💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › silas-crane-authoritarianism-and-self-creation.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 13:52:32. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Authoritarianism and Self-Creation
Author: Silas Crane
Date: June 2008
Language: en
Topics: authority, individualist, spirituality, marxism, theory and practice
Source: Reproduction of Original

Silas Crane

Authoritarianism and Self-Creation

One of the first lessons to be learned upon entering the world of

radical politics is that the craving for power is not exclusive to

tribal warlords and right-wing politicians. Indeed, much of what passes

for left-wing organizing today is driven by the same impulses towards

tyranny, conquest, and domination that characterize the world’s most

odious systems of mass enslavement. This pattern is evident in the

centralized, hierarchical forms adopted by many anti-capitalist sects;

however, the seeds are planted on a deeper level, in a mode of

self-consciousness that fosters authoritarian practices by reducing

political life to a manipulative struggle for power and strategic

advantage.

A cynical observer might trace this authoritarian tendency to an

instinctive mechanism rooted in the biological nature of the human

species – a competitive impulse, an aggressive drive, a congenital will

to power. But such explanations have less to do with science than with a

secret wish to absolve humanity’s guilt for creating an unlivable world

– while at the same time furnishing a universal excuse for our ongoing

complicity in the disaster. After all, if the will to power can be

construed as an inviolable force of nature, then the need to strive for

alternative forms of government can be discarded as illusory. This

dead-end style of argument might be acceptable to those who yearn for

reconciliation with the current order, but to the rest of us it will

seem like a diagnosis with no cure. In any case, such arguments collapse

under the weight of self-criticism, and by reminding ourselves that the

will to power – unlike, say, gravity – is something that human beings

can decide not to exercise, we take the first step towards bringing its

operations into the sphere of collective agency.

Still, among many on the anti-capitalist left, belief in the

omnipresence of power remains an unacknowledged foundation for political

thought and action. Every project of social transformation, regardless

of its self-declared motives, is treated as an attempt to elevate,

advance, or otherwise alter the standing of a particular class of human

subjects within a field of power relations. For traditional Marxists,

the relevant subjects constitute the mythical working class, and the

desired modification of power is whatever enables this class to wrest

authority and wealth away from the capitalist rulers. Less orthodox

theorists, by contrast, view this economic antagonism as one element

within a wider constellation of struggles, in which power is contested

on a multiplicity of fronts, by a multiplicity of subjects, with a

multiplicity of weapons, under a multiplicity of flags and banners.

In breaking with Marxist orthodoxy, this latter tendency gains the

advantages of analytical comprehensiveness and tactical flexibility. The

mode of engagement called for in a particular situation might be

micro-political or macro-political; it might involve acts of direct

confrontation or acts of coordinated desertion; it might be carried out

through individual sabotage or through periodic mass mobilization; it

might unfold on the battleground of discursive control or on the plane

of regimented bodily discipline. However, these strengths do not

immunize post-Marxist politics against the same insidious

power-fetishism that afflicts traditional Marxism – in which the human

capacity for critical thought is diverted from its essential calling as

a vehicle of spiritual self-orientation and reduced to a mere instrument

of classification and conquest. The result is a theoretical choice

between a passive, eschatological pseudo-science (or a passive,

‘critical’ pseudo-science; the implications are the same) in which the

ultimate meaning of History is deciphered by a vanguard of heroic

intellectuals, and a panoptic mode of analysis in which the fissured

totality of power is mapped from the standpoint of a dislocated

spectator.

Both of these enterprises are infected with a paralyzing logic of

reification, in which the established order of power is treated as a

solid, independent reality, while all political agency is displaced onto

an objectified class of revolutionary subjects. This fosters a

dissociated condition in which theory is fundamentally estranged from

the living experience of political struggle. Thought no longer springs

from the individual’s ecstatic need to “question while she walks,” but

is reduced to an exercise of frozen simulation in which walking is

impossible. Meanwhile, spontaneous attempts to create common values, or

common arts of living, are ignored or thrown by the wayside.[1] Anyone

who recognizes the need for a self-conscious commitment to human freedom

in forging a path of collective praxis is dismissed as dreadfully

utopian or hopelessly naïve. As a matter of unspoken consensus, the

prophetic labor of experimental self-creation is banished from the realm

of politics in favor of a warlike geography of power, in which

self-ordained Generals plot strategic moves within a hypostatized field

of power-relations.

It would be easy, and certainly in line with the current fashion for

intellectual hero-worship, to accuse these fetishistic thinkers of

betraying the wisdom of their masters, most notably Marx and Foucault;

but, alas, the much greater indignity lies in their debasement of the

revolutionary life itself, and in their attempts to obscure the

relationship between ethical commitment and the everyday practice of

political experimentation. An old anarchist dictum reminds us that in

giving birth to a new world our success will depend on keeping our

chosen means commensurate with the desired ends. This ground-level

teaching is an apposite starting-point for our attempt to think beyond

the contemporary obsession with power. For as long as our professed

moral “ends” are regarded as distant goals to be reached through a

manipulation of the established order of reality, an incongruous variety

of “means” can be deployed under the guise of bringing those goals

nearer to realization. At no point in this process is there an honest

confrontation with the essential meaning of political life. At no point

do we take up the radical project of determining our own nature as human

beings, our own character as a “we.” The anarchist’s instinctive

distrust of this warlike style of thinking arises not from a

beautiful-souled wish to conserve the purity of abstract moral ideals,

but from the commonsense realization that human ends which are

continually deferred to a mythic future cannot be actualized as part of

a common way of life in the present.

One way to realize the full wisdom of this anarchist teaching is to

contemplate the phrase “desired ends.” The philosopher John Stuart Mill,

in the context of his own ethical reflections, wrote that “the sole

evidence it is possible to produce that anything is desirable, is that

people do actually desire it.”[2] Mill’s academic interpreters still

wring their hands over the logical niceties of this statement, but in

doing so they lose their grip on a profound insight into the nature of

ethical commitment. Committing ourselves to a moral ideal is not a

matter of professing belief in the validity of an abstract rule or

principle, but of spontaneously enacting and embodying that ideal in our

engagement with the concrete situations of life. Our standards are

valuable only insofar as we stand up for them, take possession of them,

convert them into the materials for our self-critical experiment in

living. Only through this endless practice of valuing, choosing, and

desiring is our vision of human perfection transformed into reality;

only through our continual striving and affirmation does the highest

ethical ideal become the ground upon which we forge our path to a truly

ethical society.

This infinite labor of willing, imagining, and desiring is the spiritual

praxis through which the community of revolutionary agents creates

itself in the flesh. The starting-point for this labor is not a

determinate empirical class whose boundaries could be demarcated through

an analysis of objective social conditions. It is a not-yet community

whose engagement springs from a common desire to create and re-create

itself experimentally through the self-critical participation of its

members. It is a community that has no fixed identity, because it

reveals itself only from the inside, through its own work of autonomous

self-creation. It is a community that has no ideology, because its only

law is a passionate love of liberty, and its only authority is the

boundless emancipatory power of the human imagination. It is a community

that has no past or present, because it is by nature a movement, an

experiential work-in-progress. It is a community that has no limits,

because it travels the path of absolute freedom, and dissolves all

barriers by walking steadfastly into the horizons of the unknown.

All of this might sound rather romantic, and the idea of a not-yet

community might seem no better than a vaguely prophetic abstraction. But

in fact this spirit of democratic self-imagination marks a fundamental

departure from the prevailing schools of revolutionary thought, and its

implications are far-reaching. It is difficult to grasp the magnitude of

these implications, burdened as we are by the ossifying assumptions of

modern political ideology. But the need for a fundamental shift in our

orientation to revolutionary practice becomes clear when we examine the

Marxist-Leninist notion of communist revolution. To begin with, this

conception of revolution is the picture of an isolated event in time.[3]

Various strategic steps must be taken in preparation for the event;

others will be called for when it has finally come to pass. Yet what

matters above all is the single dramatic moment of revolutionary

upheaval: the expropriation of the means of production by the working

class and the transfer of property into the hands of the proletarian

state. And of course, this dialectical drama will be carried out at the

designated time by the objectively determinable working class, acting

under the enlightened guidance of a cadre of party intellectuals.

Simply put, it is the duty of the revolutionary party to tell the

working class what to do, and when. The intellectuals who comprise the

leadership of the party are uniquely qualified for this job, for they

alone have ascended to the privileged standpoint of total knowledge.[4]

They alone are equipped to know which social conditions are to blame for

human servitude and alienation, which classes must contribute to the

struggle for liberation, when the capitalist system will reach the point

of irreparable crisis, how that crisis will be overcome through the

emergence of a workers’ state, how that state will eventually whither

away, etc. In short, the party holds complete knowledge of the strategic

landscape of History; it knows which practical measures the revolution

will require, how those measures should be carried out, by whom, why,

and when.

This “revolutionary” formula is a recipe for disaster, and no individual

with a spark of liberty in her bones would ever dream of taking it

seriously. Yet it is typical of the bureaucratic-authoritarian outlook

that pervades modern political institutions, and its logic is replicated

in the managerial, power-building ethic that defines “revolution” for

many on the Left today. The ‘authoritarianism’ exemplified in this ethic

is not reducible to the belief that the revolutionary party must seize

state-power and establish a “dictatorship of the proletariat.” Much like

the absurd image of the party-intellectual, the ambition to rule and

discipline the masses through the state-apparatus is merely symptomatic

of a perverted relation between revolutionary theory and revolutionary

practice – and, more generally, between theoretical thought and the

determination of human destiny. The impulse that leads the Marxist

intellectual to posit an Absolute point of view is the same impulse that

leads him to claim a unique authority in deciding how the political

order should be constituted. It is this conception of theoretical

thought as a source of absolute knowledge about what must be done that

threatens to cut off radical experimentation and reduce political

inquiry to a conversation about how society should be governed, and by

whom.

It is essential for those who aspire to this position of God-like

authority to propagate the belief that human relations are saturated

with power. Otherwise, how would the rest of us know that the protection

of the rulers is necessary for our survival? The fantasy of an Absolute

point of view aids in this manipulation by fostering the illusion that

hierarchical power is a function of superior vision and understanding,

thereby legitimizing the formation of a specialized class of political

experts. At the level of the modern bureaucratic nation-state, this

legitimation takes the form of a ruling-managerial elite whose wisdom is

seen as indispensable to the flourishing of the helpless population; on

the smaller scale of the Marxist sect, it is the authority of the

spokesperson or intellectual leader that is viewed as essential. Both of

these forms of organization are based on the assumption that the

imposition of political power is inevitable, that we must find somebody

to decide our fate, and so it had better be the leader who possesses

sacred knowledge about which social order is the right one.[5]

Of course, there is no such thing as the “standpoint of the whole” – or

rather, if there is such a thing, nobody enjoys greater access to it

than anybody else. Most importantly, it is not through the authorization

of a knowing subject that a political way of life is proven to be

desirable – as if by ascending to the mountaintop of knowledge one could

obtain a list of supreme commandments about how society must be

constituted. No – it is only through the common desiring of individuals

that a political experiment proves itself to be valuable, and the

ultimate challenge of revolution is to give birth to a community that

lives and sustains itself by the authority of this democratic desire.

This means that what is desirable for “us” will always be an open

question, a question for endless experimentation, and that no

theoretical judgment will determine the correct blueprint for collective

action. Keeping the question of how to live perpetually open means

maintaining a constant vigilance over any authority that would impose

its will on the self-determining freedom of the individual. The exercise

of this self-determination involves a ruthless criticism of every

manifestation of power, a transvaluation of every false standard, a

sabotage of every system of exploitation – together with a

value-creating practice of freedom in which each individual puts herself

forward as a law and currency unto herself.

Such a critical-affirmative way of living can be developed only through

the growth of a spontaneous culture of individual self-mastery and

self-creation. Without the cultivation of concrete practices of

self-mastery, the impulse to wield mastery over others, or to imprison

oneself in a state of voluntary servitude, becomes an imminent threat.

This might seem an odd starting point for a path that seeks to overcome

collective enslavement. Domination and exploitation are usually

described in terms of systems of social organization and regimes of

social practice; the very concept of power refers to a process that is

intrinsically relational, whose operations become fully explicit only at

the level of socially constituted forms of behavior. But in fact it is

the individual agent, the human being as both subject of power and

subject of freedom, who must bear all responsibility for the

ill-constitution of the social order – for only the individual is called

upon, in each situation, to determine the ultimate meaning of the world

he inhabits. Diagnosing the sicknesses of power through an analysis of

forms of social mediation is thus a worthwhile exercise only insofar as

it bears directly on the world-transforming capabilities of free

individuals. And yet it is these very individuals – no longer in their

capacity as thinking agents, but in their incapacity as subjects

conditioned by power – through whom these deranged social forms are

constituted, and within whom their implicit logic of domination is

inscribed. What must be understood, therefore, in addressing the

problems of power and exploitation, is not only a certain way of

relating to the external world, or of interacting with one’s fellow

human beings, but also and especially a certain way of relating to

oneself.

Seen in this light, the creative nexus of power lies not in the

material-symbolic space constituted by the practical relations among

human beings – not in the realm traditionally conceived as the stage or

herding-ground of political action – but in the alienated, disoriented

self-consciousness of the individual agent. More specifically, it is in

the individual’s anxious, semi-conscious experience of himself as an

other, as an objectified value or commodity, that the operations of

power are expressed through the medium of his individual subjectivity.

In his condition of self-estrangement and self-projection, he becomes a

classifiable possession of the externalized power-image. He is no longer

an intrinsic possession of his own imagining self, no longer the

movement of his own self-creation, the boundless opening of his

freedom-to-live – for he is imprisoned within a fetishized world that is

alien to his own spontaneous thoughts and desires.

Such an individual experiences himself as subjugated or incapacitated –

but this does not mean that his body is shackled in iron chains, or that

he has lost all ability to lead a healthy and satisfied existence. The

most horrifying manifestations of power are indeed those in which

extreme human suffering is at stake – outright torture and imprisonment,

militaristic violence, mass poverty and starvation, death by preventable

disease – but in general the effects of our incapacitation are obscure

to us, hygienically removed from the scenes of our domesticated

life-world. The barbaric mechanisms of selection and exploitation in

which we are constantly implicated, the cruelty and predation concealed

within our everyday routines – all of these horrors are perceived only

dimly, through a phantasmagoric membrane of idle chatter and spectacular

mediation. The faceless individuals we pass on the street may be women,

immigrants, or children who encounter low-intensity, banalized violence

in every aspect of their daily lives. They may be poor inhabitants of

rich countries who are thrown into constant struggle against the

indignities of capitalism and imperial power. Or, they may be corporate

executives and white privileged sons of senators whose quest for

supremacy transforms them into monsters and reduces their life to an

anonymous rank within the commodified global system. All of these

experiences are characteristic of a world in which the individual human

being relates to herself not as the self-imagining practitioner of

freedom, but as a docile creature submerged within a reified order of

mass authority and classification. Even where a direct confrontation

with suffering is least in evidence – even in those harmonious regions

of life where a critical attitude seems least appropriate – the reifying

logic of power threatens to impose itself in the form of linguistic

tropes, patterns of attention, and habits of valuation that breed human

misery by subordinating the individual to a false order of identity and

normalization.

Meanwhile, this estrangement and mystification of our souls blinds us to

possibilities that exceed the dominant spectrum of human experience. Our

desperate will for survival – inverted and expressed as a vertiginous

fear of freedom – keeps us locked into ritualized cycles of behavior

that reinforce our condition of enslavement, in part by hiding the

sources of our acquiescence in this miserable condition. Our dormancy

amidst the destructiveness of everyday life leaves us imprisoned in a

counterfeit world that does not reflect our own authorship. We sacrifice

our freedom on the altar of power, relinquish our sovereignty to the

idol of reification. Our lives degenerate into patterns of mindless

submission; our creative energies give way to paroxysms of dislocation

and despair. And yet these circumstances are not simply imposed on us

from the outside; they come from within us, from a part of ourselves

that we do not yet understand, and whose grip on our souls we have not

yet overcome.

Freeing ourselves from this misery is neither an easy nor an

instantaneous task, but the necessary starting point is clear enough.

Instead of serving power through a mindless renunciation of our creative

capacities, we should stand up for ourselves and think: Who am I? What

are my cares and desires? What is the measure of my value as an

individual? To what extent does the world depend on my thoughts and

actions? Critical thinking is our sharpest weapon in the struggle to

imagine the world anew – for it is the only weapon that enables us to be

born again without first being destroyed.

This brings us back to the need for a utopian culture of the self – and

to the demand for a fundamental break with the norms of bourgeois civil

society. Traditional bourgeois notions of consensus and mutual

recognition can be useful when backed up by unconstrained democratic

practice, but their ideological function is to presuppose as

already-constituted a political community that exists only in the

experimental process of creating itself. At each step in this process,

it is necessary to ask oneself who it is that is willing to consent, who

it is that presents herself as recognizable; it cannot be assumed that

this ‘someone’ is the obedient subject of modern political theory, a

“rational,” law-abiding citizen endowed by tacit contract with

inalienable rights and liberties. Neither can it be assumed that the

established political institutions of rich industrialized “democracies”

– with their borders, laws, and regimes of police discipline – will

accommodate a globalized culture of radical self-creation. As long as

institutionalized mechanisms of hierarchy, theft, and militarization are

allowed to intervene in the process of democratic self-creation, there

can be no genuine autonomy in the “public sphere.” This is not simply a

reminder of the billions of subjugated people who have been

systematically excluded from public life over the years; they do not

need to bow before any Constitution in order to claim their freedom. The

very idea of a state-instituted, corporate-managed framework for public

discussion is alien to the possibility of free and open experimentation

among self-governing individuals. The historical attempt to confine this

practice of experimentation to the realm of “civil society” is itself

rooted in the violent enforcement of private property and the surrender

of decision-making power into the hands of centralized bureaucracies.

Now the question inevitably arises: How can any society pursue a project

of radical self-criticism when its central institutions are built on the

foundations of economic exploitation, political specialization, and

social hierarchy? How can any of us speak of “consensus” and

“recognition” when the very form of subjectivity that defines public

life is infected with false authority and false value at every level of

its constitution? These are questions for which the bourgeois tradition

of political philosophy – with its authoritarian belief in rationality

as the basis for rule – can provide no answer.

A culture of anarchic self-creation would begin by putting an end to all

of this – not only through the invention of radically self-governing

political and economic forms, but through techniques of communal

experimentation, arts of individual self-expression, and pursuits of

democratic beauty as the animus for a collective art of living. To say

that a culture of the self is essential to overcoming the dominant cult

of power is to say that our everyday submission to false authority and

false value is inseparable from our spiritual tendency towards

self-renunciation. The ultimate nihilistic expression of this tendency

is a generalized condition of self-dispossession – dispossession of

individual desires, dispossession of individual creative powers,

dispossession of responsibility for deciding who we are – and this

condition is the starting point of “politics” as practiced by the heirs

of modern political theory.

Conversion to a path of self-valorization begins with the suppressed

possibilities contained within our existing way of life; the initial

movement towards an examination of the self is already present in the

individual’s ability to find a path, to step back from her habitual

involvement in the world and ask herself where she is, how she got

there, and where she is going. The alternative to this self-critical

attitude is a life of quiet desperation – a life in which we carry on

without taking an interest in our own characters, the characters of our

neighbors, or the character of the world in general. A person who lives

without taking responsibility for what is his own, without caring for

himself or making himself at home in the world, becomes nothing more

than a slave to false authorities and false values. If such a person

goes to work and receives a paycheck, then, sheep-like, he accepts the

payment as a measure of his individual worth. If he is asked by the

President to drop bombs on faraway nations, or pay taxes that will

subsidize those bombs, he pounds his chest and immediately complies. If

he receives orders not to cross the state-boundary, or transgress the

official police barricade, he obeys cheerfully and without question. All

of us are reduced to this condition of slavery at some time, but the

condition cannot be enforced without our voluntary or unconscious

submission. We can put an end to our enslavement by inventing practices

in which our refusal to obey becomes the vehicle for our own diverse

projects of creative self-valorization. A practice of self-valorization

can be simple or sophisticated; it can be a spontaneous form of

counter-conduct or counter-discipline that affirms our indomitable

singularity in the face of power and exploitation; it can be an

unpremeditated spiritual exercise in which the individual resists the

material forces of self-dispossession and actively constitutes himself

as the sovereign ruler of his own destiny. Workers’ self-management,

general strikes, self-sustaining local technology, community

skill-sharing, military desertion, civil disobedience, creation of

autonomous zones, renunciation of citizenship, experiments in absolute

democracy: all of these practices can be undertaken in the spirit of

radical self-mastery, self-valorization, and self-creation. When these

practices are rooted in cooperative networks of mutual aid and

solidarity, we gain the ability to cultivate a revolutionary way of life

without fear of repression, starvation, or despair.

Within the soul of the individual, the culture of self-creation begins

with a spirit of radical critique – a spirit in which the individual

relates to herself, and takes possession of herself, through the act of

differentiating her own nature from the nature of everything around her.

By engaging her inalienable power to think, she enacts and refines the

autonomous force of her own unique character and negates those aspects

of the world that do not pass its test. She constitutes herself as an

autonomous being – a being whose value is determined only from the

inside, only through the exercise of her own creative capacities. As she

proceeds in this way, she cultivates an attitude of engaged openness to

the world – to its meanings, its lessons, and its possibilities – and

thereby ensures that her life will be determined by no force outside her

own path of self-creation. By maintaining this critical self-possession

she arms herself against any tyrannical gods or masters that would bind

her to an extrinsic authority. She is thus able to maintain absolute

freedom in the face of violence, conformity, and domination – all in

such a way, and with such an intensity, that when she associates with

other individuals on the basis of these common practices, an

ungovernable revolutionary culture is born.

[1] Here sectarian fulminations against so-called “lifestyle anarchism”

only serve to conceal what is at stake in the question of common values.

Reasoned contempt for neo-dandyist campaigns to reduce politics to

subcultural style does not justify abandoning the Bakunian standpoint of

absolute liberty. Unconventional sartorial habit is one thing; creating

the values that will determine the direction of our common life is quite

another.

[2] John Stuart Mill, Utilitarianism, Hackett, 1979, p. 34.

[3] I will not address the claim, which still echoes in certain circles,

that “Marxist science” has discovered strict socio-economic laws and is

therefore capable of predicting the future development of capitalist

civilization. Any theory that claims advance-knowledge of what a society

of human beings will do ignores the capacity of those human beings to

determine the conditions of their own future. Even if knowledge of

social and economic systems is bound to play a part in shaping our path

of self-determination (as is undoubtedly the case), the work of politics

begins when we ask ourselves how this, or any other knowledge we might

possess, will help us constitute ourselves as a self-creating political

community. Any perspective on human life that ignores the necessary

priority of human freedom to all the results of scientific knowledge is

more akin to fortune-telling than to political theory.

[4] Perhaps the most sophisticated version of this idea comes from

Lukács (History and Class Consciousness, Cambridge, MA, 1971, p. 27):

“It is not the primacy of economic motives in historical explanation

that constitutes the decisive difference between bourgeois and Marxist

thought, but the point of view of totality.”

[5] A similar logic is found in the growing sector of non-profit

organizations, where the intense professionalization and managerial

training of activists endows them with specialized coordinator status.