💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › michel-foucault-the-order-of-discourse.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 12:41:57. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: The Order of Discourse
Author: Michel Foucault
Date: Dec. 2, 1970
Language: en
Topics: academics, post-structuralism, authority, authoritarianism, not-anarchist
Source: *Untying the text: a post-structuralist reader*
Notes: Translated by Ian McLeod

Michel Foucault

The Order of Discourse

I

I wish I could have slipped surreptitiously into this discourse which I

must present today, and into the ones I shall have to give here, perhaps

for many years to come. I should have prepreferred to be enveloped by

speech, and carried away well beyond all possible beginnings, rather

than have to begin it myself. I should have preferred to become aware

that a nameless voice was already speaking long before me, so that I

should only have needed to join in, to continue the sentence it had

started and lodge myself, without really being noticed, in its

interstices, as if it had signalled to me by pausing, for an instant, in

suspense. Thus there would be no beginning, and instead of being the one

from whom discourse proceeded, I should be at the mercy of its chance

unfolding, a slender gap, the point of its possible disappearance. I

should have liked there to be a voice behind me which had begun to speak

a very long time before, doubling in advance everything I am going to

say, a voice which would say: ‘You must go on, I can’t go on, you must

go on, I’ll go on, you must say words, as long as there are any, until

they find me, until they say me, strange pain, strange sin, you must go

on, perhaps it’s done already, perhaps they have said me already,

perhaps they have carried me to the threshold of my story, before the

door that opens on my story, that would surprise me, if it opens.’ I

think a good many people have a similar desire to be freed from the

obligation to begin, a similar desire to be on the other side of

discourse from the outset, without having to consider from the outside

what might be strange, frightening, and perhaps maleficent about it. To

this very common wish, the institution’s reply is ironic, since it

solemnises beginnings, surrounds them with a circle of attention and

silence, and imposes ritualised forms on them, as if to make them more

easily recognisable from a distance. Desire says: ‘I should not like to

have to enter this risky order of discourse; I should not like to be

involved in its peremptoriness and decisiveness; I should like it to be

all around me like a calm, deep transparence, infinitely open, where

others would fit in with my expectations, and from which truths would

emerge one by one; I should only have to let myself be carried, within

it and by it, like a happy wreck.’ The institution replies: ‘You should

not be afraid of beginnings; we are all here in order to show you that

discourse belongs to the order of laws, that we have long been looking

after its appearances; that a place has been made ready for it, a place

which honours it but disarms it; and that if discourse may sometimes

have some power, nevertheless it is from us and us alone that it gets

it.’ But perhaps this institution and this desire are nothing but two

contrary replies to the same anxiety: anxiety about what discourse is in

its material reality as a thing pronounced or written; anxiety about

this transitory existence which admittedly is destined to be effaced,

but according to a time-scale which is not ours; anxiety at feeling

beneath this activity (despite its greyness and ordinariness) powers and

dangers that are hard to imagine; anxiety at suspecting the struggles,

victories, injuries, dominations and enslavements, through so many words

even though long usage has worn away their roughness. What, then, is so

perilous in the fact that people speak, and that their discourse

proliferates to infinity? Where is the danger in that?

II

Here is the hypothesis which I would like to put forward tonight in

order to fix the terrain — or perhaps the very provisional theatre — of

the work I am doing: that in every society the production of discourse

is at once controlled, selected, organised and redistributed by a

certain number of procedures whose role is to ward off its powers and

dangers, to gain mastery over its chance events, to evade its ponderous,

formidable materiality. In a society like ours, the procedures of

exclusion are well known. The most obvious and familiar is the

prohibition. We know quite well that we do not have the right to say

everything, that we cannot speak of just anything in any circumstances

whatever, and that not everyone has the right to speak of anything

whatever. In the taboo on the object of speech, and the ritual of the

circumstances of speech, and the privileged or exclusive right of the

speaking subject, we have the play of three types of prohibition which

intersect, reinforce or compensate for each other, forming a complex

grid which changes constantly. I will merely note that at the present

time the regions where the grid is tightest, where the black squares are

most numerous, are those of sexuality and politics; as if discourse, far

from being that transparent or neutral element in which sexuality is

disarmed and politics pacified, is in fact one of the places where

sexuality and politics exercise in a privileged way some of their most

formidable powers. It does not matter that discourse appears to be of

little account, because the prohibitions that surround it very soon

reveal its link with desire and with power. There is nothing surprising

about that, since, as psychoanalysis has shown, discourse is not simply

that which manifests (or hides) desire — it is also the object of

desire; and since, as history constantly teaches us, discourse is not

simply that which translates struggles or systems of domination, but is

the thing for which and by which there is struggle, discourse is the

power which is to be seized. There exists in our society another

principle of exclusion, not another prohibition but a division and a

rejection. I refer to the opposition between reason and madness.2 Since

the depths of the Middle Ages, the madman has been the one whose

discourse cannot have the same currency as others. His word may be

considered null and void, having neither truth nor importance, worthless

as evidence in law, inadmissible in the authentification of deeds or

contracts, incapable even of bringing about the trans-substantiation of

bread into body at Mass. On the other hand, strange powers not held by

any other may be attributed to the madman’s speech: the power of

uttering a hidden truth, of telling the future, of seeing in all naivety

what the others’ wisdom cannot perceive. It is curious to note that for

centuries in Europe the speech of the madman was either not heard at all

or else taken for the word of truth. It either fell into the void, being

rejected as soon as it was proffered, or else people deciphered in it a

rationality, naive or crafty, which they regarded as more rational than

that of the sane. In any event, whether excluded, or secretly invested

with reason, the madman’s speech, strictly, did not exist. It was

through his words that his madness was recognised; they were the place

where the division between reason and madness was exercised, but they

were never recorded or listened to. No doctor before the end of the

eighteenth century had ever thought of finding out what was said, or how

and why it was said, in this speech which nonetheless determined the

difference. This whole immense discourse of the madman was taken for

mere noise, and he was only symbolically allowed to speak, in the

theatre, where he would step forward, disarmed and reconciled, because

there he played the role of truth in a mask. You will tell me that all

this is finished today or is coming to an end; that the madman’s speech

is no longer on the other side of the divide; that it is no longer null

and void; on the contrary, it puts us on the alert; that we now look for

a meaning in it, for the outline or the ruins of some oeuvre; and that

we have even gone so far as to come across this speech of madness in

what we articulate ourselves, in that slight stumbling by which we lose

track of what we are saying. But all this attention to the speech of

madness does not prove that the old division is no longer operative. You

have only to think of the whole framework of knowledge through which we

decipher that speech, and of the whole network of institutions which

permit someone — a doctor or a psychoanalyst — to listen to it, and

which at the same time permit the patient to bring along his poor words

or, in desperation, to withhold them. You have only to think of all this

to become suspicious that the division, far from being effaced, is

working differently, along other lines, through new institutions, and

with effects that are not at all the same. And even if the doctor’s role

were only that of lending an ear to a speech that is free at last, he

still does this listening in the context of the same division. He is

listening to a discourse which is invested with desire, and which — for

its greater exaltation or its greater anguish — thinks it is loaded with

terrible powers. If the silence of reason is required for the curing of

monsters, it is enough for that silence to be on the alert, and it is in

this that the division remains. It is perhaps risky to consider the

opposition between true and false as a third system of exclusion, along

with those just mentioned. How could one reasonably compare the

constraint of truth with divisions like those, which are arbitrary to

start with or which at least are organised around historical

contingencies; which are not only modifiable but in perpetual

displacement; which are supported by a whole system of institutions

which impose them and renew them; and which act in a constraining and

sometimes violent way? Certainly, when viewed from the level of a

proposition, on the inside of a discourse, the division between true and

false is neither arbitrary nor modifiable nor institutional nor violent.

But when we view things on a different scale, when we ask the question

of what this will to truth has been and constantly is, across our

discourses, this will to truth which has crossed so many centuries of

our history; what is, in its very general form, the type of division

which governs our will to know (notre volonte de savoir), then what we

see taking shape is perhaps something like a system of exclusion, a

historical, modifiable, and institutionally constraining system. There

is no doubt that this division is historically constituted. For the

Greek poets of the sixth century BC, the true discourse (in the strong

and valorised sense of the word), the discourse which inspired respect

and terror, and to which one had to submit because it ruled, was the one

pronounced by men who spoke as of right and according to the required

ritual; the discourse which dispensed justice and gave everyone his

share; the discourse which in prophesying the future not only announced

what was going to happen but helped to make it happen, carrying men’s

minds along with it and thus weaving itself into the fabric of destiny.

Yet already a century later the highest truth no longer resided in what

discourse was or did, but in what it said: a day came when truth was

displaced from the ritualised, efficacious and just act of enunciation,

towards the utterance itself, its meaning, its form, its object, its

relation to its reference. Between Hesiod and Plato a certain division

was established, separating true discourse from false discourse: a new

division because henceforth the true discourse is no longer precious and

desirable, since it is no longer the one linked to the exercise of

power. The sophist is banished. This historical division probably gave

our will to know its general form. However, it has never stopped

shifting: sometimes the great mutations in scientific thought can

perhaps be read as the consequences of a discovery, but they can also be

read as the appearance of new forms in the will to truth. There is

doubtless a will to truth in the nineteenth century which differs from

the will to know characteristic of Classical culture in the forms it

deploys, in the domains of objects to which it addresses itself, and in

the techniques on which it is based. To go back a little further: at the

turn of the sixteenth century (and particularly in England), there

appeared a will to know which, anticipating its actual contents,

sketched out schemas of possible, observable, measurable, classifiable

objects; a will to know which imposed on the knowing subject, and in

some sense prior to all experience, a certain position, a certain gaze

and a certain function (to see rather than to read, to verify rather

than to make commentaries on); a will to know which was prescribed (but

in a more general manner than by any specific instrument) by the

technical level where knowledges had to be invested in order to be

verifiable and useful. It was just as if, starting from the great

Platonic division, the will to truth had its own history, which is not

that of constraining truths: the history of the range of objects to be

known, of the functions and positions of the knowing subject, of the

material, technical, and instrumental investments of knowledge. This

will to truth, like the other systems of exclusion, rests on an

institutional support: it is both reinforced and renewed by whole strata

of practices, such as pedagogy, of course; and the system of books,

publishing, libraries; learned societies in the past and laboratories

now. But it is also renewed, no doubt more profoundly, by the way in

which knowledge is put to work, valorised, distributed, and in a sense

attributed, in a society. Let us recall at this point, and only

symbolically, the old Greek principle: though arithmetic may well be the

concern of democratic cities, because it teaches about the relations of

equality, geometry alone must be taught in oligarchies, since it

demonstrates the proportions within inequality. Finally, I believe that

this will to truth — leaning in this way on a support and an

institutional distribution — tends to exert a sort of pressure and

something like a power of constraint (I am still speaking of our own

society) on other discourses. I am thinking of the way in which for

centuries Western literature sought to ground itself on the natural, the

‘vraisemblable’, on sincerity, on science as well — in short, on ‘true’

discourse. I am thinking likewise of the manner in which economic

practices, codified as precepts or recipes and ultimately as morality,

have sought since the sixteenth century to ground themselves,

rationalise themselves, and justify themselves in a theory of wealth and

production. I am also thinking of the way in which a body as

prescriptive as the penal system sought its bases or its justification,

at first of course in a theory of justice, then, since the nineteenth

century, in a sociological, psychological, medical, and psychiatric

knowledge: it is as if even the word of the law could no longer be

authorised, in our society, except by a discourse of truth. Of the three

great systems of exclusion which forge discourse — the forbidden speech,

the division of madness and the will to truth. I have spoken of the

third at greatest length. The fact is that it is towards this third

system that the other two have been drifting constantly for centuries.

The third system increasingly attempts to assimilate the others, both in

order to modify them and to provide them with a foundation. The first

two are constantly becoming more fragile and more uncertain, to the

extent that they are now invaded by the will to truth, which for its

part constantly grows stronger, deeper, and more implacable. And yet we

speak of the will to truth no doubt least of all. It is as if, for us,

the will to truth and its vicissitudes were masked by truth itself in

its necessary unfolding. The reason is perhaps this: although since the

Greeks ‘true’ discourse is no longer the discourse that answers to the

demands of desire, or the discourse which exercises power, what is at

stake in the will to truth, in the will to utter this ‘true’ discourse,

if not desire and power? ‘True’ discourse, freed from desire and power

by the necessity of its form, cannot recognise the will to truth which

pervades it;3 and the will to truth, having imposed itself on us for a

very long time, is such that the truth it wants cannot fail to mask it.

Thus all that appears to our eyes is a truth conceived as a richness, a

fecundity, a gentle and insidiously universal force, and in contrast we

are unaware of the will to truth, that prodigious machinery designed to

exclude. All those who, from time to time in our history, have tried to

dodge this will to truth and to put it into question against truth, at

the very point where truth undertakes to justify the prohibition and to

define madness, all of them, from Nietzsche to Artaud and Bataille, must

now serve as the (no doubt lofty) signs for our daily work.

III

There are, of course, many other procedures for controlling and

delimiting discourse. Those of which I have spoken up to now operate in

a sense from the exterior. They function as systems of exclusion. They

have to do with the part of discourse which puts power and desire at

stake. I believe we can isolate another group: internal procedures,

since discourses themselves exercise their own control; procedures which

function rather as principles of classification, of ordering, of

distribution, as if this time another dimension of discourse had to be

mastered: that of events and chance. In the first place, commentary. I

suppose — but without being very certain — that there is scarcely a

society without its major narratives, which are recounted, repeated, and

varied; formulae, texts, and ritualised sets of discourses which are

recited in welldefined circumstances; things said once and preserved

because it is suspected that behind them there is a secret or a

treasure. In short, we may suspect that there is in all societies, with

great consistency, a kind of gradation among discourses: those which are

said in the ordinary course of days and exchanges, and which vanish as

soon as they have been pronounced; and those which give rise to a

certain number of new speech-acts which take them up, transform them or

speak of them, in short, those discourses which, over and above their

formulation, are said indefinitely, remain said, and are to be said

again. We know them in our own cultural system: they are religious or

juridical texts, but also those texts (curious ones, when we consider

their status) which are called ‘literary1; and to a certain extent,

scientific texts. This differentiation is certainly neither stable, nor

constant, nor absolute. There is not, on the one side, the category of

fundamental or creative discourses, given for all time, and on the

other, the mass of discourses which repeat, gloss, and comment. Plenty

of major texts become blurred and disappear, and sometimes commentaries

move into the primary position. But though its points of application may

change, the function remains; and the principle of a differentiation is

continuously put back in play. The radical effacement of this gradation

can only ever be play, utopia, or anguish. The Borges-style play of a

commentary which is nothing but the solemn and expected reappearance

word for word of the text that is commented on; or the play of a

criticism that would speak forever of a work which does not exist. The

lyrical dream of a discourse which is reborn absolutely new and innocent

at every point, and which reappears constantly in all freshness, derived

from things, feelings or thoughts. The anguish of that patient of

Janet’s for whom the least utterance was gospel truth, concealing

inexhaustible treasures of meaning and worthy to be repeated,

re-commenced, and commented on indefinitely: ‘When I think,’ he would

say when reading or listening, ‘when I think of this sentence which like

the others will go off into eternity, and which I have perhaps not yet

fully understood .‘4 But who can fail to see that this would be to annul

one of the terms of the relation each time, and not to do away with the

relation itself? It is a relation which is constantly changing with

time; which takes multiple and divergent forms in a given epoch. The

juridical exegesis is very different from the religious commentary (and

this has been the case for a very long time). One and the same literary

work can give rise simultaneously to very distinct types of discourse:

the ‘Odyssey’ as a primary text is repeated, in the same period, in the

translation by Berard, and in the endless ‘explications de texte’, and

in Joyce’s ‘Ulysses’. For the moment I want to do no more than indicate

that, in what is broadly called commentary, the hierarchy between

primary and secondary text plays two roles which are in solidarity with

each other. On the one hand it allows the (endless) construction of new

discourses: the dominance of the primary text, its permanence, its

status as a discourse which can always be re-actualised, the multiple or

hidden meaning with which it is credited, the essential reticence and

richness which is attributed to it, all this is the basis for an open

possibility of speaking. But on the other hand the commentary’s only

role, whatever the techniques used, is to say at last what was silently

articulated ‘beyond’, in the text. By a paradox which it always

displaces but never escapes, the commentary must say for the first time

what had, nonetheless, already been said, and must tirelessly repeat

what had, however, never been said. The infinite rippling of

commentaries is worked from the inside by the dream of a repetition in

disguise at its horizon there is perhaps nothing but what was at its

point of departure — mere recitation. Commentary exorcises the chance

element of discourse by giving it its due; it allows us to say something

other than the text itself, but on condition that it is this text itself

which is said, and in a sense completed. The open multiplicity, the

element of chance, are transferred, by the principle of commentary, from

what might risk being said, on to the number, the form, the mask, and

the circumstances of the repetition. The new thing here lies not in what

is said but in the event of its return. I believe there exists another

principle of rarefaction of a discourse, complementary to the first, to

a certain extent: the author. Not, of course, in the sense of the

speaking individual who pronounced or wrote a text, but in the sense of

a principle of grouping of discourses, conceived as the unity and origin

of their meanings, as the focus of their coherence. This principle is

not everywhere at work, nor in a constant manner: there exist all around

us plenty of discourses which circulate without deriving their meaning

or their efficacity from an author to whom they could be attributed:

everyday remarks, which are effaced immediately; decrees or contracts

which require signatories but no author; technical instructions which

are transmitted anonymously But in the domains where it is the rule to

attribute things to an author — literature, philosophy, science — it is

quite evident that this attribution does not always play the same role.

In the order of scientific discourse, it was indispensable, during the

Middle Ages, that a text should be attributed to an author, since this

was an index of truthfulness. A proposition was considered as drawing

even its scientific value from its author. Since the seventeenth

century, this function has steadily been eroded in scientific discourse:

it now functions only to give a name to a theorem, an effect, an

example, a syndrome. On the other hand, in the order of literary

discourse, starting from the same epoch, the function of the author has

steadily grown stronger: all those tales, poems, dramas or comedies

which were allowed to circulate in the Middle Ages in at least a

relative anonymity are now asked (and obliged to say) where they come

from, who wrote them. The author is asked to account for the unity of

the texts which are placed under his name. He is asked to reveal or at

least carry authentification of the hidden meaning which traverses them.

He is asked to connect them to his lived experiences, to the real

history which saw their birth. The author is what gives the disturbing

language of fiction its unities, its nodes of coherence, its insertion

in the real. I know that I will be told: ‘But you are speaking there of

the author as he is reinvented after the event by criticism, after he is

dead and there is nothing left except for a tangled mass of scribblings;

in those circumstances a little order surely has to be introduced into

all that, by imagining a project, a coherence, a thematic structure that

is demanded of the consciousness or the life of an author who is indeed

perhaps a trifle fictitious. But that does not mean he did not exist,

this real author, who bursts into the midst of all these worn-out words,

bringing to them his genius or his disorder.’ It would of course, be

absurd to deny the existence of the individual who writes and invents.

But I believe that — at least since a certain epoch — the individual who

sets out to write a text on the horizon of which a possible oeuvre is

prowling, takes upon himself the function of the author: what he writes

and what he does not write, what he sketches out, even by way of

provisional drafts, as an outline of the oeuvre, and what he lets fall

by way of commonplace remarks — this whole play of differences is

prescribed by the author-function, as he receives it from his epoch, or

as he modifies it in his turn. He may well overturn the traditional

image of the author; nevertheless, it is from some new author-position

that he will cut out, from everything he could say and from all that he

does say every day at any moment, the still trembling outline of his

oeuvre. The commentary-principle limits the chance-element in discourse

by the play of an identity which would take the form of repetition and

sameness. The author-principle limits this same element of chance by the

play of an identity which has the form of individuality and the self. We

must also recognise another principle of limitation in what is called,

not sciences but ‘disciplines’: a principle which is itself relative and

mobile; which permits construction, but within narrow confines. The

organisation of disciplines is just as much opposed to the principle of

commentary as to that of the author. It is opposed to the principle of

the author because a discipline is defined by a domain of objects, a set

of methods, a corpus of propositions considered to be true, a play of

rules and definitions, of techniques and instruments: all this

constitutes a sort of anonymous system at the disposal of anyone who

wants to or is able to use it, without their meaning or validity being

linked to the one who happened to be their inventor. But the principle

of a discipline is also opposed to that of commentary: in a discipline,

unlike a commentary, what is supposed at the outset is not a meaning

which has to be rediscovered, nor an identity which has to be repeated,

but the requisites for the construction of new statements. For there to

be a discipline, there must be the possibility of formulating new

propositions, ad infinitum. But there is more; there is more, no doubt,

in order for there to be less: a discipline is not the sum of all that

can be truthfully said about something; it is not even the set of all

that can be accepted about the same data in virtue of some principle of

coherence or systematicity. Medicine is not constituted by the total of

what can be truthfully said about illness; botany cannot be defined by

the sum of all the truths concerning plants. There are two reasons for

this: first of all, botany and medicine are made up of errors as well as

truths, like any other discipline — errors which are not residues or

foreign bodies but which have positive functions, a historical

efficacity, and a role that is often indissociable from that of the

truths. And besides, for a proposition to belong to botany or pathology,

it has to fulfil certain conditions, in a sense stricter and more

complex than pure and simple truth: but in any case, other conditions.

It must address itself to a determinate plane of objects: from the end

of the seventeenth century, for example, for a proposition to be

‘botanical’ it had to deal with the visible structure of the plant, the

system of its close and distant resemblances or the mechanism of its

fluids; it could no longer retain its symbolic value, as was the case in

the sixteenth century, nor the set of virtues and properties which were

accorded to it in antiquity. But without belonging to a discipline, a

proposition must use conceptual or technical instruments of a

well-defined type; from the nineteenth century, a proposition was no

longer medical — it fell ‘outside medicine’ and acquired the status of

an individual phantasm or popular imagery — if it used notions that were

at the same time metaphorical, qualitative, and substantial (like those

of engorgement, of overheated liquids or of dried-out solids). In

contrast it could and had to make use of notions that were equally

metaphorical but based on another model, a functional and physiological

one (that of the irritation, inflammation, or degeneration of the

tissues). Still further: in order to be part of a discipline, a

proposition has to be able to be inscribed on a certain type of

theoretical horizon: suffice it to recall that the search for the

primitive language, which was a perfectly acceptable theme up to the

eighteenth century, was sufficient, in the second half of the nineteenth

century, to make any discourse fall into — I hesitate to say error —

chimera and reverie, into pure and simple linguistic monstrosity. Within

its own limits, each discipline recognises true and false propositions;

but it pushes back a whole teratology of knowledge beyond its margins.

The exterior of a science is both more and less populated than is often

believed: there is of course immediate experience, the imaginary themes

which endlessly carry and renew immemorial beliefs; but perhaps there

are no errors in the strict sense, for error can only arise and be

decided inside a definite practice; on the other hand, there are

monsters on the prowl whose form changes with the history of knowledge.

In short, a proposition must fulfil complex and heavy requirements to be

able to belong to the grouping of a discipline; before it can be called

true or false, it must be ‘in the true’, as Canguilhem would say. People

have often wondered how the botanists or biologists of the nineteenth

century managed not to see that what Mendel was saying was true. But it

was because Mendel was speaking of objects, applying methods, and

placing himself on a theoretical horizon which were alien to the biology

of his time. Naudin, before him, had of course posited the thesis that

hereditary traits are discrete; yet, no matter how new or strange this

principle was, it was able to fit into the discourse of biology, at

least as an enigma. What Mendel did was to constitute the hereditary

trait as an absolutely new biological object, thanks to a kind of

filtering which had never been used before: he detached the trait from

the species, and from the sex which transmits it; the field in which he

observed it being the infinitely open series of the generations, where

it appears and disappears according to statistical regularities. This

was a new object which called for new conceptual instruments and new

theoretical foundations. Mendel spoke the truth, but he was not ‘within

the true’ of the biological discourse of his time: it was not according

to such rules that biological objects and concepts were formed. It

needed a complete change of scale, the deployment of a whole new range

of objects in biology for Mendel to enter into the true and for his

propositions to appear (in large measure) correct. Mendel was a true

monster, which meant that science could not speak of him; whereas about

thirty years earlier, at the height of the nineteenth century, Scheiden,

for example, who denied plant sexuality, but in accordance with the

rules of biological discourse, was merely formulating a disciplined

error. It is always possible that one might speak the truth in the space

of a wild exteriority, but one is ‘in the true’ only by obeying the

rules of a discursive ‘policing’ which one has to reactivate in each of

one’s discourses. The discipline is a principle of control over the

production of discourse. The discipline fixes limits for discourse by

the action of an identity which takes the form of a permanent

re-actuation of the rules. We are accustomed to see in an author’s

fecundity, in the multiplicity of the commentaries, and in the

development of a discipline so many infinite resources for the creation

of discourses. Perhaps so, but they are nonetheless principles of

constraint; it is very likely impossible to account for their positive

and multiplicatory role if we do not take into consideration their

restrictive and constraining function.

IV

There is, I believe, a third group of procedures which permit the

control of discourses. This time it is not a matter of mastering their

powers or averting the unpredictability of their appearance, but of

determining the condition of their application, of imposing a certain

number of rules on the individuals who hold them, and thus of not

permitting everyone to have access to them. There is a rarefaction, this

time, of the speaking subjects; none shall enter the order of discourse

if he does not satisfy certain requirements or if he is not, from the

outset, qualified to do so. To be more precise: not all the regions of

discourse are equally open and penetrable; some of them are largely

forbidden (they are differentiated and differentiating), while others

seem to be almost open to all winds and put at the disposal of every

speaking subject, without prior restrictions. In this regard I should

like to recount an anecdote which is so beautiful that one trembles at

the thought that it might be true. It gathers into a single figure all

the constraints of discourse: those which limit its powers, those which

master its aleatory appearances, those which carry out the selection

among speaking subjects. At the beginning of the seventeenth century,

the Shogun heard tell that the Europeans’ superiority in matters of

navigation, commerce, politics, and military skill was due to their

knowledge of mathematics. He desired to get hold of so precious a

knowledge. As he had been told of an English sailor who possessed the

secret of these miraculous discourses, he summoned him to his palace and

kept him there. Alone with him, he took lessons. He learned mathematics.

He retained power, and lived to a great old age. It was not until the

nineteenth century that there were Japanese mathematicians. But the

anecdote does not stop there: it has its European side too. The story

has it that this English sailor, Will Adams, was an autodidact, a

carpenter who had learnt geometry in the course of working in a

shipyard. Should we see this story as the expression of one of the great

myths of European culture? The universal communication of knowledge and

the infinite free exchange of discourses in Europe, against the

monopolised and secret knowledge of Oriental tyranny? This idea, of

course, does not stand up to examination. Exchange and communication are

positive figures working inside complex systems of restriction, and

probably would not be able to function independently of them. The most

superficial and visible of these systems of restriction is constituted

by what can be gathered under the name of ritual. Ritual defines the

qualification which must be possessed by individuals who speak (and who

must occupy such-and-such a position and formulate suchand-such a type

of statement, in the play of a dialogue, of interrogation or

recitation); it defines the gestures, behaviour, circumstances, and the

whole set of signs which must accompany discourse; finally, it fixes the

supposed or imposed efficacity of the words, their effect on those to

whom they are addressed, and the limits of their constraining value.

Religious, judicial, therapeutic , and in large measure also political

discourses can scarcely be dissociated from this deployment of a ritual

which determines both the particular properties and the stipulated roles

of the speaking subjects. A somewhat different way of functioning is

that of the ‘societies of discourse’, which function to preserve or

produce discourses, but in order to make them circulate in a closed

space, distributing them only according to strict rules, and without the

holders being dispossessed by this distribution. An archaic model for

this is provided by the groups of rhapsodists who possessed the

knowledge of the poems to be recited or potentially to be varied and

transformed. But though the object of this knowledge was after all a

ritual recitation, the knowledge was protected, defended and preserved

within a definite group by the often very complex exercises of memory

which it implied. To pass an apprenticeship in it allowed one to enter

both a group and a secret which the act of recitation showed but did not

divulge; the roles of speaker and listener were not interchangeable.

There are hardly any such ‘societies of discourse’ now, with their

ambiguous play of the secret and its divulgation. But this should not

deceive us: even in the order of ‘true’ discourse, even in the order of

discourse that is published and free from all ritual, there are still

forms of appropriation of secrets, and non-interchangeable roles. It may

well be that the act of writing as it is institutionalised today, in the

book, the publishingsystem and the person of the writer, takes place in

a ‘society of discourse’, which though diffuse is certainly

constraining. The difference between the writer and any other speaking

or writing subject (a difference constantly stressed by the writer

himself), the intransitive nature (according to him) of his discourse,

the fundamental singularity which he has been ascribing for so long to

‘writing’, the dissymmetry that is asserted between ‘creation’ and any

use of the linguistic system — all this shows the existence of a certain

‘society of discourse’, and tends moreover to bring back its play of

practices. But there are many others still, functioning according to

entirely different schemas of exclusivity and disclosure: e.g.,

technical or scientific secrets, or the forms of diffusion and

circulation of medical discourse, or those who have appropriated the

discourse of politics or economics. At first glance, the ‘doctrines’

(religious, political, philosophical) seem to constitute the reverse of

a ‘society of discourse’, in which the number of speaking individuals

tended to be limited even if it was not fixed; between those

individuals, the discourse could circulate and be transmitted. Doctrine,

on the contrary, tends to be diffused, and it is by the holding in

common of one and the same discursive ensemble that individuals (as many

as one cares to imagine) define their reciprocal allegiance. In

appearance, the only prerequisite is the recognition of the same truths

and the acceptance of a certain rule of (more or less flexible)

conformity with the validated discourses. If doctrines were nothing more

than this, they would not be so very different from scientific

disciplines, and the discursive control would apply only to the form or

the content of the statement, not to the speaking subject. But doctrinal

allegiance puts in question both the statement and the speaking subject,

the one by the other. It puts the speaking subject in question through

and on the basis of the statement, as is proved by the procedures of

exclusion and the mechanisms of rejection which come into action when a

speaking subject has formulated one or several unassimilable statements;

heresy and orthodoxy do not derive from a fanatical exaggeration of the

doctrinal mechanisms, but rather belong fundamentally to them. And

conversely the doctrine puts the statements in question on the basis of

the speaking subjects, to the extent that the doctrine always stands as

the sign, manifestation and instrument of a prior adherence to a class,

a social status, a race, a nationality, an interest, a revolt, a

resistance or an acceptance. Doctrine binds individuals to certain types

of enunciation and consequently forbids them all others; but it uses, in

return, certain types of enunciation to bind individuals amongst

themselves, and to differentiate them by that very fact from all others.

Doctrine brings about a double subjection: of the speaking subjects to

discourses, and of discourses to the (at least virtual) group of

speaking individuals. On a much broader scale, we are obliged to

recognise large cleavages in what might be called the social

appropriation of discourses. Although education may well be, by right,

the instrument thanks to which any individual in a society like ours can

have access to any kind of discourse whatever, this does not prevent it

from following, as is well known, in its distribution, in what it allows

and what it prevents, the lines marked out by social distances,

oppositions and struggles. Any system of education is a political way of

maintaining or modifying the appropriation of discourses, along with the

knowledges and powers which they carry. I am well aware that it is very

abstract to separate speechrituals, societies of discourse, doctrinal

groups and social appropriations, as I have just done. Most of the time,

they are linked to each other and constitute kinds of great edifices

which ensure the distribution of speaking subjects into the different

types of discourse and the appropriation of discourses to certain

categories of subject. Let us say, in a word, that those are the major

procedures of subjection used by discourse. What, after all, is an

education system, other than a ritualisation of speech, a qualification

and a fixing of the roles for speaking subjects, the constitution of a

doctrinal group, however diffuse, a distribution and an appropriation of

discourse with its powers and knowledges? What is ‘ecriture’ (the

writing of the ‘writers’) other than a similar system of subjection,

which perhaps takes slightly different forms, but forms whose main

rhythms are analogous? Does not the judicial system, does not the

institutional system of medicine likewise constitute, in some of their

aspects at least, similar systems of subjection of and by discourse?

V

I wonder whether a certain number of themes in philosophy have not come

to correspond to these activities of limitation and exclusion , and

perhaps also to reinforce them. They correspond to them first of all by

proposing an ideal truth as the law of discourse and an immanent

rationality as the principle of their unfolding, and they re-introduce

an ethic of knowledge, which promises to give the truth only to the

desire for truth itself and only to the power of thinking it. Then they

reinforce the limitations and exclusions by a denial of the specific

reality of discourse in general. Ever since the sophists’ tricks and

influence were excluded and since their paradoxes have been more or less

safely muzzled, it seems that Western thought has taken care to ensure

that discourse should occupy the smallest possible space between thought

and speech. Western thought seems to have made sure that the act of

discoursing should appear to be no more than a certain bridging (apport)

between thinking and speaking — a thought dressed in its signs and made

visible by means of words, or conversely the very structures of language

put into action and producing a meaning-effect. This very ancient

elision of the reality of discourse in philosophical thought has taken

many forms in the course of history. We have seen it again quite

recently in the guise of several familiar themes. Perhaps the idea of

the founding subject is a way of eliding the reality of discourse. The

founding subject, indeed, is given the task of directly animating the

empty forms of language with his aims; it is he who in moving through

the density and inertia of empty things grasps by intuition the meaning

lying deposited within them; it is likewise the founding subject who

founds horizons of meaning beyond time which history will henceforth

only have to elucidate and where propositions, sciences and deductive

ensembles will find their ultimate grounding. In his relation to

meaning, the founding subject has at his disposal signs, marks, traces,

letters. But he does not need to pass via the singular instance of

discourse in order to manifest them. The opposing theme, that of

originating experience, plays an analogous role. It supposes that at the

very basis of experience, even before it could be grasped in the form of

a cogito, there were prior significations — in a sense, already said —

wandering around in the world, arranging it all around us and opening it

up from the outset to a sort of primitive recognition. Thus a primordial

complicity with the world is supposed to be the foundation of our

possibility of speaking of it, in it, of indicating it and naming it, of

judging it and ultimately of knowing it in the form of truth. If there

is discourse, then, what can it legitimately be other than a discreet

reading? Things are already murmuring meanings which our language has

only to pick up; and this language, right from its most rudimentary

project, was already speaking to us of a being of which it is like the

skeleton. The idea of universal mediation is yet another way, I believe,

of eliding the reality of discourse, and despite appearances to the

contrary. For it would seem at first glance that by rediscovering

everywhere the movement of a logos which elevates particularities to the

status of concepts and allows immediate consciousness to unfurl in the

end the whole rationality of the world, one puts discourse itself at the

centre of one’s speculation. But this logos, in fact, is only a

discourse that has already been held, or rather it is things themselves,

and events, which imperceptibly turn themselves into discourse as they

unfold the secret of their own essence. Thus discourse is little more

than the gleaming of a truth in the process of being born to its own

gaze; and when everything finally can take the form of discourse, when

everything can be said and when discourse can be spoken about

everything, it is because all things, having manifested and exchanged

their meaning, can go back into the silent interiority of their

consciousness of self. Thus in a philosophy of the founding subject, in

a philosophy of originary experience, and in a philosophy of universal

mediation alike, discourse is no more than a play, of writing in the

first case, of reading in the second, and of exchange in the third, and

this exchange, this reading, this writing never put anything at stake

except signs. In this way, discourse is annulled in its reality and put

at the disposal of the signifier. What civilisation has ever appeared to

be more respectful of discourse than ours? Where has it ever been more

honoured, or better honoured? Where has it ever been, seemingly, more

radically liberated from its constraints, and universalised? Yet it

seems to me that beneath this apparent veneration of discourse, under

this apparent logophilia, a certain fear is hidden. It is just as if

prohibitions, barriers, thresholds and limits had been set up in order

to master, at least partly, the great proliferation of discourse, in

order to remove from its richness the most dangerous part, and in order

to organise its disorder according to figures which dodge what is most

uncontrollable about it. It is as if we had tried to efface all trace of

its irruption into the activity of thought and language. No doubt there

is in our society, and, I imagine, in all others, but following a

different outline and different rhythms, a profound logophobia, a sort

of mute terror against these events, against this mass of things said,

against the surging-up of all these statements, against all that could

be violent, discontinuous, pugnacious, disorderly as well, and perilous

about them — against this great incessant and disordered buzzing of

discourse. And if we want to — I would not say, efface this fear, but —

analyse it in its conditions, its action and its effects, we must, I

believe, resolve to take three decisions which our thinking today tends

to resist and which correspond to the three groups of functions which I

have just mentioned: we must call into question our will to truth,

restore to discourse its character as an event, and finally throw off

the sovereignty of the signifier.

VI

These are the tasks, or rather some of the themes, which govern the work

I should like to do here in the coming years. We can see at once certain

methodological requirements which they imply. First of all, a principle

of reversal: where tradition sees the source of discourses, the

principle of their swarming abundance and of their continuity, in those

figures which seem to play a positive role, e.g. , those of the author,

the discipline, the will to truth, we must rather recognise the negative

action of a cutting-up and a rarefaction of discourse. But once we have

noticed these principles of rarefaction, once we have ceased to consider

them as a fundamental and creative instance, what do we discover

underneath them? Must we admit the virtual plenitude of a world of

uninterrupted discourses? This is where we have to bring other

methodological principles into play. A principle of discontinuity, then:

the fact that there are systems of rarefaction does not mean that

beneath them or beyond them there reigns a vast unlimited discourse,

continuous and silent, which is quelled and repressed by them, and which

we have the task of raising up by restoring the power of speech to it.

We must not imagine that there is a great unsaid or a great unthought

which runs throughout the world and intertwines with all its forms and

all its events, and which we would have to articulate or to think at

last. Discourses must be treated as discontinuous practices, which cross

each other, are sometimes juxtaposed with one another, but can just as

well exclude or be unaware of each other. A principle of specificity: we

must not resolve discourse into a play of pre-existing significations;

we must not imagine that the world turns towards us a legible face which

we would have only to decipher; the world is not the accomplice of our

knowledge; there is no prediscursive providence which disposes the world

in our favour. We must conceive discourse as a violence which we do to

things, or in any case as a practice which we impose on them; and it is

in this practice that the events of discourse find the principle of

their regularity. The fourth rule is that of exteriority: we must not go

from discourse towards its interior, hidden nucleus, towards the heart

of a thought or a signification supposed to be manifested in it; but, on

the basis of discourse itself, its appearance and its regularity, go

towards its external conditions of possibility, towards what gives rise

to the aleatory series of these events, and fixes its limits. Four

notions, then, must serve as the regulating principle of the analysis:

the event, the series, the regularity, the condition of possibility.

Term for term we find the notion of event opposed to that of creation,

series opposed to unity, regularity opposed to originality, and

condition of possibility opposed to signification. These other four

notions (signification, originality, unity, creation) have in a general

way dominated the traditional history of ideas, where by common

agreement one sought the point of creation, the unity of a work, an

epoch or a theme, the mark of individual originality, and the infinite

treasure of buried significations. I will add only two remarks. One

concerns history. It is often entered to the credit of contemporary

history that it removed the privileges once accorded to the singular

event and revealed the structures of longer duration. That is so.

However, I am not sure that the work of these historians was exactly

done in this direction. Or rather I do not think there is an inverse

ratio between noticing the event and analysing the long durations. On

the contrary, it seems to be by pushing to its extreme the fine grain of

the event, by stretching the resolution-power of historical analysis as

far as official price-lists (les mercuriales), title deeds, parish

registers, harbour archives examined year by year and week by week, that

these historians saw — beyond the battles, decrees, dynasties or

assemblies — the outline of massive phenomena with a range of a hundred

or many hundreds of years. History as practised today does not turn away

from events; on the contrary, it is constantly enlarging their field,

discovering new layers of them, shallower or deeper. It is constantly

isolating new sets of them, in which they are sometimes numerous, dense

and interchangeable, sometimes rare and decisive: from the almost daily

variations in price to inflations over a hundred years. But the

important thing is that history does not consider an event without

defining the series of which it is part, without specifying the mode of

analysis from which that series derives, without seeking to find out the

regularity of phenomena and the limits of probability of their

emergence, without inquiring into the variations, bends and angles of

the graph, without wanting to determine the conditions on which they

depend. Of course, history has for a long time no longer sought to

understand events by the action of causes and effects in the formless

unity of a great becoming, vaguely homogeneous or ruthlessly

hierarchised; but this change was not made in order to rediscover prior

structures, alien and hostile to the event. It was made in order to

establish diverse series, intertwined and often divergent but not

autonomous, which enable us to circumscribe the ‘place’ of the event,

the margins of its chance variability, and the conditions of its

appearance. The fundamental notions which we now require are no longer

those of consciousness and continuity (with their correlative problems

of freedom and causality), nor any longer those of sign and structure.

They are those of the event and the series, along with the play of the

notions which are linked to them: regularity, dimension of chance

(alea), discontinuity, dependence, transformation; it is by means of a

set of notions like this that my projected analysis of discourses is

articulated, not on the traditional thematics which the philosophers of

yesterday still take for ‘living’ history, but on the effective work of

historians. Yet it is also in this regard that this analysis poses

philosophical, or theoretical, problems, and very likely formidable

ones. If discourses must be treated first of all as sets of discursive

events, what status must be given to that notion of event which was so

rarely taken into consideration by philosophers? Naturally the event is

neither substance nor accident, neither quality nor process; the event

is not of the order of bodies. And yet it is not something immaterial

either; it is always at the level of materiality that it takes effect,

that it is effect; it has its locus and it consists in the relation, the

coexistence, the dispersion, the overlapping, the accumulation, and the

selection of material elements. It is not the act or the property of a

body; it is produced as an effect of, and within, a dispersion of

matter. Let us say that the philosophy of the event should move in the

at first sight paradoxical direction of a materialism of the

incorporeal. Furthermore, if discursive events must be treated along the

lines of homogeneous series which, however, are discontinuous in

relation to each other, what status must be given to this discontinuity?

It is of course not a matter of the succession of instants in time, nor

of the plurality of different thinking subjects. It is a question of

caesurae which break up the instant and disperse the subject into a

plurality of possible positions and functions. This kind of

discontinuity strikes and invalidates the smallest units that were

traditionally recognised and which are the hardest to contest: the

instant and the subject. Beneath them, and independently of them, we

must conceive relations between these discontinuous series which are not

of the order of succession (or simultaneity) within one (or several)

consciousnesses; we must elaborate — outside of the philosophies of the

subject and of time — a theory of discontinuous systematicities.

Finally, though it is true that these discontinuous discursive series

each have, within certain limits, their regularity, it is undoubtedly no

longer possible to establish links of mechanical causality or of ideal

necessity between the elements which constitute them. We must accept the

introduction of the alea as a category in the production of events.

There once more we feel the absence of a theory enabling us to think the

relations between chance and thought. The result is that the narrow gap

which is to be set to work in the history of ideas, and which consists

of dealing not with the representations which might be behind discourse,

but with discourses as regular and distinct series of events — this

narrow gap looks, I’m afraid, like a small (and perhaps odious) piece of

machinery which would enable us to introduce chance, the discontinuous,

and materiality at the very roots of thought. This is a triple peril

which a certain form of history tries to exorcise by narrating the

continuous unravelling of an ideal necessity. They are three notions

that should allow us to connect the history of systems of thought to the

practice of historians. And they are three directions which the work of

theoretical elaboration will have to follow.

VII

The analyses which I propose to make, following these principles and

making this horizon my line of reference, will fall into two sets. On

the one hand the ‘critical’ section, which will put into practice the

principle of reversal: trying to grasp the forms of exclusion, of

limitation, of appropriation of which I was speaking just now; showing

how they are formed, in response to what needs, how they have been

modified and displaced, what constraint they have effectively exerted,

to what extent they have been evaded. On the other hand there is the

‘genealogical’ set, which puts the other three principles to work: how

did series of discourses come to be formed, across the grain of, in

spite of, or with the aid of these systems of constraints; what was the

specific norm of each one, and what were their conditions of appearance,

growth, variation. First, the critical set. A first group of analyses

might deal with what I have designated as functions of exclusion. I

formerly studied one of them, in respect of one determinate period: the

divide between madness and reason in the classical epoch. Later, I might

try to analyse a system of prohibition of language, the one concerning

sexuality from the sixteenth to the nineteenth century. The aim would be

to see not how this interdiction has been progressively and fortunately

effaced, but how it has been displaced and re-articulated from a

practice of confession in which the forbidden behaviour was named,

classified, hierarchised in the most explicit way, up to the appearance,

at first very timid and belated, of sexual thematics in

nineteenth-century medicine and psychiatry; of course these are still

only somewhat symbolic orientation-points, but one could already wager

that the rhythms are not the ones we think, and the prohibitions have

not always occupied the place that we imagine. In the immediate future,

I should like to apply myself to the third system of exclusion; this I

envisage in two ways. On the one hand, I want to try to discover how

this choice of truth, inside which we are caught but which we

ceaselessly renew, was made — but also how it was repeated, renewed, and

displaced. I will consider first the epoch of the Sophists at its

beginning, with Socrates, or at least with Platonic philosophy, to see

how efficacious discourse, ritual discourse, discourse loaded with

powers and perils, gradually came to conform to a division between true

and false discourse. Then I will consider the turn of the sixteenth

century, at the time when there appears, especially in England, a

science of the gaze, of observation, of the established fact, a certain

natural philosophy, no doubt inseparable from the setting-up of new

political structures, and, inseparable, too, from religious ideology;

this was without a doubt a new form of the will to know. Finally, the

third orientation-point will be the beginning of the nineteenth century,

with its great acts that founded modern science, the formation of an

industrial society and the positivist ideology which accompanied it.

These will be my three cross-sections in the morphology of our will to

know, three stages of our philistinism. I would also like to take up the

same question again, but from a quite different angle: to measure the

effect of a discourse with scientific claims — a medical, psychiatric,

and also sociological discourse — on that set of practices and

prescriptive discourses constituted by the penal system. The starting

point and basic material for this analysis will be the study of

psychiatric expertise and its role in penal practices. Still looking at

it from this critical perspective, but at another level, the procedures

of limitation of discourses should be analysed. I indicated several of

these just now: the principle of the author, of commentary, of the

discipline. A certain number of studies can be envisaged from this

perspective. I am thinking, for example, of an analysis of the history

of medicine from the sixteenth to the nineteenth century. The objective

would be not so much to pinpoint the discoveries made or the concepts

put to work, but to grasp how, in the construction of medical discourse,

and also in the whole institution that supports, transmits and

reinforces it, the principle of the author, of the commentary, and of

the discipline were used. The analysis would seek to find out how the

principle of the great author operated: Hippocrates and Galen, of

course, but also Paracelsus, Sydenham, or Boerhaave. It would seek to

find out how the practice of the aphorism and the commentary were

carried on, even late into the nineteenth century, and how they

gradually gave place to the practice of the case, of the collection of

cases, of the clinical apprenticeship using a concrete case. It would

seek to discover, finally, according to what model medicine tried to

constitute itself as a discipline, leaning at first on natural history,

then on anatomy and biology. One could also consider the way in which

literary criticism and literary history in the eighteenth and nineteenth

centuries constituted the person of the author and the figure of the

oeuvre, using, modifying, and displacing the procedures of religious

exegesis, biblical criticism, hagiography, historical or legendary

‘lives’, autobiography, and memoirs. One day we will also have to study

the role played by Freud in psychoanalytic knowledge, which is surely

very different from that of Newton in physics (and of all founders of

disciplines), and also very different from the role that can be played

by an author in the field of philosophical discourse (even if, like

Kant, he is at the origin of a different way of philosophising). So

there are some projects for the critical side of the task, for the

analysis of the instances of discursive control. As for the genealogical

aspect, it will concern the effective formation of discourse either

within the limits of this control, or outside them, or more often on

both sides of the boundary at once. The critical task will be to analyse

the processes of rarefaction, but also of regrouping and unification of

discourses; genealogy will study their formation, at once dispersed,

discontinuous, and regular. In truth these two tasks are never

completely separable: there are not, on one side, the forms of

rejection, exclusion, regrouping and attribution, and then on the other

side, at a deeper level, the spontaneous surging-up of discourses which,

immediately before or after their manifestation, are submitted to

selection and control. The regular formation of discourse can

incorporate the procedures of control, in certain conditions and to a

certain extent (that is what happens, for instance, when a discipline

takes on the form and status of a scientific discourse); and conversely

the figures of control can take shape within a discursive formation (as

is the case with literary criticism as the discourse that constitutes

the author): so much so that any critical task, putting in question the

instances of control, must at the same time analyse the discursive

regularities through which they are formed; and any genealogical

description must take into account the limits which operate in real

formations. The difference between the critical and the genealogical

enterprise is not so much a difference of object or domain, but of point

of attack, perspective, and delimitation. Earlier on I mentioned one

possible study, that of the taboos which affect the discourse of

sexuality. It would be difficult, and in any case abstract, to carry out

this study without analysing at the same time the sets of discourses —

literary, religious or ethical, biological or medical, juridical too —

where sexuality is discussed, and where it is named, described,

metaphorised, explained, judged. We are very far from having constituted

a unitary and regular discourse of sexuality; perhaps we never will, and

perhaps it is not in this direction that we are going. No matter. The

taboos do not have the same form and do not function in the same way in

literary discourse and in medical discourse, in that of psychiatry or in

that of the direction of conscience. Conversely, these different

discursive regularities do not have the same way of reinforcing,

evading, or displacing the taboos. So the study can be done only

according to pluralities of series in which there are taboos at work

which are at least partly different in each. One could also consider the

series of discourses which in the sixteenth and seventeeth centuries

dealt with wealth and poverty, money, production, commerce. We are

dealing there with sets of very heterogeneous statements, formulated by

the rich and the poor, the learned and the ignorant, protestants and

catholics, officers of the king, traders or moralists. Each one has its

own form of regularity, likewise its own systems of constraint. None of

them exactly prefigures that other form of discursive regularity which

will later take on the air of a discipline and which will be called ‘the

analysis of wealth’, then ‘political economy’. Yet it is on the basis of

this series that a new regularity was formed, taking up or excluding,

justifying or brushing aside this one or that one of their utterances.

We can also conceive of a study which would deal with the discourses

concerning heredity, such as we can find them, up to the beginning of

the twentieth century, scattered and dispersed through various

disciplines, observations, techniques and formulae. The task would then

be to show by what play of articulation these series in the end

recomposed themselves, in the epistemologically coherent and

institutionally recognised figure of genetics. This is the work that has

just been done by Francois Jacob with a brilliance and an erudition

which could not be equalled. Thus the critical and the genealogical

descriptions must alternate, and complement each other, each supporting

the other by turns. The critical portion of the analysis applies to the

systems that envelop discourse, and tries to identify and grasp these

principles of sanctioning, exclusion, and scarcity of discourse. Let us

say, playing on words, that it practises a studied casualness. The

genealogical portion, on the other hand, applies to the series where

discourse is effectively formed: it tries to grasp it in its power of

affirmation, by which I mean not so much a power which would be opposed

to that of denying, but rather the power to constitute domains of

objects, in respect of which one can affirm or deny true or false

propositions. Let us call these domains of objects positivities, and let

us say, again playing on words, that if the critical style is that of

studious casualness, the genealogical mood will be that of a happy

positivism. In any event, one thing at least has to be emphasised:

discourse analysis understood like this does not reveal the universality

of a meaning, but brings to light the action of imposed scarcity, with a

fundamental power of affirmation. Scarcity and affirmation; ultimately,

scarcity of affirmation, and not the continuous generosity of meaning,

and not the monarchy of the signifier. And now, let those with gaps in

their vocabulary say — if they find the term more convenient than

meaningful — that all this is structuralism.

VIII

I know that but for the aid of certain models and supports I would not

have been able to undertake these researches which I have tried to

sketch out for you. I believe I am greatly indebted to Georges Dumezl,

since it was he who urged me to work, at an age when I still thought

that to write was a pleasure. But I also owe a great deal to his work.

May he forgive me if I have stretched the meaning or departed from the

rigour of those texts which are his and which dominate us today. It was

he who taught me to analyse the internal economy of a discourse in a

manner quite different from the methods of traditional exegesis or

linguistic formalism. It was he who taught me to observe the system of

functional correlations between discourses by the play of comparisons

from one to the other. It was he who taught me how to describe the

transformations of a discourse and its relations to institutions. If I

have tried to apply this method to discourses quite different from

legendary or mythical narratives, it was probably because I had in front

of me the works of the historians of science, especially Georges

Canguilhem. It is to him that I owe the insight that the history of

science is not necessarily caught in an alternative: either to chronicle

discoveries or to describe the ideas and opinions that border science on

the side of its indeterminate genesis or on the side of its later

expulsions, but that it was possible and necessary to write the history

of science as a set of theoretical models and conceptual instruments

which is both coherent and transformable. But I consider that my

greatest debt is to Jean Hyppolite. I am well aware that in the eyes of

many his work belongs under the aegis of Hegel, and that our entire

epoch, whether in logic or epistemology, whether in Marx or Nietzsche,

is trying to escape from Hegel: and what I have tried to say just now

about discourse is very unfaithful to the Hegelian logos. But to make a

real escape from Hegel presupposes an exact appreciation of what it

costs to detach ourselves from him. It presupposes a knowledge of how

close Hegel has come to us, perhaps insidiously. It presupposes a

knowledge of what is still Hegelian in that which allows us to think

against Hegel; and an ability to gauge how much our resources against

him are perhaps still a ruse which he is using against us, and at the

end of which he is waiting for us, immobile and elsewhere. If so many of

us are indebted to Jean Hyppolite, it is because he tirelessly explored,

for us and ahead of us, this path by which one gets away from Hegel,

establishes a distance, and by which one ends up being drawn back to

him, but otherwise, and then constrained to leave him once again. First

of all Jean Hyppolite took the trouble to give a presence to the great

and somewhat ghostly shadow of Hegel which had been on the prowl since

the nineteenth century and with which people used to wrestle obscurely.

It was by means of a translation (of the ‘Phenomenology of Mind’) that

he gave Hegel this presence. And the proof that Hegel himself is well

and truly present in this French text is the fact that even Germans have

consulted it so as to understand better what, for a moment at least, was

going on in the German version. Jean Hyppolite sought and followed all

the ways out of this text, as if his concern was: can we still

philosophise where Hegel is no longer possible? Can a philosophy still

exist and yet not be Hegelian? Are the non-Hegelian elements in our

thought also necessarily non-philosophical? And is the

anti-philosophical necessarily non-Hegelian? So that he was not merely

trying to give a meticulous historical description of this presence of

Hegel: he wanted to make it into one of modernity’s schemata of

experience (is it possible to think science, history, politics and

everyday suffering in the Hegelian mode?); and conversely he wanted to

make our modernity the test of Hegelianism and thereby of philosophy.

For him the relation to Hegel was the site of an experiment , a

confrontation from which he was never sure that philosophy would emerge

victorious. He did not use the Hegelian system as a reassuring universe;

he saw in it the extreme risk taken by philosophy. Hence, I believe, the

displacements he carried out, not so much within Hegelian philosophy but

upon it, and upon philosophy as Hegel conceived it. Hence also a whole

inversion of themes. Instead of conceiving philosophy as the totality at

last capable of thinking itself and grasping itself in the movement of

the concept, Jean Hyppolite made it into a task without end set against

an infinite horizon: always up early, his philosophy was never ready to

finish itself. A task without end, and consequently a task forever

re-commenced, given over to the form and the paradox of repetition:

philosophy as the inaccessible thought of the totality was for Jean

Hyppolite the most repeatable thing in the extreme irregularity of

experience; it was what is given and taken away as a question endlessly

taken up again in life, in death, in memory. In this way he transformed

the Hegelian theme of the closure on to the consciousness of self into a

theme of repetitive interrogation. But philosophy, being repetition, was

not ulterior to the concept; it did not have to pursue the edifice of

abstraction, it had always to hold itself back, break with its acquired

generalities and put itself back in contact with nonphilosophy. It had

to approach most closely not the thing that completes it but the thing

that precedes it, that is not yet awakened to its disquiet. It had to

take up the singularity of history, the regional rationalities of

science, the depth of memory within consciousness — not in order to

reduce them but in order to think them. Thus there appears the theme of

a philosophy that is present, disquieted, mobile all along its line of

contact with non-philosophy, yet existing only by means of

non-philosophy and revealing the meaning it has for us. If philosophy is

in this repeated contact with non-philosophy, what is the beginning of

philosophy? Is philosophy already there, secretly present in what is not

itself, starting to formulate itself half-aloud in the murmur of things?

But then perhaps philosophical discourse no longer has a raison d’etre;

or must it begin from a foundation that is at once arbitrary and

absolute? In this way the Hegelian theme of the movement proper to the

immediate is replaced by that of the foundation of philosophical

discourse and its formal structure. And finally the last displacement

that Jean Hyppolite carried out on Hegelian philosophy: if philosophy

must begin as an absolute discourse, what about history? And what is

this beginning which begins with a single individual, in a society, in a

social class, and in the midst of struggles? These five displacements,

leading to the extreme edge of Hegelian philosophy, and no doubt pushing

it over on to the other side of its own limits, summon up one by one the

great figures of modern philosophy, whom Hyppolite never ceased

confronting with Hegel: Marx with the questions of history, Fichte with

the problem of the absolute beginning of philosophy, Bergson with the

theme of contact with the non-philosophical, Kierkegaard with the

problem of repetition and truth, Husserl with the theme of philosophy as

an infinite task linked to the history of our rationality. And beyond

these philosophical figures we perceive all the domains of knowledge

that Jean Hyppolite invoked around his own questions: psychoanalysis

with the strange logic of desire; mathematics and the formalisation of

discourse; informationtheory and its application in the analysis of

living beings; in short, all those domains about which one can ask the

question of a logic and an existence which never stop tying and untying

their bonds. I believe that Hyppolite’s work, articulated in several

major books, but invested even more in his researches, in his teaching,

in his perpetual attention, in his constant alertness and generosity ,

in his responsibilities which were apparently administrative and

pedagogic but in reality doubly political, came upon and formulated the

most fundamental problems of our epoch. There are many of us who owe him

an infinite debt. It is because I have no doubt borrowed from him the

meaning and possibility of what I am doing, and because he very often

gave me illumination when I was working in the dark, that I wanted to

place my work under his sign, and that I wanted to conclude this

presentation of my plans by evoking him. It is in his direction, towards

this lack — in which I feel both his absence and my own inadequacy —

that my questionings are now converging. Since I owe him so much, I can

well see that in choosing to invite me to teach here, you are in large

part paying homage to him. I am grateful to you, profoundly grateful,

for the honour that you have done me, but I am no less grateful for the

part he plays in this choice. Though I do not feel equal to the task of

succeeding him, I know that, on the other hand, if such a happiness

could have been granted us tonight, he would have encouraged me by his

indulgence. And now I understand better why I found it so difficult to

begin just now. I know now whose voice it was that I would have liked to

precede me, to carry me, to invite me to speak, to lodge itself in my

own discourse. I know what was so terrifying about beginning to speak,

since I was doing so in this place where I once listened to him, and

where he is no longer here to hear me.