đž Archived View for library.inu.red âş file âş brian-martin-how-nonviolence-is-misrepresented.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 08:02:28. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄď¸ Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: How nonviolence is misrepresented Author: Brian Martin Date: July-September 2008 Language: en Topics: nonviolence, pacifism, anti-pacifism, Peter Gelderloos, a reply Source: https://www.bmartin.cc/pubs/08gm2.htm
Peter Gelderloos in his book How Nonviolence Protects the State claims
that nonviolence is ineffective, racist, statist, patriarchal,
tactically and strategically inferior, and deluded.[1] His attack on
nonviolence is fierce and unrelenting.
To assess Gelderloosâ views, I first outline the case for nonviolence
and the associated case against violence. This provides a foundation for
examining Gelderloosâ arguments. I give special attention to his
questionable assumption that violence always triumphs over nonviolence.
In my judgement, Gelderloosâ arguments are based on pervasive double
standards. In addition, he fails to spell out what levels and types of
violence he considers acceptable, an omission that undermines his
argument. Finally, I comment on connections between anarchism and
violence/nonviolence.
I am a longstanding supporter of nonviolent action, so it is predictable
that I am critical of Gelderloosâs arguments. But I also believe
critical analysis is valuable. Nonviolent activists can become more
effective by subjecting their beliefs to logical scrutiny and empirical
testing.
Through history classes, Hollywood movies and the daily news, most
people come to believe two things about violence. One is that groups
with a greater capacity for violence â armies, weapons, military
industry and ruthlessness â can nearly always win over those with a
lesser capacity. This is the assumption behind the question âWhat would
you do to stop the Nazis?â asked rhetorically as a presumed refutation
of nonviolence.[2] Second, most people believe that violence is a tool,
usually a neutral tool. If it is used by bad guys â the enemy,
terrorists or criminals â violence is bad, but when used by good guys â
âour sideâ â then it is good. Most supporters of revolutionary warfare
accept these assumptions: they believe revolution is a good cause and
hope to use armed struggle to achieve it.
Nonviolent action challenges both these assumptions: the successes of
nonviolent action challenge the belief that superior violence always
succeeds; the characteristics of nonviolent action make it an especially
appropriate tool for helping create a nonviolent society.
Mohandas Gandhi was the key figure in creating awareness of nonviolent
action as a distinctive approach to social change, principally through
campaigns in South Africa beginning in 1906 and then in India from 1915
through the 1940s. Nonviolent action had been used for centuries before
Gandhi. For example, Hungarians who opposed domination by Austria used a
range of methods of noncooperation from 1850 to 1867.[3] One of Gandhiâs
achievements was to put nonviolent action on the agenda as a strategic
approach.
Gandhiâs campaigns had an enormous influence worldwide, leading to the
development and diffusion of nonviolent campaigning skills and insights.
In many social movements, nonviolent action has become the preferred
approach.
Nonviolent action, as a technique of political communication and waging
conflict, can be distinguished from conventional action and from
violence.
Conventional political action includes voting, lobbying and campaigning
â anything that is routine within a society. Conventional economic
action includes working, and buying and selling goods and shares.
Conventional social action includes meetings of clubs or neighbours,
charitable work and much else. Nonviolent action, in contrast, goes
beyond routine behaviour, often by challenging conventional practices.
Examples include protesters disrupting a government meeting by dressing
as clowns, a neighbourhood association setting up an alternative system
of social welfare, war resisters refusing to pay taxes, consumer
activists blocking service in a bank by opening and closing small
accounts, bus drivers refusing to collect fares, office workers sending
large files to clog an email system, and communities setting up local
currencies.
The boundary between conventional and nonviolent action depends on the
circumstances. When government repression is severe, handing out a
leaflet might count as nonviolent action, whereas in some places strikes
are so common and widely accepted that participating in one might be
considered conventional action.
Violence means physical force used against humans, including
imprisonment, beatings, shootings, bombings and torture.[4] Nonviolent
action excludes these. Sabotage â violence against objects â lies at the
boundary between violence and nonviolence.[5]
Nonviolent action thus encompasses a wide range of activities that go
beyond conventional, routine action but do not involve physical violence
against humans. When people think about nonviolent protests, rallies and
sit-ins commonly come to mind, but there are many other sorts, such as
workers refusing to tear down an iconic building, judges resigning in
protest over political pressure, roads activists digging up streets and
planting crops, and office workers misplacing or destroying files on
dissidents targeted for surveillance and arrest.
Nonviolent action is action â it doesnât include passivity or inaction â
and it goes beyond conventional methods of political communication and
waging conflict, such as discussion, negotiation or lobbying. Nonviolent
action is nonviolent on the part of those who use it. Their opponents
can and often do use violence, sometimes brutally.
Nonviolent action can be divided into actions against something, such as
most strikes and boycotts, and actions for something, such as workers
organising to produce socially useful products or doing their jobs
without bosses. The against actions typically target injustices; the for
actions typically seek to build a better society.
With this picture of nonviolent action, what are the reasons for
choosing it rather than conventional action or violence? There are two
main traditions, commonly called principled and pragmatic
nonviolence.[6] Principled nonviolence is undertaken for moral reasons,
namely that it is wrong to use violence. This is the Gandhian tradition.
Pragmatic nonviolence is undertaken because it is believed to be more
effective than alternatives, in particular more effective than violence.
Principled nonviolent activists refuse to use violence under any
circumstances. For example, they refuse to join armies, no matter how
worthy the cause. However, many principled nonviolent activists pay
close attention to effectiveness: they refuse to use violence, but they
choose their tactics carefully.[7] Pragmatic nonviolent activists, on
the other hand, often proclaim their commitment to nonviolence, knowing
this increases their credibility. So, in practice, there is an overlap
of principled and pragmatic rationales.
Here I concentrate on arguments for pragmatic nonviolence because they
allow a more direct comparison with Gelderloosâ case. Principled
nonviolence has its own arguments and criteria which are important but
given less attention here.
Gene Sharp, the most prominent researcher of pragmatic nonviolence,
divides the methods of nonviolent action into three types:
protest disrobings and renunciation of honours;
strikes and boycotts;
alternative institutions.[8]
From a pragmatic perspective, what are the reasons for choosing
nonviolent action? In other words, what are the benefits of nonviolent
action compared to alternatives? Out of many that could be listed, here
are four.
1. Nonviolent action involves withdrawal of support from the system. It
is a challenge to the legitimacy of standard behaviours or policies.[9]
In contrast, conventional actions, such as voting, implicitly support
the system by using its own methods.
2. Nonviolent action usually wins more support than does violence.
Nonviolent actions â at least when well chosen â leave open a greater
opportunity for communication. Opponents, by not being physically
harmed, are accorded a certain respect: implicitly, their health and
life are respected. Opponents are less fearful and hence do not have to
be as ferocious in defence or attack.
When violence is used against nonviolent protesters, this is widely seen
as unjust, and can lead to a major reaction against the violent
attackers, a process Sharp calls political jiu-jitsu.[10] This can
stimulate protest supporters to become more active, encourage uninvolved
third parties to join the side of the protesters and even disgust some
opponents of the protesters, causing their loyalty to shift.
3. Nonviolent action allows widespread participation. Women, children,
elderly people and people with disabilities can participate in many
forms of nonviolent action. This can be a goal in itself.
Much nonviolent action can be organised openly. This allows greater
participation than clandestine operations.
Much nonviolent action is empowering for participants, promoting
feelings of capability, solidarity and satisfaction.[11] Greater
participation means greater empowerment.
4. Nonviolent action as a method is compatible with the goal of a
nonviolent society.
Using methods that reflect the goal is called prefiguration: the methods
prefigure â in other words, anticipate or replicate in advance â the
goal. Prefiguration provides training and experience in what is being
sought. It helps create an element of the goal, even if a campaign is
unsuccessful. And it helps keep efforts on track.
If the goal is a society without organised violence, nonviolent action
has all these prefigurative advantages. It provides experiences in
living without using violence; it reduces immediate violence in the here
and now, even when campaigns fail; and it ensures that efforts are in a
nonviolent direction.
Each of these four points can be applied to violence.
1. Violence involves a withdrawal of consent from the system. In this
regard, violence and nonviolence are similar.
2. Violence often alienates potential supporters. Opponents may dig in
and resist more strenuously. A psychological perspective called
correspondent inference theory helps explain why. People often infer
someone elseâs motivations by looking at the consequences of their
actions. If the actions lead to people dying, the inference is that
activists are motivated to kill â not to liberate, which might be their
actual motivation. This theory helps explain why terroristsâ motives are
so widely misinterpreted.[12]
Violence targets individuals, but harming individuals is not an
effective way to challenge systems of oppression. Killing a politician
does not undermine the state, because politicians can be replaced,
sometimes with ones who are worse. Furthermore, a person who is a
politician has other roles, such as parent, friend and musician.
Violence, by not discriminating between roles, destroys much that is
good, rather than targeting the damaging roles and building on the
beneficial ones.[13]
When challengers use violence, this gives greater legitimacy to state
violence against them. The jiu-jitsu effect is reduced, even when the
state uses far more violence than challengers.
3. Violence restricts participation. Young fit men predominate in both
armies and armed liberation movements. The secrecy accompanying armed
struggle also limits participation.
Violence can be empowering for those involved, but limited participation
means the empowerment is restricted.
4. Violence as a method clashes with the goal of a nonviolent society.
Using violence gives training, experience and legitimacy to violence. It
causes immediate suffering. And it is easier for campaigns to go off
track, down a path towards ongoing violence and associated domination.
Points 2, 3 and 4 constitute the core of the case against violence, from
a nonviolence point of view.
Note that these arguments for nonviolent action and against violence are
tendencies, not universal truths. For example, nonviolent action usually
wins more support than violence, but not always. Some nonviolent methods
allow only limited participation whereas some violent movements have
many participants. In adopting nonviolent action from a pragmatic point
of view, attention needs to be given to the circumstances.
Many nonviolent campaigns are largely spontaneous, without much
preparation, planning or training. No one expects armed movements
without weapons, training or plans to be very successful. Considering
the vast amounts of money and effort put into military operations, it is
reasonable to expect that nonviolent action could become far more
effective with more resources.
For those with a principled commitment to nonviolence, the circumstances
do not matter: they reject violence, even if assassinating a dictator
might reduce the suffering of millions. But there is an important link
between pragmatic assessments and principled stands. If, pragmatically,
nonviolent action is usually a better choice, then it can be
(pragmatically) sensible to make a principled commitment, because it
reduces the risks of misunderstanding by participants, of being falsely
labelled violent by opponents, and of going off track in a violent
direction.
Gelderloos is an anarchist. He opposes systems based on hierarchy and
supports egalitarian social relationships created and maintained by the
people involved in them. He is opposed to the state, capitalism, racism
and patriarchy. Being opposed to capitalism puts him in the left
generally, but as an anarchist he is opposed to the state, including
state socialism whether advocated by reformist socialists seeking state
power through electoral means or by Marxist-Leninists who want to seize
control of the state, most commonly through armed struggle, in order to
crush capitalism. Gelderloos wants instead to destroy the state â and
capitalism, racism and patriarchy â so that people can create their own
non-hierarchical systems of self-rule.
Gelderloos is an activist and has spent time in prison as a result of
protest actions. His passionate commitment to liberation cannot be
doubted. But while respecting his vision, dedication and energy, it is
possible to criticise his arguments, conclusions and methods.
Rather than take up Gelderloosâ claims about nonviolence one by one, it
is more illuminating to understand his perspective as stemming from a
few key assumptions. At the core of his thinking is the view that
nonviolence cannot be successful against violence.
The state, in the conventional sociological conception, is based on a
monopoly over the use of legitimate violence. Gelderloos supports
revolutionary change including overthrow and dissolution of the state.
He believes that leaders of the state will not acquiesce. Hence, he
concludes, physical force must be used.
If nonviolent action cannot succeed against violence, then Gelderloosâ
other conclusions follow.
violence (pp. 7â22).
preaching nonviolence, and abandoning to state repression those who do
not listen obediently, white activists who think they are concerned
about racism are actually enacting a paternalistic relationship and
fulfilling the useful role of pacifying the oppressed.â (p. 34).
challenge that Gelderloos believes can overthrow it, namely violence:
âPut quite plainly, nonviolence ensures a state monopoly on violence.â
(p. 45).
powerful tool â violence â against male domination: âa pacifist practice
that forbids the use of any other tactics leaves no option for people
who need to protect themselves from violence now.â (p. 67).
against authority will be violent, because authority itself is violent
and the inevitable repression is an escalation of that violence....
Lobbying for social change is a waste of scarce resources for radical
movements.â (p. 94).
would be much easier to end the psychological patterns of violence and
domination once we had destroyed the social institutions, political
bodies, and economic structures specifically constituted to perpetuate
coercive domination. But proponents of nonviolence boldly sound the call
to retreat, declaring that we should treat the symptoms while the
disease is free to spread itself, defend itself, and vote itself pay
raises.â (p. 126).
Some of these arguments sound strange. How, for example, can nonviolence
be patriarchal when women have been so prominent in nonviolent action
whereas armed groups are almost always dominated by men? But Gelderloosâ
argument has an underlying coherence built on his assumption that
nonviolence cannot succeed against violence, which leads to his
conclusion that violence is needed to overthrow oppressive systems,
including patriarchy: âif a movement is not a threat, it cannot change a
system based on centralized coercion and violenceâ (p. 22). Here,
âthreatâ means the potential to use violence. Because nonviolence, in
Gelderloosâ eyes, doesnât pose a threat in this sense, he concludes that
it is patriarchal.
Therefore, rather than address in detail Gelderloosâ claims about
racism, patriarchy and the like, it is more useful to tackle his central
claim that nonviolence is unable to be effective against violence,
especially because this assumption is a common one. So how does
Gelderloos support this claim?
He certainly doesnât do it by addressing nonviolence theory: he does not
systematically examine it.[14] Gelderloos treats all nonviolence as
principled nonviolence, thereby missing pragmatic nonviolence. He
mentions Gene Sharp only in passing and does not discuss Sharpâs theory
of power or Sharpâs methods and dynamics of nonviolent action. He does
not address the key dynamic of political jiu-jitsu, which explains how
violence used against nonviolent protesters can be counterproductive.
Nor does Gelderloos examine George Lakeyâs strategy for nonviolent
revolution.[15] In fact, he assumes that nonviolence cannot be
revolutionary, for example referring to ânonviolent and revolutionary
activistsâ (p. 83).
Instead, Gelderloos assesses nonviolence by examining a number of
nonviolent campaigns. He dismisses every one as not really constituting
a success by using a series of arguments, deployed selectively, often
with a double standard in relation to violence.
1. Gelderloosâ first argument against nonviolent campaigns is to say
that they werenât entirely nonviolent. If he can point to evidence of
violence in campaigns, he dismisses the contribution of nonviolent
action. Referring to 1962 black riots in Georgia and Alabama, Gelderloos
concludes âPerhaps the largest of the limited, if not hollow, victories
of the civil rights movement came when black people demonstrated they
would not remain peaceful forever.â (p. 12)
There is a double standard here. In guerrilla struggles and other
campaigns involving violence, there is also a great amount of nonviolent
action, for example during the Vietnam war, the Iraq war and the second
Palestinian intifada. Why should violence be given all the credit when
both violence and nonviolence are used?
2. Gelderloosâ second argument against nonviolent campaigns is to say
they didnât really change anything. They werenât liberation. They didnât
overthrow the state â just the current rulers â and didnât overthrow
capitalism. âThe liberation movement in India failed. The British were
not forced to quit India. Rather, they chose to transfer the territory
from direct colonial rule to neocolonial rule.â (p. 9)
With this argument, Gelderloos again exhibits a double standard, because
he doesnât assess violent campaigns with the same stringent
expectations. He refers approvingly to the Black Panthers in the US in
the 1960s and 1970s and the anarchist revolutionaries in the Ukraine in
the early 1920s, among others, none of which overthrew capitalism or the
state. He lauds these initiatives for standing up to the state, for
showing what can be accomplished, for striking fear into the heart of
rulers and for empowering participants. That is all well and good, but
he doesnât give nonviolent campaigns credit for equivalent
accomplishments.
Gelderloos doesnât give a single example of an armed struggle leading to
the sort of liberated society he espouses. Why not? Undoubtedly because
successful armed struggles â such as in China, Cuba, Algeria and Vietnam
â have not abolished the state but rather, if anything, strengthened it.
Armed struggle encourages militarisation of the movement, making it more
hierarchical and authoritarian. These features seldom wither away after
revolutionary victories.
3. If a campaign fails, Gelderloos attributes this to the use of
nonviolent action and insufficient use of violence. In the 1989
pro-democracy movement in China, âthe students who had put themselves in
control of the movement refused to arm themselves ...â (pp. 122â123).
The double standard here is that Gelderloos does not mention the failure
of armed movements in Bolivia, Latvia, Malaya, Philippines, Uruguay and
many other countries.
Gelderloos ignores the difference between spontaneous and strategic
nonviolent action.[16] Many failed campaigns have relied mainly on
spontaneous nonviolent action, without careful planning and training. To
dismiss these as failures of nonviolent action as a method would be like
dismissing violence as a method because of the failure of spontaneous
rioting.
4. In referring to recent campaigns that unseated governments in Serbia,
Ukraine and other countries, Gelderloos says they were âorchestratedâ by
the US government (p. 100). He doesnât give any evidence for this claim,
aside from citing one newspaper story.
It is true that the US government has provided financial assistance to
some nonviolent movements, for example Otpor in Serbia, a key resistance
group in triggering the mass movement that brought down president
Slobodan Milosevic in 2000. The contribution of US government assistance
to these movements has been debated, not least among nonviolent
activists, some of whom have argued against accepting assistance because
of the risk of being accused of being pawns of the US government.
Gelderloos addresses none of the complexities of these situations,
simply assuming that because the US government was involved, therefore
it orchestrated the whole operation.[17]
The double standard in this case is that Gelderloos does not make a
similar claim in relation to violent struggles. During the Vietnam war,
the National Liberation Front received considerable assistance from the
Soviet government. Does this mean the NLFâs victory was orchestrated by
the Soviet government? Of course not. The struggleâs success depended on
the massive support and sacrifice of the Vietnamese people. Exactly the
same can be said about nonviolent campaigns that receive US government
funding: the campaigns would not stand a chance without popular support.
There is also a double standard in Gelderloosâ failure to mention cases
in which the US government supported violent resistance. In Afghanistan
after the 1979 Soviet invasion, the CIA covertly funded mujahideen
opponents. In Kosovo, the US government ignored a decade-long nonviolent
struggle[18] and then supported an armed movement, the Kosovo Liberation
Army, previously classified as terrorists. By Gelderloosâ logic, these
armed struggles were orchestrated by the US government and therefore the
role of violence can be discounted.
5. Gelderloos ignores a great number of nonviolent campaigns, thereby
avoiding the need to address their challenge to his argument. His claim
about US government orchestration falls down entirely for nonviolent
campaigns prior to the 1990s, before which there is no evidence of any
US government assistance. In one of many examples, in 1944 the dictator
of El Salvador â a US client state â was toppled in a popular nonviolent
campaign.[19]
Gelderloos claims that the nonviolent strategy of generalised
disobedience cannot bring power to the people because the state still
controls key resources and the loyalty of the military and police: âin
recent decades, the only significant military defections have occurred
when the military faced violent resistance and the government seemed to
be in its death throes.â (p. 99). To the contrary, there are quite a few
cases in which military defections have occurred without there being
much violent resistance, including the Philippines in 1986, various
Eastern European countries in 1989, the Soviet Union in 1991, and Serbia
in 2000. Gelderloos is right that military defections are essential for
revolution,[20] but defections can occur as a result of nonviolent
methods such as fraternisation.
Gelderloosâ dismissal of the power of nonviolent action is so one-sided
and filled with double standards that it would be easy to miss an
important point: there has been very little systematic comparison of the
effectiveness of violence and nonviolence.
Making comparisons is complex, because the success of a campaign or
movement depends on many factors, including belief systems, human and
material resources, social cohesion, political alignments and
international factors, in addition to the methods used by activists. The
choice of violent or nonviolent methods may tip the balance in some
circumstances, but the other factors still need to be considered.[21]
In the vast body of research on social movements, there is little on the
effectiveness of violence. In one of the few relevant studies,
sociologist William Gamson in his book The Strategy of Social Protest
analyses 53 US challenging groups between 1800 and 1945. In a chapter
titled âThe success of the unruly,â he assesses outcomes for groups that
used violence compared to those that were recipients of violence without
fighting back.[22] In this comparison, groups that used violence were
far more likely to be successful, namely to gain acceptance and obtain
new advantages. However, Gamson is reluctant to attribute success to
violence, arguing instead that âit is not the weakness of the user but
the weakness of the target that accounts for violenceâ: violence is âas
much a symptom of success as a cause.â[23]
Gamson does not use the expression ânonviolent actionâ nor refer to any
writings in the area. He does, though, analyse movementsâ use of
âconstraintsâ including strikes, boycotts and denunciation. He finds
that movements that used constraints but not violence were far more
likely to be successful than ones that did not use constraints. In
effect, he shows that coercive methods of nonviolent action â what Sharp
would call methods of noncooperation and intervention â are associated
with success.
Gamsonâs study, while illuminating, does not directly compare the
effectiveness of options for a given movement because, as he well
recognises, he is analysing different movements in different
circumstances. However, he does give strong backing for the conclusion
that a movement being âunrulyâ is associated with success.[24] Violence
and nonviolence are different ways of being unruly.
In 2005, Freedom House published a study of 67 political transitions
occurring in countries with authoritarian governments in the period
1973â2000, looking at the level of violence, the source of violence and
the forces driving the transitions. Using Freedom Houseâs pre-existing
ratings of freedom in the countries before and after the transitions,
the authors were able to assess the comparative roles of violence and
nonviolence. Their principal findings:
forces are a major source of pressure for decisive change in most
transitions.â
âtop-downâ transitions that were launched and led by elites.â
coalitions is the most important of the factors examined in contributing
to freedom.â
significantly enhanced when the opposition does not itself use
violence.â[25]
These conclusions go directly against Gelderloosâ claims. Though he
might dismiss them because of the politics of Freedom House or because
none of the political transitions involved revolutionary overthrow of
capitalism and the state, nonetheless they undermine his claims about
the comparative ineffectiveness of nonviolent action.
In a forthcoming paper, Maria Stephan and Erica Chenoweth analyse data
for 323 violent and nonviolent resistance campaigns from 1900 to 2006,
concluding that nonviolent campaigns are more likely to achieve
strategic objectives. They say, âNonviolent campaigns are more likely to
win legitimacy, attract widespread domestic and international support,
neutralize the opponentâs security forces, and compel loyalty shifts
amongst erstwhile opponent supporters than armed campaigns, which enjoin
the active support of a relatively small number of people, offer the
opponent a justification for violent counter-attacks, and are less
likely to prompt loyalty shifts and defections.â[26] Additional careful
studies of campaigns and outcomes are needed because it is so easy to
reach a desired conclusion by the choice of a few selected examples.
Gelderloos frequently highlights the violence of the state â âthe
greatest purveyor of violenceâ (p. 158) â and other systems of
oppression, with the implicit assumption that this justifies violence to
destroy these systems. The issue of the legitimacy receives quite a lot
of attention in discussions of violence. William T. Vollmann in his
mammoth analysis of violence, Rising Up and Rising Down, focuses on
justifications for and consequences of violence, and includes a detailed
moral calculus.[27]
But just because violence might be justified does not mean it is the
best option. If someone at a party swears at you, you might be legally
and morally justified in suing for slander, but it is seldom a wise idea
to do so: it is likely to be very costly and could harm your reputation
even more.[28] Similarly for violence: although justified, it might be
counterproductive in legitimising counter-violence, reducing
participation, and leading down a path towards more violence. This
highlights, once again, the importance of careful comparisons of the
effectiveness of violence and nonviolence, taking into account both
immediate outcomes and longer-term impacts on morale, solidarity and
mobilisation.
Gelderloosâ arguments against nonviolent action in part miss the mark
because he misconstrues nonviolence and makes claims without evidence.
For example:
rocking the boat or causing conflict, you are doing something wrongâ (p.
20). The only evidence given for this sweeping claim is one email. Note
that Gelderloosâ persistent use of the term pacifist is misleading.
Historically, many pacifists do not engage in nonviolent action and many
nonviolent activists are not pacifists.
due consideration.â (p. 66). Actually, many nonviolent activists are
feminists and have worked against male violence.[29]
misconception.[30] The terms satyagraha and nonviolent action were
developed to supersede the misleading expression âpassive resistance.â
underestimates the culture industry and thought control by the media.â
(p. 85). Persuasion is only one of the ways that nonviolence works.
Sharp lists dozens of methods of noncooperation and intervention.[31]
power and pretending they are engaged in some process of magically
transforming the state through the âpower of love,â or their ânonviolent
witness,â or by disseminating heartwrenching images of cardboard puppets
through the media, or some other swill.â (p. 108). Actually, nonviolent
activists have repeatedly confronted state power.[32]
130). The usual claim is that means influence ends.[33]
violence and nonviolence, is unrealistic and self-defeating.â (p. 139).
Nonviolent activists are well aware of degrees of violence. It is
possible to draw a line between violence and nonviolence in theory and
practice while recognising different types of actions within each
category.
There are many other examples of contentious statements by Gelderloos
for which he gives no evidence or cites an email or personal comment but
draws conclusions apparently intended to apply to all nonviolent
activists. Gelderloos may be correct that some nonviolent activists are
â perhaps unconsciously â racist, paternalist or too timid. But this
does not mean that nonviolent action, as a method of struggle, has the
same characteristics, any more than the racism or other features of
violent activists mean that violence is racist.
Gelderloos often uses sources in a selective, misleading fashion. For
example, he criticises an article by Carol Flinders about women and
nonviolence, incorrectly portraying it as saying women are inherently
nonviolent.[34] He cites Martha McCaugheyâs book Real Knockouts, an
analysis of the womenâs self-defence movement, in support of his
argument for womenâs violence against patriarchy, missing the complexity
and sophistication of McCaugheyâs argument.[35]
Gelderloos approvingly quotes (pp. 114â115) Martin Oppenheimerâs book
The Urban Guerrilla concerning shortcomings of nonviolence but omits any
mention of Oppenheimerâs trenchant criticisms of violence, such as:
subversive of democratic values and institutions, and the habit of
solving political issues through violent means, far from liberating,
imprisons persons and personalities so that truly democratic
participation in decision-making become nearly impossible.â
it tend not to be the kind of people who will create a positive,
humanistic order ... the kind of organization seemingly required to
conduct a violent effort is inherently subversive of such an order.â
being therapeutic, endangers when it does not utterly destroy the
humanistic component of a social movement.â[36]
How Nonviolence Protects the State is curiously coy about the actual
role violence might play in liberation. Gelderloos explicitly rejects
presenting a definition of violence: â... one of the critical arguments
of this book is that violence cannot be clearly defined.â (p. 3). He
says that many activists consider everyday activities, such as âbuying
clothes made in a sweatshopâ, to be violent and says the concept of
violence isnât useful when âno two people can really agree on what it
meansâ (pp. 124â125). However, even though activists may have different
conceptions about terms, itâs still possible for analysts to agree on
meanings.
Gelderloos, by leaving violence ill-defined, is able to avoid spelling
out what he sees as the appropriate or inappropriate use of violence in
liberation. He prefers to focus on hierarchy as the key to oppression
and to say that all means of challenging hierarchy should be considered,
without bothering about the difference between violence and nonviolence.
He advocates a diversity of tactics, assuming that the more tactics are
available to be used, the more effective a movement can be. Because a
commitment to nonviolence means ruling out some tactics, Gelderloos
concludes that nonviolence is bound to be less effective than a broader
diversity of tactics.
There are a few clues in the text about what sorts of actions Gelderloos
is thinking about:
burning down the office of a magazine that consciously markets a beauty
standard that leads to anorexia and bulimia, kidnapping the president of
a company that conducts women-traffickingâ (p. 67)
toxicâ; âkill the general who sends out the soldiers who rape women in a
war zoneâ (p. 69)
grassroots media outletsâ (p. 90).
The question arises: are there any methods that Gelderloos rejects? Does
he reject use of machine guns? Does he reject missiles? Does he reject
biological weapons? Does he reject nuclear weapons? Does he reject
torture?[37] If Gelderloos rejects any of these methods, perhaps because
they are inhumane or counterproductive, then he is drawing a line,
accepting that not all methods are acceptable in a diversity of tactics.
One of Gelderloosâ chief complaints is that nonviolent activists are
unwilling to support activists who use violence. Is Gelderloos willing
to support any activist, even ones who use land mines and chemical
weapons? If not, then his strictures against nonviolent activists, who
draw a line at a different place, reflect a double standard in his
argument.
Because Gelderloos articulately describes himself as an anarchist, some
readers might gain the mistaken impression that he speaks for anarchists
generally. Actually, anarchists have long debated and disagreed about
the use of violence in bringing about social change. Some anarchists
believe violence is warranted and necessary. The most famous armed
struggle by anarchists was during the Spanish revolution and civil war
from 1936â1939, when workers ran farms and factories and anarchist
militias defended the revolution both from Francoâs fascists (backed by
Hitler) and from communists. However, since then anarchist armed
struggle has not played a prominent role, though a few anarchists have
advocated using guerrilla methods designed for an industrialised
country.[38]
There is also a parallel strand within anarchism that opposes use of
violence.[39] Furthermore, some anarchists are openly committed to
nonviolence.[40]
Pragmatically, the prospects for armed liberation within industrialised
countries have been minimal for decades. In this context, many
anarchists believe that using violence would be futile.[41] Prominent
anarchist Murray Bookchin wrote,
The state power we face is too formidable, its armamentarium is too
destructive, and, if its structure is still intact, its efficiency is
too compelling to be removed by a contest in which weaponry is the
determining factor. The system must fall, not fight; and it will fall
only when its institutions have been so hollowed out by the new
Enlightenment, and its power so undermined physically and morally, that
an insurrectionary confrontation will be more symbolic than real.[42]
Another rationale arises out of the anarchist belief in prefiguration,
namely that means should reflect ends. If the goal is a world without
organised violence, this means avoiding violence in the struggle for
such a world. However, anarchists have long debated the application of
this principle to the use of violence.[43]
Marxists, in contrast, seldom subscribe to prefiguration. They instead
assume that the ends justify the means, most notoriously in capturing
state power to smash capitalism, after which the state is supposed to
wither away: the ultimate Marxist goal is communism, in which there is
no state, the same goal as anarchists. (This is the original meaning of
communism, as distinct from the reality of states ruled by Communist
parties.) Anarchists in the 1800s argued against Marxists, prophetically
warning that capturing state power was a prescription for dictatorial
rule.
Gandhi can be considered an anarchist.[44] He opposed the state,
proposing instead village democracy. He refused an offer to lead newly
independent India, unlike those anarchists who joined the government of
Republican Spain in the 1930s.
The goal of anarchists is a society built around non-hierarchical
structures organised by the people involved in them â an approach known
as self-management â and hence anarchists strive to create
non-hierarchical structures in their own organisations and campaigns.
They have promoted cooperatives and workersâ control as alternatives to
capitalist enterprise. They have promoted egalitarian relations between
men and women.
Another point of debate within anarchism is the issue of revolution.
Some, like Gelderloos, believe in destruction of capitalism and the
state in a mass uprising to bring about self-managed systems. Others
point to examples of self-management within todayâs societies, believing
that anarchist practices can grow up in the interstices of existing
institutions, eventually supplanting them.[45] If social structures are
likened to a forest, then revolution is like cutting down the trees and
planting new species, whereas in an evolutionary model, new species grow
up between the old, eventually becoming dominant.[46]
Gelderloos gives no hint of debates over violence and revolution within
the anarchist movement: for him, anarchism seems to mean his own
particular set of beliefs. Nor does he acknowledge the anarchist
sensibility that is widespread in nonviolent movements.[47] Many
activists are sceptical of the state and other dominant institutions and
favour non-hierarchical forms of organisation, even though they are
unfamiliar with anarchist writings. They also favour nonviolent action,
which may explain why Gelderloos does not give credit to their anarchist
sensibility.
Since the days of Gandhiâs campaigns, nonviolent activists have been
criticised by supporters of armed struggle.[48] In recent years, the
most comprehensive critiques of nonviolence have been by Howard
Ryan,[49] Ward Churchill[50] and Gelderloos. Unfortunately, many
critiques suffer through inadequate understanding of nonviolence, often
due to a failure to engage with writings in the area.[51]
Gelderloos has shown enormous commitment as an activist and great energy
in compiling a comprehensive critique of nonviolence. Unfortunately, he
has missed his main target: in essence, he attacks principled
nonviolence from a perspective in which the ends justify the means. He
dismisses nonviolent action campaigns using a set of arguments that
display systematic double standards.
Underlying Gelderloosâ argument is the assumption that violence is more
effective than nonviolence. This is certainly a common assumption, but
if a critique of nonviolence is to have any real teeth, the assumption
needs to be justified and counterexamples addressed.
Gelderloos shows almost no awareness of the pragmatic tradition in
nonviolent action. He misrepresents nonviolent action as consisting
solely of protest and persuasion, missing the more coercive methods of
noncooperation and intervention. Furthermore, he ignores a large number
of major nonviolent struggles, successful and unsuccessful.
A key omission in Gelderloosâ argument is a discussion of limits in a
diversity of tactics: he does not say whether any methods should be
ruled out. Almost any activist will agree that some methods should not
be used, whether it is assassination, land mines or biological weapons.
The question then becomes where to draw the line.
The limitations of Gelderloosâ argument point to some ways for
nonviolent activists to improve the presentation of their own views.
nonviolence by using simple examples, for example of when violence is
counterproductive for the state or protesters.
for example by pointing out failures of violence.
nonviolence, and the interaction between principles and effectiveness.
I thank Andy Chan, Howard Clark, Jørgen Johansen, Colin Salter, Maria
Stephan, Ralph Summy, Tom Weber and Steve Wright for valuable comments.
[1] Peter Gelderloos, How Nonviolence Protects the State (Cambridge, MA:
South End Press, 2007).
[2] For a discussion, see Michael C. Stratford, â
Can nonviolent defence be effective if the opponent is ruthless?: the Nazi case
,â Social Alternatives, Vol. 6, No. 2, April 1987, pp. 49â57; Brian
Martin, â
,â Social Alternatives, Vol. 6, No. 3, August 1987, pp. 47â49; Jacques
Semelin, Unarmed Against Hitler: Civilian Resistance in Europe 1939â1943
(Westport, CT: Praeger, 1993); Ralph Summy, âNonviolence and the case of
the extremely ruthless opponent,â Pacifica Review, Vol. 6, No. 1,
May-June 1994, pp. 1â29.
[3] TamĂĄs Csapody and Thomas Weber, âHungarian nonviolent resistance
against Austria and its place in the history of nonviolence,â Peace &
Change, Vol. 32, No. 4, October 2007, pp. 499â519.
[4] The damage done to people through oppressive systems, such as
exploitation, poverty and preventable disease, is commonly called
structural violence.
[5] Some forms of sabotage, for example workers damaging equipment to
interrupt production, such as in Nazi weapons factories, are commonly
seen as nonviolent action. Others, such as blowing up large dams, are
not, especially when the risk of hurting people is significant.
Disagreements and disputes about sabotage are a recurring feature of
discussions about nonviolent action.
[6] Judith Stiehm, âNonviolence is two,â Sociological Inquiry, Vol. 38,
Winter 1968, pp. 23â30.
[7] Gene Sharp, Gandhi as a Political Strategist (Boston: Porter
Sargent, 1979).
[8] Gene Sharp, The Politics of Nonviolent Action (Boston: Porter
Sargent, 1973), Part Two. On Sharpâs relation to Gandhi, see Thomas
Weber, âNonviolence is who? Gene Sharp and Gandhi,â Peace & Change, Vol.
28, April 2003, pp. 250â270.
[9] Sharp, Politics of Nonviolent Action, pp. 7â62; Gene Sharp, Social
Power and Political Freedom (Boston: Porter Sargent, 1980), pp. 21â67,
309â378.
[10] Sharp, Politics of Nonviolent Action, pp. 657â703.
[11] Ibid., pp. 777â799.
[12] Max Abrahms, âWhy terrorism does not work,â International Security,
Vol. 31, No. 2, Fall 2006, pp. 42â78.
[13] I thank Jørgen Johansen for this point.
[14] Kurt Schock, âNonviolent action and its misconceptions: insights
for social scientists,â PS: Political Science and Politics, Vol. 36, No.
4, October 2003, pp. 705â712, lists 18 common misconceptions about
nonviolent action. Gelderloos holds quite a few of them.
[15] George Lakey, Strategy for a Living Revolution (New York: Grossman,
1973). On nonviolent revolution see also Bart de Ligt, The Conquest of
Violence: An Essay on War and Revolution (London: George Routledge &
Sons, 1937); Dave Dellinger, Revolutionary Nonviolence: Essays
(Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1970); Narayan Desai, Towards a
Non-violent Revolution (Rajghat, Varanasi: Sarva Seva Sangh Prakashan,
1972); Geoffrey Ostergaard, Nonviolent Revolution in India (New Delhi:
Gandhi Peace Foundation, 1985). On anarchist views, see Andy Chan,
âViolence, nonviolence, and the concept of revolution in anarchist
thought,â Anarchist Studies, Vol. 12, No. 2, 2004, pp. 103â123.
[16] On the latter, see Peter Ackerman and Christopher Kruegler,
Strategic Nonviolent Conflict: The Dynamics of People Power in the
Twentieth Century (Westport, CT: Praeger, 1994); Robert L. Helvey, On
Strategic Nonviolent Conflict: Thinking about the Fundamentals (Boston:
Albert Einstein Institution, 2004).
[17] Valerie Bunce and Sharon Wolchik, âBringing down dictators:
American democracy promotion and electoral revolutions in postcommunist
Eurasia,â Mario Einaudi Center for International Studies, Cornell
University, Working Paper 5â07, July 2007, p. 15: âTo reduce the
electoral revolutions to the machinations of the U.S., however, is a
serious mistake.â See also Andrew Wilson, Ukraineâs Orange Revolution
(New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2005), pp. 183â189. I thank
Howard Clark for recommending these references.
[18] Howard Clark, Civil Resistance in Kosovo (London: Pluto, 2000).
[19] Patricia Parkman, Nonviolent Insurrection in El Salvador: The Fall
of Maximiliano HernĂĄndez MartĂnez (Tucson: University of Arizona Press,
1988). For other cases and analysis see Peter Ackerman and Jack DuVall,
A Force More Powerful: A Century of Nonviolent Conflict (New York: St.
Martinâs Press, 2000); Ralph E. Crow, Philip Grant, and Saad E. Ibrahim
(eds.), Arab Nonviolent Political Struggle in the Middle East (Boulder:
Lynne Rienner, 1990); Philip McManus and Gerald Schlabach (eds.),
Relentless Persistence: Nonviolent Action in Latin America
(Philadelphia: New Society Press, 1991); Patricia Parkman,
Insurrectionary Civic Strikes in Latin America 1931â1961 (Cambridge, MA:
Albert Einstein Institution, 1990); Kurt Schock, Unarmed Insurrections:
People Power Movements in Nondemocracies (Minneapolis, MN: University of
Minnesota Press, 2005); Stephen Zunes, âUnarmed insurrections against
authoritarian governments in the Third World: a new kind of revolution,â
Third World Quarterly, Vol. 15, No. 3, 1994, pp. 403â426; Stephen Zunes,
Lester R. Kurtz, and Sarah Beth Asher (eds.), Nonviolent Social
Movements: A Geographical Perspective (Oxford: Blackwell, 1999).
[20] Katherine Chorley, Armies and the Art of Revolution (London: Faber
& Faber, 1943).
[21] I thank Howard Clark for emphasising this point.
[22] William A. Gamson, The Strategy of Social Protest (Homewood, IL:
Dorsey Press, 1975), pp. 72â88. I thank Doug McAdam for recommending
this reference.
[23] Ibid., p. 82.
[24] A similar argument is made by Frances Fox Piven and Richard A.
Cloward, Poor Peopleâs Movements: Why They Succeed, How They Fail (New
York Vintage, 1979). See also Doug McAdam and Yang Su, âThe war at home:
antiwar protests and Congressional voting, 1965 to 1973,â American
Sociological Review, Vol. 67, October 2002, pp. 696â721.
[25] Adrian Karatnycky and Peter Ackerman, How Freedom is Won: From
Civic Resistance to Durable Democracy (New York: Freedom House, 2005),
pp. 6â8.
[26] Maria J. Stephan and Erica Chenoweth, âWhy civil resistance works:
the strategic logic of nonviolent political conflict,â International
Security, Vol. 33, No. 1, Summer 2008, pp. 7â44.
[27] William T. Vollman, Rising Up and Rising Down, 7 volumes (San
Francisco: McSweeneyâs Books, 2003). Vollman makes derogatory comments
about Gandhiâs views. However, he neither addresses pragmatic
nonviolence nor systematically compares nonviolence and violence.
[28] Truda Gray and Brian Martin, â
Defamation and the art of backfire
,â Deakin Law Review, Vol. 11, No. 2, 2006, pp. 115â136.
[29] Aruna Gnanadason, Musimbi Kanyoro and Lucia Ann McSpadden (eds.),
Women, Violence and Nonviolent Change (Geneva: WCC Publications, 1996);
Pam McAllister, The River of Courage: Generations of Womenâs Resistance
and Action (Philadelphia: New Society Press, 1991).
[30] This is the first misconception listed by Schock, âNonviolent
action and its misconceptions.â
[31] Sharp, Politics of Nonviolent Action, Part Two.
[32] See the sources cited earlier on toppling regimes.
[33] See the quote from Martin Oppenheimer in the text below.
[34] Carol Flinders, âNonviolence: does gender matter?â PeacePower:
Journal of Nonviolence & Conflict Resolution, Vol. 2, Issue 2, Summer
2006. Gelderloos (p. 160, note 31) says that Flinders praised the
âinnate pacifism of âdevout Hindu wivesââ whereas Flinders actually just
referred to the behaviour of âdevout Hindu wivesâ without praising it or
attributing it to innate pacifism.
[35] Martha McCaughey, Real Knockouts: The Physical Feminism of Womenâs
Self-Defense (New York: New York University Press, 1997).
[36] Martin Oppenheimer, The Urban Guerrilla (Chicago: Quadrangle Books,
1969), pp. 50, 57 and 64. Emphasis in the original.
[37] Producing effective fighters requires special training to break
down instinctive reluctance to kill: see Dave Grossman, On Killing: The
Psychological Cost of Learning to Kill in War and Society (Boston:
Little, Brown, 1995). Gelderloos does not say whether he endorses this
sort of training for activists.
[38] International Revolutionary Solidarity Movement, First of May
Group, Towards a Citizensâ Militia: Anarchist Alternatives to NATO and
the Warsaw Pact (Over the Water, Sanday, Orkney: Cienfuegos Press,
1980).
[39] You Canât Blow up a Social Relationship: The Anarchist Case against
Terrorism (San Francisco: See Sharp Press, 1990).
[40] For example, Anarchists Against the Wall is âa direct action groupâ
of Israeli activists that âworks in cooperation with Palestinians in a
joint non violent struggle against the occupationâ:
[http://www.awalls.org][http://www.awalls.org]]. I thank Maria Stephan
for this example.
[41] Andy Chan, âAnarchists, violence and social change: perspectives
from todayâs grassroots,â Anarchist Studies, Vol. 3, No. 1, Spring 1995,
pp. 45â68.
[42] Murray Bookchin, Toward an Ecological Society (Montreal: Black Rose
Books, 1980), p. 260.
[43] Benjamin Franks, Rebel Alliances: The Means and Ends of
Contemporary British Anarchisms (Edinburgh: AK Press, 2006), pp.
139â152; Vernon Richards (ed.), Violence & Anarchism: A Polemic (London:
Freedom Press, 1993).
[44] Geoffrey Ostergaard and Melville Curle, The Gentle Anarchists: A
Study of the Leaders of the Sarvodaya Movement for Non-violent
Revolution in India (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1971).
[45] Colin Ward, Anarchy in Action (London: George Allen and Unwin,
1973).
[46] I owe this metaphor to Val Plumwood and Richard Sylvan.
[47] Brian Martin, â
Eliminating state crime by abolishing the state
â in Jeffrey Ian Ross (ed.), Controlling State Crime: An Introduction
(New York: Garland, 1995), pp. 389â417, at pp. 400â401.
[48] Gandhiâs approach has been criticised from a variety of
perspectives: Thomas Weber, âGandhian nonviolence and its critics,â
Gandhi Marg, Vol. 28, No. 3, October-December 2006, pp. 269â283.
[49] Howard Ryanâs book Critique of Nonviolent Politics: From Mahatma
Gandhi to the Anti-Nuclear Movement â a sympathetic critique that
engages with nonviolence writings in a well-informed way â is no longer
available online. For a detailed review see Brian Martin, â
Critique of violent rationales
,â Pacifica Review, Vol. 9, No. 1, 1997, pp. 83â91. [Update, 2010:
Howard Ryanâs book is now available. The review gives links.]
[50] Ward Churchill, Pacifism as Pathology: Reflections on the Role of
Armed Struggle in North America (Edinburgh: AK Press, 2007). Churchillâs
analysis has many of the same assumptions, omissions and double
standards as Gelderloosâ.
[51] William Meyersâ Nonviolence and Its Violent Consequences (Gualala,
CA: III Publishing, 2000) shows little awareness of writings on
nonviolence. Steven Best and Anthony J. Nocella II (eds.), Terrorists or
Freedom Fighters: Reflections on the Liberation of Animals (New York:
Lantern Books, 2004) has many contributions discussing nonviolence but
almost no recognition of pragmatic nonviolence.