💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › petr-kropotkin-law-and-authority.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 13:22:13. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Law and Authority
Author: PĂ«tr Kropotkin
Date: 1886
Language: en
Topics: law, authority, the state,
Source: Retrieved on March 1st, 2009 from http://dwardmac.pitzer.edu/anarchist_archives/kropotkin/lawauthority.html][dwardmac.pitzer.edu]].  Proofread version retrieved on October 4th, 2019, from [[http://www.revoltlib.com/?id=309.
Notes: Printed by the New Temple Press, Norbury Crescent, Norburt, S.W.

PĂ«tr Kropotkin

Law and Authority

I

“When ignorance reigns in society and disorder in the minds of men, laws

are multiplied, legislation is expected to do everything, and each fresh

law being a fresh miscalculation, men are continually led to demand from

it what can proceed only from themselves, from their own education and

their own morality.” It is no revolutionist who says this, nor even a

reformer. It is the jurist, [Joseph] Dallois, author of the Collection

of French law known as “Repertoire de la Legislation.” And yet, though

these lines were written by a man who was himself a maker and admirer of

law, they perfectly represent the abnormal condition of our society.

In existing States a fresh law is looked upon as a remedy for evil.

Instead of themselves altering what is bad, people begin by demanding a

law to alter it. If the road between two villages is impassable, the

peasant says: — “There should be a law about parish roads.” If a

park-keeper takes advantage of the want of spirit in those who follow

him with servile observance and insults one of them, the insulted man

says: — “There should be a law to enjoin more politeness upon

park-keepers.” If there is stagnation in agriculture or commerce, the

husbandman, cattle-breeder, or corn speculator argues, “It is protective

legislation that we require.” Down to the old clothesman there is not

one who does not demand a law to protect his own little trade. If the

employer lowers wages or increases the hours of labour, the politician

in embryo exclaims, “We must have a law to put all that to rights,”

instead of telling the workers that there are other, and much more

effectual means of settling these things straight; namely, recovering

from the employer the wealth of which he has been despoiling the workmen

for generations. In short, a law everywhere and for everything! A law

about fashions, a law about mad dogs, a law about virtue, a law to put a

stop to all the vices and all the evils which result from human

indolence and cowardice.

We are so perverted by an education which from infancy seeks to kill in

us the spirit of revolt, and to develop that of submission to authority;

we are so perverted by this existence under the rule of a law, which

regulates every event in life — our birth, our education, our

development, our love, our friendship — that, if this state of things

continues, we shall lose all initiative, all habit of thinking for

ourselves. Our society seems no longer able to understand that it is

possible to exist otherwise than under the reign of Law, elaborated by a

representative government and administered by a handful of rulers; and

even when it has gone so far as to emancipate itself from the thraldom,

its first care had been to reconstitute it immediately. “The Year I. of

Liberty” has never lasted more than a day, for after proclaiming it men

put themselves the very next morning under the yoke of Law and

Authority.

Indeed, for some thousands of years, those who govern us have done

nothing but ring the changes upon “Respect for law, obedience to

authority.” This is the moral atmosphere in which parents bring up their

children, and school only serves to confirm the impression. Cleverly

assorted scraps of spurious science are inculcated upon the children to

prove necessity of law; obedience to the law is made a religion; moral

goodness and the law of the masters are fused into one and the same

divinity. The historical hero of the schoolroom is the man who obeys the

law, and defends it against rebels.

Later, when we enter upon public life, society and literature,

impressing us day by day and hour by hour, as the water-drop hollows the

stone, continue to inculcate the same prejudice. Books of history, of

political science, of social economy, are stuffed with this respect for

law; even the physical sciences have been pressed into the service by

introducing artificial modes of expression, borrowed from theology and

arbitrary power, into knowledge which is purely the result of

observation. Thus our intelligence is successfully befogged, and always

to maintain our respect for law. The same work is done by newspapers.

They have not an article which does not preach respect for law, even

where the third page proves every day to demonstrate the imbecility of

that law, and shows how it is dragged through every variety of mud and

filth by those charged with its administration. Servility before the law

has become a virtue, and I doubt if there was ever even a revolutionist

who did not begin in his youth as the defender of law against what are

generally called “abuses,” although these last are inevitable

consequences of the law itself.

Art pipes in unison with would-be science. The hero of the sculptor, the

painter, the musician, shields Law beneath his buckler, and with

flashing eyes and distended nostrils stands ever ready to strike down

the man who would lay hands upon her. Temples are raised to her;

revolutionists themselves hesitate to touch the high priests consecrated

to her service, and when revolution is about to sweep away some ancient

institution, it is still by law that it endeavours to sanctify the deed.

The confused mass of rules of conduct called Law, which has been

bequeathed to us by slavery, serfdom, feudalism, and royalty, has taken

the place of those stone monsters before whom human victims used to be

immolated, and whom slavish savages dared not even touch lest they

should be slain by the thunderbolts of heaven.

This new worship has been established with especial success since the

rise to supreme power of the middle class — since the great French

Revolution. Under the ancien regime, men spoke little of laws; unless,

indeed, it were, with Montesquieu, Rousseau and Voltaire, to oppose them

to royal caprice; obedience to the good pleasure of the king and his

lackeys was compulsory on pain of hanging or imprisonment. But during

and after the revolutions when the lawyers rose to power, they did their

best to strengthen the principle upon which their ascendancy depended.

The middle class at once accepted as a dyke to dam up the popular

torrent. The priestly crew hastened to sanctify it, to save their bark

from foundering amid the breakers. Finally the people received it as an

improvement upon the arbitrary authority and violence of the past.

To understand this, we must transport ourselves in imagination into the

eighteenth century. Our hearts must have ached at the story of the

atrocities committed by the all-powerful nobles of that time upon the

men and women of the people, before we can understand what must have

been the magic influence upon the peasant’s mind of the words, “Equality

before the law, obedience to the law without distinction of birth or

fortune.” He, who until then, had been treated more cruelly than a

beast, he who had never had any rights, he who had never obtained

justice against the most revolting actions on the part of a noble,

unless in revenge he killed him and was hanged — he saw himself

recognized by this maxim, at least in theory, at least with regard to

his personal rights, as the equal of his lord. Whatever this law might

be, it promised to affect lord and peasant alike; it proclaimed the

equality of rich and poor before the judge. The promise was a lie, and

to-day we know it; but at that period it was an advance, a homage to

justice, as hypocrisy is a homage rendered to truth. This is the reason

that when the saviours of the menaced middle class (the Robespierres and

the Dantons) took their stand upon the writings of the Rousseaus and the

Voltaires, and proclaimed “respect for law, the same for every man,” the

people accepted the compromise; for their revolutionary impetus had

already spent its force in the contest with a foe whose ranks drew

closer day by day, they bowed their neck beneath the yoke of law to save

themselves from the arbitrary power of their lords.

The Middle Class has ever since continued to make the most of this

maxim, which with another principle, that of representative government,

sums up the whole philosophy of the bourgeois age, the XIX century. It

has preached this doctrine in its schools, it has propagated it in its

writings, it has moulded its art and science to the same purpose, it has

thrust its beliefs into every hole and corner — like a pious

Englishwoman, who slips tracts under the door — and it has done all this

so successfully that to-day we behold the issue in the detestable fact,

that, at the very moment when the spirit of turbulent criticism is

re-awakening, men who long for freedom begin the attempt to obtain it by

entreating their masters to be kind enough to protect them by modifying

the laws which these masters themselves have created!

But times and tempers are changed since a hundred years ago. Rebels are

everywhere to be found, who no longer wish to obey the law without

knowing whence it comes, what are its uses, and whither arises the

obligation to submit to it, and the reverence with which it is

encompassed. The rebels of our day are criticizing the very foundations

of Society, which have hitherto been held sacred, and first and foremost

amongst them that fetish, law. Just for this reason the upheaval which

is at hand is no mere insurrection, it is a Revolution.

The critics analyse the sources of law, and find there either a god,

product of the terrors of the savages, and stupid, paltry and malicious

as the priests who vouch for its supernatural origin, or else,

bloodshed, conquest by fire and sword. They study the characteristics of

law, and instead of perpetual growth corresponding to that of the human

race, they find its distinctive trait to be immobility, a tendency to

crystallise what should be modified and developed day by day. They ask

how law has been maintained, and in its service they see the atrocities

of Byzantinism, the cruelties of the Inquisition, the tortures of the

Middle Ages, living flesh torn by the lash of the executioner, chains,

clubs, axes, the gloomy dungeons of prisons, agony, curses and tears. In

our own days they see, as before, the axe, the cord, the rifle, the

prison; on the one hand, the brutalised prisoner, reduced to the

condition of a caged beast by the debasement of his whole moral being,

and on the other hand, the judge, stripped of every feeling which does

honour to human nature, living like a visionary in a world of legal

fictions, reveling in the infliction of imprisonment and death, without

even suspecting, in the cold malignity of his madness, the abyss of

degradation into which he has himself fallen before the eyes of those

whom he condemns.

They see a race of law-makers legislating without knowing what their

laws are about; to-day voting a law on the sanitation of towns, without

the faintest notion of hygiene, to-morrow making regulations for the

armament of troops, without so much as understanding a gun; making laws

about teaching and education without ever having given a lesson of any

sort, or even an honest education to their own children; legislating in

all directions, but never forgetting the penalties to be meted out to

ragamuffins, the prison and the galleys, which are to be the portion of

men a thousand times less immoral than these legislators themselves.

Finally, they see the gaoler on the way to lose all human feeling, the

detective trained as a blood-hound, the police spy despising himself;

“informing,” metamorphosed into a virtue; corruption, erected into a

system; all the vices, all the evil qualities of mankind countenanced

and cultivated to insure the triumph of law.

All this we see, and, therefore, instead of inanely repeating the old

formula, “Respect the law,” we say, “Despise law and all its

attributes!” In place of the cowardly phrase, “Obey the law,” our cry is

“Revolt against all laws!”

Only compare the misdeeds accomplished in the name of each law, with the

good it has been able to effect, and weigh carefully both good and evil,

and you will see if we are right.

II

Relatively speaking, law is a product of modern times. For ages and ages

mankind lived without any written law, even that graved in symbols upon

the entrance stones of a temple. During that period, human relations

were simply regulated by customs, habits and usages, made sacred by

constant repetition, and acquired by each person in childhood, exactly

as he learned how to obtain his food by hunting, cattle-rearing, or

agriculture.

All human societies have passed through this primitive phase, and to

this day a large proportion of mankind have no written law. Every tribe

has its own manners and customs; customary law, as the jurists say. It

has social habits, and that suffices to maintain cordial relations

between the inhabitants of the village, the members of the tribe or

community. Even amongst ourselves — the “civilized” nations — when we

leave large towns, and go into the country, we see that there the mutual

relations of the inhabitants are still regulated according to ancient

and generally accepted customs, and not according to the written law of

the legislators. The peasants of Russia, Italy and Spain, and even of a

large part of France and England, have no conception of written law. It

only meddles with their lives to regulate their relations with the

State. As to relations between themselves, though these are sometimes

very complex, they are simply regulated according to ancient custom.

Formerly, this was the case with mankind in general.

Two distinctly marked currents of custom are revealed by analysis of the

usages of primitive people.

As man does not live in a solitary state, habits and feelings develop

within him which are useful for the preservation of society and the

propagation of the race. Without social feelings and usages, life in

common would have been absolutely impossible. It is not law which has

established them; they are anterior to all law. Neither is it religion

which has ordained them; they are anterior to all religions. They are

found amongst all animals living in society. They are spontaneously

developed by the very nature of things, like those habits in animals

which men call instinct. They spring from a process of evolution, which

is useful, and, indeed, necessary, to keep society together in the

struggle it is forced to maintain for existence. Savages end by no

longer eating one another, because they find it in the long run more

advantageous to devote themselves to some sort of cultivation, than to

enjoy the pleasure of feasting upon the flesh of an aged relative once a

year. Many travelers have depicted the manners of absolutely independent

tribes, where laws and chiefs are unknown, but where the members of the

tribe have given up stabbing one another in every dispute, because the

habit of living in society has ended by developing certain feelings of

fraternity and oneness of interest, and they prefer appealing to a third

person to settle their differences. The hospitality of primitive

peoples, respect for human life, the sense of reciprocal obligation,

compassion for the weak, courage, extending even to the sacrifice of

self for others, which is first learnt for the sake of children and

friends, and later, for that of members of the same community — all

these qualities are developed in man anterior to all law, independently

of all religion, as in the case of the social animals. Such feelings and

practices are the inevitable results of social life. Without being, as

say priests and metaphysicians, inherent in man, such qualities are the

consequence of life in common.

But side by side with these customs, necessary to the life of societies

and the preservation of the race, other desires, other passions, and

therefore other habits and customs, are evolved in human association.

The desire to dominate others and impose one’s own will upon them; the

desire to seize upon the products of the labour of a neighbouring tribe;

the desire to surround oneself with comforts without producing anything,

whilst slaves provide their master with the means of procuring every

sort of pleasure and luxury — these selfish, personal desires give rise

to another current of habits and customs. The priest and the warrior,

the charlatan who makes a profit out of superstition, and after freeing

himself from the fear of the devil, cultivates it in others; and the

bully, who procures the invasion and pillage of his neighbours, that he

may return laden with booty, and followed by slaves; these two, hand in

hand, have succeeded in imposing upon primitive society customs

advantageous to both of them, but tending to perpetuate their domination

of the masses. Profiting by the indolence, the fears, the inertia of the

crowd, and thanks to the continual repetition of the same acts, they

have permanently established customs which have become a solid basis for

their own domination.

For this purpose, they would have made use, in the first place, of that

tendency to run in a groove, so highly developed in mankind. In children

and all savages it attains striking proportions, and it may also be

observed in animals. Man, when he is at all superstitious, is always

afraid to introduce any sort of change into existing conditions; he

generally venerates what is ancient. “Our fathers did so and so; they

got on pretty well; they brought you up; they were not unhappy; do the

same!” the old say to the young, every time the latter wish to alter

things. The unknown frightens them, they prefer to cling to the past,

even when that past represents poverty, oppression and slavery. It may

even be said that the more miserable a man is, the more he dreads every

sort of change, lest it may make him more wretched still. Some ray of

hope, a few scraps of comfort, must penetrate his gloomy abode before he

can begin to desire better things, to criticise the old ways of living,

and prepare to imperil them for the sake of bringing about a change. So

long as he is not imbued with hope, so long as he is not freed from the

tutelage of those who utilise his superstition and his fears, he prefers

remaining in his former position. If the young desire any change, the

old raise a cry of alarm against the innovators. Some savages would

rather die than transgress the customs of their country, because they

have been told from childhood that the least infraction of established

routine would bring ill-luck, and ruin the whole tribe. Even in the

present day, what numbers of politicians, economists, and would-be

revolutionists act under the same impression, and cling to a vanishing

past. How many care only to seek for precedents. How many fiery

innovators are mere copyists of bygone revolutions.

The spirit of routine, originating in superstition, indolence, and

cowardice, has in all times been the mainstay of oppression. In

primitive human societies, it was cleverly turned to account by priests

and military chiefs. They perpetuated customs useful only to themselves,

and succeeded in imposing them on the whole tribe. So long as this

conservative spirit could be exploited so as to assure the chief in his

encroachments upon individual liberty, so long as the only inequalities

between men were the work of nature, and these were not increased a

hundred-fold by the concentration of power and wealth, there was no need

for law, and the formidable paraphernalia of tribunals and

ever-augmenting penalties to enforce it.

But as society became more and more divided into two hostile classes,

one seeking to establish its domination, the other struggling to escape,

the strife began. Now the conqueror was in a hurry to secure the results

of his actions in a permanent form, he tried to place them beyond

question, to make them holy and venerable by every means in his power.

Law made its appearance under the sanction of the priest, and the

warrior’s club was placed at its service. Its office was to render

immutable such customs as were to the advantage of the dominant

minority. Military authority undertook to ensure obedience. This new

function was a fresh guarantee to the power of the warrior; now he had

not only mere brute force at his service; he was the defender of law.

If law, however, presented nothing but a collection of prescriptions

serviceable to rulers, it would find some difficulty in insuring

acceptance and obedience. Well, the legislators confounded in one code

the two currents of custom, of which we have just been speaking, the

maxims which represent principles of morality and social union wrought

out as a result of life in common, and the mandates, which are meant to

ensure external existence to inequality. Customs, absolutely essential

to the very being of society, are, in the code, cleverly intermingled

with usages imposed by the ruling caste, and both claim equal respect

from the word. “Do not kill,” says the code, and hastens to add, “And

pay tithes to the priest.” “Do not steal,” says the code, and

immediately after, “He who refuses to pay taxes, shall have his hand

struck off.”

Such was law; and it has maintained its two-fold character to this day.

Its origin is the desire of the ruling class to give permanence to

customs imposed by themselves for their own advantage. Its character is

the skilful commingling of customs useful to society, customs which have

no need of law to insure respect, with other customs useful only to

rulers, injurious to the mass of the people, and maintained only by the

fear of punishment.

Like individual capital, which was born of fraud and violence, and

developed under the auspices of authority, law has no title to the

respect of men. Born of violence and superstition, and established in

the interests of consumer, priest and rich exploiter, it must be utterly

destroyed on the day when the people desire to break their chains.

We shall be still better convinced of this when, in the next chapter, we

have analysed the ulterior development of laws under the auspices of

religion, authority and the existing parliamentary system.

III

We have seen in the previous chapter how law originated in established

usage and custom, and how, from the beginning it has represented a

skilful mixture of social habits, necessary to the preservation of the

human race, with other customs, imposed by those who used popular

superstition, as well as the right of the strongest for their own

advantage. This double character of law has determined its own later

development during the growth of political organisation. Whilst in the

course of ages the nucleus of social custom inscribed in law has been

subjected to but slight and gradual modifications, the other portion has

been largely developed in defections indicated by the interests of the

dominant classes, and to the injury of the classes they oppress. From

time to time these dominant classes have allowed a law to be extorted

from them which presented, or appeared to present, some guarantee for

the disinherited. But then such laws have but repealed a previous law,

made for the advantage of the ruling caste. “The best laws,” says

[Thomas Henry] Buckle, “were those which repealed the preceding ones.”

But what terrible efforts have been needed, what rivers of blood have

been spilt, every time there has been a question of the repeal of one of

these fundamental enactments serving to hold the people in fetters.

Before she could abolish the vestiges of serfdom and feudal rights, and

break up the power of the royal court, France was forced to pass through

four years of revolution and twenty years of war. Decades of conflict

are needful to repeal the least of the iniquitous laws, bequeathed us by

the past, and even then they scarcely disappear except in periods of

revolution.

The history of the genesis of capital has already been told by

Socialists many times. They have described how it was born of war and

pillage, of slavery and serfdom, of modern fraud and exploitation. They

have shown how it is nourished by the blood of the worker, and how

little by little it has conquered the whole world. The same story,

concerning the genesis and development of law has yet to be told. As

usual, the popular intelligence has stolen a march upon men of books. It

has already put together the philosophy of this history, and is busy

laying down its essential landmarks.

Law, in its quality of guarantee of the results of pillage, slavery and

exploitation, has followed the same phrases of development as capital;

twin brother and sister, they have advanced hand in hand, sustaining one

another with the suffering of mankind. In every country in Europe their

history is approximately the same. It has differed only in detail; the

main facts are alike; and to glance at the development of law in France

or Germany is to know its essential traits, its phases of development,

in most of the European nations.

In the first instance, law was a national part of contract. Such a

contract was agreed upon between the legions and people at the Champs de

Mars,[1] a relic of the same period is preserved even yet in the Field

of May of the primitive Swiss cantons despite the alterations effected

by the interference of centralising and middle-class civilisation.

It is true that this contract was not always freely accepted. Even in

those early days the rich and strong were imposing their will upon the

rest. But at all events they encountered an obstacle to their

encroachments in the mass of the people, who often made them feel their

power in return.

But as the Church on one side and the nobles on the other, succeeded in

enthralling the people, the right of law-making escaped from the hands

of the nation and passed into those of the privileged orders. Fortified

by the wealth accumulating in her coffers, the Church extended her

authority; she tampered more and more with private life, and under

pretext of saving souls, she seized upon the labour of her serfs, she

gathered taxes from every class, she increased her jurisdiction, she

multiplied penalties, and enriched herself in proportion to the number

of offences committed, for the produce of every fine poured into her

coffers. Laws had no longer any connection with the interest of the

nation. “They might have been supposed to emanate rather from a council

of religious fanatics than from legislators,” observes an historian of

French Law.

At the same time, as the baron likewise extended his authority over

labourers in the fields and artisans in the towns, he, too, became

legislator and judge. The few relics of national law dating from the

tenth century are merely agreements regulating service, statute labour,

and tribute due from serf and vassals to their lord. The legislators of

that period were a handful of brigands organised for the plunder of a

people daily becoming more peaceful, as they applied themselves to

agricultural pursuits. These robbers exploited the feelings for justice

inherent in the people, they posed as the administrators of that

justice, made a source of revenue for themselves out of its fundamental

principles and concocted laws to maintain their own dominations.

Later on, these laws collected and classified by jurists, formed the

foundation of our modern codes. And are we to talk about respecting

these codes, the legacy of baron and priest?

The first revolution, the revolt of the townships, was successful in

abolishing a portion only of these laws, the charters of enfranchised

towns are, for the most part, a mere compromise between baronial and

episcopal legislation, and the new relations created within the free

borough itself. Yet what a difference between these laws, and the laws

we have now! The town did not take upon itself to imprison and execute

citizens for reasons of State: it was content to expel anyone who

plotted with the enemies of the city, and to raze his house to the

ground. It confined itself to imposing fines for so-called “crimes and

misdemeanours” and in the townships of the twelfth century may even be

discerned the just principle to-day forgotten, which holds the whole

community responsible for the misdoing of each of its members. The

societies of that time looked upon crime as an accident or misfortune; a

conception common amongst the Russian peasantry at this moment.

Therefore, they did not admit of the principle of personal vengeance as

preached by the Bible, but considered that the blame for each misdeed

reverted to the whole society. It needed all the influence of the

Bysantine Church, which imported into the West the refined cruelties of

Eastern despotism, to introduce into the manners of Gauls and Germans

the penalty of death, and the horrible fortunes afterwards inflicted on

those regarded as criminals. Just in the same way, it needed all the

influence of the Roman code, the product of the corruption of Imperial

Rome, to introduce the notions as to absolute property in land, which

have overthrown the communistic customs of primitive people.

As we know, the free townships were not able to hold their own. Torn by

intestine dissensions between rich and poor, burgher and serf, they fell

an easy prey to royalty. And as royalty acquired fresh strength, the

right of legislation passed more and more into the hands of a clique of

courtiers. Appeal to the nation, was made only to sanction the taxes

demanded by the King. Parliament summoned at intervals of two centuries,

according to the good pleasure or caprice of the Court, “Councils

Extraordinary,” Assemblies of Notables, Ministers, scarce heeding the

“grievances of the King’s subjects” — these are the legislators of

France. Later still, when all power is concentrated in a single man, who

can say “I am the State,” edicts are concocted in the “secret counsels

of the Prince,” according to the whim of a minister, or of an imbecile

King; and subjects must obey on pain of death. All judicial guarantees

are abolished; the nation is the serf of royalty, and of a handful of

courtiers. And at this period the most horrible penalties startle our

gaze — the wheel, the stake, flaying alive, tortures of every

description, invented by the sick fancy of monks and madmen, seeking

delight in the sufferings of executed criminals.

The great Revolution began the demolition of this framework of law,

bequeathed to us by feudalism and royalty. But after having demolished

some portions of the ancient edifice, the Revolution delivered over the

power of law-making to the bourgeoisie, who, in their turn, began to

raise a fresh framework of laws, intended to maintain and perpetuate

middle-class domination amongst the masses. Their Parliament makes laws

right and left, and mountains of law accumulate with frightful rapidity.

But what are all these laws at bottom?

The major portion have but one object — to protect private property,

i.e., wealth acquired by the exploitation of man by man. Their aim is to

open out to capital fresh fields for exploitation, and to sanction the

new forms which that exploitation continually assumes, as capital

swallows up another branch of human activity, railways, telegraphs,

electric light, chemical industries, the expression of man’s thought in

literature and science, etc. The object of the rest of these laws is

fundamentally the same. They exist to keep up the machinery of

government, which serves to secure to capital the exploitation and

monopoly of the wealth produced. Magistrature, police, army, public

instruction, finance, all serve one God — capital; all have but one

object — to facilitate the exploitation of the worker by the capitalist.

Analyse all the laws passed for the last eighty years and you will find

nothing but this. The protection of the person, which is put forward as

the true mission of law occupies an imperceptible space amongst them,

for, existing society, assaults upon the person, directly dictated by

hatred and brutality, tend to disappear. Nowadays, if anyone is

murdered, it is generally for the sake of robbing him; rarely from

personal vengeance. But if this class of crimes and misdemeanours is

continually diminishing, we certainly do not owe the change to

legislation. It is due to the growth of humanitarianism in our

societies, to our increasingly social habits rather than to the

prescriptions of our laws. Repeal to-morrow every law dealing with the

protection of the person, and to-morrow stop all proceedings for

assault, and the number of attempts, dictated by personal vengeance and

by brutality, would not be augmented by one single instance.

It will, perhaps, be objected that, during the last fifty years, a good

many liberal laws have been enacted. But, if these laws are analysed, it

will be discovered that this liberal legislation consists in the repeal

of the laws bequeathed to us by the barbarism of preceding centuries.

Every liberal law, every radical programme, may be summed up in these

words, abolition of laws grown irksome to the middle-class itself, and

as an extension to all citizens of liberties enjoyed by the townships of

the twelfth century. The abolition of capital punishment, trial by jury

for all “crimes” (there was a more liberal jury in the twelfth century),

the election of magistrates, the right of bringing public officials to

trial, the abolition of standing armies, free instruction, etc.,

everything that is pointed out as an invention of modern liberalism, is

but a return to the freedom which existed before Church and King had

laid hands upon every manifestation of human life.

Thus the protection of exploitation directly by laws on property, and

indirectly by the maintenance of the State, is both the spirit and the

substance of our modern codes, and the one function of our costly

legislative machinery. But it is time we gave up being satisfied with

mere phrases, and learned to appreciate their real signification. The

law, which on its first appearance presented itself as a compendium of

customs useful for the preservation of society, is now perceived to be

nothing but an instrument for the maintenance of exploitation, and the

domination of the toiling masses by rich idlers. At the present day its

civilising mission is nil; it has but one object, to bolster up

exploitation.

This is what is told us by history as to the development of law. Is it

in virtue of this history that we are called upon to respect it?

Certainly not. It has no more title to respect than capital; the fruit

of pillage; and the first duty of the revolutionists of the nineteenth

century will be to make a bonfire of all existing laws, as they will of

all titles to property.

IV

The millions of laws which exist for the regulation of humanity, appear

upon investigation to be divided into three principal categories —

protection of property, protection of persons, protection of government.

And by analysing each of these three categories, we arrive at the same

logical and necessary conclusion: the uselessness and hurtfulness of

law.

Socialists know what is meant by protection of property. Laws on

property are not made to guarantee either to the individual or to

society the enjoyment of the produce of their own labour. On the

contrary, they are made to rob the producer of a part of what he has

created, and to secure to certain other people that portion of the

produce which they have stolen either from the producer or from society

as a whole. When, for example, the law establishes Mr. So-and-So’s right

to a house, it is not establishing his right to a cottage he has built

for himself, or to a house he has erected with the help of some of his

friends. In that case no one would have disputed his right. On the

contrary, the law is establishing his right to a house which is not the

product of his labour; first of all, because he has had it built for him

by others to whom he has not paid the full value of their work; and next

because that house represents a social value, which he could not have

produced for himself. The law is establishing his right to what belongs

to everybody in general to nobody in particular. The same house built in

the midst of Siberia would not have the value it possesses in a large

town, and, as we know, that value arises from the labour of something

like fifty generations of men who have built the town, beautified it,

supplied it with water and gas, fine promenades, colleges, theatres,

shops, railways and roads leading in all directions. Thus, by

recognising the right of Mr. So-and-So to a particular house in Paris,

London or Rouen, the law is unjustly appropriating to him a certain

portion of the produce of the labour of mankind in general. And it is

precisely because this appropriation and all other forms of property,

bearing the same character, are a crying injustice, that a whole arsenal

of laws, and a whole army of soldiers, policemen and judges are needed

to maintain it against the good sense and just feeling inherent in

humanity.

Well, half our laws, the civil code in each country, serves no other

purpose than to maintain this appropriation, this monopoly for the

benefit of certain individuals, against the whole of mankind.

Three-fourths of the causes decided by the tribunals are nothing but

quarrels between monopolists — two robbers disputing over their booty.

And a great many of our criminal laws have the same object in view,

their end being to keep the workman in a subordinate position towards

his employer, and thus afford security for exploitation.

As for guaranteeing the product of his labour to the producer, there are

no laws which even attempt such a thing. It is so simple and natural, so

much a part of the manners and customs of mankind; that law has not

given it so much as a thought. Open brigandage, sword in hand, is no

feature of our age. Neither does one workman ever come and dispute the

produce of his labour with another. If they have a misunderstanding they

settle it by calling in a third person, without having recourse to law.

The only person who exacts from another what the other has produced, is

the proprietor, who comes in and deducts the lion’s share. As for

humanity in general, it everywhere respects the right of each to what he

has created, without the interposition of any special laws.

As all the laws about property, which make up thick volumes of codes,

and are the delight of our lawyers, have no other object than to protect

the unjust appropriating of human labour by certain monopolists, there

is no reason for their existence, and, on the day of the Revolution,

social revolutionists are thoroughly determined to put an end to them.

Indeed, a bonfire might be made with perfect justice of all laws bearing

upon the so-called “rights of property,” all title-deeds, all registers,

in a word, of all that is in any way connected with an institution which

will soon be looked upon as a blot in the history of humanity, as

humiliating as the slavery and serfdom of past ages.

The remarks just made upon laws concerning property are quite as

applicable to the second category of laws; those for the maintenance of

government, i.e., Constitutional Law.

It again is a complete arsenal of laws, decrees, ordinances, orders in

council, and what not, all serving to protect the diverse forms of

representative government, delegated or usurped, beneath which humanity

is writhing. We know very well — Anarchists have often enough pointed

out in their perpetual criticism of the various forms of government —

that the mission of all governments, monarchical, constitutional, or

republican, is to protect and maintain by force the privileges of the

classes in possession, the aristocracy, clergy and traders. A good third

of our laws — and each century possesses some tens of thousands of them

— the fundamental laws on taxes, excise duties, the organisation of

ministerial departments and their offices, of the army, the police, the

Church, etc., have no other end than to maintain, patch up, and develop

the administrative machine. And this machine in its turn serves almost

entirely to protect the privileges of the possessing classes. Analyse

all these laws, observe them in action day by day, and you will discover

that not one is worth preserving.

About such laws there can be no two opinions. Not only Anarchists, but

more or less revolutionary radicals also, are agreed that the only use

to be made of laws concerning the organisation of government is to fling

them into the fire.

The third category of law still remains to be considered, that relating

to the protection of the person and the detection and prevention of

“crime.” This is the most important, because most prejudices attach to

it; because, if law enjoys a certain amount of consideration, it is in

consequence of the belief that this species of law is absolutely

indispensable to the maintenance of security in our societies. These are

laws developed from the nucleus of customs useful to human communities,

which have been turned to account by rulers to sanctify their own

domination. The authority of the chiefs of tribes, of rich families in

towns, and of the king, depended upon their judicial functions, and even

down to the present day, whenever the necessity of government is spoken

of, its function as supreme judge is the thing implied. “Without a

government men would tear one another to pieces,” argues the village

orator. “The ultimate end of all government is to secure twelve honest

jurymen to every accused person,” said Burke.

Well, in spite of all the prejudices existing on this subject, it is

quite time that anarchists should boldly declare this category of laws

as useless and injurious as the preceding ones.

First of all, as to so-called “crimes” — assaults upon persons — it is

well-known that two-thirds, and often as many as three-fourths, of such

“crimes” are instigated by the desire to obtain possession of someone’s

wealth. This immense class of so-called “crimes and misdemeanours” will

disappear on the day on which private property ceases to exist. “But,”

it will be said, “there will always be brutes who will attempt the lives

of their fellow citizens, who will lay their hands to a knife in every

quarrel, and revenge the slightest offence by murder, if there are not

laws to restrain and punishments to withhold them.” This refrain is

repeated every time the right of society to punish is called in

question.

Yet there is one fact upon this head which at the present time, is

thoroughly established; the severity of punishment does not diminish the

amount of crime. Hang, and, if you like, quarter murderers, and the

number of murders will not decrease by one. On the other hand, abolish

the penalty of death, and there will not be one murder more; there will

be fewer. Statistics prove it. But if the harvest is good, and bread

cheap, and the weather fine, the number of murders immediately

decreases. This again is proved by statistics. The amount of crime

always augments and diminishes in proportion to the price of provisions

and the states of the weather. Not that all murders are actuated by

hunger. That is not the case. But when the harvest is good and

provisions are at an obtainable price, and when the sun shines, men,

lighter hearted and less miserable than usual, do not give way to gloomy

passions, do not from trivial motives, plunge a knife into the bosom of

a fellow creature.

Moreover, it is also a well-known fact that the fear of punishment has

never stopped a single murderer. He who kills his neighbour from revenge

or misery does not reason much about consequence; and there have been

few murderers who were not firmly convinced that they should escape

prosecution.

Without speaking of a society in which a man will receive a better

education, in which the development of all his faculties, and the

possibility of exercising them, will procure him so many enjoyments,

that he will not seek to poison them by remorse — without speaking of

the society of the future — even in our society, even with those sad

products of misery, whom we see to-day in the public-houses of great

cities — on the day when no punishment is inflicted upon murderers, the

number of murders will not augment by a single case; and it is extremely

probable that it will be, on the contrary, diminished by all those cases

which are due at present to habitual criminals, who have been brutalised

in prison.

We are continually being told of the benefits conferred by law, and the

beneficial effect of penalties, but have the speakers ever attempted to

strike a balance between the benefits attributed to laws and penalties,

and the degrading effect of these penalties upon humanity? Only

calculate all the evil passions awakened in mankind by the atrocious

punishments formerly inflicted in our streets! Man is the cruelest

animal upon earth; and who has pampered and developed the cruel

instincts unknown, even amongst monkeys; is it is not the king, the

judge, and the priests, armed with law, who caused flesh to be torn off

in strips, boiling pitch to be poured into wounds, limbs to be

dislocated, bones to be crushed, men to be sawn asunder to maintain

their authority? Only estimate the torrent of depravity let loose in

human society by the “informing” which is countenanced by judges, and

paid in hard cash by governments, under pretext of assisting in the

discovery of “crime.” Only go into the gaols and study what man becomes

when he is deprived of freedom and shut up with other depraved beings,

steeped in the vice and corruption which oozes from the very walls of

our existing prisons. Only remember that the more these prisons are

reformed, the more detestable they become; our model modern

penitentiaries are a hundred-fold more abominable than the dungeons of

the middle ages. Finally, consider what corruption, depravity of mind,

is kept up amongst men by the idea of obedience, the very essence of

law; of chastisement; of authority having the right to punish, to judge

irrespective of our conscience and the esteem of our friends; of the

necessity for executioners, gaolers and informers — in a word, by all

the attributes of law and authority. Consider all this, and you will

assuredly agree with us in saying that a law inflicting penalties is an

abomination which should cease to exist.

Peoples without political organisation, and therefore less depraved than

ourselves, have perfectly understood that the man who is called

“criminal” is simply unfortunate; that the remedy is not to flog him, to

chain him up, or to kill him on the scaffold or in prison, but to

relieve him by the most brotherly care, by treatment based on equality,

by the usages of life amongst honest men. In the next revolution we hope

that this cry will go forth:

“Burn the guillotine; demolish the prisons; drive away the judges,

policemen and informers — the impurest race upon the face of the earth;

treat as a brother the man who has been led by passion to do ill to his

fellow; above all take from the ignoble products of middle-class

idleness the possibility of displaying their vices in attractive

colours; and be sure that but few crimes will mar our society.”

The main supports of crime are idleness, law and authority; laws about

property, about government, laws about penalties and misdemeanours; and

authority, which takes upon itself to manufacture these laws and to

apply them.

No more laws! No more judges! Liberty, equality, and practical human

sympathy are the only effectual barriers we can oppose to the

anti-social instincts of certain amongst us.

[1] The annual assembly of the early Franks, originally held in March,

there the first month of the year.