💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › john-zerzan-the-case-against-art.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 11:40:16. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: The Case Against Art
Author: John Zerzan
Language: en
Topics: anti-civ, art
Source: Retrieved on 11th February, 2009 from http://www.primitivism.com/case-art.htm

John Zerzan

The Case Against Art

Art is always about “something hidden.” But does it help us connect with

that hidden something? I think it moves us away from it.

During the first million or so years as reflective beings, humans seem

to have created no art. As Jameson put it, art had no place in that

“unfallen social reality” because there was no need for it. Though tools

were fashioned with an astonishing economy of effort and perfection of

form, the old cliche about the aesthetic impulse as one of the

irreducible components of the human mind is invalid.

The oldest enduring works of art are hand-prints, produced by pressure

or blown pigment — a dramatic token of direct impress on nature. Later

in the Upper Paleolithic era, about 30,000 years ago, commenced the

rather sudden appearance of the cave art associated with names like

Altamira and Lascaux. These images of animals possess an often

breathtaking vibrancy and naturalism, though concurrent sculpture, such

as the widely-found “venus” statuettes of women, was quite stylized.

Perhaps this indicates that domestication of people was to precede

domestication of nature. Significantly, the “sympathetic magic” or

hunting theory of earliest art is now waning in the light of evidence

that nature was bountiful rather than threatening.

The veritable explosion of art at this time bespeaks an anxiety not felt

before: in Worringer’s words, “creation in order to subdue the torment

of perception.” Here is the appearance of the symbolic, as a moment of

discontent. It was a social anxiety; people felt something precious

slipping away. The rapid development of the earliest ritual or ceremony

parallels the birth of art, and we are reminded of the earliest ritual

re-enactments of the moment of “the beginning,” the primordial paradise

of the timeless present. Pictorial representation roused the belief in

controlling loss, the belief in coercion itself.

And we see the earliest evidence of symbolic division, as with the

half-human, half-beast stone faces at El Juyo. The world is divided into

opposing forces, by which binary distinction the contrast of culture and

nature begins and a productionist, hierarchical society is perhaps

already prefigured.

The perceptual order itself, as a unity, starts to break down in

reflection of an increasingly complex social order. A hierarchy of

senses, with the visual steadily more separate from the others and

seeking its completion in artificial images such as cave paintings,

moves to replace the full simultaneity of sensual gratification.

LĂ©vi-Strauss discovered, to his amazement, a tribal people that had been

able to see Venus in daytime; but not only were our faculties once so

very acute, they were also not ordered and separate. Part of training

sight to appreciate the objects of culture was the accompanying

repression of immediacy in an intellectual sense: reality was removed in

favor of merely aesthetic experience. Art anesthetizes the sense organs

and removes the natural world from their purview. This reproduces

culture, which can never compensate for the disability.

Not surprisingly, the first signs of a departure from those egalitarian

principles that characterized hunter-gatherer life show up now. The

shamanistic origin of visual art and music has been often remarked, the

point here being that the artist-shaman was the first specialist. It

seems likely that the ideas of surplus and commodity appeared with the

shaman, whose orchestration of symbolic activity portended further

alienation and stratification.

Art, like language, is a system of symbolic exchange that introduces

exchange itself. It is also a necessary device for holding together a

community based on the first symptoms of unequal life. Tolstoy’s

statement that “art is a means of union among men, joining them together

in the same feeling,” elucidates art’s contribution to social cohesion

at the dawn of culture. Socializing ritual required art; art works

originated in the service of ritual; the ritual production of art and

the artistic production of ritual are the same. “Music,” wrote

Seu-ma-tsen, “is what unifies.”

As the need for solidarity accelerated, so did the need for ceremony;

art also played a role in its mnemonic function. Art, with myth closely

following, served as the semblance of real memory. In the recesses of

the caves, earliest indoctrination proceeded via the paintings and other

symbols, intended to inscribe rules in depersonalized, collective

memory. Nietzsche saw the training of memory, especially the memory of

obligations, as the beginning of civilized morality. Once the symbolic

process of art developed it dominated memory as well as perception,

putting its stamp on all mental functions. Cultural memory meant that

one person’s action could be compared with that of another, including

portrayed ancestors, and future behavior anticipated and controlled.

Memories became externalized, akin to property but not even the property

of the subject.

Art turns the subject into object, into symbol. The shaman’s role was to

objectify reality; this happened to outer nature and to subjectivity

alike because alienated life demanded it. Art provided the medium of

conceptual transformation by which the individual was separated from

nature and dominated, at the deepest level, socially. Art’s ability to

symbolize and direct human emotion accomplished both ends. What we were

led to accept as necessity, in order to keep ourselves oriented in

nature and society, was at base the invention of the symbolic world, the

Fall of Man.

The world must be mediated by art (and human communication by language,

and being by time) due to division of labor, as seen in the nature of

ritual. The real object, its particularity, does not appear in ritual;

instead, an abstract one is used, so that the terms of ceremonial

expression are open to substitution. The conventions needed in division

of labor, with its standardization and loss of the unique, are those of

ritual, of symbolization. The process is at base identical, based on

equivalence. Production of goods, as the hunter-gatherer mode is

gradually liquidated in favor of agriculture (historical production) and

religion (full symbolic production), is also ritual production.

The agent, again, is the shaman-artist, enroute to priesthood, leader by

reason of mastering his own immediate desires via the symbol. All that

is spontaneous, organic and instinctive is to be neutered by art and

myth.

Recently the painter Eric Fischl presented at the Whitney Museum a

couple in the act of sexual intercourse. A video camera recorded their

actions and projected them on a TV monitor before the two. The man’s

eyes were riveted to the image on the screen, which was clearly more

exciting than the act itself. The evocative cave pictures, volatile in

the dramatic, lamp-lit depths, began the transfer exemplified in

Fischl’s tableau, in which even the most primal acts can become

secondary to their representation. Conditioned self-distancing from real

existence has been a goal of art from the beginning. Similarly, the

category of audience, of supervised consumption, is nothing new, as art

has striven to make life itself an object of contemplation.

As the Paleolithic Age gave way to the Neolithic arrival of agriculture

and civilization — production, private property, written language,

government and religion — culture could be seen more fully as spiritual

decline via division of labor, though global specialization and a

mechanistic technology did not prevail until the late Iron Age.

The vivid representation of late hunter-gatherer art was replaced by a

formalistic, geometric style, reducing pictures of animals and humans to

symbolic shapes. This narrow stylization reveals the artist shutting

himself off from the wealth of empirical reality and creating the

symbolic universe. The aridity of linear precision is one of the

hallmarks of this turning point, calling to mind the Yoruba, who

associate line with civilization: “This country has become civilized,”

literally means, in Yoruba, “this earth has lines upon its face.” The

inflexible forms of truly alienated society are everywhere apparent;

Gordon Childe, for example, referring to this spirit, points out that

the pots of a Neolithic village are all alike. Relatedly, warfare in the

form of combat scenes makes its first appearance in art.

The work of art was in no sense autonomous at this time; it served

society in a direct sense, an instrument of the needs of the new

collectivity. There had been no worship-cults during the Paleolithic,

but now religion held sway, and it is worth remembering that for

thousands of years art’s function will be to depict the gods. Meanwhile,

what Glu:ck stressed about African tribal architecture was true in all

other cultures as well: sacred buildings came to life on the model of

those of the secular ruler. And though not even the first signed works

show up before the late Greek period, it is not inappropriate to turn

here to art’s realization, some of its general features.

Art not only creates the symbols of and for a society, it is a basic

part of the symbolic matrix of estranged social life. Oscar Wilde said

that art does not imitate life, but vice versa; which is to day that

life follows symbolism, not forgetting that it is (deformed) life that

produces symbolism. Every art form, according to T.S. Eliot, is “an

attack upon the inarticulate.” Upon the unsymbolized, he should have

said.

Both painter and poet have always wanted to reach the silence behind and

within art and language, leaving the question of whether the individual,

in adopting these modes of expression, didn’t settle for far too little.

Though Bergson tried to approach the goal of thought without symbols,

such a breakthrough seems impossible outside our active undoing of all

the layers of alienation. In the extremity of revolutionary situations,

immediate communication has bloomed, if briefly.

The primary function of art is to objectify feeling, by which one’s own

motivations and identity are transformed into symbol and metaphor. All

art, as symbolization, is rooted in the creation of substitutes,

surrogates for something else; by its very nature therefore, it is

falsification. Under the guise of “enriching the quality of human

experience,” we accept vicarious, symbolic descriptions of how we should

feel, trained to need such public images of sentiment that ritual art

and myth provide for our psychic security.

Life in civilization is lived almost wholly in a medium of symbols. Not

only scientific or technological activity but aesthetic form are canons

of symbolization, often expressed quite unspiritually. It is widely

averred, for example, that a limited number of mathematical figures

account for the efficacy of art. There is Cezanne’s famous dictum to

“treat nature by the cylinder, the sphere and the cone,” and Kandinsky’s

judgement that “the impact of the acute angle of a triangle on a circle

produces an effect no less powerful than the finger of God touching the

finger of Adam in Michelangelo.” The sense of a symbol, as Charles

Pierce concluded, is its translation into another symbol, this an

endless reproduction, with the real always displaced.

Though art is not fundamentally concerned with beauty, its inability to

rival nature sensuously has evoked many unfavorable comparisons.

“Moonlight is sculpture,” wrote Hawthorne; Shelley praised the

“unpremeditated art” of the skylark; Verlaine pronounced the sea more

beautiful than all the cathedrals. And so on, with sunsets, snowflakes,

flowers, etc., beyond the symbolic products of art. Jean Arp, in fact,

termed “the most perfect picture” nothing more than “warty, threadbare

approximation, a dry porridge.”

Why then would one respond positively to art? As compensation and

palliative, because our relationship to nature and life is so deficient

and disallows an authentic one. As Motherlant put it, “One gives to

one’s art what one has not been capable of giving to one’s own

existence.” It is true for artist and audience alike; art, like

religion, arises from unsatisfied desire.

Art should be considered a religious activity and category also in the

sense of Nietzsche’s aphorism, “We have Art in order not to perish of

Truth.” Its consolation explains the widespread preference for metaphor

over a direct relationship to the genuine article. If pleasure were

somehow released from every restraint, the result would be the

antithesis of art. In dominated life freedom does not exist outside art,

however, and so even a tiny, deformed fraction of the riches of being is

welcomed. “I create in order not to cry,” revealed Klee.

This separate realm of contrived life is both important and in

complicity with the actual nightmare that prevails. In its

institutionalized separation it corresponds to religion and ideology in

general, where its elements are not, and cannot be, actualized; the work

of art is a selection of possibilities unrealized except in symbolic

terms. Arising from the sense of loss referred to above, it conforms to

religion not only by reason of its confinement to an ideal sphere and

its absence of any dissenting consequences, but it can hence be no more

than thoroughly neutralized critique at best.

Frequently compared to play, art and culture — like religion — have more

often worked as generators of guilt and oppression. Perhaps the ludic

function of art, as well as its common claim to transcendence, should be

estimated as one might reassess the meaning of Versailles: by

contemplating the misery of the workers who perished draining its

marshes.

Clive Bell pointed to the intention of art to transport us from the

plane of daily struggle “to a world of aesthetic exaltation,”

paralleling the aim of religion. Malraux offered another tribute to the

conservative office of art when he wrote that without art works

civilization would crumble “within fifty years” ... becoming “enslaved

to instincts and to elementary dreams.”

Hegel determined that art and religion also have “this in common,

namely, having entirely universal matters as content.” This feature of

generality, of meaning without concrete reference, serves to introduce

the notion that ambiguity is a distinctive sign of art.

Usually depicted positively, as a revelation of truth free of the

contingencies of time and place, the impossibility of such a formulation

only illuminates another moment of falseness about art. Kierkegaard

found the defining trait of the aesthetic outlook to be its hospitable

reconciliation of all points of view and its evasion of choice. This can

be seen in the perpetual compromise that at once valorizes art only to

repudiate its intent and contents with “well, after all, it is only

art.”

Today culture is commodity and art perhaps the star commodity. The

situation is understood inadequately as the product of a centralized

culture industry, a la Horkheimer and Adorno. We witness, rather, a mass

diffusion of culture dependent on participation for its strength, not

forgetting that the critique must be of culture itself, not of its

alleged control.

Daily life has become aestheticized by a saturation of images and music,

largely through the electronic media, the representation of

representation. Image and sound, in their ever-presence, have become a

void, ever more absent of meaning for the individual. Meanwhile, the

distance between artist and spectator has diminished, a narrowing that

only highlights the absolute distance between aesthetic experience and

what is real. This perfectly duplicates the spectacle at large: separate

and manipulating, perpetual aesthetic experience and a demonstration of

political power.

Reacting against the increasing mechanization of life, avantgarde

movements have not, however, resisted the spectacular nature of art any

more than orthodox tendencies have. In fact, one could argue that

Aestheticism, or “art for art’s sake,” is more radical than an attempt

to engage alienation with its own devices. The late 19^(th) century art

pour l’art development was a self-reflective rejection of the world, as

opposed to the avantgarde effort to somehow organize life around art. A

valid moment of doubt lies behind Aestheticism, the realization that

division of labour has diminished experience and turned art into just

another specialisation: art shed its illusory ambitions and became its

own content.

The avant-garde has generally staked out wider claims, projecting a

leading role denied it by modern capitalism. It is best understood as a

social institution peculiar to technological society that so strongly

prizes novelty; it is predicated on the progressivist notion that

reality must be constantly updated.

But avant-garde culture cannot compete with the modern world’s capacity

to shock and transgress (and not just symbolically). Its demise is

another datum that the myth of progress is itself bankrupt.

Dada was one of the last two major avant-garde movements, its negative

image greatly enhanced by the sense of general historical collapse

radiated by World War I. Its partisans claimed, at times, to be against

all “isms,” including the idea of art. But painting cannot negate

painting, nor can sculpture invalidate sculpture, keeping in mind that

all symbolic culture is the co-opting of perception, expression and

communication. [nor can writing negate writing, nor can typing radical

essays onto diskettes to assist in their publication ever be liberating

— even if the typer breaks the rules and puts in an uninvited comment]

In fact, Dada was a quest for new artistic modes, its attack on the

rigidities and irrelevancies of bourgeois art a factor in the advance of

art; Hans Richter’s memoirs referred to “the regeneration of visual art

that Dada had begun.” If World War I almost killed art, the Dadaists

reformed it.

Surrealism is the last school to assert the political mission of art.

Before trailing off into Trotskyism and/or art-world fame, the

Surrealists upheld chance and the primitive as ways to unlock “the

Marvellous” which society imprisons in the unconscious. The false

judgement that would have re-introduced art into everyday life and

thereby transfigured it certainly misunderstood the relationship of art

to repressive society. The real barrier is not between art and social

reality, which are one, but between desire and the existing world. The

Surrealists’ aim of inventing a new symbolism and mythology upheld these

categories and mistrusted unmediated sensuality. Concerning the latter,

Breton held that “enjoyment is a science; the exercise of the senses

demands a personal initiation and therefore you need art.”

Modernist abstraction resumed the trend begun by Aestheticism, in that

it expressed the conviction that only by a drastic restriction of its

field of vision could art survive. With the least strain of

embellishment possible in a formal language, art became increasingly

self-referential, in its search for a “purity” that was hostile to

narrative. Guaranteed not to represent anything, modern painting is

consciously nothing more than a flat surface with paint on it.

But the strategy of trying to empty art of symbolic value, the

insistence on the work of art as an object in its own right in a world

of objects, proved a virtually self-annihilating method. This “radical

physicality,” based on aversion to authority though it was, never

amounted to more, in its objectiveness, than simple commodity status.

The sterile grids of Mondrian and the repeated all-black squares of

Reinhardt echo this acquiescence no less than hideous 20^(th) century

architecture in general. Modernist self-liquidation was parodied by

Rauschenberg’s 1953 Erased Drawing, exhibited after his month-long

erasure of a de Kooning drawing. The very concept of art, Duchamp’s

showing of a urinal in a 1917 exhibition notwithstanding, became an open

question in the ’50s and has grown steadily more undefinable since.

Pop Art demonstrated that the boundaries between art and mass media

(e.g. ads and comics) are dissolving. Its perfunctory and mass-produced

look is that of the whole society and the detached, blank quality of a

Warhol and his products sum it up. Banal, morally weightless,

depersonalized images, cynically manipulated by a fashion-conscious

marketing stratagem: the nothingness of modern art and its world

revealed.

The proliferation of art styles and approaches in the ’60s — Conceptual,

Minimalist, Performance, etc. — and the accelerated obsolescence of most

art brought the “postmodern” era, a displacement of the formal “purism”

of modernism by an eclectic mix from past stylistic achievements. This

is basically a tired, spiritless recycling of used-up fragments,

announcing that the development of art is at an end. Against the global

devaluing of the symbolic, moreover, it is incapable of generating new

symbols and scarcely even makes an effort to do so.

Occasionally critics, like Thomas Lawson, bemoan art’s current inability

“to stimulate the growth of a really troubling doubt,” little noticing

that a quite noticeable movement of doubt threatens to throw over art

itself. Such “critics” cannot grasp that art must remain alienation and

as such must be superseded, that art is disappearing because the

immemorial separation between nature and art is a death sentence for the

world that must be voided.

Deconstruction, for its part, announced the project of decoding

Literature and indeed the “texts,” or systems of signification,

throughout all culture. But this attempt to reveal supposedly hidden

ideology is stymied by its refusal to consider origins or historical

causation, an aversion it inherited from

structuralism/poststructuralism. Derrida, Deconstruction’s seminal

figure, deals with language as a solipsism, consigned to

self-interpretation; he engages not in critical activity but in writing

about writing. Rather than a de-constructing of impacted reality, this

approach is merely a self-contained academicism, in which Literature,

like modern painting before it, never departs from concern with its own

surface.

Meanwhile, since Piero Manzoni canned his own feces and sold them in a

gallery and Chris Burden had himself shot in the arm, and crucified to a

Volkswagen, we seen in art ever more fitting parables of its end, such

as the self-portraits drawn by Anastasi — with his eyes closed.

“Serious” music is long dead and popular music deteriorates; poetry

nears collapse and retreats from view; drama, which moved from the

Absurd to Silence, is dying; and the novel is eclipsed by non-fiction as

the only way to write seriously.

In a jaded, enervated age, where it seems to speak is to say less, art

is certainly less. Baudelaire was obliged to claim a poet’s dignity in a

society which had no more dignity to hand out. A century an more later

how inescapable is the truth of that condition and how much more

threadbare the consolation or station of “timeless” art.

Adorno began his book thusly: “Today it goes without saying that nothing

concerning art goes without saying, much less without thinking.

Everything about art has become problematic; its inner life, its

relation to society, even its right to exist.” But Aesthetic Theory

affirms art, just as Marcuse’s last work did, testifying to despair and

to the difficulty of assailing the hermetically sealed ideology of

culture. And although other “radicals,” such as Habermas, counsel that

the desire to abolish symbolic mediation is irrational, it is becoming

clearer that when we really experiment with our hearts and hands the

sphere of art is shown to be pitiable. In the transfiguration we must

enact, the symbolic will be left behind and art refused in favor of the

real. Play, creativity, self-expression and authentic experience will

recommence at that moment.