist as
individualist anarchist) rejects the abstract subjecthood defined by the
polis, preferring instead the embodied real defined through lived
experience. This perspective also seems more compatible with ecological
principles: with beings not static, determined, or separate from their
ecology. It recognizes that unique beings are composed of other unique
beings, in both mind and matter, yet retain their uniqueness. The unique
being is both singular and plural. Singular in that every being is the
unique set of contingencies that only it can be made up of, and plural
in that they are continuously in flux: becoming something they werent
prior in potentially many ways at once. This capacity is the liberatory
potential of the unique being as practiced through the creative
unlearning of assigned values: the power to not only transform oneself,
but to lose oneself. This is the freedom of forgetting, of letting go of
control. It is anti-humanist in that it rejects the determined ideal of
the Human, in favor of the indeterminate living of human beings. It is a
passion for being. It values difference over sameness, and finds
disagreement more interesting than agreement. It values heresy and play,
and takes seriously laughing at itself.
“The universe, in its greatness, can seem to want to crush me, but it
cannot penetrate me, I, who am a formative and indispensable part, and
the further the unique strives to spread itself out and its aim and its
action, the more deeply it understands its situation and its need for
the cosmos.” – Anselm Ruest and Salomo Friedlaender,
Contributions to the History of Individualism
[1] For now, Im choosing unique being to describe what could be also
called person, individual, or the overly complicated singularity, but
the appropriate term (or if there should be one) is up for debate.
[2] This is by far the most familiar understanding, which is why almost
any discussion of individualism immediately points to it. This creates a
predicament: drop the term individualist for something lesser known, or
fight for it. Im undecided, since both options seem to mislead either
way. Since collectivist tendencies dominate the general discourse, the
same predicament applies to anarchism as well.
[3] Self interest does not imply that others are not taken into
consideration or separate from the self, in fact the opposite: it is in
one’s self interest to highly consider and not neglect the mutuality
between beings, for they are composed of each other. It emphasizes that
acting for oneself in turn benefits those with whom one is interacting,
and by the wants of desire, not the shoulds of duty.