đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș spooky-vulgar-anarcho-communism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 14:11:30. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Vulgar Anarcho-Communism Author: Spooky Date: June 26th, 2020 Language: en Topics: anarcho-communism, anti-statism, post-left, c4ss Source: Retrieved on 2020-06-27 from https://c4ss.org/content/53016
Radical positions are always a hard sell. To some extent, this is an
inherent aspect of advocating any alternative system of social
organization, instead of just proposing reform and âbipartisan
solutions.â Some, perhaps too many, have attempted to dull the edges of
their political labels by wrapping their ideology in broader language,
using âcommon senseâ rhetoric, and reducing their viewpoints to simple
but incomplete definitions. One of the most successful examples of this
is Noam Chomskyâs definition of anarchism as âopposition to unjustified
hierarchies.â This has persuaded many people who otherwise might never
have investigated these ideas, myself included.
However, by hanging onto such a moderate definition, some people have
effectively created a separate branch of libertarian thought that they
describe as âanarchism,â though their vision of statelessness is notably
distinct. Similar to Kevin Carsonâs coinage of âvulgar libertarianism,â
I find it appropriate to think of these people as vulgar
anarcho-communists (or vulgar ancoms as a shorthand); they represent a
strain of leftism which focuses more on broad conceptions of âequalityâ
and collective ownership rather than embracing the implications of
statelessness.
The most significant issue with this position is an insistence on the
link between anarchism and a monolithic definition of âdemocracy,â
involving some form of universal consensus or majoritarian
decision-making system that affects every member of a given community or
network. Some adherents advocate for a system of representation
involving âdelegatesâ who bargain, vote, and interact with other
communities in a type of inter-communal congress. This system, to a
disturbing amount of self-proclaimed anarchists, is either not
considered a hierarchy at all or somehow justified due to its
âdemocraticâ nature.
This principle is significant to the point that vulgar anarcho-communism
could adequately be described as a type of minarchism or council
communism. While this isnât inherently a bad thing, the issue is how the
adherents of this tendency morph the definition of the state to near
unrecognizability. Vulgar ancoms frequently dial back their opposition
to the state, clarifying that they donât oppose âgovernment,â just âthe
state,â by which they generally mean the worst parts of existing nation
states â the police, military, politicians, etc.
They often propose that workersâ councils, communes, or some form of
local municipal government will be the primary unit of organization in a
post-capitalist society. Cops wouldnât exist, they argue, since without
a state there would be no âpolice forceâ in the current sense. Instead,
they claim, defense would be provided by a voluntary community
self-defense team that can be recalled by the community at any time in
the event that their services are no longer satisfactory. The specifics
regarding how these institutions are organized varies widely â some
involving a rotating staff of commune members and others just being a
fixed group of volunteers â but they are almost always described as
being âdemocratically runâ in some sense.
Emerican Johnsonâs five-part series âHow Would Anarchism Actually Work?â
is a great illustration of this particular vision of âanarchism.â While
Iâm not claiming that all anarcho-communists subscribe to Johnsonâs
particular view of anarchism, the concepts covered in the series serve
as effective examples of some common âvulgar ancomâ perspectives.
Every human being in an anarchistic society will have a right to having
all of their material needs met in full. Food, clothing, shelter,
electricity, running water, internet and health care and so on. In
exchange for having their needs met, individuals must agree to a
reasonable contribution to the commune. Itâs important to note that what
constitutes a reasonable contribution will vary from individual to
individual⊠Ideally, for most folks, this would look something like a 15
to 20 hour workweek that includes labor performed for the commune.
As I said before, this resembles council communism more than it does a
stateless society. Work weeks and âreasonable contributionsâ of labor
donât sound like desirable conditions at all, regardless of how such a
decision was reached. Democracy, to vulgar anarcho-communists, is a
means that justifies most ends; if the people vote on a temporary method
of organization, then it has legitimacy. This is shockingly similar to
the means used by right-libertarians to justify âvoluntaryâ employment
contracts that they might otherwise view as coercive, swapping out the
logic of the market with the logic of the democratic process. In some
cases, including Johnsonâs, this is used in an attempt to justify
âanarchoâ-re-education centers.
⊠crime in an anarchist society would be seen as âtreatable,â a social
problem that would be corrected with rehabilitative measures that are
tailored to each individualâs circumstances⊠Most crimes would be
addressed through counseling, education, and other such communal
interventions designed to heal the individual and the community. If an
individualâs harmful behavior stems not just from social problems but
from some biological or neurological condition, then they would be
committed to a âspecial circumstancesâ hospital, which would cater
specifically to those needsâŠ
My goal in presenting these moments from Johnsonâs work is to show where
such a myopic focus on democracy and communist economic relationships
can lead. These vulgar anarcho-communist tendencies appear to be popular
in radical and anti-capitalist spaces, perhaps causing many to think
itâs the predominant strain of libertarian socialism. In part, this is
due to the tactics used by Chomsky and Johnson, pacifying the premise of
the ideology in order to attract moderate onlookers. While appealing to
democracy and anti-capitalism seems to have worked as a PR strategy, the
lack of focus on anti-statism, individual autonomy, and the consistent
rejection of all hierarchies has led to a lot of confusion over what
anarchists actually want.
Attempts at pacifying anti-statism often involve catering to moderates
who insist that we need certain answers to how post-capitalist
infrastructure will function. Unfortunately, this has led many to
dedicate themselves to drawing detailed blueprints of Ancomistan rather
than fully exploring the implications of statelessness. The fact that we
donât have all the answers to how roads will be built or how video games
will be made isnât necessarily a weakness. The greatest strengths of a
stateless society lie in its total decentralization, as experiments with
many different types of social institutions and economic arrangements
are made possible in the absence of government mandates that prop up
monolithic systems. Vulgar anarcho-communism completely ignores this
potential in favor of one template that claims to benefit everyone,
despite the sheer impossibility of fulfilling such a promise.
We donât need to water down our ideals to win favor with fence-sitters.