đž Archived View for library.inu.red âş file âş todd-may-the-poststructural-anarchist.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 14:21:10. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄď¸ Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: The poststructural anarchist Author: Todd May Date: July 12, 2013, interview Language: en Topics: post-anarchism, post anarchism, post-structuralist, anti-humanism, critical theory Source: http://www.3ammagazine.com/3am/the-poststructural-anarchist/][www.3ammagazine.com]], snapshot from [[https://web.archive.org/web/20150617134711/http://www.3ammagazine.com/3am/the-poststructural-anarchist/. Notes: Todd May interviewed by Richard Marshall for 3:AM Magazine.
Todd May is the poststructuralist anarchist who thinks anarchism is more
than just a critique of the state, that there is more than one struggle,
that Foucault, Deleuze and Lyotard are important, that postructuralism
is elusive, that anarchism is bottom-up and liberalism is top-down, that
âhow might one live?â is the down and dirty question, that Foucaultâs
thought will remain standing when the dust is settled, that what it
means to be human is a matter of practices, that Ranciere gets him
emotionally, that friendship offers a different model from
neo-liberalism and that his conception is about resistance not cohesion.
High Five!
3:AM: What made you become a philosopher? Were you always aware of a
kind of crisis?
Todd May: Many philosophers I talk with seem to get their start in
philosophy from a teacher, often a college professor, that turns them on
to the subject. For me, it was different. I went to a high school in New
York City during the late 1960s and early 1970s, where ideas and crisis
were in the air. It was the kind of place where Melville, Faulkner, and
Dostoyevsky, along with the Vietnam War, were regular staples of
conversation. So early on I became interested in both ideas and
political resistance. In college I studied psychology, but was never far
from philosophy: I read Being and Time with a philosophy grad student.
Another friend of mine, also a grad student in philosophy, gave me
Merleau-Pontyâs Phenomenology of Perception as a graduation present. In
the few years I took off between college and grad school, I read most of
Merleau-Pontyâs work. Eventually I decided I wanted to go to grad school
in clinical psychology, but wanted a phenomenologically oriented one,
and so chose Duquesne University. But, as it happens, at the end of my
first year there I was introduced to the work of Foucault and Deleuze,
who raised unsettling questions for me about the entire project of
psychotherapy. I pressed these questions in my classes at Duquesne,
admittedly with the passion of which a person committed to ideas is
capable, and at the end of my second year was informed that my funding
was going to be cut off. So I spent a few more years reading and
thinking about what is often called âpoststructuralism,â and finally
applied to Penn State, where I had the chance to study these thinkers
more rigorously. A friend of mine who is a radical lawyer once asked me
why I wanted to study philosophy if I was so interested in politics. My
response, to which he offered me a mocking stare, was that I felt
somehow that in order to understand and solve political problems I
needed to be able to grasp their ontological underpinnings.
3:AM: Youâve written about and are associated with âpoststructuralist
anarchism.â I think you see it as coming out of an awareness that
political philosophy was in crisis following the fall of the Soviet
Union which kind of made it official that Marxism was dead. Can you say
something about how you understand this crisis give that for many â and
yourself â the Soviet block was hardly a viable model for political
change?
TM: For most traditional anarchists like Peter Kropotkin and Emma
Goldman, the Soviet Union was a crisis almost from the beginning. They
saw it as hierarchical in character, and in that way a continuation of
the kinds of domination characteristic of capitalist society. In fact,
earlier on, in his dispute with Marx, Mikhail Bakunin predicted that a
Marxist takeover of the state would simply reproduce the hierarchical
structure of social and political relations. As The Who said, âHere
comes the new boss, same as the old boss.â This is where anarchism
becomes associated with a critique of the state. My own reading of
anarchism is, however, that it is much more than a critique of the
state. It is a critique of domination in all its formsâpolitical,
economic, gender, racial, etc. So while the anarchists were certainly
right about the Soviet Union, we should read their work as a more
general critique of domination. Granted, this general critique is at
times in the background of their work, but it is nevertheless
recognizable. In this way, they differ importantly from Marx. For Marx,
there is an Archimedean point of social change since there is a central
point of domination: the extraction of surplus value from the workers.
Therefore, there is really only a single struggle: the struggle for the
ownership of means of production.
By contrast, for the anarchists there is no single struggle. As the
British anarchist Colin Ward once said, there are always a series of
struggles along a variety of fronts. This is where the
poststructuralists, and especially Foucault, intersect with anarchism.
Foucault traces historically different ways in which people become
dominated. He does not reduce them to a single site or single type, but
seeks to understand them in their specificity. The disciplinary power he
writes about in Discipline and Punish is different from the role of
sexuality he describes in the first volume of his history of sexuality,
which in turn is different from the neoliberal governmentality he
addresses in his lectures The Birth of Biopolitics. So while the
nineteenth and early twentieth century anarchists were able to resist
the reductionism of a Marxist program, later thinkers like Foucault,
Deleuze, and Lyotard offer perspectives for theorizing the
irreducibility of political relations and political struggle. That
allows them to, among other things, take on board the feminist and
anti-racist understandings that developed over the course of the
twentieth century.
Where does that leave us in thinking about our politics? Broadly with a
bottom-up view of political struggle and change. Rather than seeking the
Archimedean point of struggle, we must analyze the different and
intersecting facets of domination in their particularity, and struggle
against them. This does not preclude top-down theorizing altogether, but
it offers a framework for political reflection and action that has been
neglected in much of political philosophy.
3:AM: So poststructuralist anarchism is to be understood as being framed
by French poststructuralist and in particular the works of Foucault,
Deleuze and Lyotard. Before coming to this trio and how they seem to
offer a viable political philosophy and an alternative to Marxism can
you tell us what you understand by âpost structuralismâ and by
âanarchismâ in this context?
TM: Poststructuralism is an elusive term. It is a bit chronological,
like post-impressionism, and a bit conceptual. As chronological, it
refers to the theories that arose in the wake of the heyday of
structuralism. We might think of recent French philosophical history in
terms of three successive movements, at least up until around the
mid-1980s. There is the existentialism of the forties and fifties, which
is rejected by the structuralism of the late 1950s and 1960s. And then,
later in the 1960s, poststructuralism arises in part as a response to
structuralism but not as dismissive of it as structuralism is of
existentialism. This chronological view is a bit oversimplified. For
instance, the structuralist Lacan was writing well before the 1950s, and
Deleuzeâs influential book on Nietzsche was published in 1962. But if we
think of the prominence of the movements, this chronology offers a rough
idea. Conceptually, structuralism rejects the primacy of the subject in
existentialism, seeing the subject as constituted more than
constituting. But for the structuralists, what constitutes the subject
is more or less monolithic. For Lacan, it is the unconscious, for
Levi-Strauss the structures of kinship, and for Althusser, at least in
the last instance, it is the economy. Poststructuralism rejects these
monolithic accounts of the structuring of the subject. For Foucault, the
subject is a product of the intersection of particular practices of
knowledge and power. For Deleuze, whatever actuality the subject
presents carries within it a virtual field of difference that can make
it very much other than it is now. Lyotard, in his turn, takes up themes
in both Foucault and Deleuze during different points in his career, but
in his major work The Differend offers a view of the subject as both
constituted and constituting through a variety of different discursive
practices. I havenât mentioned Derrida here, who is often thought of as
the central poststructuralist. However, even though he does not figure
in my poststructuralist anarchism, he can also be seen as a figure who
sees the subject as partially constituted by something that lies outside
of it and that cannot be brought into conceptual presence, like Deleuze.
Although his view of what it is that does the constituting is diverges
from Deleuzeâs.
As for anarchism, it is the historical movement that, theoretically at
least, is rooted in the work of William Godwin and Pierre-Joseph
Proudhon, articulated most clearly in the work of Bakunin, Kropotkin,
Goldman, and others. It is often, as I said, associated with an
anti-statist position, but in my view is better defined as a commitment
to two positions: a critique of domination in all its forms and an
embrace of bottom-up organizing and resistance. Viewing things this way
leaves aside another strain of anarchist thoughtâthe individualist
anarchism associated with Benjamin Tucker and Max Stirner, and whose
modern proponents are libertarians like Robert Nozick. However, the term
anarchism is commonly thought to apply to the former more than the
latter.
3:AM: Lyotard writes about the postmodernâ rather than the
poststructioralist condition. Is this a distinction that matters?
TM: I have never liked the term postmodernism. If poststructuralism is a
difficult term to define, then trying to capture postmodernism is like
trying to stabilize mercury with your thumb. My understanding is that it
was coined around 1979 by Christopher Jencks in regard to architecture.
In the arts, it is often seen as a view that there is nothing new to be
done, so art must recycle old themes and styles, often although not
always in an ironic style. And one can see this in certain artists, like
David Salle and Julian Schnabel. People claim this label for David
Foster Wallace as well, but if the ironic recycling of old themes and
styles is characteristic of literature, then why isnât Joyce a
postmodernist? Moreover, I donât see any domination of what is called
postmodern literature in the 1980s similar to what happened in painting
or perhaps in architecture at that time. In philosophy, outside of
Lyotardâs work, it is practically nonexistent. For Lyotard,
postmodernism was largely what he called the rejection of grand
narratives, single overarching stories that explain, say, who we are and
how we got here. As a definition of postmodernism, it has resonances
with my definition of poststructuralism. However, even here there are
complications. For Foucault, for instance, what might be called
micropolitics is a way of analyzing our historical situation, whereas
for Lyotard it sometimes seems like an alternative political position to
be embraced. That is, while for Foucault the move to micropolitics is
analytical, for Lyotard it sometimes comes off as normative.
3:AM: What are the advantages of this approach to say Rawlsian
âdifference principleâ approaches to political theory, or Nozickâs or,
say, the Critical Theorists of Adorno, Lukacs, and Habermas?
TM: The anarchist angle of approach is quite different from that of
liberal theory on the one hand and Critical Theory on the other. At a
first go, we might say that if anarchism is a bottom-up approach,
liberalism is top-down. That is to say, liberalism starts with a set of
principles (different principles for different theorists) that focus on
the state, where anarchism starts with the people in the polity and asks
what kind of social relations ought to obtain between and among them.
This distinction isnât entirely clean, however. It seems to me that both
Rawls and anarchists share some important moral principles about how
people should be treatedâor if sharing is too strong, then at least
there is some important overlap. Rawls, like most liberals, then tries
to conceive a state that can meet the demands of those principles.
Anarchists are leery of the focus on the state. They are concerned that
the state, being an important site of power relationships, is not the
proper focus for enacting those principles. So they turn to the people
themselves, asking how people can organize themselves into a just
polity.
For my own part, I think that liberalism, especially in the hands of
people like Rawls and Sen, is often correct at the level of moral
principle but often naive about power. This naivete happens at two
levels. First, they fail to recognize many of the power games that occur
at the level of the state and that preclude meeting the moral principles
that they set out. In fact, if you look at many movements for justice,
it is often at the level of the people that they begin: the state often
does not create justice but responds to demands for justice from its
people. Second, they do not recognize what seems to me a central insight
of Foucaultâs work: that power often works not by restriction but by
production. That is, power helps produce who we are. So, for instance,
one of the reasons people conform to and even endorse unjust social
arrangements is that they have been inculcated into practices of
normality that make these social arrangements seem natural. (That is a
one-sentence and entirely superficial summary of Discipline and Punish.)
This is not to say that thereâs a conspiracy involved. Rather, it is to
say that power often operates at the level of our daily practices,
making us who we are. If this is right, then political resistance also
has to focus on those practices, that is, it has to be bottom-up.
That said, unlike many anarchists, I do not oppose the state in
principle. I think it is less effective in creating change than liberal
theory would allow, but there does seem to me an important place for
thinking about the justice of the state. So while there are advantages
to the anarchistâor poststructuralist anarchistâapproach to political
thought, I do not believe that it is a substitute for liberalism.
As far as Critical Theory goes (and letâs keep in mind that the recent
work of Habermas is probably more liberal that Critical Theoretical), it
has much insight to offer. However, that insight is embedded in a
largely Marxist perspective that shares the difficulties of being a
single explainer theory of the kind poststructuralism rejects. So the
advantage of anarchism to Critical Theory lies in its ability to take on
board the insights the latter offers while not reducing political
thought to the Marxist framework.
3:AM: âŞYou read Deleuze through the lens of a single giant question: How
might one live? I think you see this as a question that has replaced the
modern ethical question of how should one act, which in turn replaced
the ancient question of how should one live? Can you say why Deleuzeâs
question is a better one than the ancient or modern questions?âŹ
TM: The distinction into three questions is one down and dirty way of
trying to see what Deleuze is getting at. The question of how might one
live is a Nietzschean question. When he criticized the moral question of
how one should act, he did so in the name of the creativity of different
lives. Deleuze is thinking in very much the same terms. He wants to know
what possible new and different lives might be lived. In this sense, I
think that by replacing the modern question with the Nietzschean one, he
opens the possibility of thinking and living differently. Of course, in
order to see how that possibility worked, one would need to study his
ontology of difference, which is a much larger question.âŹ
âŞHowever I do want to distinguish my own views from Deleuzeâs here. For
Deleuze, as for many contemporary Continental thinkers who follow his
and Foucaultâs work, the modern question of how one should act needs to
be jettisoned. As Deleuze would put it, we need to abandon morality in
favor of ethics, where ethics is defined in Nietzschean and Spinozist
terms. I think this view is mistaken. While the question of how one
might live is certainly worth reflecting on, and Deleuze provides an
interesting framework for doing so, it cannot replace the modern
question. After all, not all creations are worthwhile ones. Certain
creations commended by Nietzsche, for example, particularly the more
martial ones, strike me as repellent. Alongside the need to create,
then, is the parallel need to assess our creations. And for that, the
question of how one should act remains relevant. âŹ
This may be a bit of an aside, but I have found over the years that many
of the claims of overthrowing the philosophical tradition that get made
in Continental thought are overblown. When one begins digging into the
claims of many recent French thinkers, one is often brought back to
traditional philosophical questions. To be sure, this can happen in new
and interesting ways. But the old questions donât go away so quickly.âŹ
3:AM: How does Deleuze answer the question? Is it to be constantly
unsettled? Is this anarchism? And is this best seen as a continuation of
ideas found in Spinoza, Bergson and Nietzsche?
TM: Deleuzeâs answer to this question, in a word, is âexperiment.â This
answer is rooted in his ontology, and Deleuze is above all an
ontologist. It is impossible to give an overview of his ontological view
in the short context of an interview, but at the risk of being at once
obscure and oversimplifying, let me say this. He believes that the
actual identities that we encounter carry within them a field of
difference that allows them to be very different from what they are. The
scientist Ilya Prigogine, a fan of Deleuzeâs ontology, offers an
illustrative example. There are certain gasses that exhibit an unusual
behavior in conditions that are far from equilibrium. Imagine, he says,
a container with a barrier in the middle. The barrier has a single small
hole. Now imagine pouring a blue gas into one side of the container and
a red gas into the other. Over time, one might expect that both sides
would look more or less purple. But in conditions far from equilibrium,
some gasses do something else. At regular intervals, each side will
switch from blue to red, and then back again. Itâs as though the gas
molecules know what the other molecules are going to do, and they all
coordinate behavior. Of course, the molecules arenât conscious. In
Deleuzeâs terms, there is a field of difference that actualizes itself
under certain physical conditions.
How might one live, then, in Deleuzeâs view? We donât know what lives we
are capable of. So a life ought to be an experiment, or a set of
experiments, in living. We investigate what is possible, what we can
become. This investigation is not limited to anything individualistic.
In fact, Deleuzeâs ontology is not an individualistic one. Experiments
can happen at the individual, group, and even subindividual level.
All of this is not, in itself, anarchism in the political sense.
However, it does refuse an arche of the human, a constrained view of
human flourishing that the state would then seek to maintain or enforce.
As for the three thinkers you mention near the end, Deleuze borrows from
all of them. From Spinoza he borrows a monism (difference is not
transcendent to identity, but within it); from Bergson he borrows a rich
conception of the past and duree, and from Nietzsche he borrows several
elements, including the distinction between active (experimenting) and
reactive (seeking to stop others from experimenting).
3:AM: Can you say how Levinas, Derrida, Lyotard and Nancy contribute to
our understanding of Deleuze and poststructuralist anarchism?
TM: Levinas, Derrida, and Nancy donât contribute to our understanding of
either, particularly of Deleuze. I mentioned above that Derrida and
Deleuze have very distinct approaches to difference. For Derrida,
difference is an economic relation between presence and absence that
refuses to be captured by our perceptual experience or conceptual
categories. Nancy works with a similar, although not identical,
approach. Derrida winds up in an ethical position very close to Levinas,
where one must be vulnerable to the other that one cannot assimilate to
oneâs own categories. He applies this in particular, although not
exclusively, to the situation of immigrants in Europe. We might say that
the ethics of Levinas, Derrida, and Nancy, is an ethics of
vulnerability.
By contrast, Deleuzeâs ethics of one of experimentation, or, to use
another term loosely, an ethics of expression. It is not, of course,
commending expression of any pre-given identity. But it does commend
investigating what one is capable of rather than making oneself
vulnerable to the other. In this way, it is Nietzschean in inspiration.
It is not, to be sure, an ethics of invulnerability. To experiment is,
in an important way, to render oneself vulnerable. But it is to render
oneself vulnerable to the experiment itself, not necessarily to others.
This is why Deleuzeâs models for experimentation are often artists.
3:AM: Foucault you see as working âbetween genealogy and epistemology
and asking the shadowy Kantian question : What is our present? Is it
again because Foucault is asking a question that sits more easily with
Deleuzeâs one about how should live than how we should act that you find
him important? Can you say something about Foucault approaches his
question and why this connects with the post structuralist anarchist
tradition and not, say, a phenomenological approach, or German Idealism?
TM: Foucault, I believe, is the most important of his generation of
French thinkers. When the dust settles on the French philosophical
movements of the 1970s and 1980s, it is his thought that will remain
standing. When I look back at my book on poststructuralist anarchism, I
see the influence of his thought more than that of Deleuze or Lyotard.
In utilizing Nietzscheâs genealogical methodâbut with a lot more care to
the facts of historyâFoucault shows how to understand the way power
works on the ground, in everyday lives. In introducing the idea that
power doesnât just repress, it produces, he helps us understand how we
can become complicit in the things that oppress us in ways that are
beyond just being misled or having false beliefs. And in seeing the
intersection between knowledge and power, he opens the door to new types
of reflection on the ways in which we seek to know ourselves. Among the
effects of all this is to loosen the Marxist grip on leftist thought, a
grip whose effects were a reductionist view of power and domination.
This allows a renewed thinking of anarchism, one that both intersects
with and develops the anarchist themes of thinking of power as
multifacted and needing to confront domination from the ground up.
Foucaultâs rejection of phenomenology, which to my mind is a bit too
cavalierâespecially in the case of Merleau-Pontyâis complicated in its
inspiration. For one thing, like Deleuze, he believed that we needed to
look at how the perceiving subject is constituted rather than
constituting. For another thing, much of the French generation of his
time associated phenomenology with Sartre, and associated Sartre with
the idea of a master thinker that dictated to others where their
interests lie. Since Foucault rejects the role of intellectual as master
thinker, and so rejects Sartre, it is unsurprising that he would take a
jaundiced view of phenomenology.
On the other hand, the rejection of German idealism, especially Hegel,
is, I think, partly a result of a reductionist view of Hegelâs thought.
The more simply one understands the workings of the dialectic, the more
constraining Hegelâs thought seems to be. I think that in the background
of the rejection of Hegel is an interpretation of his thought that would
probably itself be disallowed by top Hegel scholars like Robert Pippin.
There is probably also a sociological element to the rejection of both
phenomenology and Hegel. Sartre and Merleau-Ponty on the one hand and
the great Hegelian Jean Hyppolite on the other were the teachers under
whom Foucaultâs generation studied. And there is a tradition in recent
French philosophy of having to move beyond the previous generation. I
once described French philosophy as instantiating Woody Allenâs
description, in Annie Hall, of relationships being like sharks: they
have to keep moving forward or they die. That seems to be a going theme
of French thought over the last sixty or seventy years.
3:AM: Youâve written about our practices, our selves and what it means
to be human which seems to draw on many of the ideas youâve discussed so
far. So how should we go about answering the question: What does it mean
to be human?
TM: The book Our Practices, Ourselves was a project of writing for a
wider audience without losing philosophical rigor. In that book I argue
that who each of us is as a human being is largely a product of the
practices one engages in. I define a practice as a regularity or set of
regularities of behavior, usually goal-directed, that is socially
normatively governed. It seems to me that in thinking about who we are,
instead of looking for some core âme-nessâ inside of us, we should
instead look at the practices we participate in and the ways we
participate in those practices. From what Iâve said so far about
anarchism and French thought, this way of seeing things should not be
surprising. The subtitle of the bookâwhat it means to be humanâdoes not
point at the attempt to distinguish humans from other animals, but
rather suggests that who we are as human beings is dominantly a matter
of our participation in practices. In the book I try to show how
knowledge arises from within practices, how it can intersect with power
as Foucault suggests, and how we can situate a lot of our normative
thought within practices.
3:AM: You recently turned your attention to the thought of Jacques
Ranciere and the idea of equality in action in relation to some
contemporary political movements such as Montreals Sans-Status Algerian
refugee movement, the first Palestinian Intifada and the Zapatistas. So
can you say something about what you find important in Ranciere? Is it
his focus on equality that you see as promising reinvigoration of
democratic arrangements, supplanting things such as identity,
meritocracy and the market , for example?
TM: That is exactly it. One of the frustrating aspects of Foucaultâs
work is that he never puts his normative cards on the table. I think
this is because he did not want to prescribe for others. But the idea
that, as an intellectual, he shouldnât engage in such prescription is
itself a normative stand. Moreover, books like Discipline and Punish
have a strong critical bent, even though the normative bases of the
criticism are not laid out. What Ranciere brings to political discussion
is a particular normative orientation: that democratic movements
operate, whether consciously or not, on the presupposition of the
equality of everyone. When I first read his political work, I was struck
by two things. The first was theoretical: his ideas offer a normative
framework within which to see the critical work of Foucault and others.
In addition, it was consonant with the anarchist orientation of my own
political thought.
The second thing I was struck by, and this elicited a more emotional
reaction, is that he seems to capture the sense of the political
movements I have been involved in when they are at their best. The
anti-apartheid movement, the Palestinian and gay rights movements, are
most exciting when they are not just demanding equality, but
presupposing it in their collective action. That is the idea I try to
capture in my book on Ranciere and the political movements you mention.
It also provides a basis for thinking about nonviolence in political
action, a project I am beginning to work on now.
3:AM: Inequality has never been quite so stark and obvious to so many as
it is now. And it seems obvious that that issue seems to require a
political solution. So many will be surprised to find that in Ranciere
he links his political thinking with an art theory? How plausible do you
find this element of his ideas? Is he asking to look in unlikely places
to find that democracy and equality can work?
TM: Actually, the relation between his political views and his aesthetic
ones is tricky. Both speak about equality, but in different ways. For
Ranciere, politics is collective action under the presupposition of
equality. In aesthetics, equality arises in more modern artwork, for
example in Flaubertâs treatment of all subjects as worthy of literary
address. Ranciere says that the two overlap, but there is no coincidence
between political and aesthetic equality. Art does not exist to serve
the political movement of equality.
3:AM: Your book âFriendship In An Age Of Economic Economicsâ comes out
of the postructuralist anarchist tradition weâve talking about. Itâs
subtitled: âresisting the forces of neoliberalism.â So how do you
approach friendship so that it can do that?
TM: The friendship book is certainly indebted to the ideas of Foucault
and Ranciere, but it is more focused specifically on the problem of what
neoliberalism makes of us and what we can do about it. In his set of
lectures entitled The Birth of Biopolitics, Foucault notes that American
neoliberalism is not just an economic theory, but a view of what human
beings are like: entrepreneurs of themselves, human capital that invests
itself to various ends. The decline of the welfare state has contributed
to our being such entrepreneurs. After all, if youâre not going to get
any support in case you falter in your life, then you had better invest
whatever resources you haveâmoney, talent, charm, good looksâin the most
efficient way possible. My argument in the book is that close friendship
can offer us a different model for being together from the one
neoliberalism promotes, which sees our relations to others as
investments in future gain. In a close friendship, for instance, people
donât worry so much about who has done what for whom and when. There
isnât a balance sheet being kept between the friends. In fact,if a
balance sheet does emerge, that usually means there is a problem in the
friendship. In addition to providing an alternative model for human
relationships, close friendships can teach some of the skills that
solidarity work requires, like trust. This does not mean that everyone
in a solidarity movement can become good friends. They canât. But
friendship teaches us ways of relating to one another that the
individualizing and isolating influences of neoliberalism diminish or at
times even extinguish.
3:AM: Sibyl Schwarzenbach also sees friendhipâs political dimension
although she is not coming from your tradition. Do you see overlaps as
well as contrasts between the positions regarding friendship?
TM: I am familiar with her idea only through the 3 a.m. interview you
did with her. Her concept is an interesting one; it is aligned with the
concept of solidarity in some ways, but, as she points out, does not
have some of the masculinist or exclusivist baggage. My focus is much
more on the close friendships that develop between specific people. Near
the end of my book, I suggest that such friendships, in addition to
providing an alternative social space to neoliberal relationships, also
might provide training in the trust required of solidarity movements.
Moreover, I cite as an element of that trust Ranciereâs conception of
the presupposition of equality between people. There is where, I think,
my views might intersect with hers, although they remain on different
registers. Schwarzenbachâs view is tailor made for public cohesion. When
reading it, I was reminded of some of the social attitudes
characteristic of Denmark, where I teach for a couple of weeks every
year. The relation of my own view to public cohesion is not as direct.
Partly this is because the kinds of friendships I focus on can be
exclusivist as well as providing tools for solidarity. And partly it is
because my own concern is with movements of resistance, not with general
social cohesion.
3:AM: And finally, are there five books you could recommend that would
take us further into this set of ideas?
TM: Foucaultâs Discipline and Punish and the first volume of his History
of Sexuality, Deleuzeâs Difference and Repetition (a bear to read, but
enormously influential), Lyotardâs The Differend, and Ranciereâs
Disagreement.