💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › tom-nomad-pacifism-zine.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 14:21:24. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Pacifism
Author: Tom Nomad
Date: 7/15/2020 (written in 2009)
Language: en
Topics: diversity of tactics, nonviolence, Insurrectionist Theory, anti-pacifism, pacifism, anti-globalization movement
Source: Seith Communiti Imprint
Notes: Published in an edition of 50 physical copies by Seith Communiti multimedia imprint. seithcommuniti.noblogs.org Free dissemination and reproduction of this text is encouraged.

Tom Nomad

Pacifism

“Put quite plainly, nonviolence ensures a state monopoly on violence.

States- the centralized bureaucracies that protect capitalism; preserve

a white supremacist, patriarchal order; and implement imperialist

expansion- survive by assuming the role of sole legitimate purveyor of

violent force within a territory. Any struggle against oppression

necessitates a conflict with the state. Pacifists do the state’s work by

pacifying the opposition in advance. States, for their part, discourage

militancy within the opposition, and encourage passivity”

— Peter Gelderloos. How Nonviolence Protects the State (2007, South End

Press)

Introduction

Perhaps one of the most exhausting debates within “activist” movements

is the discourse concerning the effectiveness of “violent” vs

“nonviolent” tactical sets. For numerous reasons, and for quite some

time, this debate has gone nowhere. In many instances, both sides of

this debate make sweeping generalizations about the other, which engages

tactics on the level of effectiveness without examining the very

constructed abstractions inherent in either approach. This debate has

gained some energy once again with the success of insurrectionary

anarchist tactics at the IMF/World Bank demonstrations in the Fall of

2007, the Republican National Convention in 2008, and the recent

uprising in Greece; all at a time when the mainstream pacifist antiwar

movement has been relegated to the dustbin of ineffective social

movements, and one that sees many in the “official” Left defecting in

droves to join the “Obamanation” (as many anarchists have come to call

the recent cult of personality around the election campaign of Barack

Obama). Many involved in social movements have to come to grips with one

stunning fact that many of us seem to forget: none of the tactical sets

that we have employed have resulted in a substantial victory over the

moves of capital and state. Despite this, I cannot count how many times

I have been subjected to a lecture from an old pacifist claiming “Well,

these are the tactics that we have always used, and they have worked so

far.” If the current social and political condition is what results from

nonviolence working, I would hate to see what happens when it fails!

What this all comes down to is the reality that nonviolence has not

worked as a force of social change, and that historical precedence of a

tactic does not guarantee its legitimacy. This historical precedent is

just another glaring example of the near-total inability of pacifists to

make sweeping social upheaval a possibility – for this reason we must

deal a critical blow to the legitimacy of nonviolence as an organizing

tactic that hopes to threaten the order of things as they exist.

Nonviolence has become accepted by the state as a generally harmless

form of action, a classic example being the action done in front of the

White House on September 26, 2005. Over 150 people — including the

activist celebrity Cindy Sheehan — sat down in front of the gate of the

White House to wait to be arrested. Outside of the utter pointlessness

of this action (as if the state cares if people get locked up for

political action in an age of vast prison expansion and privatization),

there were details that many of the observers of this action were

unaware of. The organizers had told the police that they were planning

an action, and entered into a process of negotiation with them a month

prior. They came to agree that people would be arrested and not cuffed,

walked over to a processing van which would be on site, and asked to pay

$50, then they would be released. In essence, organizers negotiated with

the police an agreement to make the action the least disruptive that it

possibly could be. This is where the nonviolent paradigm has led us —

the question is why? I suggest that this is not an unintended

consequence, but rather a mentality which is inherent to the nonviolent

perspective.

We need to first examine the ontological assumptions that structure the

kernel of nonviolence. Two pieces of writing stand out in particular in

how well they represent the two most common arguments for nonviolence

outside of those offered religious / new ageism (which are based on the

mass-authoritarian imposition of religious norms over movements rather

than a ground-up tendency toward nonviolence upon which this piece

intends to focus). The first piece is “The Politics of Nonviolent

Action” by Gene Sharp, a tactician on a series of “nonviolent”

campaigns, well-known and often cited (and often challenged) theorist

and historian of nonviolence. In this piece, Sharp puts forward the

common belief that nonviolent struggle is necessary to create a

nonviolent world. He bases this theory around an articulation of a

networked idea of political power; that the state persists in its

actions because of structuring of social consent, and that nonviolent

action presents a mechanism to hinder undesirable actions by the state

while constructing the basis for a new political paradigm through the

exercise of popular or constituent power. The second piece worth

examining is the anarchist pamphlet “You Can’t Blow Up A Social

Relationship”, which presents an argument uniquely suited to the

framework of anti-authoritarian movements. The central argument made in

the pamphlet is that revolutionary violence is a “strategy of

impatience,” (12) and a characteristically vanguardist tactical set that

presents nothing but authoritarian possibilities. The arguments within

these two pieces mutually reinforce each other in several interesting

ways (which we examine later) — but perhaps most fundamentally they

share the common the assumption of the legitimacy of mass politics and

the pure ideality of the state. This assumption of the nature of the

state and our ability to withhold consent from its perpetuation forms

the crux of their arguments and would have to be the case in order for

nonviolence to be more than an individual aesthetic morality in one’s

self-discovery quest. The very contradictory nature of reality

illustrations that this assumption is also the basis of their collective

failure — and thus, the pivot-point that leads to the latent

authoritarianism of nonviolence.

Basis For Nonviolence

Before attempting to move further, perhaps it is necessary to draw a

simple distinction, to identify what we are concerned with here. Many

nonviolent actions are carried out for reformist goals, for example the

mainstream antiwar movement or other protests aimed at putting political

pressure on the state spurred onward by popular demonstrations of

grievance with the system and its functions. For many of us enaged in

political movements, a pig in makeup is still obviously a pig — putting

restrictions on police violence still makes it police violence, and

making capitalism “ethical” (a complete impossibility) still preserves

the forced equivalence and channeling of everyday life through the

commodity form as condition of possibility. Reformist movements are

worth even less than the wasted paper, money and gas spent on mobilizing

huge spectacles of conformity. What we prefer to focus on is the

destabilizing potentiality of the tactics and ontological frameworks of

nonviolence. Put another way, the only paradigm of nonviolence that is

even worth considering is some set of tactics amounting to

“revolutionary nonviolence”. All other forms, because they do not even

maintain the illusion of attempting to combat the violence endemic in

capitalism, are merely a neoliberal lifestyle choice.

The position of a revolutionary nonviolence has been argued by such

widely divergent people as The Catholics Workers, Crass, and Albert

Einstein. The actions that have emerged from this tradition are

spectacular and tactically diverse, and have ranged from the

“nonviolent” barricading of a military research lab in Pittsburgh, the

“nonviolent” breaking and entering into draft offices and subsequent

arsons of draft records, the “nonviolent” sawing-down of telephone poles

at NORAD which connected global positioning satellite dishes from the

central computer infrastructure, the “nonviolent” hacking the US

military missile targeting system which delayed the invasion of Iraq

(unfortunately only by 48 hours), etc. In other words, nonviolent

actions without the goal of reform can be effective at sabotage and

disruption given the right circumstances, clandestine planning and

strategic structure. Despite these moments of rupture, is there a

greater possibility for nonviolent acts to smash the state apparatus?

Many pacifists take their lead from Sharp, who at many points described

himself as a “tactical pacifist”, and notable in that his vision of

nonviolence departs from a discussion on the functioning of political

power. He states,

“There appears to be two views of the nature of power. One can see

people as dependent upon good will, the decisions and the support of

their government, or any other hierarchical system to which they belong.

Or, conversely, one can see that government or system dependent on the

people’s good will, decisions and support” (Sharp, 8).

The division that Sharp illustrates here lies between understanding of

the state as an entity as such which controls and oppresses the actions

within its area of control, and an understanding of the state as the

structuring of consent. Sharp goes on to argue that the structuring of

political violence is the structuring of violence to combat the state

qua monolith. In other words, what Sharp lays out is a matrix in which

the state can only be viewed through two lenses, as a complex

relationship of theoretical investments which structures a form of

consent — a sort of philosophical state — and a monolithic material

structure which represses through force. From this simple reductionism,

Sharp then proceeds to argue that political violence can only function

to attack the state as a monolithic structure of force, which is bound

to fail. There are a wide array of issues with this view, including the

vast historical reductionism that lays at the heart of this matrix; but

most problematically, this simplistic matrix is grounded in a

fundamental misunderstanding of how logistics of force function, how

dispersed apparatuses of force can emerge, and how this complex dynamic

of shifting force is the only actual way that we can understand the

space through which ideas can leave the conceptual space to be imposed

materially through force. By misunderstanding how dispersed logistical

force functions, Sharp renders himself incapable of speaking of the

state in a material way, in the sense of actions taken, and as a result,

is incapable of understanding the relationship between ideas and action,

let alone the tactical logistics of state action, without which it is

impossible to speak of tactics at all.

As Paolo Virno argues, the state is the entity which turns multitudes

into people (21), it functions to the degree that it can eliminate

difference and impose sameness, and as such presents itself as

equivalence, as a force which creates sameness. Though this seems

abstract, we experience this constantly through law, the imposition of

sovereign determinations of how we must act, and the concept of

citizenship, the transformation of a person into a person as defined by

the state. Within the Newtonian assumption of equivalence, the

equivalence posited is an ontological determination – that of the

necessary equivalence of like and like. The positing of the Newtonian

move — the generation of the frozen temporality of the equivalence — in

being ontological is a claim on space-time generally, it names some and

space as nothing other than an expression of that equivalence, that

definition imposed through state action. This is borne out in practical

experience; the state is an apparatus which frames, limits, and channels

actions into acceptable channels — legalistic or informal. This activity

of generalization, however, is not simply an ideological process, which

would assume a total sameness in how different persons understand ideas.

It is also not borne out of the activities of a monolithic structure,

which does not exist without this sameness already being existent.

Rather, the state functions as a complex mechanism. On one hand, the

state departs from defining existence based on the declarations of the

sovereign (that one or those that hold power). To the degree that we

approach existence as unique, that we approach those that exist as

unique, and to the degree that we assume that our actions have effects

which change the conditions we exist within, in even simple ways, then

nothing can possibly function monolithically. Rather, the state is a

logistics, constructed from the attempt to structure cohesion in the

midst of difference and historical fluctuation, which deploys force in

an attempt to end difference, eliminate historical flux, to structure

existence through force; a paradoxical process of utilizing a logistics

grounded in difference (those that make up the actions of the logistics)

and operated through actions which are supposed to have effects, only to

eliminate difference and the effects of actions or historical flux.

Everyday over a million people get up, put on uniforms, and go to work

in the bureaucracies and control mechanisms of the state, every cop

makes a decision every day to be a cop. Hobbes surmises:

“The only way to erect such a Common Power…is, to conferre all their

power and strength upon one Man, or upon one Assembly of men, that may

reduce all their Wills, by plurality of voices, onto one Will: which is

as much as to say, to appoint one man, or Assembly of men, to beare

their Person…This is more than Consent or Concord; it is a reall Unitie

of them all, in one and the same Person…This done, the Multitude so

united in one Person, is called a Common-wealth…”(227)

The state is the generation of the Subject from the multitude of

discontinuous acts, it forms the conditions of possibility for the act

by structuring the continuity within which the act occurs. In this sense

Sharp is correct — the state is not a monolith. He departs from this

correct argument and combines it with the absurd reductionism at the

heart of his critique of violence — that it can only attack monolithic

structures, to form the foundations of his notion of revolutionary

non-violence. This becomes important, as he goes on to claim that

nonviolence gains legitimacy because it deals with power “at its source”

(Sharp, 10). His claim that nonviolence builds the basis of a new

presumably-nonhierarchical form of power, through the absence of the act

qua coercion. Sharp claims that nonviolence can be deployed as a form of

non-cooperation which attacks power at its base: the very structuring of

consent necessary for the state to function (36). This begins to sketch

out a concept of revolutionary nonviolence based around the generation

of mass noncooperation; in essence, he is attempting to construct a

concept of nonviolence as war machine unto itself.

The nonviolent war machine is a tactic of refusal based in a

destabilization concept. If the state is the structuring of consent for

its existence as a series of acts, then refusal of the mandates of the

state undermines the states ability to implement equivalences. In other

words, the assertion here is that the world does not function through

this monolithic consent, but rather, that this consent has been

functioning as a sort of ruse of complex deception; in this he is

positing a sort of division between the organicism of life in its

complexity and the inorganicism of the state, in its monolithic process.

In taking this position, Sharp is constructing a conflict between

masses; the mass of “fools” who are convinced by the state, and the

masses of organic beings fighting against the consensus of the “fools”.

Life within this structure becomes defined absolutely, both by the state

in the process of creating the mass, and in the claim Sharp makes about

some sort of inherent human existence. In a sense it is the theory of

nonviolence as virus - the hope is that noncooperation will spread

exponentially throughout the base of consensus. In this sense,

nonviolence is a defensive move against the inorganic construction of

the state — in defending an already present human condition from

encroachment by the state, the nonviolent activist is exercising an

ability that is always already latent. But because of this defensive

character inherent within the base, Sharp creates the condition that the

nonviolent act must always be the mass act. Everyone in the factory

needs to seize the factory or strike, all people need to march to the

sea to pound salt, etc. In this sense, nonviolence is the genesis of a

form of alternate stability — formed around the maxim to not impose upon

the consent of the base.

The other basis for revolutionary nonviolence in an anarchist context is

the argument presented in “You Can’t Blow Up A Social Relationship”. The

piece’s central thesis – that violent insurrection is an inherently

vanguardist pursuit – is an argument not intended for nor effective

within authoritarian circles (which willingly accept the authoritarian

vanguard role inherent in its strategies — hell, this pamphlet may just

encourage them); rather, it is aimed at making an appeal to

anti-authoritarians who utilize insurrectionary tactics within their

waging of social war.

“A democracy can only be produced if a majority movement is built. The

guerrilla strategy depends on a collapse of will in the ruling class to

produce the social crisis out of which the revolution occurs, whether

the majority favors it or not. Any reading of guerrilla strategists

reveals that it is a philosophy of impatience” (“You Can’t Blow Up A

Social Relationship”, 12)

Although every example cited by the authors are drawn from guerrilla

forces that unapologetically assume an authoritarian character as

integral to their revolutionary paradigm, this argument is still worth

our consideration as anti-authoritarians. What the authors are

attempting to argue is that a violent revolution is incapable of being a

populist revolution. In the structuring of the concept of revolutionary

violence around impatience, they equated all violent action to

vanguardism, claiming in essence that the violent insurrection generates

its own structuring of authority around the revolutionary act — a “with

us or against us” mentality. In choosing to act before waiting for the

will of the masses, the insurrectionist is unilaterally defining the

conditions of action within the plane of resistance. They state,

“concentrating on the supposed insanity of the guerrillas or terrorists

is an attempt to provide a justification for murderousness towards them

and for the introduction of general repression” (16).

Now this is not wholly incorrect; violent actions do draw an increase in

repression from the state. Yet this is problematic in a very basic way.

The claim that the acts of the insurrectionists is the cause of

political repression by the state ignores the fact that the existence of

the equivalent Subject qua state that is the condition of possibility

for generalized repression. There are practical examples that back this

up; in Italy over the course of the 20^(th) century, it has become

routine for fascists (potentially acting in conjuction of the will of

the state and metapolitical state if Operation Gladio is to be taken at

face-value) to bomb a target and blame it on the anarchists to draw

state repression onto anarchist militants. It is not the

insurrectionists that generate the repression, however, but rather it is

the state reaction that generates repression. The state is a posited

equivalence which has exceeded and become the condition of possibility

for everyday life. Whether we like it or not, the pigs believe that they

control the streets.

In the generation of the Newtonian equivalence all outlying variables

need to be eliminated. Like the airstream pattern studies that generated

the basis for chaos theory, as an equivalence progresses it needs to

either freeze time (impossible) or reincorporate or eliminate

potentially destabilizing elements in order to maintain its coherence

(Gleick, 15) . If all acts present a destabilization in continuity – if

acts form a continuity of discontinuity — then acts are reincorporated

or repressed due to the threat of entropy which they pose to the

abstracting machine. So it is not the act that generates repression, it

is the existence of the abstracting apparatus of the state that

generates repression in an attempt to maintain coherence. All effective

insurrectionary events will draw repression by the state to the degree

that they are potentially destabilizing. This is why I personally hate

the anarchist complaint about police brutality following action — isn’t

this the point?; we reject the state because it can employ violence to

prevent us from living our desires?, because it makes us all equivalent?

If we are serious about this struggle, we have to expect that the state

will attack with everything they have, within the very amorphous social

limits of acceptability (for instance, the pigs largely no longer use

water cannons because it hearkens back to images of white pigs firing

water cannons on black civil rights demonstrators — but will they

hesitate to use a water cannon if they had to? We saw them deployed on

the streets of St Paul during the RNC in 2008.)

Both of these arguments make a similar set of assumptions that construct

a framework for nonviolent action. Both depart from the long-held idea

that violence is used against the state in order to “sever the head of

state” and impose a new form of organization. They are correct to argue

that this frames revolutionary violence as a completely vanguardist

enterprise that does not engage with power on the level of deployment.

This approach has been the downfall of both authoritarian communism

(which was able to take power in certain sites but left the general

social structuring of power untouched while imposing another structure

to control those flows), and anarchist assassinations (which did cause a

general amount of chaos in the ruling structures of the Western early

20^(th) century but failed to accomplish its larger goals). They reject

the imposition of a mass political solution imposed by a minority group,

only to rebuild the idea of mass politics.

The argument that both put forth is that noncoercive nonviolent acts

attack power at the level of deployment — everyday life — by opening up

a non-authoritarian social refusal. Yet both pieces rely on the

construction of the nonviolent equivalence. Rather than the mass Subject

imposed by the violent imposition of social order through violent

action, they both construct the Subject of mass action based in a

definitionality of nonviolence, where the legitimacy of participants is

defined through their adherence to an externally defined morality. This

imposes the restriction on temporality and action through the assertion

of an inherent nonviolent noncooperation; the argument is that we always

have the ability to withdraw consent from the state through mass

nonviolent action. Yet, if violence is considered as inherently

authoritarian, nonviolence then becomes the condition of possibility for

action. For example – an imposition of nonviolence occurred in Seattle

during the WTO demonstrations in 1999 where pacifist demonstrators

pepper-sprayed anarchists attempting to smash windows in Niketown

(Nike’s corporate store in Downtown Seattle). Here is an axiom of

nonviolence that was violently imposed against so-called authoritarian

violence. Like the state apparatus, nonviolence generates a Newtonian

equivalence. Once a certain tactical set is rejected absolutely, all

attempts at this can be repressed to preserve the nonviolent aspects of

the act.

The Impossibility of Nonviolent Revolution

The question of so-called non-violent revolution is not merely a moral

question, as it is often framed, or a tactical question, as framed by

the pieces discussed here, but exists at the confluence in which

morality, an abstract generalization of actions within a discourse of

proper action, and tactics, the material dynamics of action at a

particular time and space. This raises a clear problem however. The

discourse of tactics, as discussed by Clausewitz and others, is one in

which the concept always fails; in which the idea never grasps the

complexity of the moment in, and relies on simplifications and

equivalencies to be able to identify objects and phenomena with concepts

and names. In other words, the simplifications of the concept — the ways

that concepts speak in general and attempt to speak of equivalencies —

eliminates the complex uniqueness of the dynamics of any present moment.

As such, to posit a conceptual qualifier to a moment, and to attempt to

speak of the moment through the concept, abstracts the particularity of

the moment out of existence. As such, to attempt to place a conceptual

universal morality at the core of materially particular action means

that, at best, we are left with a framework that is incapable of

speaking of the moments — of tactics themselves — in the process of only

processing the dynamics of action as they relate to an abstract moral

framework. This abstracts tactics into a discussion of morality, limits

the possibility of action, imposes this sameness of action, and fails to

be capable of elastically responding to shifts in the tactical scenarios

of lived moments.

Take, for example, the crowd control procedures outlined in “Field

Manual 3–19.15: Civil Disturbance Operations” issued by the US military

to National Guard forces and police departments. Although there are many

manuals which address civil disturbance operations, it is this

particular manual upon which that most of the police civil disturbance

operations manuals are based, including the recently-released RNC Civil

Disturbance Manual used by the St Paul Police Department. The main goal

of the procedures outlined in the manual are based on the generation of

equivalences in order to respond to a situation in order to maintain

stability, but not necessarily to end all political acts – thus

preserving the illusion of acceptable political expression within the

confines of state surveillance. Beyond this, Field Manual 3–19.15 is the

standard operations manual for crowd control situations — repeatedly

cited and mimicked by pigs all over the country learning how to deal

with the rise in political demonstrations. The manual proceeds by

generating a series of categories of analysis. Firstly, the crowd is

analyzed and positioned into three classes: “public disorder” is when a

small crowd is gathering; “public disturbance’ is when a crowd begins to

chant or engage in mild actions like marching or nonviolently blocking a

road; and finally, “riot” when the crowd begins to engage in property

destruction or other forms of violence (1–5). “Commanders must be aware

of the possibility that some individuals or groups within an organized

demonstration may have the intent to cause disruption, incite violence,

destroy property, and provoke authorities” (1–3). Their pre-action

preparation lays out a series of considerations for the pigs to take

into account; they are advised to avoid confrontation, focus on

prevention, and define goals beforehand. “Crowd situations are highly

unpredictable, but one thing seems certain- confrontation will likely

cause crowd resistance. When pushed, people tend to resist opposition to

the realization of their purpose” (2–5). It goes on to recommend that

the pigs communicate with the “leaders” of the protest (which in the

context of anarchist blocs has led to some quite funny situations with

very confused pigs) in order to form a working relationship which

results in “protest groups largely policing themselves” (2–7). If this

fails, the pigs then move into what they call scaleable effects. In

other words, they will attempt to develop a matrix of escalation, moving

from warnings to disperse to shows of force and finally escalating force

(2–13).

Current crowd control doctrine places an emphasis on crowd dispersal.

Forced dispersal may result in a crowd breaking up into multiple groups

that scatter over a large area. This may pose even greater public order

problems and may pose a continued threat to control forces. A crowd is

often controlled better by means of containment (confining its

activities to a given area). A crowd has limited duration, and its

numbers are likely to diminish as individual needs take precedence over

those of the crowd (2–22).

This all provides the revolutionary anti-authoritarian with valuable

insight into the mindset of the pigs within the state. The goal of the

pigs is not to prevent actions, nor to put a blanket level of force

around the action itself; rather the goal is to respond to

destabilization with increasing armed stability. The main variable

within in the approaches laid out here is that the pigs need to have a

situation which they can generalize and respond to. The manual states,

“forced dispersal may result in a crowd breaking up into multiple groups

scattered over a large area. This may pose even greater public order

problems and may pose a continued threat to control forces” (2–22). In

other words, the decentralization of insurrectionary violence generates

a potential entropy within their strategic framework. The concern of the

pigs is to contain and de-escalate the situation, by force if necessary.

The state tolerates and even solicits certain political acts (notably,

large self-regulating nonviolent demonstration actions), in order to

maintain the myth of political freedom within the state apparatus to the

degree that these acts are emptied of their destabilizing and entropic

properties.

Nonviolence plays neatly into the state’s strategy of containment and

mitigation — and that is why pacifists pose no threat. Recall the two

fundamental characteristics of the nonviolence discourses analyzed

earlier: that pacifists approach the state as a pure ideality which —

and this is the second point of agreement — can be combated through mass

noncooperation. The state as the state of technique and stabilization

responds to acts of destabilization to the degree that they are

potentially entropic. This leads our nonviolence proponents into their

ideologically self-defeating trap. The mass Subject of nonviolence is

the Subject of necessary mass action, or unified and striated action,

based in the definitionality of nonviolence. So they become presented

with a choice: the Subject of nonviolence — always already generated as

an equivalence- can engage in only those acts that are limited in the

potential for destabilization. If the action carried out is not

effective, if it fails to generate a potential destabilization (most

nonviolent actions fall into this category), then the action defeats

itself. If the action does become effective, then the violence of the

state — which forms the condition of possibility for the state - goes

unopposed. The nice pacifists sit in the road till they either get bored

with the police escort or get dispersed through the use of force. The

posited equivalence of the Subject qua nonviolence is, like all

Newtonian moves, an equivalent impossible to act situationally; thus it

is no wonder that the pacifists almost never achieve anything.

Peace Police

The ineffectiveness and technocratic aspects of nonviolence manifest

most practically in the sets of nonviolence guidelines that many of us

have grown completely sick of being handed printed upon small fliers

before every mass demonstration that we choose to attend. Many of these

sets of rules tend to be very similar – as such here is the guideline

set by the Declaration of Peace. This was an antiwar campaign which had

some potential to challenge the state on their original premise – that a

date should be set for the withdrawal of American troops from Iraq or

else trigger a wave or direct action across the US. Any entropic

potential which the mobilization possessed dissipated upon the

unilateral institution of nonviolence guidelines by the organizing

group. The Declaration Of Peace guidelines set the parameters upon which

actions will be carried out:

all we encounter.

consequences of our actions.

purposes).(

http://declarationofpeace.org/nonviolence-guidelines

)

Under these guidelines any participant cannot be stoned, hostile towards

the pigs, smash windows, and must voluntarily allow themselves to be

arrested- need I say more? The very framework prevents confrontation or

any attempt to destabilize a situation. The goal of these actions is to

“invite the majority in this country to take steps to call for an end to

the US war in Iraq.” Thus we return to the stated goal of nonviolent

action to encourage the building of the mass nonviolent Subject — the

Subject of nonconfrontation. The generation of the Subject qua

nonviolence exceeds and limits the potential for action, and thus the

potential for the constitution of agency, which in turn limits the

agent; when action is defined, and the possibilities of existence in

that moment limited, the autonomy and agency of that who acts is also

consequently stolen away. We can see this theft of autonomy clearly in

the tendency of pacifists to form “peace police” groups to police the

actions of others. It become common at demonstrations to endure the

presence of people clad in orange or green vests tasked with preventing

people from violating these guidelines and acting as a de-escalating

buffer between the crowd and the pigs. By the inclusion of these “Peace

Police,” nonviolent organizers attempt to mitigate as much

destabilization as possible by forcibly limiting the actions of the more

insurrectionary among us, thus effectively prohibiting us from

manifesting a resistance that departs from our lives and contexts by

substituting our positionality for one within an abstracted nonviolent

Subject.

A sobering example of this took place at the first major antiwar

movement march in DC following the commencement of this most recent

phase of the genocidal Iraq War, wherein the pigs attacked the black

bloc while still on the permitted march route. Instead of allowing space

for self-defense and tactical fluidity, the organizer-appointed “Peace

Police” physically prevented the bloc from leaving the permitted route

to get to a space that was more easily defensible. This resulted in a

shouting match that eventually escalated into a fist fight between

anarchists and “peace police”, all while still attempting to repel a

police assault on the protest. The march ended when the pigs decided to

tear gas and charge the crowd; most of the pacifists ran, leaving the

bloc to defend 35,000 people trapped in a park fearing arrest and

further brutalization by the state. While the bloc ultimately prevented

the pigs from entering the park — giving everyone else space to rest and

recover — it resulted in a slew of broken bones and arrests within the

bloc. Meanwhile, the bloc once again had to fend off the “Peace Police,”

who were attempting to de-escalate the situation by attempting to push

anarchists off the street from behind while the pigs attacked from the

front. Are the actions of those employed by the organizers to “keep the

peace” between radicals and the state not replicating the very form of

action which the state treats as its limit before the attempting to

control a situation by force — allowing the participants to police

themselves and mitigate any potential destabilization within their ranks

— here in a very literal sense?

I personally witnessed one of the Declaration of Peace actions occur at

the Hart Senate Office Building where the organizers and pigs negotiated

the terms upon which the demonstration would be able to occur. All signs

and banners were confiscated, and activists were told that if they

talked they would be arrested. In the end, a mass of 50 or so people

stood in the lobby of the building — silently and without signs — until

they were all arrested one-by-one and put on a bus to be dropped in

another area of town. Following the action, the organizers attempted to

present this as a victory – to which I say again, if this is victory I

would hate to see defeat.

Diversity Of Tactics

Naturally, much like the Subject qua nonviolence, there is also a

possibility for the Subject qua violence. If it is accepted fact that

violence and total war are conditions of possibility for everyday life

in the age of globalization, then while violence is endemic to all

relations of power the construction of a Subject around the

definitionality of tactical violence recreates the problematic

equivalence of the Subject qua nonviolence. If nonviolence, in its

positing of a generalized equivalence, creates another form of stability

and a space for negotiation with the state, that does not mean that one

can generate the ideology of violence. Violence, if it is to maintain

the potential for destabilization of the political apparatus, cannot

become another form of equivalence, nor are all violences the same — a

point missed by many pacifists in their admonishment. War machines and

the reappropriation that intends to counter them are fundamentally

different, yet it is problematic to begin to argue for the tactical

universality of violence without also generating a negotiable

equivalence.

This seems to have landed us at an impasse, given the terms of the

discussion as it exists. We clearly cannot speak of a tactical

nonviolence, which becomes separated from the particularity of action in

tactical scenarios through its retreat into moral generalities. We also

cannot speak of a generalized violence without falling into the same

trap. However, the question in not an impossibility; only the attempt to

have a singular total answer is. The reality of our scenario is that

tactics shift, goals differ and situations are fluid. As such, the

question of the correct, or proper, tactics is one that is often

discussed in the abstract, even if that abstraction eliminates the

subject of the discussion, tactics itself. If we are to approach the

state as a fluid, complex logistics, rather than some sort of monolithic

entity or reductive concept of a mythical consensus, then we have to

come to terms with what is actually occurring; that we are placing

ourselves into situations of acute conflict, which are complex, kinetic,

shifting situations which we are doing the best we can to survive and be

as effective as possible. Just as with perspectives that argue to a

universalized violence, non-violence is also completely incapable of

responding to, or even discussing, actual material dynamics and actual

tactical scenarios without preconditions and overabstractions.

One recent approach to moving beyond this impasse — outside of agreeing

to disagree — is the discourse of a diversity of tactics. Employing a

diversity of tactics creates the space for agency to be situationally,

politically and positionally dependent; one engages in the tactics with

which they have a desire to engage. To illustrate a real-world

application of this paradigm, examine the St. Paul Principles, developed

to facilitate actions at the 2008 Republican National Convention

protests.

“The principles are: 1) Our solidarity will be based on a respect for a

diversity of tactics and the plans of other groups, 2) The actions and

tactics used will be organized to maintain a separation of time or

space, 3) Any debates or criticisms will stay internal to the movement,

avoiding any public or media denunciations of fellow activists and

events, 4) We oppose any state repression of dissent, including

surveillance, infiltration, disruption and violence. We agree not to

assist law enforcement actions against activists and others” (

http://www.nornc.org/st-paul-principles/

)

These have become the standard point of departure for discussion and

deployment of destabilization actions, which has been useful in forging

an agreement between various groups and collectives around tactical

limits. This framework is a fluid and dynamic way of making sure that

all groups — regardless of tactics — have space for their own desires,

regardless of how totally ineffective many of these forms are. Diversity

of tactics at once rejects the equivalence of all acts by generating an

“ecosystem of resistance” (a term used a lot on the ground in St Paul

during the RNC) which knows no limitations. This move away from the

essentialized act creates a space which is always already destabilized

to the degree that there is a multiplicity of actions, either announced

publicly or not, while still making sure that there is a support

infrastructure in place for legal and medic support. It is an approach

based in a approach firmly rooted in theories of the multitude; “for

Spinoza, the multitudo indicates plurality which persists as such in the

public scene, in collective action, in the handling of communal affairs,

without converging into a One” (Virno, 21). It generates an environment

of potential non-reducability, an environment which rejects the

equivalence of situationality posited by the state and its civil

disturbance approaches.

Conclusion

The practical meaning of the tactical impasse of nonviolence is that the

Subject qua nonviolence frames and limits acts through the

definitionality of a fluid nonviolence immobilized in the nonviolence

guideline. In other words, the adherence to an abstract nonviolence

supersedes the tactical necessities of the situation itself, it is

nothing but institutionalized ineffectiveness. There are a series of

equivalences made in the calculations of the nonviolent action. First,

the guidelines are determined through the naming and defining of the

concept of nonviolence which comes to supersede the act and agents

themselves, substituting the equivalence for the actual participants and

situation. This is the very same move made by the state, just in a

microcosmic form. Secondly, the Subject qua state is taken as the plane

of engagement, they are the Subject of consent, doing nothing but

reinforcing the Newtonian equivalence of the state as such and

generating another appropriation of mass politics — negating the actual

existence of actual agents. In positing this series of equivalences, the

defining of nonviolence comes to supersede the actual goals of the

action itself in favor of building mass consent and support for

nonviolent tactics and politics. Can someone explain to me how this is

different than the assumption of mass movementism from Leninism to

electoral neoliberalism?

Nonviolence refuses to engage in tactics that would be effective to

rather serve the interest of preserving the mass image of nonviolence.

But how is nonviolence possible in an apparatus that has formed us in

the image of total war? To define nonviolence means to section it off

from violence; but if everything is saturated with violence, the

battlefield abolished, then this form of definitionality becomes pure

simulacra, a generated construct that by design exceeds everyday life

and forms its Subject in the cryogenic time of Newtonian equivalence.

This becoming-cryogenic prevents any form of nonviolence from responding

to attempts by the forces of the state to enforce stability over a

situation, the tactics are set, the participants are “responsible” and

harmless, and the action becomes nothing but theatre, and ineffective

theatre at that.

Bibliography

“You Can’t Blow Up A Social Relationship”. anonymous. 1979

Politics of Nonviolence. Sharp, Gene. Boston. Porter Sargent. 1973

Leviathan. Hobbes, Thomas. New York. Penguin Classic. 1982

Grammar of the Multitude. Virno, Paolo. New York. Semiotexte. 2004

Chaos: Making a New Science. Gleick, James. New York. Penguin. 2008

“Field Manual 3–19.15: Civil Disturbance Operations”. United States

Army. 2005

St Paul Principles. retrieved 1/30/2009.

www.nornc.org/st-paul-principles

Declaration of Peace Nonviolent Guidelines. retrieved 1/31/2009.

http://declarationofpeace.org/nonviolence-guidelines