đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș william-gillis-from-stirner-to-mussolini.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 14:41:53. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: From Stirner to Mussolini Author: William Gillis Date: March 28th, 2022 Language: en Topics: fascism, anti-fascism, Italy, fascist creep, analysis, book review, Benito Mussolini, individualism, Max Stirner Source: Retrieved on March 28th, 2022 from https://c4ss.org/content/56480
In 1910 Luigi Fabbri and Armando Borghi abducted an anarchist woman who
had shamed their friend by divorcing him. Together, they forced her into
a gynecological exam so the doctor could publicly pronounce her deformed
and incapable of sex.
All three were prominent leaders in the Italian anarchist scene and
involved in criminal activities. Despite having been abducted, medically
raped, and slandered by her scene rivals, when the cops raided them for
publishing anti-war articles, Maria Rygier refused to turn on anyone and
tried to take full responsibility. She was sentenced to three years in
prison where she was again medically raped, this time by representatives
of the state.
Disenchanted with the anarchist sceneâs patriarchs and looking for
support from dissidents within the movement, upon release Rygier took up
with a prominent Stirnerite, Massimo Rocca. But if youâre looking for a
triumphant vindication of individualist underdogs against rapist scene
patriarchs, this is not that story. Despite their origins in the
anarchist movement, Rygier and Rocca would go on to play central roles
in the emergence and establishment of fascism. Many of their followers
would join them as fascists, with one, Leandro Arpinati, even rising to
the status of âsecond Duce,â just behind Mussolini in power and
popularity.
Stephen B. Whitakerâs obscure book The Anarchist-Individualist Origins
of Italian Fascism has been cited on occasion by communist reactionaries
as a cudgel against anarchism and individualism. Yet whatever their
misappropriations, the title shouldnât be read to imply this is a book
blaming individualist anarchism for the rise of fascism, it merely
focuses on one specific ideological arena among many others (like
syndicalism and communism) where fascists found root and that
contributed to the stew of early fascist ideology. There are many
origins of fascism. Whitaker is quite clear from the outset, âI believe
[anarchismâs] intellectual influence on fascism was quite small,â on the
other hand, certain readings of Stirner and certain fringe currents in
the anarchist movement, âwere quite influential.â No one should be under
the illusion that influence is the same thing as causal blame, yet, at
the same time, the specific social points of overlap and mutations of an
ideological current can be critical to understanding the initial rise of
fascism and continuing weak points for entryism today.
Whitaker is not particularly hostile to anarchism or its individualist
currents, but at the same time is very clearly ignorant of it; his
understanding of anarchism as a philosophy seemingly stems entirely from
reading George Woodcock, Max Stirner, and a couple haughtily ignorant
liberal commentators in political science journals clumsily trying to
categorize anarchism within their discursive frameworks. (More on how
badly he butchers Stirner later.) Unsurprisingly his ideological
contextualizations are often impaired as a result. But Whitaker also
appears to be a sincere historian and his book is still a treasure trove
of references to interviews, letters, and articles nowhere else
translated to English. Of course Iâm not fluent in Italian, and was
limited in how much I could verify via google translate and via other
sources, but together the bookâs references reveal a deeply
dysfunctional anarchist scene, undermined by toxic personalities,
powerful patriarchs, and horrible edgelord takes that itâs unfortunately
quite easy to see contemporary parallels to.
Again I must emphasize that similar specialized historical accounts can
and have been written of Fascismâs parallel origins in liberal,
communist, and conservative circles. The question that antifascist
anarchists should zero in on is what can we learn from this?
The standard defensive take is that every sort of person can take a
reactionary turn. If fascism can win converts from every ideology that
just goes to show such conversions have non-ideological or
pre-ideological motivations. But this is a plainly spurious defense.
Anarchism, Communism, and Liberalism have won proponents from every
single ideology under the sun, including the ranks of fascists. This
does not mean that there are not specific things that can be said,
specific dynamics or tendencies that can be analyzed, about how a
specific ideology most often wins converts from another specific
ideology, to what degree it is successful, and through what arguments or
conceptual dynamics. Moreover ideologies and movements are not
homogeneous, that anarchism, communism, and liberalism may each have
corners or failure modes particularly conducive to corruption in
specific ways is all the more imperative to examine such rather than
sweeping everything under a rug.
Nothing is more inane and anti-individualist than defensive closing of
ranks. Why should it remotely matter if a communist or liberal might
attempt to utilize factoids about the individualist anarchists who
joined fascism as some kind of rhetorical cudgel against us? Why should
we care more about what liberals or communists think and say than we
care about finding the truth for ourselves?
Whitakerâs historical account focuses on four individuals â Massimo
Rocca, Maria Rygier, Torquato Nanni (a socialist politician with some
anarchist inclinations), and Leandro Arpinati â and traces their
personal trajectories around and through the Italian anarchist scene and
the early fascist movement. Itâs important to note that each of these
figures had a rocky relationship with fascism as it developed and
ultimately felt jilted by certain developments, but it is just as
important to note that their objections were not grounded in anything
like anarchist principles. These were not hybrids of anarchism and
fascism, but straight up fascists, even if they occupied contentious
sub-positions within fascism. And sadly they were not isolated wingnuts,
but important and influential individuals with supporters. Rocca and
Rygier were internationally respected and published anarchist voices.
Arpinati served as Undersecretary to the Minister of the Interior where
he acquired his title as âsecond Duce of fascism.â Rocca pushed
Mussolini into his pivot to a pro-war socialism. All were friends with
Mussolini.
While their individual reasons and arguments differed in some ways, in
broad strokes there was a subsection of the egoist anarchist scene in
Italy that embraced participation in the First World War and used their
printing presses and clandestine distribution capacity to disrupt the
Italian Left and strengthen Mussolini as a champion. Partially as a
result of this defection of individualist printmakers & distroists,
between 1915 and 1920 no significant anarchist journals were published
in Bologna. This turn to warmongering was a conjunction of a
fetishization of violence among some individualists and a broader
populist perception of Italy as a poor nation revolting against the rich
through the medium of national conflict in sections of the wider Left
(particularly among syndicalists). Mixed up and loosely cited Nietzsche
and Stirner were leveraged to defend a haughty elitism of the ubermensch
while the charisma of militancy brought prestige and followers.
In some cases the mutations and contortions were clearly venal and
opportunistic, the result of specific types of rotten character that had
regrettably found a place in the milieu, but in many cases it seems like
certain ideological formulations ratcheted themselves.
Itâs worth going through the individuals Whitaker traces with some
depth, if only because thereâs so little coverage of them in English.
The most important for an ideological autopsy, in my opinion, was
Massimo Rocca (who went by Libero Tancredi while he identified as an
anarchist but swapped back to his legal name as a fascist). This
assholeâs roots as an anarchist ideologue are sharp and colorful, and
show his early differences from the mainstream anarchist scene.
âIn 1905 , Rocca moved to Milan to become editor of Li Grido della
folla. Under his leadership the newspaper began to take on a more
belligerent tone, exalting regenerative violence and chaos; referring to
dynamite as âholyâ; and, condemning basic legal rights, humanitarianism,
and ethics. ⊠He and others like him distributed pamphlets and put up
posters which spoke of rebellion against the âmyth of positive evolution
in society, naturalism in science, societyâs ingenious faith in
progressââ
Rocca was expelled from Il Grido della folla and left Milan, the
heartland of individualist anarchism in Italy, for Rome to found Il
Novatore anarchico.
âAt the 1906 anarchist congress of Monino, near Rome, supporters of
Roccaâs newspaper, the novatoriani, started a massive fistfight during
which pistol shots were fired and at least one person received knife
wounds.â
The novatori proclaimed that âa war today is more fatal to the
bourgeoisie than the proletariat and is a favorable occasion for
starting a revolution.â And Rocca declared that âanarchism in the truest
sense of the word, is the revolt of the ego against altruism.â (Abele
Rizieri Ferrari, who a little later came to be known under the pen name
âRenzo Novatore,â would have been 16 at the time; Rocca, his senior, was
just 22.)
Despite Rocca having a militant following within the scene, he got into
serious conflicts with other individualists (a far more diverse lot,
including many sharply altruistic and focused on morality) and he was
accused of looting funds from Romeâs Libertarian Youth newspaper to fill
the coffers of Il Novatore. This was a pattern, to say the least.
âhe would convince anarchist colleagues to pay for his meals in the
local trattoria by railing against them during the meal with snippets of
his Stirnerian-Neitzschean logic such as, âYou pay for my lunch because
youâre weak. I, on the other hand, am strong.ââ
When the outcry at his general scumfuckery built to a sufficient level,
Rocca skipped town, moving to the US, where he contributed to other
anarchist publications (from Paris to Chicago) and continued to publish
Il Novatore. His popular notion of an elite rebellious minority, a
libertarian aristocracy, seeking to elevate themselves slowly drifted
over time, with the Italian race increasingly filling the role of this
minority on the global stage. Similarly, as Whitaker puts it, he urged
folks to
âabandon intellect and focus on instinct which, according to Rocca,
leads people to think of themselves as Unique Ones, to revert to their
more ânaturalâ state, rejecting the abstract structures of the
intellect.â
This reading of Stirner as a rejection of reason for nature/instinct was
not the only hot take he had percolating. Achieving the union of egos,
Rocca speculated, would require the inception of a truly brutal and
total war of all against all, with the eventual survivors finding
themselves balanced in detentes with one another. Thus: cynical egoism
and violence â even on the part of conservatives and the state â is only
ever good because it ratchets society towards this rupture.
And ultimately one final breach grew: Rocca fervently believed that
morality was a spook, and humanitarianism or altruism particularly
pernicious, but he struggled with inevitable critiques that any position
one might take (like rejection of altruism) would still itself
constitute a morality. And so Rocca finally came to accept that the best
way to smash the most repugnant morality was to replace it with an
explicitly and consciously fake, arbitrary, and hollow morality.
Humanitarianism was too potent and perpetually reemergent a spook, the
only way to smash it was to replace it with blind duty, with the
arationality of obedience to the collective will the best possible
escape from spooked thinking. Nationalism was thus a useful tool to
suppress the intellect and return to instinct/nature.
If this sounds too severe a contortion to warrant any consideration
besides a laugh, consider the tens of millions who praised Trumpâs
honesty because his flagrant lies didnât hide that they were lies. It is
sometimes argued in certain lazy currents of philosophy that reason
constitutes a tyranny because it has an overwhelming and almost
inescapable force in our minds. The compulsion that reasoned argument
exerts on us is starkly unique, and thus unfair. Through reason we are
not just forced into a single path, we are forced in the most intimate
and mentally demanding way possible. Reason, once it sinks its teeth
into us, never lets us go, never grants us a momentâs release, instead
it ratchets in reinforcing spirals that consume our minds. Stirner uses
the phrase âthe rule of absolute thought.â Itâs easy to see how reason
is self-reinforcing. Doubt, curiosity and the care to get things right
reinforce themselves; a little investigation proves how much more
investigation is required. Many of us embrace this and see such
reflection and vigilance as the very core of agency and freedom. But in
Stirnerâs language, the âlabor of thoughtâ is a sanctified spook that
âmisleads people into scrupulousness and deliberation.â Of course
thereâs many ways to read Stirnerâs passages on âthoughtâ as itself a
fixed idea and few of them look anything like an endorsement of Roccaâs
flight. Yet it is true that many feel a certain kind of release from the
tyranny of responsibility and diligence when they embrace a self-aware
lie. Every day that you renew your service to the lie, its blatant
nature is inescapable and reminds you of your conscious rejection of
scruples. Escaping the âtyranny of thoughtâ back to instinct is no easy
task and Rocca believed heâd found the path. Whatâs a little absolute
authoritarianism if it allows you the âfreedomâ of turning your brain to
goo?
And of course who would drive and sit on top of this authoritarian beast
besides the elite rebels, the truly unique ones:
âIt is useful to note the difference between single rebels and the great
mass of subversives. It is necessary to distinguish between those who
know how to be uniquely themselves⊠These are the only ones who have the
right not to obey the law. The others⊠deserve the intervention of
social coercion to force them to submit to the consequences and
responsibility of their actions, which they do not know how to take
freely,â
It was this language of elites that Rocca was able to make palatable to
the existing forces of the right as he pivoted politically. What once
had been a moral or rebel aristocracy of enlightened insurrectionaries
could hook up with the self-legitimizing narratives of the actual ruling
aristocracy. In this way the scandalously militant and revolutionary
rhetoric of the left could be repackaged in ways the right could
actually embrace. This is perhaps one of the most key aspects of fascism
that distinguishes it from mere militant reaction or hypernationalism:
the palingenesis. Fascism is not just an embrace of hierarchy and raw
power, a rejection of modernism or the enlightenment project, a
shrinking of empathy and care to just âoneâs ownâ; it supercharged
existing reactionary forces by giving them a revolutionary project. No
longer pallid defenders of the status quo, reactionaries could finally
dream about their own violent rupture to a fantastical future.
Itâs important to emphasize that, despite being a complete asshole whose
self-serving actions repeatedly burned bridges and whose ideology was
almost as toxic as it gets, Rocca was not a marginal and isolated
wingnut but a prominent figure in the anarchist movement who gave
speeches and contributed to numerous journals and had a militant base of
friends and followers. Rocca and Rygier existed alongside Fabbri and
Borghi on a shortlist of anarchist intellectuals who debated publicly,
mobilized followers, and whose words were carried across Italy.
The fact that their distros/journals were quite active and they drew
crowds and speaking opportunities has been largely obscured by
anarchists who have, from the start, emphasized the (also valid) degree
to which these assholes were marginal. A good example of early language
dismissing them can be found in the very fun Living Like Nomads: The
Milanese Anarchist Movement Before Fascism by Fausto Butta, where he
quotes Luigi Molinari,
âIt is time to end this opportunistic lie that a considerable number of
anarchists support the war ⊠Who are, then, these warmonger anarchists?
Maria Rygier and Libero Tancredi! The former represents nobody but
herself; she is free to contradict her noble past and abandon to their
destiny those proletarians in whom she had instilled an anti-militarist
consciousness. The latter has never been an anarchist, in scientific
terms. His anarchism really is a synonym of chaos, and on this point he
surely agrees with the bourgeois newspapers, to which he has always
contributed and to which he is giving a benevolent serviceâ
But while itâs true the overwhelming majority of the Italian anarchist
movement (individualists included) sided with Malatesta against the war,
itâs hardly like Rygier and Rocca had no followers or compatriots.
Prominent individualist writers like Oberdan Gigli and Mario Gioda
joined the pro-war anarchists and their current had a whole newspaper,
La Guerra Sociale (whose director Edoardo Malusardi also went from
individualist anarchism to fascism).
Rocca would eventually stray so far as to be repeatedly attacked and
hospitalized by anarchists, but itâs a testament to his influence and
status that he continued to get invitations to give addresses at
anarchist meetings, even while his crew was increasingly socially
shunned.
When the fascios were founded Rocca was one of the core founding members
in Rome, and he managed to become seen as fascismâs leading economic
proponent. Roccaâs downfall with fascist ranks came from his sharper
elitism. He led a faction that believed fascists â not their wider base
of support â were Nietzschean elites who should eliminate all others
from political power, disdaining the non-mobilized middle class that
merely supported the fascists rather than leading their streetfighting.
This, of course, was not a politically opportune stance for Mussolini,
so Rocca was pushed out in 1924. He continued to push his same line and
became denounced as âantifascistâ for it. But even exiled to France in
1926 he continued to push for Mussolini to return to âtrue fascismâ and
take more power for the true elites, writing multiple fascist books,
grumbling about how local actual antifascists shunned him, and working
as a paid informer to the fascist secret police during the occupation of
France.
In seeming contrast to Roccaâs individualist anarchist arc is the
socialist Torquato Nanni, one of the many, many, many state socialists
who followed Mussolini to fascism, albeit one closer in many ways to
certain anarchist circles.
Nanni started as a passionate anti-clerical activist and socialist
leader on the border of Romagna and Tuscany who had strong associations
with anarchists, particularly Arpinati. Nanniâs politics are far more
muddled and thereâs a case for disputing his inclusion in a book on
individualist anarchists, after all he was a participant in the
Socialist Party and a sitting mayor, even if he wasnât hugely into the
party. He was an enthusiastic supporter of the Bolshevik revolution as a
presumed horizontal direct democracy. This was a man friendly with the
staunchly non-individualist Fabbri and Borghi in a period when Rocca and
eventually Rygier were fighting with them. Whitaker focuses on his
affinities with individualist anarchists, but I think itâs important to
clarify how muddled the situation is.
Itâs true that Nanni emphasized socialism as an individual faith of a
noble elite few, was hostile to the reformism of the party and saw the
value of socialism in âcritique, disintegration, and offensive,â but all
things considered he reads most strongly to me more like a modern
Bookchinite, or maybe even a council communist, than anything close to
an individualist anarchist. His fixation on direct democracy and the
Paris Commune are hardly the markers of individualist anarchism. Indeed,
as mentioned, he became the mayor of Santa Sofia with the intent of
transforming the local administrative region into a true workers
council.
Nanni, long more of a militant than a reformist despite his own
political office, was basically at odds with the Socialist Party during
the crisis about âinterventionismâ in the first world war, but slunk
back to the party in 1918, more inspired by the Bolsheviks than
Mussoliniâs increasingly doomed pro-war crusade. Yet in the September
1919 occupation of Fiume he swapped right back into deep alliance with
Mussolini. In no small part because Nanni wanted a revolution, any
revolution. He became increasingly convinced that the Italian socialists
simply didnât have the bloodlust necessary for a revolution as
successful as the Bolsheviksâ, and the fascists did have that bloodlust.
This is a common line in all the characters here, and it had wide
currency across ideological camps in Italy of the time. The infamous
syndicalist Georges Sorel, we mustnât forget, leapt from praising Lenin
to Mussolini, because hey at least the fascists were mobilized for
violence. The common valuing of militancy for militancyâs sake, on
violence as an immediatist or irrationalist means without ends, was
conjoined at the same time with an apocalyptic hunger for a revolution
to shatter the establishment and existing order, no matter who it took
to get it going. All of the figures Whitaker covers were influenced by
this combination. It is also, sadly, rather timeless. National
Bolsheviks and eco-fascists today continue to leverage the same sort of
argument, âIâll ally with anyone serious about smashing The Bad System
and steeled for action, everything else is a distraction.â Whether
capitalism or civilization is held as the ur-enemy that we must narrowly
focus on defeating at any cost, fascist creep goes into overdrive. And
the same sort of somewhat paradoxical conjunction of irrationalist
immediatism with revolutionary instrumentalism. We see the same with
folks urging collaboration with boogaloos while griping that
âantifascism is just liberalism because it shies away from absolute
violence; at least these reactionaries are happy to shed blood here and
now.â The cult of militancy and rupture remains eternally attractive to
a certain set.
If the only problem, the only thing holding us back from a revolution,
is timidity and unwillingness to act, to spill blood, then even the most
reactionary scumbag is more sympathetic and has more potential than the
mewling handwringing of some â no doubt liberal â comrade wondering if
we really need to stomp this row of infants to death to prove our
militancy. And woe betide the sort of sniveling coward who asks
questions like âokay but what exactly is the causal relationship between
these means and the ends weâre seeking?â
Whitaker emphasizes the anarchist influences upon Nanni and I think
seems confident to simply point out his revolutionary focus and belief
in autonomous participatory communes, conjoined with his noises about
âthe individualâ but while Nanni was certainly not a classic
organizationalist or party man, itâs unclear to me how much Whitaker
thus believes or seeks to imply he should be classified with the
individualist anarchists. Every anarchist makes obligatory noises about
individual idealism or individuality â as individualist anarchists know
all too well, this often means very little in practice.
Nevertheless, one way in which Nanni is central to the story of the
individualist anarchists who went fascist is through his close
friendship with Leandro Arpinati. Indeed, Nanni would eventually write
Arpinatiâs biography.
Arpinati is the most central figure in Whitakerâs book, the common
thread he traces to illustrate the other converts to fascism in passing.
Originally a young militantly anti-clerical socialist who worked for
Nanni, doing public lighting for Santa Sofia, he abandoned socialism for
anarchism in 1909.
Arpinatiâs mixture of Stirner and Nietzsche, or at least the popular
interpretations going around, made him something of a wingnut in his
initial affinity group, but he was embraced by them because 1) there
were so few anarchists in his town, and 2) he repeatedly demonstrated
personal militancy and bravery, like disarming a farmer threatening to
murder his wife. I also canât help but get the impression â reading
between the lines â that Arpinati was quite charismatic in his
streetfighter youth.
The first meeting between Mussolini and Arpinati was hostile. The
anarchist-turned-socialist Andrea Costa had died and the local
socialists of Civitella were dedicating a covered market to the traitor,
Arpinatiâs crew went to paste up denunciations while Mussolini issued
the dedication and denounced them from stage, quoting Stirner at them.
Despite â or perhaps because of â these initial sparks, they grew close.
Arpinati was taken with Mussoliniâs political power and Mussolini wanted
local allies, so they patched things up and Arpinatiâs anarchist crew
operated as occasional local bodyguards for Mussolini. While Arpinatiâs
crew had started out rather mainline-anarchist, his influence had been
significant and more and more newcomers drifted to his take on
individualism.
But, after his father died, Arpinati moved to Bologna in 1910 and worked
as a railway electrician. There he was a follower of Rygier and earned a
reputation as a scab by consistently voting against strikes, rejecting
them as deplorable collective action rather than individualist attack,
all while he bummed around the anarchist scene for food and lodging.
When war broke out Arpinati refused to support the local railway workers
in a general strike. Itâs hard not to wonder if this was rooted in
anything different than his contrarian rejections of prior strikes. Yet
Nanni, recounting this, praised him for having the foresight to see war
as a fecund site of rupture: âIn a flash of intuition his spirit
anticipated that revision of all human values â social, ideological,
moral â which the war had brought with it.â Itâs also true that Arpinati
saw the union bosses as out of line with the rank-and-file on the issue
of war. But whatever his strongest motivation, he radicalized harder and
harder in support of the war and contrarian hostility to his comrades.
This embrace of war found immediate expression in constant brawls with
anti-war anarchists.
âHe took to brush-cutting his hair when his head was not bandaged â so
that opponents could not âimmobilize his head while others punched him
in the face.ââ
A particularly striking image amid these fights is a meeting of the
anarchist union Societa Operaia where Arpinati, Rygier, and Rocca fought
some two hundred members of their audience who assaulted the stage for
over an hour with thrown chairs and general fisticuffs.
Suffice to say, the anarchist movement as a whole had ceased to tolerate
their bullshit. And Arpinati was more than a happy pugilist in response.
Amid the fighting at home he tried to sign up for the military but was
rejected. This deeply undermined his standing in the facsist movement
for decades. Common graffiti in Bologna later under fascism would read
âDid Arpinati fight in the war? No!â
Anarchists too had a certain disgust for the pro-war non-serving
Arpinati and, after joining the first Bolognese fascio de combattimento
in 1919, he got a very harsh reception in his hometown of Civitella.
This was basically the end of his presence in the anarchist movement.
Soon enough he and Rocca were being used as bodyguards by Mussolini.
This was a period of conflict within fascist circles over right and left
alliances, with the Bolognese fascist chapter veering further left than
Mussolini and appointing a secretary âfrom the ranks of the
anarcho-syndicalists.â (Whitaker gives no further details than that,
being focused on the individualist currents, and my Italian isnât good
enough to go looking for the scandalous particulars.) In any case the
Bolognese chapter was a disaster electorally and collapsed in numbers
before it was basically seized, replaced, and taken control of by
Arpinati in 1920. Militancy progressed rapidly as strikes and minor land
reform stirred up class conflict and Arpinati and the fascists
positioned themselves as defenders against socialist bullies (a similar
note to his hostility to union bosses).
âOn May Day the fascists paraded through Bologna singing the movementâs
fight song, Giovinezza, and taunting the socialists. Much to Arpinatiâs
surprise and delight, the socialists did not respond to âthe myth of
[their] invincibility in the public squares of the city.â Arpinati wrote
to Pasella, âThe local socialists showed exasperating calm; the Chamber
of Labor remained hermetically sealed all day. I am convinced they will
never make the revolution.â
Itâs important to note just how critical the youth and student
population was to the fascist movement at this time (a far cry from the
relatively aging chuds and boneheads that primarily comprise their
rallies in our own era). Most members were between the ages of 16 and
26, and the absence of students over the summer collapsed the fascist
fighting forces. But when the students returned, Arpinati once again led
armed fascists through the streets and ended up in a gun battle with
socialists, successfully killing a young worker. This victory got
Arpinati appointed head of the armed squads and the ranks swelled from
20 to over 300.
Arpinati occupied a weird hybrid space during this period. The anarchist
movement hated his guts, and the goals of his pro-war organizing and
their anti-war organizing couldnât be more different, but he still had a
certain identification with the anarchists. He evidently conceptualized
his differences primarily in terms of who was likely to actually achieve
the glorious revolution or rupture, anarchists or fascists.
âOn June 26th, 1920, active troops from two of the Armyâs best divisions
mutinied, refusing to board ships⊠The anarchists called a general
strike in support of the mutineers and within 24 hours Bologna was in
revolt⊠When [the socialists] refused to support the anarchists, âthe
Ancona rebels greeted this message with howls of indignation⊠When the
revolt collapsed on Jun 30th, Arpinati took it as further proof that the
socialists would not make a revolution.â
In short, while the anarchist movement was anti-war, its revolt in that
name was far more sympathetic to Arpinati than the socialist suppression
of the revolt. At least the anarchists were in favor of revolutionary
action. (As is their wont, the socialists approved brutal state action
to put down the anarchists, tools that the fascists would promptly turn
on them.)
Bookstore burnings, gunfights and grenade throwings ensued between the
fascists and the state socialists, just as Arpinati had cut his teeth
trading live fire with anarchists, with the cops backing Arpinatiâs
fascists and the landowners, Catholic orgs, and wealthy throwing money
on them. âBy March, membership in the fascio rose to between five and
eight thousand.â One of the successes of Arpinatiâs street terror was
that it largely avoided the socialist leadership to instead prioritize
murdering small socialist functionaries. The socialist leadership didnât
care as much about such lower level folks and the political leaders of
other parties didnât see this as a threat to norms protecting them, so
the fascists were largely free to terrorize the socialist base into
hiding. Beyond the examples of murders, one particularly gruesome detail
Whitaker gives is of a basement Arpinati used to personally torture
opponents.
During this period Arpinatiâs personal friendships managed to win him
converts from the ranks of antifascists. (Iâll say nothing about
contemporary embarrassments of self-proclaimed antifascists maintaining
friendships and even romantic liaisons with fascists, but at least there
are stronger pressures to disassociate and draw lines today.) Similarly
he was involved in repeatedly intervening to save Nanni from his own
fascist rank-and-file who just wanted to kill a socialist of any stripe.
But within a couple years Arpinati himself was outmaneuvered in power
games by a syndicalist also climbing the fascist ranks and he briefly
declared himself done and ran off to Libya, before inevitably returning
and once again clawing his way up.
By 1924 he was once again the official leader of the Bolognese fascists
and he turned his attention to systematically building support for the
fascist regime, stealing control of nurseries and summer camps from the
socialists and pouring money into sports projects and leagues. If you
check Arpinatiâs wikipedia page today practically the bulk of it is
about his ties to various sports.
In 1929 Mussolini appointed Arpinati Undersecretary to the Ministry of
the Interior, removing Arpinati from his very strong regional powerbase
to try to undermine him. But he only grew in power, becoming the âSecond
Duceâ of fascism by 1932. Itâs easy to see how this heralded his fall,
accusation of âantifascism,â imprisonment, and internal exile in 1934,
but his stances within the fascist milieu were increasingly out of line
with the necessities of state.
Arpinati was obviously centrally attracted to the violence and the
revolutionary potential of fascism, to be valued in-themselves, happily
chucking any socialist ends. But he also saw nationalism and street
violence as âantiauthoritarianâ because they broke the status quo and
allowed the suppressed natural elites like him to claw their way up. He
continued his prior fight with syndicalism from within fascism just as
he had fought it within anarchism. His focus on natural elites (he
published Evola naturally) made him hostile to attempts to build a wider
base and bring people into the party.
Arpinati kept some power and popularity and as the second world war
dragged on he refused entreaties by Mussolini to help him restructure
the government, instead trying to make a play to fund the resistance
movements and place himself on Mussoliniâs throne after the Allies
ousted him. Thereâs a neat little anecdote about how the deluded fool
felt sure the anarchists would hear him out and, lol, of course we
didnât. He made other plays, hoping the monarchy would rise against
Mussolini and install himself; he also personally helped evacuate
British generals trapped behind lines, in hopes of winning standing with
the Allies. Thankfully, Arpinati and Nanni were assassinated together in
April 1945 before he could regain footing in the post-war era.
In contrast to Arpinati and Nanni, and more in keeping with Rocca, was
the saga of Maria Rygier, who we already saw betrayed and attacked by
the patriarchs of the anarchist milieu.
Her break with organizationalist ranks greenlit widespread misogynist
attacks on her, with Borghi attacking her femininity, dress, figure,
sanity, etc. But even as she repeatedly went down for others and sealed
her lips behind bars, the organizationalist left spared no sympathy for
her. Syndicalist leaders even rejected prison reform while Rygier was a
quite prominent recurring prisoner, stating:
âprisons, except for extreme cases of political persecution, are not for
conscientious workers, but for the dregs of society!â
Leading Rygier to furiously rejoin:
âsyndicalism, when it is not union action⊠is reduced to a single
passive exercise: write, write, write, with presumptuous dilettantism,
insensitive to the fervor of battleâ
Itâs hard not to read this onto her parallel narrative arc from staunch
anti-militarist to nationalist warmonger. The syndicalists and scene
patriarchs no doubt deserved her absolute hatred, but one can see in the
above passage this hatred mutating to focus on their lack of militancy.
Where she went to prison and proved her commitment, so many of her
abusers and detractors sat relatively comfortably at home and
pontificated in abstract sneers. Of course commitment is not the same
thing as militancy, to say nothing of making a fetish of violence, but
the slippage between those ideas sure is perennial. When a detractor has
never risked their own skin, has never applied their fists, itâs hard
not to fixate on that division between you. Of course, certain people
like Fabbri and Borghi absolutely did take personal risks, but itâs easy
to understand Rygier seeing things differently from her position.
Obviously Rygierâs plight in the scene is sympathetic, yet no amount of
persecution by your âown sideâ can ever excuse or justify pivoting to
evil for friends and/or revenge. Whatâs morally correct doesnât become
fungible just because you face abuse and the enemy offers community and
means of retaliation. Itâs actually quite easy to give oneâs life for
anarchy in a single moment of bravery and pain, but the true test of
commitment is whether youâre willing to shoulder pain and isolation over
decades, to be constantly betrayed by âcomrades.â A shallow violent
militancy is often the easy way out compared to saying the unpopular
thing, resisting the popular or mythologized abusers, and sticking to it
through all the backlash.
Today we regularly hear people whine that they had no choice but to
become a tankie, or proudboy, or ecofascist, or work for a liberal
organization alongside cops, because some folks were mean to them and
the monsters were nice. I can think of nothing as spineless and craven
as making your values so un-fixed as to be dependent upon whether they
get you friends.
Rygier unfortunately sought allies not just with vile scumfucks on the
edge of the anarchist milieu like Rocca, but by March 1917 she had also
joined masons and sitting politicians in forming The Committee of Public
Safety to force Italy to more deeply commit to the war. This included a
plan to âexecute the king and hold the royal family hostageâ to ensure a
dictatorship. They planned and advocated mass repression and
imprisonment of Germans and anti-war activists (including virtually the
entire anarchist movement).
Mid 1920 Rygierâs commitment to fascism wavered, as Mussolini declared
war on Masonry. She threw herself in the opposite direction and got
attacked and her place ransacked by fascists. Throughout all of this she
continued to loudly assert that she had proof Mussolini had been an
informant for the French secret police and that it was this evidence
that provided her with insurance and was stopping Mussolini from
imprisoning or killing her. Nevertheless, eventually she realized that
bragging about blackmail diminishes its effectiveness and she fled to
France.
Whitaker doesnât cover much of Rygier after her departure and thereâs
even less available online. But itâs important to note the opportunism
and lack of principle to her supposed âanti-fascismâ and critiques of
Mussolini. Basically her argument was that Mussolini was a blackmailer
and opportunist (pot meet kettle), as well as a stooge of France to
undermine Italian national interests. Like Rocca, Nanni, and Arpinati
she was shunned by actual anti-fascists, although unlike Nanni and
Arpinati she didnât catch a bullet for her sins. She died a monarchist.
Although Whitaker centers four figures in his history, no one should
walk away with the impression that these were the only examples of
fascist creep in anarchist ranks.
I already mentioned the individualist anarchist newspaper editor turned
fascist, Edoardo Malusardi, but there was also Mario Gioda, an
individualist-anarchist and follower of Rocca who became the leader of
the Turin fascio and slaughtered eleven workers in December 1922. Gioda
came to be seen as an urban elitist and eventually marginalized within
fascist ranks. Whitaker mentions Mammolo Zamboni, another anarchist
turned fascist seen as heretical by other fascists, because he was
protected by Arpinati.
And there was Leo Longanesi, an anti-conformist who explicitly sought to
blend anarchism with conservatism and who represented an agrarian
populist wing within fascism. Longanesi gets the best quote in
Whitakerâs book:
â[fascism was composed of] ruffians, violent people, married people,
braggarts⊠vaguely fanatic people who agitate for no particular reason
against all that they do not understand, more than anything else from a
natural need to exalt themselves and rail against something: unable to
clearly formulate their own ideas, they condemn those of others: in
continuous personal rivalries, yesterday anarchists, tomorrow police
informers, today individualists, tomorrow communists⊠readers of
pamphlets, debtors, eternal idlers and inventors of systems for winning
at roulette, living in perennial and confused fanaticism.â
I list these other individuals to push back against the inevitable
attempts to dismiss and minimize all contact between individualist
anarchism and fascism.
While liberals, syndicalists, state socialists and communists each have
a vast array of members who jumped ship for fascism â anyone thinking of
using these details as indictment of individualist anarchism should
think long and hard before throwing stones on this â and the vast
majority of individualist anarchists in Italy obviously did not become
fascists, there was undeniably a lot of crossover in the early days.
While nowhere near as much as he was tied to the socialist movement (see
the copious praise that Lenin and Trotsky heaped on him) or the liberals
and conservatives that flocked to his promises, Mussolini was
astonishingly deeply enmeshed with anarchists. His father was part of
Bakuninâs anarchist international. He was personally close with the
infamous muslim individualist anarchist Leda Rafanelli in Milan. He knew
Carlo Tresca, praised Gaetano Bresci and Malatesta, collaborated with
Luigi Bertoni and translated two of Kropotkinâs books. He praised
Stirner and Nietzsche and quoted them at his adversaries. Mussolini even
appealed to (individualist) anarchism openly as justification of
fascism: âTo us, the doomed ones of individualism, there is nothing left
for the dark present and the gloomy tomorrow but the ever consoling
religion⊠of anarchism!â Mussolini even supported Sacco and Vanzetti and
complained privately to his friends that American fascists didnât side
with them.
Running away from this history will get us nowhere and provide no useful
antibodies against the resurgence of fascist creep in the worst fringes
of our movement.
Yet I certainly wouldnât recommend Whitakerâs book as a corrective.
The ideological analysis in The Individualist Anarchist Origins of
Fascism is just all kinds of shoddy and Iâve done my best to strip it
out in relaying the preceding historical accounts. Itâs hard to exactly
peg where Whitaker is coming from in terms of his own ideology. At many
points he seems to be condemning individualist anarchism from a
socialist perspective, at other points from a liberal perspective, but
there are a few distinct points in the book where he even seems
sympathetic to his fascist characters. He clearly finds individualism
somewhat suspect (or at least alien), thinks the extrajudicial execution
of Nanni and Arpinati is self-evidently bad (a crime!), and bemoans that
Arpinati has been written off as a fascist rather than recognized for
his accomplishments in good government. But even that shocking and
disgusting sympathy gets nuanced with something that looks like a
critique of the ways that historical narratives have pretended that
fascism was completely wiped away and wasnât part of contiguous
traditions through modern Italy.
Whitaker claims he wrote the book to push back against historical
accounts that flatten or homogenize fascismâs internal ideological
diversity and also cleave it from all prior and following history.
Thatâs certainly well and good, but the end result is a book certain to
mislead liberals and socialists, or, even worse, provide grist to actual
fascists. Itâs a useful book for anarchists, but for anyone not already
fluent in anarchism thereâs a serious danger of his warped accounting
doing lasting damage.
As Iâve mentioned, in (barely) trying to understand anarchism, he pulls
heavily from really unqualified liberal academics and from Woodcockâs
infamously problematic summary of anarchism. A lot has been written
critically on Woodcockâs 1962 Anarchism, its influences and resulting
influence. Woodcock was a pacifist with snobbish literary focuses, and
while he was involved in anarchist circles before the war, he was also
rather representative of the survivors that flourished in the post-war
period. He was running from the legacy of violent direct action and
concerned with social legitimacy, desperate to write off figures like
Bakunin as evil firebrands and to reframe figures like Kropotkin in
terms of his own perspective. His book was strongly slanted to reproduce
that analysis as well as to characterize anarchism in the rear-view
mirror as a failed project and historical episode. For anarchists like
my father that came up in the 50s and 60s itâs an incredibly apt summary
of their zeitgeist. But Woodcockâs Anarchism is not the place to find a
charitable or even fair reading of individualist insurrectionaries.
Woodcock was also writing to an audience of post-war liberals, whose
reference frame was very different from that of anarchism. The academic
liberals that Whitaker cites are all in this frame and to them anarchism
is not just a deludedly utopian artifact of lost history, but also a
deeply strange one that they are preoccupied with trying to fit into
their own notions of individualism and communitarianism. Since neither
they nor Whitaker really bother to read beyond some surface selections,
they do a lot of strawman inference to try and resolve how anarchism
solves the problems most pressing about it in their paradigm.
Thereâs also a belief that anarchism is centrally defined by the belief
that human nature is good. This â as Iâve repeatedly tried to emphasize
to contemporary anarchists â was the widespread takeaway for decades
after Kropotkinâs Mutual Aid (one of the few anarchist texts to survive
in influence and circulation in the US after the Palmer raids). It
wasnât just the warped takeaway of liberal critics, but it was also
sincerely what much of the rank-and-file movement came to believe over
these decades. Watch documentaries of old anarchists that persisted
through the 40s and 50s and you hear repeated explicit references to
this. Humans are essentially good in our core nature and weâve lost
sight of that and been warped by social institutions. This generation of
the movement took very strongly to Wilhelm Reich (silly orgone and all)
because he was a prominent figure pushing this same simplistic
perspective. Even if Kropotkin had a more nuanced view, what was printed
in Mutual Aid and in Ethics didnât do much of anything to counter such
beliefs and on-the-ground popular mobilizing narratives; movements donât
do nuance. This widespread appeal to nature as good directly coursed
into the creation of green anarchism and primitivism. Even if there
remained minority currents in anarchism that objected or didnât
formulate their perspectives in such terms, ânature = goodâ is indeed
reflective of the mainstream in this era.
But where Whitaker and the liberals he cites go wrong is in reading this
perspective backward into the anarchist movement in the 19th century and
early 20th. Certainly there was some presence around the milieu of the
occasional appeals to human nature (and nature more widely) as good and
the ground of anarchismâs values, but it was hardly hegemonic the way it
became during anarchismâs midcentury retreat and eclipse. Indeed much of
anarchism at this time was a fiery prometheanism, believing fanatically
in progress through science, reason, and technology, with the radical
new technologies of revolver and dynamite as unprecedented levelers that
would enable the transition to a society never before enacted. This was
not the narrative of Rousseau or Lewis Henry Morgan that liberal
discourse is familiar with. The movement was a point of intersection
between quite varying currents that all had similar conclusions about
the rejection of domination, and that mixed, hybridized, innovated, and
drew in wildly varying influences. Figures like William Godwin were
utilitarians who believed in a long struggle towards human perfection
until everyone was so individually enlightened that coercion would
become a distant memory. Such was absolutely not a perspective that
humans were naturally good but corrupted by social institutions, but
that rather humans could, with some work, recognize and come to change
ourselves towards what was good (like freedom), including in our bodies
(Godwin and the cosmist currents both endorsed radical self-alterations
to cure involuntary death). There were many other currents of course, I
emphasize the promethean ones as strenuous counterexamples to this
midcentury liberal notion of anarchism as an appeal to nature.
Because Whitaker and his liberal sources are reading things through that
lens they radically misunderstand and misrepresent the whole of
anarchism and the messy diversity of individualist anarchism, finally
characterizing Stirner in such nature-worshiping terms:
âStirner, too, sanctioned the authority of nature, presupposing in his
Union of Egoists that each of the Unique Ones was at heart good. Like
other nineteenth-century anarchists, therefore, even Stirner fell back
on the notion that some natural authority would be âinvoked
spontaneously by each person,â despite the âmassive tension between each
individual and the society in which he was ensnared.â â (Whitaker
internally quoting from Fowlerâs The Anarchist Tradition of Political
Thought)
Meanwhile, actual Stirner:
âOwner and creator of my right, I recognize no other source of right
than â me, neither God nor the State nor nature nor even man himself
with his âeternal rights of man,â neither divine nor human right.â
Whitakerâs reading of Stirner goes on to create a funhouse narrative
whereby Stirner is a moralist of The Natural and focused on Logic &
Reason, as a âdiscipleâ of Hegel, and as a mere proto-Nietzsche he is
later surpassed by Nietzsche who embraces true moral relativism. Thereâs
so much askew with this account itâs staggering.
There are many ways to read an author and exegesis of Stirner is almost
as completely boring and fruitless as exegesis of Marx, many a brain has
curdled pursuing either. I have no interest in excavating or defending
The Real Stirner, but some reads are just laughably divergent from
anything close to reality.
I think the more interesting question is: did figures like Rocca happen
to misread Stirner partly in the same way that Whitaker does?
And it seems very clear from his own words that Rocca did see Stirner as
advocating a rejection of thought and return to natural instinct. Indeed
this seems to be one of the weird instances where we can actually see
some evidence that these fascists actually read Stirner rather than just
picking up âthe gistâ from social interactions where he at best served
as a cartoonish meme. And not just The Ego And Its Own! Itâs in
Stirnerâs Critics where he rambles at length about rejecting thought for
its own sake, valuing it only in terms of its capacity to to dissolve
oneâs scruples. Thereâs a bit of a leap necessary to go from there to
worshiping natural instinct, and there is text of Stirner critiquing
being dragged along by oneâs hungers, but inveighing against thought
itself is not the sort of 101 level canard most people opportunistically
pick up from Stirner at a glance. Granted, itâs quite at odds with
Whitakerâs framing of Stirner as Logic & Reason bro, but we can pick out
a kind of coherent arc where thought is the realm of spooks intervening
over and distracting from the physical base of your impulses and
instincts.
While, again, words cannot emphasize how dreary and wasteful I find
arguments over what constitutes The Real Stirner, this is not such a
rare reading. Iâve encountered it among green anarchists and even
neoreactionaries. It has a certain kind of gravitational pull because it
avoids the perpetual goalpost moving of simply declaring every single
conceivable sentence one could offer up within language as just another
specter of reified thought. The Natural thus provides a ground, a clear
goal, an explanation of what all Stirner was on about that many people
find comfortingly clear. Of course even these Stirnerites wouldnât
capitalize it as an abstract concept âThe Naturalâ but they would
nevertheless emphasize that the point is something like listening to
your body or more directly flowing from its desires rather than getting
lost in a tangle of cognition and social concepts.
Whether collapsing desire construction and mutation down to a direct
connection with oneâs base instincts can be really extended into a
general endorsement of âthe authority of natureâ is less interesting
than whether folks repeatedly feel an attraction to such leaps.
Certain currents of fascists have repeatedly embraced Stirner, not as in
an attempt to claim something popular for themselves, as many egoists
have dismissively assumed, but because they clearly and explicitly find
personal resonances with Stirner. Youâll often find Stirner right beside
Evola on fascist reading lists in 8chan or the like, not because theyâre
consciously trying to steal Stirner â the vast majority of their
audience has never even heard of him â but because those recommending
him have their own connection to and sincere fondness for him. These
fascists see themselves as individualists par excellence and itâs vital
that we understand fascism as not necessarily the exact opposite of
individualism but often as a perversion or specific form of
individualism. This requires going beyond the inane boomer
mis-definitions of fascism in mere terms of totalitarianism,
collectivism, or homogeneity. And it requires us to kick off from a
defensive posturing that dare not concede any rhetorical ground.
In particular we must understand that nationalism has two sides, not
just the construction of a flat and illusory solidarity with oneâs
countrymen, but the stripping away of empathy and identification with
the foreigner. And of the two it is the latter that is the graver
mistake and more deadly poison. The mistake of nationalism, nativism,
etc, is most centrally about reducing oneâs circle of care. When
fascists scream that an American or a White life should be worth more to
you than a Korean life, they are not demanding you elevate your
compassion for some average American, they are demanding you decrease
your compassion for every Korean. And when they justify this by
appealing to some supposed natural or inherent pull to value oneâs kin
over strangers, the proper retort is not to litigate whether or not you
are truly âkinâ with every other American. The fascist wants to get
around to reducing that circle of care too! Contemporary fascist
movements have embraced the micro-scale and hyper-local. Ask a fascist
today if he thinks there should be border controls between US states or
counties and heâll often smirkingly answer in the affirmative. From
neoreactionaries to national-anarchists and countless other currents,
the evolution of the fascist movement has been to collapse the already
small number of individuals you are allowed to care about. To
characterize fascism in terms of a drive for some vast homogenous and
totalizing society is to miss that fascist movements have always
positioned themselves as defending a diverse patchwork of isolated
islands against the (supposed) homogenizing effects of global
connectivity. The Third Reich explicitly positioned itself as the
champion of local culture against the corruption of global civilization.
The fascist project is in no small part to shrink your identification
with others, to remove all sense of a common spark of creative
brilliance, emerging and situated in different contexts, different
lives, and to instead suppress this identification ultimately even in
yourself.
The creative nothing was probably meant as a non-concept, a kind of
topological defect or singularity in our language that formal
conceptualization cannot capture. The sort of beyond the horizon where
Wittgenstein thought everything important laid. I am, in my old age as a
cranky ideologue, a notorious criminal many times over convicted of
scientism, not particularly sympathetic anymore to the usage of
non-concepts of any kind. In my mind theyâve long since revealed
themselves as a cheap trick, a rug to sweep things under, a shell game
for folks running scams in the back alleys of philosophy. But even those
who embrace or accept the appeal to such non-concepts must still admit
they have a certain tendency to get immediately replaced by concepts.
What fits into the hole? A mere phenomenological experience of almost
cartesian remove and immanence? An anti-reductionist vitalism? A
collapse to bare pre-conceptual biological instinct? A self-reflective
loop of conscious integration? The array of things folks have implicitly
or explicitly stitched into the âcreative nothingâ is vast and quite
varied.
Some provide a springboard for empathic blurring of identification, in
this sense the stripping away of arbitrary conceptual scaffoldings and
historical happenstance allows for a very humanist move from identifying
as a thing or a set of things (just more inert chains) into identifying
with all fountainheads of the âcreative nothing.â This replicates the
core premise of anarchism: your freedom is my freedom, because what
matters is freedom, not the arbitrary particularities of some given
context in which it is expressed. We are not our various social or
physical identities or some clotting of memetic parasites in our brains,
but the motion underneath, and that motion is itself the same motion in
my brain and yours. The same underlying characteristic or property.
This, in various languages, is a common conclusion of some different
concepts that get plugged into âthe creative nothing.â
But in many other approaches the stripping away does not arrive at a
common freedom but at an even more particularized and isolated last
twitch of the mind. This is the place that Rocca went by embracing
natural preconceptual instinct as the antithesis to âthought for
thoughtâs sake.â It is also how fascists use Stirner to this day. In
their hands Stirner is a tool to strip away, to reject any recognition
of commonality. Why should you care about the stranger under the bombs
in another country? If they are your property to be used, they are at
best not particularly ready-to-hand, and at worst something more like a
tool abandoned to the weeds at the edge of your farm. Indeed what could
conceivably move you to care about their plight but some alien parasite,
some Humanist Brainwashing? To care about the abstraction of people far
away, laboring under the terror of the drones, is surely to fall prey to
the God that is the abstract âMan.â
Long ago, in the era before fascism was discovered by liberals (so prior
to 2017), I happened across a small brand-new blog of right-libertarians
mocking C4SS. The thrust of their critique was that mutualists clearly
hadnât read Stirner because they still did cringey humanist shit like
care about foreigners. I laughed and rolled my eyes even further to
discover theyâd registered a .biz domain â an affectation that had just
gotten popular among right-libertarians. There was no way this
âtherightstuff.bizâ would ever draw an audience, just another shitty
wordpress by two random dudes. âŠLater, of course, they would start a
podcast on that site called âThe Daily Shoah.â
Now obviously their usage of Stirner was rather mercenary. I mean they
also had posts up at the same time praising tradcath shit. It should not
be contentious that if you weld Stirner to Catholicism youâre gonna have
to strip away some of Stirner. But we can recognize that while also
recognizing that what would become the most popular nazi podcast wasnât
citing a then still quite obscure figure like Stirner to gain points,
but because they actually sincerely found value in him. And that value
was precisely in stripping away compassion for others. Mike Peinovich
and Alex McNabb had been attracted to right-libertarianism because it
provided justifications to dismiss the suffering of those without their
privilege and a narrative that let them see themselves as elite. But
they chafed at libertarianismâs strict morality and occasional concern
with the oppressed, as well as the implicit globalist cosmopolitanism of
markets. In Stirner they found an escape, a way to renounce those
fetters and embrace the callousness they actually felt. And while
Stirner does not share the inextricable essentialist elitism of
Nietzsche who despairs of a world drowning in sheeple, the reader is
still invited to an elite circle of the few brilliant souls who cast
themselves free of specters. Casting off the âfixed ideaâ of caring
about others from the apex of a hierarchy of enlightenment has obvious
resonances with fascistic frames, although the boys would quickly
discover they could get even stronger highs mainlining anti-semitic
conspiracies and racial pseudoscience.
Now obviously this example of neonazi usage of Stirner requires them to
scratch off more than a few things and certainly requires ignoring the
absolute nuclear bomb of his line, âI love men too â not merely
individuals, but every one.â But letâs be frank: Stirner wrote very much
in the way of snarky critique, and very little in the way of positive
argument. He emphasizes tearing down fixed concepts or memetic
complexes, and gives only the most tepid excuse or even appeal to not be
a massive prick. Heâs strong on âI will not be ruledâ but relatively
fleetingly and barely makes any substantive case for the other half of
anarchism: âI shall not rule.â Why should we love? Stirnerâs avoidance
of positive ethics, leaves him to functionally duck the question âI love
them because love makes me happy, I love because loving is natural to
me.â But what if loving isnât natural to you? What if you were born
feeling no sense of solidarity, empathy, or compassion, and find
happiness in torturing animals? And wait just a minute: how is anything
ânaturalâ to a creative nothing? Why should arguments of what is
ânaturalâ matter to a creative nothing? Is Rocca right that the ego
boils down to a return from the compounding loop of reflective thought
to natural instinct?
In every choice of one value or identification over another there are
mechanisms of causation and reasoning that are always inherently at
play. Everyone has a morality and ethics is innate to the very process
of weighing any choice. Those who never joined us in explicitly plugging
conceptual mechanisms into the hole of the creative nothing are free to
drift loftily above any consideration of this tangle; a lack of
awareness can, of course, serve as a sense of freedom. If youâre not
aware of the actual causal mechanisms by which one choice tugs at you
more than another you can treat the happenstance flicker of feelings
across your life as a kind of fountain of randomness or even wildness.
But nothing is really left to object to the âStirneriteâ who simply
happens to feel flickers of sadism and a lust for power. And even less
is able to be objected to when the fascist argues that caring about
strangers is unnatural, because their distance from immediate stimuli
and instinctive responses, to say nothing of continual social
entanglement, makes it impossible to be tormented by their torment or
refreshed by their refreshment without requiring the adoption of the
dread conceptualization.
I do not mean to imply that answers cannot be given, and some self
professed âStirneritesâ have indeed given various answers. My point here
is that these are non-trivial issues and fascists or other reactionaries
coming down on the other side of them are not simply reading âdonât do a
collectivismâ and doing a collectivism anyway. They are diverging in
ways from Stirnerâs own trajectory, but they are often still sincerely
reading him and being influenced by him. Even if they end up running
with him into absolute batshit scumfuckery like Rocca and Arpinati.
For decades Sidney Parker was one of the most prominent individualist
anarchists and Stirnerite egoists in the world, certainly the
anglosphere, ruling as editor of Minus One and EGO, writing the
introduction to a popular print of The Ego and Its Own, and generally
being a thorn in the side of the British anarchist scene. In 1993,
Parker finally abandoned anarchism, writing:
âAnarchism is a creed of social transformation aiming at the ending of
all domination and exploitation of man by man. Its adherents seek the
creation of the Judeo-Christian myth of a heaven on earth. The central
anarchist tenet is: Dominating People Is Wrong. It is based on the
belief that all, or almost all, individuals are, or can be, equally
capable of taking part in decision-making.
I no longer accept these propositions.
As a conscious egoist I can see no reason why I should not dominate
others â if it is my interest to do so and within my competence.
Similarly, I am prepared to support others who dominate if that will
benefit me. âIf the condition of the State does not bear hard on the
closet-philosopher, is he to occupy himself with it because it is his
âmost sacred duty?â So long as the State does according to his wish,
what need has he to look up from his studies?â (Stirner) Sometimes,
indeed, I may behave in an âanarchistâ fashion, but, by the same token,
I may also behave in an âarchistâ fashion. The belief in anarchism
imprisoned me in a net of conceptual imperatives. Egoism leaves any way
open to me for which I am empowered.â
And of course Parker endorsed racial hierarchy and emphatically embraced
Ragnar Redbeard, the inane âanarchistâ writer constantly endorsed
alongside Stirner by fascists, whose book Might Is Right has had many
republications literally covered in swastikas. Countless other more
personal and intimate examples of such turns exist, although itâs beyond
the purview of this book review to laboriously list them all. This is
adamantly not to say that every or even most egoist anarchists become
fascists or such outright scumbags. But if being an anarchist and
respected egoist for decades like Parker still isnât an inoculation
against such heel turns today we canât just write off Rocca and Arpinati
as strange historical anomalies and continuing fascist and reactionary
endorsement of Stirner a completely illiterate opportunism.
While I found value in Stirner in my youth, I must admit I have never
been able to fathom the people who defensively cling to him, who
identify with him as some kind of flag. I suppose if you are too weak to
stand in the face of sneering collectivists it may help to have
something else to throw in front of you as a shield. Some external
authority to prop up your voice and draw the fire of responses away from
you personally. Some shared idol to rally a tribe of dissidents. And, of
course, if the outgroup comes for this token, the ingroup must always
circle the wagons lest they be picked off one by one by the hordes of
moralist communist bureaucrats all around. But I dunno, surely folks
understand that an actual fiery individualism wouldnât feel the need to
remind everyone of oneâs asserted individualism or to immediately form
and cling to some new tribe?
I am, to say the least, disappointed and vexed by the incessant shallow
dismissal that âStirner opposed collectivism and nationalism is
collectivism, theyâre exact opposites, fascist Stirnerites are a
complete contradiction from which nothing can be learned.â Of course,
Stirner would have laughed at the nazis. Of course, he personally had
passages at odds with some of their specific positions. But the idea
that thereâs an ideological complete contradiction is simply not true.
No one spontaneously explodes upon emphasizing some parts of his texts
and ignoring others, much less in rearranging and reconstructing things,
or just using him as a loose springboard for what arguments they find
personally compelling instead.
The actual living person Johann Kaspar Schmidt who got the âbig
foreheadâ nickname Max Stirner, was, like any other person, of such vast
complexity as to defy compression into any set of texts, much less the
few we have from him. He might have had a somewhat unified and coherent
philosophical project, where each piece depends critically upon every
other piece, he might even have had radically different intuitions,
ideas, and responses than are implied within the few scant and highly
contextually-bound texts we have, but this is not how texts work. Texts,
for better or worse, end up existing as an assortment of arguments
placed alongside one another.
Iâm not suggesting that, for example, Roccaâs endorsement of a worldwide
war of all against all as the path to a union of egoists is some kind of
intelligent development on Stirner, nor anything that Johann Kaspar
Schmidt would have recognized. Rocca and Arpinati were bloodthirsty
scumfucks, Rygier a vengeful opportunist. They clearly drew at best very
loosely from Stirnerâs texts and itâs not at all clear that they had any
real love for anything else that might be called anarchist theory (and
recall that Stirner never identified with the term or the movement).
But even though Whitaker whiffs completely on understanding the
ideological elements in play, his book nevertheless documents an
anarchist scene annoyingly similar to todayâs. We donât shoot each other
with pistols at bookfairs, but the scumfuckery of some noxious egoist
wingnuts and the abusive power of some red scene patriarchs will have
immediate resonances to anyone whoâs been an anarchist for more than a
day and seen the worst corners of our scene.
This is the most chilling thing about The Anarchist-Individualist
Origins Of Italian Fascism: it reads like a friend at a potluck dishing
scene drama about one edgelord or another today. Even as the majority of
the Italian anarchist movement lies just out of focus, occasionally
throwing a chair or a rock at the protagonists and introducing an
interlude of hospitalization, you canât look away from the fuckery, you
already know it so intimately.
This is the frank truth, for all our heroism and angelic exemplars, the
anarchist milieu has always had a problem with a fringe of
militancy-worshiping shits for whom the attraction of âanarchismâ is a
promise of getting away with whatever they wanted. A âmight is rightâ
sort of attitude often tied to a fetishization of criminal/warrior
aristocratic elites in the name of militarism. The spine for âactionâ is
substituted for the spine for values. Who cares if that dude abused his
partner, he went to a tree sit once so nothing can be done.
The recruitment of such is an inevitable byproduct of how anarchism
frames itself and the struggles it is engaged in. Failing to address
these little shits â as well as allowing much of the mainstream of
anarchism to be captured by centralized power structures â leads to a
false dichotomy between tepid manipulative gatekeeping
organizationalists and bloodthirsty scumfuck âindividualistsâ where both
sides reinforce the other. If youâre not in favor of breaking glass in
motel pools to cut up children (because âsocial warâ) you must therefore
be with the pacifist lib grifters and identity politicians.
I started this review with Borghi and Fabbriâs medical rape of Rygier
mostly because itâs a shocking lost fact that should damn well be at
least a footnote on every goddamn thing about either of them, but also
because I know damn well that this review will be screamed about and
relayed to people as some outrageous outsider hitpiece on Stirner,
egoism, or individualist anarchism. And at the exact same time many
opportunist communists will salivate to link it as some kind of proof
that Max Stirner secretly lived another century, grew a mustache, and
renamed himself Adolf Hitler.
But I think Rygierâs turn to fascism is fascinating because we can
appreciate that she was no doubt motivated by her extremely fucked up
adversaries in the anarchist movement. You canât learn just how far
Borghi and Fabbri went in their struggle for popularity and influence
against her, as well as their allegiance to their bro, and not fucking
loathe them. And we can absolutely lay some of the blame for her pivot
to fascism at their feet while relieving her of not one iota of
responsibility and agency. Blame can overlap and multiply! Itâs not
zero-sum!
Too often the worst sort of abuse or misbehavior is covered up by âthe
other side is worse!!â Just as fascist creep is cultivated by a failure
to recognize and excise it, it is also cultivated by failing to handle
other problems. False binaries are created by inaction against or
tolerance of different flavors of fucked up shit. Green reactionaries
take root in part by pointing out how bad the bureaucratic reds are.
Nazbols take root by emphasizing just how bad the capitalist libs are.
Ranks close, political identities become mutable flags of convenient
counter-coalitions rather than anything consistent.
The Italian individualist anarchists were absolutely right to take issue
with the organizationalist currents that dominated the scene, that often
pacified and attempted to control or centralize anarchism (and thus give
space to corruption). But there wasnât a strong base of options beyond
Fabbri and Borghi (I would kill to learn Malatestaâs complicity or
ignorance of events), so Rygier sided with Rocca. This sort of thing
could have been partially derailed if the individualists who didnât go
fascist had the spine to stand simultaneously against both sorts of rot
early on.
It would obviously be a mistake to read Whitakerâs book in isolation;
just as there are Anarchist-Individualist Origins of Fascism, there are
also Bolshevik Origins of Fascism, Socialist Origins of Fascism, Liberal
Origins of Fascism, etc. Whitaker focuses on Nanniâs supposed
individualism, but let us never forget that the vast majority of
fascismâs initial origins were with the state socialists. And in
particular, the creeping mistake of âleft unity,â the bizarre but ever
popular delusion that âweâre all on the same side,â is no small part of
how an egoist streetfighter like Arpinati could end up best friends with
a literal mayor like Nanni and then a prominent politician like
Mussolini.
The dangers of circling wagons and accepting or overlooking problematic
allies to defeat a specific enemy are eternal. In both left-unity or
individualist-unity, it was on display throughout the sordid rise of
fascism, in almost exactly the same way theyâve continued to be a
problem in the last few decades. When youâre under siege and someone
shitty offers you friendship, it takes far more spine and courage to
burn that friendship than it does to merely throw more punches against
your common enemy.
Italian anarchists took way too long to settle on deplatforming and
ostracizing the protofash egoists. Yes, streetfighting and attacks on
protofash egoist talks were common (although the Novatori started it by
starting pistol fights at conferences). But one of the most shocking
things in Whitakerâs book is that venues and conferences continued to
give them a platform basically until they were openly at war with the
entire anarchist movement as explicit fascists. Further, Arpinati was
able to recruit from anarchist ranks well into his reign of terror on
the anarchist movement because he maintained personal friendships with
specific individuals. Anarchists didnât successfully (if at all) apply
pressure to stop those friendships and so he was able to court
âantifascistsâ into flipping sides. Similarly, much confusion was
clearly had before folks recognized that there can be insurgent or
revolutionary threats that must be studiously opposed simultaneous to
our opposition to the ruling establishment, never downplaying one threat
to focus on the other, much less allying with one against the other. And
of course, we canât afford to ignore how the allure of bravery and
militancy can obscure invalidating downsides.
The absolute necessity of enforcing No Platform, pressuring
disassociation, Three Way Fight, etc. are lessons folks have obviously
learned the hard way again and again in different subcultures and scenes
as fascist creep sets in, but itâs really arresting to read the
particulars of the very first anarchists to struggle with these dynamics
at the literal dawn of the fascist movement.
Sadly, while antifascism â as a specialized project, discourse, and
milieu â has been pretty much defined by the recognition of these
lessons, this perspective isnât a given in every circle that anarchists
operate in.
It has been frequently said that, âevery anarchist is an antifascist by
definition so focusing on antifascism is a dangerous distraction.â And,
as the populist traction of the Trump era wanes, much hay has been made
once again about antifascism as implicitly liberal. Something that
focuses on minor enemies to the benefit of the status quo. Identical
things have been regularly said about âfeminism.â In some real sense
anarchism is trivially feminist by definition, but while those two
concepts should ultimately converge, they clearly havenât fully in
practice. Feminism and antifascism can be appropriated by liberals to
serve the status quo, but this is no reason to reject them. Itâs long
been my contention that the anarchist movement needs a specifically
antifascist line of consideration, of focus in analysis and practice; it
cannot simply assume that antifascism follows trivially from anarchism
(or egoism or whatever).
If today â in a world of eco-fascists many of whom who sincerely want to
collapse civilization, initiate a race war and return to closed small
tribes, or national-bolsheviks sincerely committed to war on the
existing capitalist class, to say nothing of myriad other strains â it
is self-evidently absurd to cling to old marxist analyses that fascism
is merely a stage of capitalism, or that fascists are pawns of the
capitalists. We laugh in the face of boomers who still grab at claims
that fascism is literally defined by âcultural and ideological
homogenizationâ in contrast to virtually every fascist ranting about
preserving cultural diversity from globalism. But these absurdities were
once quite popular in no small part because studying actual fascists,
tracing the potency of their ideological appeals, or remembering
knowledge gained in struggles against them was dismissed as unimportant,
or even a threat.
It was not that many years ago that âantifaâ was a widely hated word in
anarchist spaces and the most basic sorts of campaigns, to, for example,
deplatform Death In June, provoked sneering if not fervent hostility.
Itâs literally impossible for that dude to be a fascist, heâs gay. My
favorite of such takes to this day remains, âum killing people for sport
is obviously the least fascist thing, it shows they have a liberated
libido.â
Yes, this is a collectivist sort of wagon-circling, but it also stems
from dismissively approaching fascism as purely a social or even
institutional phenomenon rather than an ideological movement. Or, even
as merely a substitute word for âthe bad thing.â In this context a book
like The Anarchist-Individualist Origins of Italian Fascism can only be
treated as an infuriating attack.
How can the good thing be in any way tied to the bad thing except
through spurious and tenuous associations, a tiny spattering of
nonsensical contradictions!
Yet, I actually do think thereâs something to the instinctive
understanding that fascism is just the polar opposite of us. Even if
that doesnât mean that everyone on the opposite side of us on any issue
is therefore a fascist.
Iâve long emphasized a two-tiered description of fascism: not just as
the macroscopic politics of palingenetic ultranationalism, but also an
underlying philosophy of power beneath it that stands as the exact
opposite of anarchism. This philosophy of power is hostile to reason and
all about shrinking oneâs circle of care and identification.
Intellectual arguments for compassion and truth must be discarded as
pointless or unsustainable via moral and epistemic nihilism, but itâs
not enough to dismiss them as specters, the continuing pull of reason
and empathy requires an active resistance lest it corrupt the fascist.
Thus violence becomes a purifying loop that sheds off compassion and
reason. The self-evident lie of the nation, race, etc (virtually all
fascists admit such collective abstractions are a lie, from Anglin to
Spencer), is a useful lie not just because it provides a way to mobilize
social power, but also because it helps secure oneâs own head against
the ever threatening spiral of reason and compassion.
In this sense fascism is a project defined not just as one pole in the
eternal conflict of power vs freedom, but by its evolved resistance to
the anarchist creep, that is to say the dangerous infectiousness of our
perspective. Not just through cultivating a continuous loop of violence
that burns away the weeds of higher thought and empathy, but also
through creating social pressures to vice-signal. Even when the fascist
cannot engage in daily physical violence, he can still make a combative
public show of his lack of concern for others. He can sing ânuke em till
they glowâ or speechify about stomping the skulls of immigrant babies or
defend the cannibalism of raider societies or make memes treating
Assadâs gas attacks like Nickelodeon goop. As the infectious processes
of reason and empathy broadly ratchet towards certain social norms and
common values, the fascist finds a thin âfreedomâ in his rupture with
them, creating an opposite community with opposite values of hardness
and shallow instinct.
There is, I believe, a substantive sense in which fascism really did
emerge from (individualist) anarchism, and thatâs as our antithesis.
Yes, the socialists, liberals, and conservative influences upon fascism
were vast, and counted for the overwhelming bulk of their numbers. In
comparison, the number of âindividualist anarchistsâ who joined them was
a barely visible dust mote. But what our presence contributed was a
crystalizing clarity that catalyzed and reshaped those long-existing
reactionary elements.
In this sense, while both anarchism and fascism are modern ideologies,
we are at the same time purifications of eternal tendencies throughout
history, the modern dimension being our self-awareness.
It is frequently marveled that anarchists and fascists often agree in
our models of the world, but pick completely different values to fight
for. Where liberals, socialists, communists, libertarians,
conservatives, etc embrace delusions of some kind of compromise, some
middle path between freedom and power, anarchists and fascists both tend
to understand the actual landscape.
What matters is the values we align with.
For this reason, âI will not be ruledâ on its own is not a half-step to
anarchismâs âI will not be ruled and I will not ruleâ but sometimes a
move in the completely opposite direction.