đž Archived View for library.inu.red âş file âş harold-barclay-people-without-government.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 10:44:29. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄď¸ Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: People Without Government Author: Harold Barclay Date: September 1, 1996 revised edition Language: en Topics: anthropology, the state, state, anarchism, history Source: Retrieved on 2019-06-11 from https://anarchyinaction.org/index.php?title=People_Without_Government:_An_Anthropology_of_Anarchy][anarchyinaction.org]] and [[https://aaaaarg.fail/thing/51c5856f6c3a0e090cf20c00
Anarchism is that political philosophy which advocates the maximization
of individual responsibility and the reduction of concentrated power â
regal, dictatorial, parliamentary: the institutions which go loosely by
the name of âgovernmentâ â to a vanishing minimum. It has no connection
with bomb-throwing radicals: it has, in fact, been a point of view which
has attracted biologists, such as Kropotkin, the founder of ecology, and
anthropologists. To advocate it one must practise considerable
self-abnegation, because the type of community it envisages cannot, for
obvious reasons, be prescribed. One cannot say with Colonel Blimp
âDammit, if the blighters wonât be democratic we must make âemâ . It is
the blighters themselves who have to choose.
In this book Harold Barclay gives a scholarly account of a number of
societies which do not accept the idea of Authority as natural â in
fact, it does not occur to them. The documentation is fascinating, and
it has its uses as an answer to the mythologies of âprimitive manâ which
have propped up conventional political theories from the XVII century
on.
The question which must occur to most readers, however, is one of
relevance â rightly, in view of the contemporary excesses of
âsociobiologyâ and the currency of theories based on white rats and
Trobriand Islanders. Pygmies and Eskimos neither organise railroads nor
operate social services: modern emulators like Makhno and Durruti, or
the kids who organise free communes, look quixotic. The serious manâs
problem with the anarchist wish to be rid of government is not, I think,
that he quarrels with the idea that governments today represent little
beside psychopathology, or that politics as we practise it is the art of
preventing the possible. His doubts arise from the complexity of
society, which looks irreversible, and the need for forward planning: in
fact, the charge-sheet of many modern governments is concerned not only
with the abuses they commit, but with their culpable failure to plan. In
the past, the excesses of power were offset by its ability to provide
coordination one put up with the psychopathology of King Henry VIII
because a strong king was manifestly preferable to multiple local war
lords. But with the growth of a technologically sophisticated public it
has become plainer and plainer that today teleonomic, or purposive,
planning has become almost wholly divorced from government. It is
conducted by experts, while authority devotes itself to play-therapy.
Some scientists, who find warnings ignored and resources squandered on
pyramids, Maginot Lines and Five Year Plans unrelated to reality, talk
about the day when computers will do the planning. Unfortunately, if
they did, the playtherapy group would programme them.
Faced with this, the âserious manâ withdraws into anti-politicism, or,
in America, populism (which substitutes free enterprise and the Devil
take the hindmost for the anarchist recipes of mutual aid and direct
action) . He would be quite willing to learn from the Inuit and Pygmies
if one could convince him that their forms of organisation had any
lessons one could apply to a modern, complex community.
I think they have. The challenge âgo run a modern state like a pygmy
village and see what happensâ misses the rather unusual cast of mind
which anarchists seek to impart. Unlike Marxism or democratic
capitalism, which are institutionalised theories, the rejection of
authority as a social tool is an attitude, not a programme. Once adopted
it patterns the kind of solutions which we are disposed to accept. Nor
in order to be an anarchist ¡does one need to wait until society shares
the same attitude. Anarchists do not plan revolutions but when they
become numerous, and the type of thinking which underlies the social
organisation of the small groups Harold Barclay describes becomes
common, the thinkers constitute active, unbiddable and exemplary lumps
in the general porridge of society. If numerous enough, they begin to
affect the types of choices which societies make. Mutual aid begins to
constitute a serious alternative to administrative services, general
dissatisfaction begins to turn to civil disobedience. If ârevolutionâ
occurs in consequence it is in the form of an assault by alarmed
authority, loath to see its kingdom fail , on the increasingly
ungovernable public, in other words counterrevolution . The growing
awareness is threatened by inertia, by cooption, and by the set
non-Pygmy habit of mind which comes from centuries in which our
political muscles have atrophied.
Nor, in order to influence the course of society, do anarchistminded
thinkers have to be wholly successful any more than the Chartists were
successful. The Chartists did not secure a single demand of the Charter,
but they reformed the parliamentary process. The surviving government of
a state whose citizens thought and acted anarchistically would be an
Irish democracy â one where the head of authority is held under water
whenever it steps out of line. Poland, at the time of writing, may be
headed in that direction. And indeed not only anarchist thinking, but
even anarchist techniques, such as unanimity instead of a majority vote,
are getting incorporated into such places as unions and protest
movements which a few years ago would have used parliamentary procedure
as a matter of course.
My own view is that anarchism is an attitude, not a programme: that
attitude has enzymatic effects on the society in which it is widespread
leading quite possibly to an adhocracy, an illogical compromise between
Simon Pure anarchism and some of the old apparatus, rather as republican
sentiment has been transmuted into a constitutionalism which illogically
retains a monarch as a kind of blocking piece, to restrict the excesses
of elected representatives. There are probably instances where
decision-making has to be concentrated, provided the hot breath of the
public is on the neck of the decision-maker. One would not now agree
with the protoanarchist Godwin that it is a betrayal of liberty to play
in an orchestra if it has a conductor. Where Barclayâs anthropological
accounts are important is not as blueprints for complex societies, but
as expositions of the attitudes of humans who have found no need of
Authority. Faced with other environments, these attitudes will lead to
new social structures, since man is an adaptive thinker, but as
attitudes they are not time or place-determined. We are likely in our
time to see many local and neighbourhood exercises whose form is
classically anarchist, plus a growing tide of protest, some principled,
some merely exasperated, in which anarchist modes of action and thought
may be embodied. A society in which protest is fully effective has no
need of a set revolution, and such a society, whether triggered by
Marxist stupidity and dogmatism or Fri world military psychopathology,
is an attainable goal. Studies such as these have accordingly more than
academic importance.
Anarchy is most often equated with chaos or seen as some crackpot scheme
advanced only by bomb-throwing, wild-eyed maniacs. Certainly it is an
idea which has not been taken seriously by most. Although in recent
years there has been a slight increase in appreciation of anarchist
theory, to the extent that a greater number now consider it worthy of
mention in serious discussion, it remains largely ignored. The
anthropologically demonstrated fact that anarchy is possible is
frequently overlooked.
Over the past several generations, anthropologists, through their
ethnographic research, have documented innumerable stateless and
governmentless societies throughout the world and throughout time. And
even the devotees of Marx point to these as indicators of some earlier
stateless stage of human cultural evolution. Nevertheless there is some
considerable reluctance to define these societies as anarchies. Even
amongst anthropologists there are those so imbued with their own
cultural traditions that they will go to any lengths to avoid
recognising these systems for what they are. Because they believe social
order can exist only where there is government and law, they stretch the
meanings of these terms to cover what is clearly not government at all.
In an anthropology textbook, Hammond has written[1]: âEven when the
population is large, relatively dense, and somewhat diversified, the
absence of government does not necessarily imply the presence of
anarchyâ (239). Hoebel, who later changed his mind, has so defined law
and the state, and so interpreted the data of numerous cultures, asto
make every society a state with law (1958, 467ff) . And earlier, both
Clark Wissler and George Murdock included a âgovernmentâ as a
âuniversalâ of culture (Wissler, 1923; Murdock, 1945).
Other anthropologists readily recognise the widespread existence of
staeless societies, some even call them âfunctioning anarchiesâ. They
see the need to demonstrate the existence of such societies as a task
long since accomplished and believe we should move on to more important
problems. However, it has been my experience in more than 30 years of
teaching anthropology that, among students, about the most firmly held
myth is the one that no society can exist without government â and its
corollary that every society must have a head. If modern day students
have given up the religion of the church, they have not budged from the
religion of nationalism and statism. It is the latter which affords the
source of unity â the cementing element â in contempoary âpluralisticâ
society. Thus, the myth of the necessity of the state and of government
is decisive for that unity, as decisive as belief in God was for the
unity of Medieval society. In the universities, political âscienceâ
departments are the chief centres for the promulgation of this myth.
One task of this book, then, is to present examples of anarchy. Thereby
we will demonstrate that there are human societies which fit the
criteria of anarchy and should be recognised for what they are.
There are also other reasons for this book. I will be suggesting that
anarchy is by no means unusual; that it is a perfectly common form of
polity or political organisation. Not only is it common, but it is
probably the oldest type of polity and one which has characterised most
of human history.
In the course of this presentation, attention will be given to the kinds
of social, economic, technological and ecological contexts which appear
to be conducive to anarchic systems. We must consider the oft-made
proposition that if anarchies or governmentless, stateless societies
exist, they could do so only in the most simple form of human culture
and in the smallest type of grouping.
An important aim of this book is to give some idea of what anarchy in
practice is like. In this we must consider the various ways in which
order is maintained within anarchy. This in turn is related to the more
general problem of the dynamic interplay between freedom and authority
which characterises human society. In connection with this we must
observe how anarchy can, and does on occasion, appear to degenerate into
despotism, a process which also entails a consideration of the origins
of the state. In general,then, we will try to address the question: is
there anything to be learned from these anarchic polities?
Perhaps, finally, this essay will provide a critique of anarchist theory
and contribute, therefore, to an improved understanding of the problems
of freedom in society.
There are similarities between what is proposed for this investigation
and some of the works of Kropotkin, namely, his The State: Its Historic
Role and Mutual A id. These works were a factor in my decision to enter
the field of anthropology and also stimulated my writing of this book. I
would like to think that this book adds to, and improves upon,
Kropotkinâs pioneering investigations in this subject.
Our first task must be to clarify the meaning of anarchy in relation to
a variety of different terms. Let us begin by considering anarchy and
anarchism. These must be distinguished from one another, just as one
distinguishes âprimitive communismâ from Marxian communism. The latter
is an elaborate sociological system, a philosophy of history and an idea
for a future condition of society in which property is held in common.
âPrimitive communismâ refers to a type of economy, presumably found
among âarchaicâ or âprimitiveâ peoples, in which property is held in
common. By property is to be understood the crucial resources and means
of production of wealth. In fact, what is communally held in such
societies is invariably land; tools, livestock, and many other kinds of
resources ( eg, fishing sites) are individually owned. In any case,
Marxist theory does not identify primitive communism with the intended
Marxist communism. One might say that implicitly it is held that the
historical process involves a grand cycle where humans commence with
primitive communism and ultimately return to communism at a higher level
â which is somewhat reminiscent of the progressive-cyclic theory of
Giambattista Vico. As we distinguish between the two communisms, so we
must also distinguish between anarchy and anarchism. Anarchy is the
condition of society in which there is no ruler; government is absent.
It is also most clearly associated with those societies which have been
called âarchaicâ and âprimitiveâ, among other pejorative adjectives.
Anarchism is the social political theory; developed in 19^(th) century
Europe, which incorporates the idea of anarchy, but does so as part of,
and as a result of, a broader, self-conscious theory of values which
makes human freedom and individuality paramount. Thus, in anarchist
theory, the first premise is something which Josiah Warren called the
sovereignty of the individual and from this it follows that government
and state are oppressive of individual freedom and should be abolished.
But, at the same time, the anarchist looks to the abolition of other
institutions similarly interpreted as oppressive: the Church, the
patriarchal family and any system which appears to enshrine âirrationalâ
authority. Anarchist theory is egalitarian and antihierarchical, as well
as being decentralist. Discrimination based on ârace, colour, or creedâ
or sex are always anathema. Anarchists were probably the first advocates
of womenâs liberation. In place of the old system, anarchist theory
advocates self regulation and voluntary co-operation. Social relations
are to be carried out through free contractual agreements of mutual or
equal benefit to all parties involved. For Proudhon âmutualismâ was a
basic cornerstone of anarchy. His mutualist conception has an
interesting similarity and concordance with the contemporary
anthropological theory of Mauss and Levi-Strauss, since mutualism may be
readily seen as reciprocity. To Levi-Strauss, reciprocity as a mutual
exchange is the fundamental structural principle of . society; it is a
kind of âcategory of thoughtâ, so fundamental as to be imbedded in the
human mind. Pierre Clastres, following in the tradition of Levi-Strauss,
argues that âcoercive powerâ, that is, both state and government, are
unreciprocal since a ruler receives more than a subject, so upsetting
the balance of equity. Therefore, state and government are in opposition
to the basic principles of social life: society is against the state. In
the final chapter I shall return to Clastresâ thesis and the general
subject of reciprocity and the emergence of coercive power. Here I only
wish to indicate that anarchist theory and anthropological theory do
impinge upon one another.
In addition to mutualism, Proudhon and Bakunin, among others, also
stressed the idea of federalism, designed to facilitate relations
between increasingly larger and more widespread groups of people. The
initial building blocks of the federalist plan are the local, âface to
faceâ groups, either of neighbours or persons with common occupational
interests â in any case they have a common mutual interest in working
with each other for one or more ends. Such groups form and concern
themselves with achieving their specified goals. In order to facilitate
these ends they âfederateâ with other similar groups to form a regional
federation and in turn regional federations join with others to form yet
a broader I federation. In each case the power invested in the organised
group decreases as one ascends the different levels of integration. As
Bakunin and others said, the system was to be âbuilt from the bottom up
and not from the top downâ. Each member of a federation has a right to
withdraw if in disagreement with the majorityâs proposed action. It is
interesting to note here the similarity between anarchist federalism and
the segmentary lineage system characteristic of many anarchic polities,
especially in Africa. In both cases the sum is composed of segments and
each segment of sub segments and so on. In both cases the most effective
authority is in the smallest unit, decreasing directly as one ascends to
broader levels of integration, so that at the âtopâ, the ultimate
federation has little influence whatsoever. In both cases, as well, we
have a technique for establishing a broad network which draws
innumerable small groups into 1â! large integrated whole. One major
contrast between the two systems, however, is that federalism is based
upon the co-operation between groups â the principle of mutualism or
reciprocity â while for segmentary lineages the operative principle is
opposition or conflict between groups of the same level. Anarchist
federalism should not be confused with the kind of âconfederacyâ
advocated by such men as John Calhoun and other early 19^(th) century
American political thinkers. Anarchists would be sympathetic to such a
view only in that it proposes to strip central government of most of its
authority, permitting member states to withdraw from the system if they
see fit. However, from an anarchist point of view, Calhoun and his
sympathisers were inconsistent, in that they¡ were primarily concerned
about maximizing the power of the several states within the Union. Had
they been interested in the freedom of the individual unit members, they
would also have recognised the legitimate right of the counties to
withdraw from states, of towns to withdraw from counties and of
individuals to withdraw .from towns.[2]
Anarchism is in sum a complex theoretical orientation. It should not,
however, be seen in any sense as a single monolithic conception, or a
grand theoretical system to be compared, say, with Marxism. Anarchism,
on the contrary, entails several related, but often distinct, points of
view. And no anarchist theoretician has ever presented an integrated
theoretical system. Yet all anarchist theory shares a common concern for
the individual and freedom, opposition to the state and a desire to
establish a system of voluntary co-operation. It is obvious that the
sort of society envisioned by anarchists does not exist and, except for
a few isolated and short lived attempts, has never existed.
Nevertheless, we do have numerous examples of anarchy â societies
without government and without the state.
Just as Marxist communists might not be thoroughly pleased with a
functioning âprimitive communismâ , so we cannot expect anarchists to
approve extant anarchic polities. It is obvious that many would be
horrified by some of their characteristics. While these societies lack
government, as we shall see, patriarchy often prevails; a kind of
gerontocracy or domination by the old men is not uncommon; religious
sanctions are rampant; children are invariably in a âsecond classâ
position; women are rarely treated in any way equal to men. Indeed,
there are invariably strong pressures to conform to group traditions.
But since they are highly decentralised, lacking government and the
state, they do exemplify anarchy. And thus we must look at such systems
as examples of the application of anarchy.
It may be argued that to employ the term âanarchyâ for a major group of
human societies is ethnocentric and confuses ideology with social
classification. It is to take a highly emotionally charged word, one
with a very clear ideological connotation, identified with Euro-American
cultural traditions, and to apply it cross-culturally when those in the
other cultures would clearly lack the ideology and values of the
anarchist. Thus, not only is the word distorted, but so also is the
meaning of those cultures.
But if this is true of the word âanarchyâ, it applies equally to the use
of such words as âdemocraticâ, âgovernmentâ , âlawâ , âcapitalistâ ,
âcommunistâ and a host of others employed daily by social scientists,
yet derived from ordinary speech. Social science is full of terms in
common usage which are applied to social contexts in other cultures.
There are certainly dangers to such a procedure. It is easy to carry
extraneous ideological baggage along with the term. On the other hand,
if we cannot at all make such crosscultural transfers, we are left with
a proliferation of neologisms which become pure jargonese, enhancing
obfuscation rather than clarification. There are, after all, types of
social phenomena which occur throughout the world. Scientific
understanding is not furthered by a kind of radical phenomenology which
makes every cultural item, every individual perception, unique. I
believe many anthropologists, in their own projection of personal and
cultural values, have obstinately refused to apply the one truly
clarifying term to those numerous societies which are without government
and are, therefore, anarchies.
One of the universal characteristics of mankind, or of any species for
that matter, is that it survives and thrives in the context of some kind
of order. That is, humans have peace of mind where behaviour and events
are on the whole predictable. We are animals of habit or animals of
custom â traditionalists. Behaviour in human societies is, therefore,
stanardised and deviations are punished. A society by definition has
order and structure and operates with regularised, relatively fixed
modes of behaviour. The term âsocietyâ implies that the component
members are operating according to some ârules of the gameâ. Such rules
can be extremely vague and open to conflicting interpretations, or they
may be very specific and explicit. In any case, there are guidelines
without which we would be lost in a sea of anomie. Part of the problem
of the modem world is that many of these guildelines have become so
ambiguous that the level of general anxiety of the population increases.
It is clear that where there is no structure, there is no order and
there is no society. And, as the first lesson in any anthropology or
sociology course points out, humans without society are not human. But
another part of that first lesson is that there is an immense amount of
variation within human society, including the amount and kind of
structure and order.
Having said this, let me add ¡that humankind often seeks a holiday from
routine and structure. Max Gluckman pointed to what he called ârituals
of rebellionâ, which are periods in which the populace is expected to
behave â within limits â in a manner counter to normal expectation. Thus
there is the âMardi Grasâ, which is a traditional relaxing of behaviour
before the commencement of the exacting observations of the Lenten
season. We have Halloweâen as a traditional time when children are
.permitted a short expression of rebellion against the adult community.
Victor Turner has suggested that there are two countercurrents in a
society: one of structure and the other of communitas or antistructure.
The latter expresses the spontaneous, the unplanned and the ecstatic, as
a kind of reaction to the usual, predictable and structured. This in a
way parallels Proudhonâs view that authority and liberty operate as
antinornies within any society, each acting so as to delimit the other,
In terms of these polarities, anarchism as a social theory is allied
with communitas and liberty. Like Thoreau, anarchists are critical of
those elements within a culture which become so engrained as to be
stultifying and superficial or empty rituals. They look with favour on
the new and the untried. Perhaps Nietzscheâs call to live dangerously
has some relevance here.
On occasion, the anarchist sympathy for communitas has appeared to go to
extremes. Thus Hippies, in their rejection of modern structures,
sometimes reject every form of structure so as to enshrine dirt â the
ultimate of disorder. But while, of all social theories, anarchism has
more sympathy for communitas, it is still not opposed to structure, to
order or to society. Indeed, Proudhon once wrote that liberty is the
mother of order not the daughter. The issue for anarchists is not
whether there should be structure or order, but what kind there should
be and what its sources ought to be. The individual or group which has
sufficient liberty to be self-regulating will have the highest degree of
order; the imposition of order from above and outside induces resentment
and rebellion where it does not encourage childlike dependence and
impotence, and so becomes a force for disorder.
The relation of anarchy to power, authority, politics and political
organisation is another misunderstood area. In human groups some
manoeuvring for power characterises the relationship between individual
members. The intensity and emphasis on the contest varies from one
culture to another and from one individual to another. The cultural
values of the Pygmies to be discussed and also of such Pueblo Indian
groups as the Zuni and Hopi, play down attempts by individuals to stand
in the forefront, although one cannot say that the desire to influence
others is absent. And within every culture there is variation. Some
people strive more than others; a few even opt out. Nevertheless, the
contest for power manifests itself in some fashion within each human
group. Power means the ability to get others to do what you want them to
do. Thus, someone who convinces ten others to follow orders has more
power than someone who is able to get only one to obey. But this depends
on all other things being equal, since, for example, someone who
controls the one individual who knows how to use a nuclear detonating
device can have more power than someone who controls the behaviour of a
million ordinary men and women. Power means influence â convincing
others by logical argument, by the prestige of oneâs status or rank, by
money or bribe. Or it means implied or overt threat of injury â either
by physical or psychological means â and the ability to carry it out.
The contest for power is an important dynamic force in the social group
â a major mechanism by which the group undergoes change over time. The
âpush and pullâ of members not only causes âpalace revolutionsâ, that
is, shifts in the personnel of the less powerful and the more powerful,
but leads as well to changes in rules and values.
Ralf Dahrendorf, a German sociologist who is certainly no anarchist,
presents a thesis in a way amenable to anarchist thought, particularly
as an answer to Marx. Dahrendorf suggests that the conflict for power is
central in a society; Marx was primarily concerned with one feature of
the power complex, namely, economic power. This emphasis has meant that
those who follow Marx devalue the non-economic dimensions of power.
Consequently, we find the world full of peoplesâ democracies in which
the oppression of ordinary people is no less than it was before the
ârevolutionâ. Marxism in practice has tended to transfer the forces of
power from the capitalist to the professional bureaucrat and military
officer, primarily because it does not see that the central problem is
the problem of power itself. The anarchist insists upon addressing this
larger issue.
Neither anarchy nor anarchist theory deny power; on the contrary, in
anarchist theory this is a central issue for all human societies and the
limiting of power is a constant concern. Bakunin recognised the great
human drive for power ( Maximoff, 248ff ) . Anarchy is, after all, the
condition in which there is the maximum diffusion of power, so that
ideally it is equally distributed â in contrast to other political
theories, such as Marxism, in which power is transferred from one social
group ( class ) to another. It is, of course, true that much anarchist
thinking regarding power has been muddled by âutopianâ dreaming of the
ideal society where no-one infringes on anyone else. Godwin and
Kropotkin, for example, believed that in the course of time the human
race would evolve towards a condition where all were good to their
fellows and did not try to take advantage. But other anarchists are not
such optimists about human nature; if they were they would not be so
worried about the uses and abuses of power.
Max Weber stressed the difference between power and authority. In any
society, individual members recognise certain others as having authority
within specified realms. Thus, in modern society, members accept as
legitimate the right of certain individuals to carry and, where
ânecessaryâ, to employ firearms, in order to apprehend suspected law
breakers. These policemen invariably wear special dress. Members of this
society do not recognise as legitimate the use of force by others, such
as gangsters. In both cases coercive force is¡ employed. In the first
the power is authority since it is seen as legitimate and right; but the
second is not authority; it is the illegitimate use of power. Something
of this kind of distinction can be identified in all societies. Yet a
significant modification of Weberâs terminology is in order. Most
Canadians would eagerly subscribe to the notion that the power of the
Ottawa government is legitimate, but some would only acquiesce to that
power. The several generations of colonial rule of the Dutch in
Indonesia, for example, commenced as a pure case of the imposition of
brute and raw force. But with the passage of time it acquired a certain
âlegitimationâ , so that the power became authority in Weberâs terms.
But it becomes legitimate power because the Indonesians learned to
acquiesce: they grew accustomed to the situation and tacitly accepted
it. Raymond Firth has noted that power acquires some kind of support
from the governed either because of âroutine apathy, inability to
conceive of an alternative or acceptance of certain values regarded as
unconditionalâ (123). Most authority commences as the raw power of the
gangster and evolves into the âlegitimateâ authority of tacit
acquiescence. This is certainly the history of the nation state. Fried
observes that legitimacy is the means by which ideology is blended with
power. The function of legitimacy is âto explain and justify the
existence of concentrated social power wielded by a portion of the
community and to offer similar support to specific social orders, that
is, specific ways of apportioning and directing the flow of social
powerâ (Fried, 26).
No philosopher or social theorist accepts the legitimacy of ârawâ use of
power and none rejects totally and completely any and all kinds of
authority. Even the anarchist recognises that there is a place for
legitimate authority. An anarchist conception of legitimate authority
was long ago intimated by Proudhon: â ... if man is born a sociable
being, the authority of his father over him ceases on the day when his
mind being formed and his education finished, he becomes the associate
of his father... â (n.d. ,264) . Later Bakunin wrote: âWe recognise
then, the absolute authority of science ... Outside of this only
legitimate authority, legitimate because it is rational and is in
harmony with human liberty, we declare all other authorities false,
arbitrary and fatal â (Maximoff, 254).
Paul Goodman in Drawing the Line writes of natural coercion in which the
infant is dependent upon his mother or the student upon the teacher â
cases in which teaching is involved with the intent of increasing the
independence of the one to attain the level of the other (1946) . I
donât know whether Fromm ever read Proudhon, Bakunin or the early
Goodman, but certainly his view of the nature of authority closely
parallels and further explicates that of his anarchist predecessors.
Fromm distinguishes, as does Bakunin, between ârationalâ and
âirrationalâ authority. Rational authority has its source in competence;
it requires constant scrutiny and criticism and is always temporary. It
is based upon the equality of the authority and the subject âwhich
differ only with respect to the degree of knowledge or skill in a
particular fieldâ . âThe source of irrational authority, on the other
hand, is always power over \ peopleâ â either physical or mental power
(9). Stanley Milgram has said that people appear to believe that those
in positions of authority, including politicians, are the most
knowledgeable. But perhaps this is only wishful thinking in an attempt
to justify their authorities. People delude themselves into thinking
that through the electoral process they put those in office who are
intellectually superior.
Modern society has many in authority who have earned rationally the
right to authority, but it has many whose claim to authority is
irrational and they are our politicians, judges and policemen. These the
anarchist rejects, accepting only rational authority. Anarchists¡
recognise that there are specialists, that is, authorities in various
realms, who are accepted as such because of their expertise. Yet one can
readily see the potential danger inherent even here, that those holding
one form of authority may seek to extend their power¡ so that rational
authority is transformed into irrational authority. Closely related to
the concept of authority is that of leadership. Again, no one can deny
that there are individuals who appear in every human group who stand out
as influential persons for one reason or another. The anarchist movement
has long accepted leaders within its own folds, even though it has
remained suspicious of the general idea. Although group leadership is a
universal of human social organisation, it is, at the same time,
necessary to stress that leadership is conceived differently amongst
different peoples. The Pygmies and Hopi of Arizona express an anarchist
distrust of leaders, such that that each individual seeks to avoid the
leadership role, blending into the group as much as possible.
Since societies have order and structure and must deal with the problem
of power, they are therefore involved in politics. When we use the word
politics, we are concerned with power and its uses in a human group. Not
only do all societies have politics, but they have political
organisation or political systems â that is, standardized ways of
dealing with power problems. Political organisation is not a synonym for
government. Government is one form of political organisation. Politics
may be handled in a variety of ways; government is just one of those
ways. Thus it is clear that even anarchism as a theory does not deny or
oppose politics or political organisation. It is, on the contrary, very
political.
In the broadest sense politics can be applied to any kind of social
group-. That is, there may even be politics within the family â where
clearly the distribution of power between father, mother, son and
daughter is a major issue. A local club also has politics in a similar
small-scale fashion. Ordinarily, however, when one speaks of politics or
political organisation, one does not think of the internal affairs of
the family. Political organisation applies more to âpublicâ affairs â
relations which are territorial and cut across kinship groupings.
Politics involves a substantial geographical area â a community, or at
least an extensive neighbourhood. Yet even this kind of
conceptualisation leads to ambiguity as to whether one is dealing with
political or family affairs. We may have a confrontation between two
groups related by kinship, but beyond the level of extended family (for
example, two patrilineages), which would be considered at least as a
quasi-public affair. Nevertheless, the terms of address employed and the
atmosphere of the exchange will unmistakably be those of kinship.
Neither anarchy , nor anarchist theory in sum, is opposed to
organisation, authority, politics, or political organisation. It is
opposed to some forms of these things, especially to law, government and
the state, to which terms we must now proceed. Radcliffe-Brown proposed
the term âsanctionsâ to apply to the manner in which a social group
reacts to the behaviour of any one of its members. Thus, a positive
sanction is some form of expression of general approval. A soldier is
given a medal; a scholar an honorary degree, or a student an award;
mother kisses little junior for his good behaviour, or daddy gives him a
piece of candy. A negative sanction is the reaction of the community
against the behaviour of a member or members; it expresses disapproval.
Thus, a soldier may be court martialled; a scholar fired or put in jail;
a student failed in course work or ostracised by fellow students and the
child slapped b y his parent. It seems obvious that it is the negative
sanctions which become most important in any society.
Sanctions may also be categorised as being âdiffuseâ, âreligiousâ or
âlegalâ. Here my interpretation deviates slightly from that -of
Radcliffe-Brown. Diffuse sanctions are those which are spontaneously
applied by , any one or more members of the community. Crucial to the
conception of diffuse sanctions is the notion that their application is
not confined to the holder of a specific social role. They may be
imposed by anyone within a given age/sex grade or, occasionally, there
may be no limit to who may initiate them. This is the meaning of
diffuse: responsibility for and the right to impose the sanction is
spread out over the community. Society as a whole has the power. There
is no special elite which even claims a monopoly on the use of violence
as a sanctioning device. Further, when and if sanctions are applied is
variable, as is the intensity of the sanctions imposed.
Diffuse sanctions include gossip, name calling, arguing, fist fighting,
killing and ostracism. Duelling and formal wrestling matches are less
widespread forms. Inuit have ritualised song competitions in which two
opponents try to outdo one another in insults before an audience which
acts as judge. Diffuse sanctions may be resorted to by an individual or
a group. And their effectiveness is enhanced as the entire community
joins in participation in the sanctions. Vigilante style action and
feuds are common forms of diffuse sanction which depend upon collective
action.
In many societies, fines and other punishments are meted out by an
assembly. Radcliffe-Brown calls these âorganisedâ sanctions. Yet they
are still not âlegalâ but have the character of diffuse sanctions, of a
more formalised type, if the assembly has no authority to use force in
executing its decisions. In such instances the assembly members act as
mediators rather than judges and are successful to the extent that they
can convince two disputing parties to come to some compromise. Diffuse
sanctions are a universal form of social regulation; if a social group
has nothing else it will have various techniques which can readily be
classified as diffuse sanctions.
Religious sanctions involve the supernatural. âBlack magicâ may be
performed against a person; one may be threatened with the eternal
torment of hell, or encouraged with a positive religious sanction
promising everlasting ecstasy in heaven. The Nuer leopard skin chief may
get his will done by threatening to curse another. The Ojibwa Indians
believed infractions of the rules led to the acquisition by supernatural
means of specific kinds of diseases. Thus, religious sanctions may
either have a human executor, as in the case of a curse which must be
invoked, or be seen as automatic, as with the Ojibwa belief, or the idea
that breaking out of the ten commandments commits one to hell fire. In
another respect religious sanctions are either those which are intended
to bring forth punishment in this life, or those which are for an
after-life: physical versus ultimate spiritual punishment.
Legal sanctions involve all expressions of disapproval or approval of
the behaviour of an individual wherein: a) such expressions are
specifically delegated to persons holding defined roles, one of the
duties of which is the execution of these sanctions; b) these
individuals alone have the âauthorityâ to threaten use of violence and
use it in order to carry out their job and; c) punishments meted out in
relation to the infraction are defined within certain limits and in
relation to the âcrimeâ.
Policemen, justices of a court, jailers, executioners and lawmakers are
examples of those who may enforce legal sanctions. In our society they
collectively constitute a government. The state, through its agent the
government, declares it has the monopoly on the use of violence against
others within society, meaning that only certain agents of the state,
for example, policemen, can take a person off the street and put him or
her in jail. Only certain collectivities, that is, the courts, can
determine guilt and assess a punishment in accord with what others, the
lawmakers, have established as law. Finally the punishment connected
with a legal sanction is fairly standardised and precise. A person found
guilty of robbing a store will receive, say, a year to ten years in
prison.
Legal sanctions are laws. Laws exist where one has specific social roles
designed, or delegated, to enforce regulations by force of violence, if
necessary and where punishment has certain defined limits and is not
capricious. Law exists where you have government and the state;
conversely, if you have a government you have law. Legal sanctions, and
thus law and government, are not universal, but are characteristic of
only some human societies â albeit the most complex ones. Such societies
also, it should be borne in mind, retain a peripheral position for both
diffuse and religious sanctions.
Malinowski suggested that the term âlawâ should be applied loosely to
cover all social rules which have the support of society (Malinowski,
9â59). Such usage, however, obscures the fundamental and important
difference in the means by which different rules are enforced. Law and
government are invariably associated with rule by an elite class, while
governmentless societies are invariably egalitarian and classless.
Hence, Malinowskiâs loose usage obfuscates the important difference
concerning who, or what, enforces regulations.
It should be clear that any society characterised by the prevalence of
legal sanctions can hardly be called anarchic. As we shall note in
considering some of the case studies below, there are marginal examples.
There is no clean-cut line between anarchy and government. The relation
of anarchy to diffuse and religious sanctions, however, requires some
futher clarification. In the social theory of anarchism the idea of
voluntary co-operation has been made the positive side of the coin of
which abolition of government is the negative. Where the idea of
voluntary co-operation is so critical to anarchist thought, it is
important to consider it in relation to the nature of functioning
anarchic polities, giving special attention to the employment of diffuse
and religious sanctions. Voluntary co-operation, like its antonym,
coercion, is a highly ambiguous term. From one point of view nothing may
be seen as purely voluntary and all acts as being in some way coerced.
For one thing, it might be said that conscience, ego, id, âthe inner
spiritâ or what have you, are fully as coercive forces as the policeman,
or as public ostracism. However, coercion may be best conceived as a
relationship of command and obedience, wherein the commanding force is¡
either human or supernatural, but is always external to the individual
person. Ideally, for true voluntary co-operation t9 prevail, there must
be no such forms of external coercion. Yet, in fact, even anarchists
themselves accept the use of such coercive force and limit voluntary
co-operation. In their everyday activityâ in their writings and in their
own creation of anarchist communes and societies, anarchists use a
variety of diffuse sanctions. Some have advocated and applied what are
clearly legal sanctions.
It is sometimes difficult to distinguish the type of society envisioned
by a Bakunin or Proudhon from a decentralised federal democracy. Towards
the end of his life, Proudhon seems to have moved away from his advocacy
of voluntary association, towards a sort of minimal state. â ... (I)t is
scarcely likelyâ, he writes in Du Principe Federatif, âhowever far the
human race may progress in civilisation, morality, and wisdom, that all
traces of government and authority will vanishâ (20). For him anarchy
has become an ideal type, an abstraction, which like the similar ideal
types, democracy and monarchy, never exist in a pure form, but are
mixtures of political systems. âIn a free society, the role of the state
or government is essentially that of legislating, instituting, creating,
beginning, establishing; as little as possible should it be executing
.... Once a beginning has been made (for some project) the machinery
established, the state withdraws leaving the execution of the new task
to local authorities and citizensâ (45). Proudhon has become an advocate
of a federal or confederal system, in which the role of the centre is
reduced âto that of general initiation, or providing guarantees and
supervising ... (T)he execution of its orders (are) subject to the
approval of the federated governments and their responsible agentsâ (
49). He cites the Swiss confederation with approval. âIf I may express
myself soâ , Proudhon had written in a letter of 1864, âanarchy is a
form of government or constitution in which the principle of authority,
police institutions, restrictive and repressive measures, bureaucracy,
taxation, etc, are reduced to their simplest termsâ (quoted in Buber,
43). We are left wondering if the elder Proudhon would now not feel more
at home with such early American opponents of centralised government as
John Taylor of Caroline or John Randolph of Roanoke, even John Calhoun.
Bakunin, who absorbed most of Proudhonâs federalist ideas, presents a
similar problem. In describing his idea of a federal system in the
Organisation of the International Brotherhood, Bakunin makes some
disconcerting statements: âThe communal legislatures, however, will
retain the right to deviate from provincial legislation on secondary but
never on essential issues ... â while the provincial parliament âwill
never interfere with the domestic administration of the communes, it
will decide each communeâs quota of the provincial and national
taxationâ. There are to be¡ courts and a national parliament as well.
This national parliament âwill have the task of establishing the
fundamental principles that are to constitute the national charter and
will be binding upon all provinces wishing to participate in the
national pactâ. The national parliament âwill negotiate alliances, make
peace or war, and have the exclusive right to order (always for a
predetermined period) the formation of a national armyâ (Lehning,
72â73). Bakuninâs anarchy sounds like a decentralised federalist
democracy. Yet a year after writing this document he seems to redeem
himself for anarchy in an essay on Federalisme, Socialisme et
Antitheologisme: âJust because a region has formed part of a State, even
by voluntary accession, it by no means follows that it incurs any
obligation to remain tied to it forever.â âThe right of free union and
equally free secession comes first and foremost among all political
rightsâ (Lehning, 96).
Kropotkin favourably described the early Medieval city . commune as an
anarchistic system, when, as we shall note below, it surely had a
governmental structure. The same may be said concerning the âanarchist
collectivesâ established in the Ukraine in 1917 and later in some of
those in Spain. Even such an individualist anarchist as Josiah Warren
saw the need for organised militias. And most anarchists have
legitimised military force to achieve their ends, or have considered it
an unfortunate necessity. In a word, anarchists have sometimes been
equivocal about legal sanctions, to say the least.
In focusing on highly centralised realms of coercion in modem society
such as the state and the church, they have also tended to neglect the
sometimes more oppressive force of such diffuse sanctions as gossip and
ostracism. Nevertheless, there is an important difference between the
coercion of the state and. the coercion of diffuse sanctions, which may
in part justify anarchist reliance on the latter while rejecting the
former. In the state or government there is always a hierarchical and
status difference between those who rule and those who are ruled. Even
if it is a democracy, where we suppose that those who rule today are not
rulers tomorrow, there are nevertheless differences in status. In a
democratic system only a tiny minority will ever have the opportunity to
rule and these are invariably drawn from an elite group. Differential
status is not inherent in diffuse sanctions. Where a group or individual
employs gossip or ostracism against another person, that person may
freely use these same techniques. Where differential status is
associated with diffuse sanctions, such as in the command position of
the father over his son, we do have a form of coercion which begins to
approach that of government. Yet still the father role has the quality
of a rational authority and a young man may expect eventually to
âgraduateâ to a position of greater equality with his father, eventually
achieving fatherhood himself. In no diffuse sanctions is there a vesting
of the power to employ violence into the hands of a restricted group of
commanders.
Anarchism as a social theory cannot, and I believe in actuality does
not, reject all forms of coercion. While its advocates may wield the
slogan of voluntary co-operation, it is recognised that this too has
limits. For anarchists there is a tacit and, for many, an overt
recognition of the legitimate use of some kind of force in some
circumstances and this force is what anthropologists refer to as diffuse
sanctions. Indeed, as psychologists have informed us and as Allen Ritter
has lately reiterated, these sanctions are imperative for the
development of personality. The growth of the individualâs self image
relies upon knowing what others think of his or her behaviour. At the
same time, the operation of sanctions instills awareness of others and
so builds community by building empathy (Ritter, 1980): Concerning
religious sanctions, anarchist theoreticians have generally looked upon
religion as another oppressive system aimed at curbing the free
expression of the individual. Michael Bakunin, e.specially, saw God and
the state as two great interrelated tyrannical ogres which must be
destroyed. All well-known anarchists at least opposed the church â
religion being seen as an organised and hierarchical social structure.
Even Tolstoy agreed in this, although his anarchism derived from his
interpretation of a Christianity which stressed the literal acceptance
of the teachings of the Sermon on the Mount.
The Catholic Worker Movement is a rather unusual development within
American anarchism. Led by a convert to Catholicism, Dorothy Day, it
professes both an adherence to the principles of pacifist anarchism and
to the Roman Catholic Church â a kind of Catholic Tolstoyan movement.
Few outside this movement have understood how anarchism, or for that
matter any moderately libertarian doctrine, could be reconciled with
Roman Catholicism and its dedication to an absolutist monarchy â the
papacy â and to a rigid hierarchical structure.[3] Most anarchists see
any religion as an authoritarian system, but are all religious sanctions
necessarily incompatible with anarchy? I think not. We must appreciate
the distinction made above between those religious sanctions which
require human mediation and those which are âautomaticâ. A religious
sanction which is least compatible with anarchy and takes on some of the
character of . a legal sanction, is one which can only be invoked by a
specific individual as part of a formal office and where there is
consensus that such a person has a legitimate monopoly on the power â
ie, the authority â to impose sanctions. The priest is the best example
of this. On the other hand, where the power to invoke religious
sanctions is available to the many and not legitimately monopolised, we
have a situation which parallels diffuse sanctions. A punishment which
is believed to come directly from God or some other supernatural force,
does not require human intervention and is more on the order of
subjugation to natural occurrences such as storm and earthquake. Indeed,
it is quite clear that punishment by oneâs conscience is a sanction of
this order. Those religious sanctions which parallel diffuse sanctions,
as well as those which require no human intermediary, do not seem
incompatible with anarchy as we have here conceived it.
Conceptions of government and the state and the relationship between
them are often confused. Marxists and some anarchists, including
Bakunin, declare their opposition to the state and desire to replace
what is called âpoliticalâ government with a government over âthingsâ.
But this seems like playing with words and sloganeering.â Any âthingsâ
are going to be manipulated by people and will therefore be seen as in
need of governing because people are involved. So it is still a
government over people. Further, one cannot abolish the state and still
have a government, since the latter is the institutional apparatus by
which the state is maintained.
Nadel (1942, 69â70) has given three specific characteristics of the
state and in doing so has also indicated the role of government in the
state. First, the state is a territorial association. It claims
âsovereigntyâ over a given place in space and all those residing within
that area are subject to, and must submit to, the institution of
authority ruling or governing that territory, that is, the government.
While the state is a territorial entity, it is often an inter-tribal and
inter-racial structure. The criteria for membership are determined by
residence and by birth. Membership is ordinarily ascribed, although one
may voluntarily apply to join if one immigrates and settles within the
territory of the state.
The state has an apparatus of government and this is to some degree
centralised. The government functions to execute existing laws,
legislate new ones, maintain âorder and arbitrate conflicts to the
exclusion of other groups or individuals. It comprises specific
individuals holding defined social roles or offices. Crucial to the
definition of such roles is the claim to a monopoly of the legitimate
use of violence within that territory. The part played by the different
role holders in using violence may vary so that there can be a highly
differentiated system or division of labour (cf the discussion of legal
sanctions above). All are in any case part of a single integrated
monopolistic institution. Such a situation differs, for example, from
the role of the Inuit shaman who may threaten a victim with violence,
since the shaman cannot claim a monopoly on its legitimate use.
The ruling group in any state tends to be a specialised and privileged
body separated by its formation, status and organisation from the
population as a whole. This group collectively monopolises political
decision. In some polities it may constitute an entrenched and
self-perpetuating class. In other more open systems such as a democracy,
there is a greater circulation or regular turnover of membership of the
ruling group, so that dynasties or other kinds of closed classes of
rulers do not ordinarily occur. This, of course, contributes to the
illusion of equality of power in a democracy and obscures the division
between rulers and ruled.
Fundamental to both government and the state is the employment of
violence to enforce the law. This may be variously viewed as either the
imposition of the will of the ruling group, or as a device to maintain
order, keep the peace and arbitrate internal conflicts. In fact states
and governments fulfil all these functions by enforcing the law. It is
theorists of the left and especially anarchists, however, who emphasise
that the paramount and ultimate end of all law enforcement is to benefit
the ruling interests, even though there may be positive side effects
such as keeping the peace. They would further emphasise that the
existence of the state is conducive of strife and conflict since as a
system based upon the use of violence it thereby legitimises and incites
it. The state is further predicated upon the assumption that some should
be bosses giving orders while others should be subordinates â a
situation which can only irk the subordinates and frustrate them and,
thus, become yet another provocation of violence. Democratic systems may
ameliorate this situation but they do not cure it. By their nature state
and government discourage, if they do not outlaw, the natural voluntary
co-operation amongst people, a point made by Benjamin Tucker and more
recently in some detail by Taylor. Anarchist theory is therefore clearly
opposed to Hobbesâ thesis that without government society is nasty and
brutish. Indeed, anarchists set Hobbes on his head and argue that the
world would be more peaceful and amenable to co-operation if the state
were removed. And, clearly, the anthropological record does not support
Hobbes in any way. Stateless societies seem less violent and brutish
than those with the state.
Above all, the state and government are organisations for war. No more
efficient organisation for war has been developed. It is interesting and
perhaps ironic that right-wing and anarchist theoreticians have
converged in recognising the significance of violence to the life of the
state. Machiavelliâs practical guide to the operation of a state has
disturbed many a naive believer in democracy, since the Italian
politician recognises force and fraud as the obvious central mechanisms
for the success of any state. Von Treitschke, the German historian whose
greatest hero was Frederick the Great, observed that âwithout war no
State could be. All those we know of arose through war and the
protection of their members by armed force remains their primary and
essential task. War, therefore, will endure to the end of history as
long as there is a multiplicity of States ... the blind worshipper of an
eternal peace falls into the error of isolating the state, or dreams of
one which is universal, which we have already seen to be at variance
with reasonâ since a state always means one among states and thus
opposed to others (38). â(S)ubmission is what the State primarily
requires ... its very essence is the accomplishment of its willâ (14).
âThe State is no Academy of Arts, still less is it a Stock Exchange; it
is Power.. â (242).
The pioneer British anthropologist, Edward B Tylor, wrote in his
Anthropology, âA constitutional government whether called republic or
kingdom, is an arrangement by which the nation governs itself by means
of the machinery of a military despotismâ (156).
Nietzsche, who contrary to popular opinion was no friend of the state,
noted its predatory nature: âThe State (is) unmorality organised ... the
will to war, to conquest and revenge. â As a predator the state attempts
to become larger and larger, ever ¡expanding its sphere of influence and
subjugation at the expense of other weaker states. It is true that in
the course of time in this interstate struggle most states opt out of
the conflict and resign themselves to becoming satellites of larger
states, realising they cannot effectively compete. It is also true that
the giant states may not always. seek to gobble up weaker states,
because they find it better for their own interests to keep such states
as ostensibly independent entities. Thus, in the modem world, we have
super powers which are in the midst of the struggle for expansion,
carrying on the traditional predatory role of the state â the United
States, Russia, China, France, and. the United Kingdom ( now marginally
) . There are innumerable satellite states of each of the big predators.
There are those â usually known as âThird-worldâ states â which may try
small order predation against neighbouring states, but on the whole they
keep their independent status and opt out of full conflict because they
are buffers between, or pawns of, the big predators. Finally there are a
few states such as Switzerland and until recently Lebanon which are
perpetually neutral zones; the big predators do require such zones in
which to operate, particularly for information gathering purposes.
The classification of sanctions discussed above may now be summarised in
relation to political systems by means of the following diagram
presented as a continuum with anarchy, where there is 00 government, at
one end and archy, where the state and government clearly exist, at the
other. Under anarchy only diffuse and certain supernatural sanctions are
operative, while archy is characterised by the prevalence of legal
sanctions. In the middle, between the two poles, there is a limbo which
may be seen as a marginal form of anarchy or a rudimentary form of
governmental or archic system. There are many anomalous cases of this
kind and we shall consider some of these below. Such entities may
possibly be considered as transitional examples from anarchy to statism.
As Lowie has said, states do not appear full blown out of the stateless
condition; they too must evolve or develop and this takes time.
Maine in his Ancient Law was the first to explicate an evolutionary
typology of tribal or stateless society on the one hand and the state
type society on the other. The first was based on kinship ties, in which
every member believed he was related to all others in the group. Members
obeyed a head man, not as a ruler of a state, but as a senior kinsman,
as head of a family, a father. Early societies were all of this type and
in the course of time some evolved into societies with a different basis
of membership â that of territory . âLocal contiguityâ rather than
kinship became the basis for deciding the ultimate authority. Such a
society entails a government and a state. Gluckman has noted that Maine
meant to stress that the ârevolutionâ in social order comes about when
dwelling in a certain territory was sufficient to grant citizenship
without having to create some kinship tie either by marriage, adoption,
or through inventing a genealogical connection. âThe alteration comes
when a kinship idiom to express political association is no longer
demandedâ (86).
My continuum should not be interpreted as an evolutionary scheme, in
which culture history is a one-way street where tribal or anarchic
societies only become state type societies, while the reverse does not
occur. At any point in time, individual societies may be placed along
the continuum. In addition, any given society may have different
positions in the course of its history. The major thrust of history
seems to be the transformation of stateless into state societies, but,
as we shall note below, there are examples as well of the reverse and of
societies which seem to oscillate back and forth between the two
opposite poles. In addition, let us not forget that even if the trend of
history and evolution favours the change from anarchy to archy, this
does not thereby make that process right and good.
In selecting the various societies discussed in the following chapters,
I have attempted to obtain a wide ranging diversity in terms of
geography and cultural type. At the same time an effort has been made to
employ a sampling which offers distinct and different solutions to the
problem of order in anarchy. In other words, emphasis has been placed on
drawing examples of varying kinds of sanctions and styles of leadership.
Some cases are included whose anarchic nature will clearly be
controversial. They may represent cases of marginal anarchy or marginal
âstatismâ.
We may distinguish among the several examples of anarchic polities
between those which are âunintentionalâ and those which are
âintentionalâ. The latter are deliberate, planned attempts by
individuals to initiate a social order according to some preconceived
programme. To use another descriptive adjective, they are âUtopianâ
experiments along anarchist lines. Most of the sample are
âunintentionalâ, the kind of societies which, like nearly all those in
the human adventure, have grown âlike Topsyâ, in the absence of any
overall conscious plan.
Finally, concerning these unintentional societies, it should be borne in
mind that for most of them the conditions described no longer obtain.
With the advent of European imperialism these anarchic polities â which
are clearly the least understood by European colonialists of all
non-European political arrangements â were transformed to fit into the
pattern of government and order as conceived by the masters. In the
descriptions which follow, however, the present tense will be used so as
to suggest an âethnographic presentâ.
The discussion of the several anarchic polities is placed within the
context of a typology of societies long in vogue in anthropological
circles: that is, according to their primary mode of subsistence. Thus,
some are hunters and gatherers of wild animals and plants; others are
chiefly simple gardeners or horticulturalists primarily dependent upon
cultivating domesticated plants with hand tools and human Jabour power
alone. A third type are pastoralists who specialise in herding livestock
and at the same time may give incidental attention to cultivation of
plants. Finally, we may speak of agricultural peoples who are dependent
upon a more extensive form of plant cultivation using animal traction
or, more recently, tractor power. Here the chief technological symbol is
the use of the plough. Such societies depend upon a mixture of plant
cultivation and livestock husbandry.
Some anthropologists have made much more of such a classification of
societies than may in fact be warranted. For them the significance of
this classification is that one may predict from subsistence numerous
other strategic characteristics of such societies. Therefore, the
classification, it is held, bears out the theoretical orientation of a
materialist conception of humans and their culture. This is the view
that the subsistence base of a society determines the type of social
system. This is not the place to enter into a detailed argument
concerning this thesis. Yet usage of this classification here, as in
many other anthropological works, should not be taken as support for
this point of view. The classification is employed because it offers a
convenient way of dividing, and so dealing with, a variety of human
situations. And like any classification and its implicit theory it bears
elements of truth. Thus, we know that practically all hunting-gathering
people lack a complex division of labour, social classes-, the state and
government, and at the other end of the spectrum that practically all
agricultural societies have social classes, a complex division of
labour, the state and government. It is clear that hunting gathering
cannot provide the necessary material wherewithal to sustain such
elaborate social systems as can an agricultural system. Thus,
hunting-gathering societies are, with only a few exceptions,
âegalitarianâ societies in Friedâs classification, or âband typeâ
societies in Serviceâs. And most examples of anarchic polities are
likewise to be drawn from hunting-gathering peoples, whilst agricultural
societies are almost entirely stratified (Fried) and state type systems
where anarchy is at best a marginal occurrence.
As is so true of single factor determinist theories, this one as well,
which rests upon material subsistence, has a ring of truth if we remain
at the level of certain broad generalities and probabilities. However,
such theories break down when we attempt to employ them in explaining
the wide variations which occur, for example, within hunting-gathering
systems, or the more precise dynamics pertaining to specific aspects of
the social order. Nor are they able to explain variations in ideology.
Like the geographical environment, mode of subsistence may be said to
set limits to what a people by themselves can do and can develop, but
within these limits there are, given the inventive genius of the human
mind, all kinds of variations which are possible and are not purely
epiphenomena of material conditions of life.
Any society at a given time is the product of the collective interaction
of its several parts, not of one phenomenon alone. Food gathering of a
specific kind is in part a determinant of population size and diversity,
as well as of the extent to which sufficient wealth can be produced to
allow for certain development in social organisation. Population size
and density have much to do with the kinds of social organisation which
can appear. For example, a small population can readily sustain a polity
based solely upon kinship. At the same time hunting and gathering, like
any other mqde of subsistence, is also heavily dependent upon the kinds
of technology available. Yet the technology and, thus, the whole
hunting-gathering base, depends upon the non-material factor of
knowledge which is inside peopleâs heads. Knowledge in turn is focussed
or oriented by the prevalent kinds of cultural values â what is held to
be the important ends of life â and in turn by the existing kinds of
technology. In a word the most satisfactory model of a social order may
be as an interacting multi-factor system.
The sequence from hunting-gathering through horticulture, pastoralism to
agriculture should not be seen as a fixed model of stages of cultural
evolution through which every culture must pass, nor should it be viewed
as a sequence of ever increasing complexity. It is true that all
societies either are, or were once, dependent on hunting-gathering and
that most present day agricultural societies started out as
hunting-gatherers and evolved into horticulturalists .. But there are a
variety of other ways or sequences in which societies may develop
besides this process. The model of cultural evolution is multilineal,
not unilineal.
Regarding degrees of complexity, some hunting-gathering societies are
more complex than some horticultural ones, some even more than a few
pastoral ones. And some of the horticultural societies are as complex as
some of the agricultural ones. In the descriptions which follow the
emphasis will be upon determining patterns and techniques of leadership
and mechanisms of social control as indices of anarchic polity. The
relations between the sexes and between age groups are two areas of
concern to anarchists, and in any modern anarchist theory there is a
demand for full sexual equality and at least an opposition to any
irrational authority over the young. In what follows we will not have a
great deal to say on this subject. The truth is that few societies grant
anything approaching sexual equality and female equality is clearly not
a feature for which most of the societies discussed below are to be
noted.[4] Similarly, the young are invariably subordinate to their
elders and more often than not in an arbitrary manner. We stick to the
strict meaning of anarchy as a polity without rulers, without
government, but again freely admit that this may leave much to be
desired by those who are ideologically anarchists and by others
concerned about liberty as well. Anarchy does not necessarily mean
freedom.
Finally, there is a problem with the names commonly applied to several
of the groups discussed in that they have an ethnocentric origin. At the
same time appropriate alternatives are difficult to locate. Thus, while
Eskimo has its origin in a pejorative, the alternative, Inuit, which is
the name they use for themselves, has an ethnocentric ring as well. It
means people or human beings carrying with it the implication that
outsiders are not human. Berber is no doubt the most pejorative
appelation of all â it means barbarian. But these people lack a single
blanket term for themselves. Most, however, use some form of Imazighen,
that is, âfree menâ, and I would surmise that none of them would resent
being so called. In this text I have tried to employ neutral terms for
the various groups, but I have not been able to produce any exhaustive
ethnocentric-free list of names. I still use Pygmy for lack of an
alternative and for all I know the names of many groups may disguise
insults of one kind or another. I will use Inuit instead of Eskimo; San
instead of Bushman; Samek instead of Lapp and Imazighen instead of
Berber.
âAmong the lessons to be learnt from the life of rude tribes is how
society can go on without the policeman to keep orderâ (Tylor, II, 134)
.
The hunting-gathering type is obviously the oldest kind of human
society, characterising the human way of life from its cultural
beginnings and for about 99% of the time thereafter. Beginning about
12,000 years ago, with the invention of plant cultivation and animal
husbandry, hunting and gathering began to decline. Today, there is
practically no group on earth which relies completely on this way of
life. Even the Inuit and Arctic Indians have abandoned full dependence
upon hunting and gathering in favour of a livelihood aimed in great part
at obtaining furs and manufacturing itenis for an international luxury
market. Elsewhere, the huntergatherers such as those to be found in
India or in parts of East and Central Africa, are usually specialised
castes of professional hunters dependent upon an adjacent agricultural
or horticultural society.
Hunter-gatherers constitute simple societies and are primitive in the
sense that primitive means that they are more similar to the oldest
forms of human society than are other extant ones.[5] But it is an error
to conceive of these societies as being the same as those archaic
societies. Contemporary hunter-gatherers are present-day people who,
like everyone else, have a history; they are not petrified hangovers
from a Paleolithic past. They have changed at a different rate than most
other people and in different ways. Their histories represent various
paths of evolutionary development, not necessarily some fixed stage
within, or at the bottom of, an evolutionary sequence.
Although hunting-gathering is a type or class of societies, such
societies are not undifferentiated, like so many peas in a pod. Contrary
to some popular views, there is a considerable variation among them. In
delineating the highlights of the type then we should indicate some of
the more significant variations. These societies are dependent upon the
acquisition of wild, undomesticated foods: wild game, fish and plants.
Nevertheless we find there is some tendency to specialise in exploiting
selected resources. Thus, there are those who are largely hunters of sea
mammals; others tend more to fishing. There are peoples who may be
called big game hunters and those who specialise more . in collecting
wild seeds. There are also many who are much more omnivorous in their
habits.[6]
Reliance upon wild sources of food places greater limits on potential
cultural development than any other form of subsistence. There are more
severe limits on what a people can do and can invent and utilise when
they must rely upon the often precarious and insecure sources offered by
nature alone. There is less guarantee as to where the next meal might
come from than in an agricultural society. But it is not a life that
demands unceasing labour or a kind of bare hand to mouth existence. This
is a condition which more appropriately describes a peasantry or 19^(th)
century factory working class. Ordinarily hunters and gatherers produce
a food supply sufficient for an adequate caloric intake for each member
of the group, plus enough for the ritual and ceremonial requirements
traditional for the society. Some, chiefly fishing specialists, have
been able to build up âsurplusesâ and enjoy a more secure food supply
than many an agriculturalist. In any event, the parameters of no human
societyâs subsistence are ever so rigid as to preclude freedom in
experimentation and innovation.
Hunting-gathering societies invariably have a band type organisation.
This means that the basic stable territorial group is a relatively small
one, usually under 100 persons. It contains at least a core of
individuals who are kinsmen and in most cases all in the band are
related to one another. The group is identified with some territory
which it, as well as others, sees as belonging to it.
Nomadism is normally a characteristic of such societies. Yet this does
not mean aimless wandering. Rather there is periodic movement according
to some rational plan from one encampment site to another. Nomadism, and
especially pedestrian nomadism, inhibits the accumulation of material
goods. Nomadic hunters do not make good pack rats since one can hardly
carry a mess of junk from one camp to another. A minority of
hunting-gathering people have been sedentary, dwelling in villages.
Hunting-gathering societies share a technology based upon the use of
stone, wood, bone and ivory tools. They do not of themselves know the
art of metallurgy.
There is a minimal social differentiation and specialisation of tasks.
The social roles are limited to those of kinship and to roles based on
sex and on relative age. The society is characterised by what
Radcliffe-Brown referred to as a high degree of .substitutability. That
is, it is easy to substitute one person for another. One adult male can
be fairly readily replaced by another. So each person of the same sex
and approximate age is expected to be able to do what any other one in
the same category can do. Thus, the adult male is a jack of all trades,
or, more correctly, there are no trades. Nevertheless, there are in such
societies inÎźividuals who do tend to specialise, so that one person may
become more adept at fashioning arrow heads than any other in the group
and another more knowledgeable in performing rituals or in making cures.
Indeed, in some cases the shaman becomes at least a part-time
specialist.
Such societies are also egalitarian to the extent that âthere are as
many positions of prestige in any given age-sex grade as there are
persons capable of filling them ... â. At the same time âan egalitarian
society does not have any means of fixing or limiting the number of
persons capable of executing powerâ (Fried, 33). Egalitarian does not,
however, mean that there is any equality between sexes and between
different age groups. In a few hunting-gathering societies, such as the
Inuit there is greater equality between the sexes. Nevertheless males
are still considered superior.
There are also a few hunting-gathering societies which must be
considered as rank societies âin which positions of valued status are
somehow limited so that not all those of sufficient talent to occupy
such statuses actually achieve them. Such a society may or may not be
stratified. That is, a society may sharply limit its positions of
prestige without affecting the access of its entire membership to the
basic resources upon which life dependsâ (Fried, 1 10). In a
classification based on different criteria, Elman Service describes
âchiefdomsâ as a type of society with some close parallels to Friedâs
rank societies. âChiefdoms are redistributional societies with a
permanent central agency of co-ordination.â The central agency acquires
an economic, religious and political role (Service, 1962, 144). The
âredistributorâ of communal wealth is a âchief or person in an
established position of influence, responsibility and wealth. The
political role of this redistributor or âchiefâ varies considerably. At
the anarchic âpoleâ we have the examples of the Yurok and Northwest
Coast Indians given below. At the other extreme there are Polynesian and
African chiefs who are in effect petty kings. Among hunter-gatherers
these âchieflyâ or ârankâ style societies tend to be the wealthiest and
economically most secure. Anarchy is the order of the day among
hunter-gatherers. Indeed, critics will ask why a small face-to-face
group needs a government anyway. And certainly any which may be called
fully egalitarian according to Friedâs definition are anarchic.
If this is so we can go further and say that since the egalitarian
hunting-gathering society is the oldest type of human society and
prevailed for the longest period of time â over thousands of decades â
then anarchy must be the oldest and one of the most enduring kinds of
polity. Ten thousand years ago everyone was an anarchist.
, the indigenous residents of the North American Arctic, are a
well-known people â both in terms of their adaptation to the hard life
of the far north and as participants in an egalitarian social system.
Even Hoebel recognises their âprimitive anarchyâ (1954, 67).
Social groupings among Inuit have been referred to as tribes by some
observers, but the term designates a particular geographical group which
shares a common culture and language. It has no political significance.
Birket-Smith writes:
âThus among the Inuit there is no state which makes use of their
strength, no government to restrict their liberty of action. If anywhere
there exists that community, built upon the basis of the free accord of
free people, of which Kropotkin dreamt, it is to be found among these
poor tribes neighboring upon the North Poleâ (144).
Traditionally Inuit formed local communities or bands which in some
cases consisted of a few dozen members and in others of ten times that
number. In each band there is at least one outstanding individual and
usually one person whom the others recognise as a first among equalsâ
(Birket-Smith, 145). Birket-Smith reports that among the Central Eskimos
of the Northern Canadian mainland this person is called âisumataq , he
who thinks, the implication being he who thinks for the othersâ (145).
But one might also surmise that the title implies that the person is
considered the most intelligent in the group.
In any case, an important basis for leadership is demonstrated ability
in activities necessary for survival in this climate: hunting, provision
of food and shelter, shrewdness and astuteness. Spencer, describing the
North Alaskan Inuit, says that one of the recognised leaders of the
community would be a man of wealth â that is, a big boat owner (65). Yet
this man has also achieved his position by knowledge and skill in
exploiting the local environment. Aside from such secular leadership,
shamans are an important element in Inuit politics as well as religion.
A shaman may be a respected hunter, but his power derives from his
special relationship with the supernatural forces. The shaman is a
curer, a diviner, a conjurer, a magician and a leader in religious
ceremony. The Inuit shaman is believed to have the power to ascend into
the heavens and descend into the underground, to control weather and
other natural phenomena. He can invoke supernatural forces to benefit a
person and he can also invoke them to cause injury. Among the Copper
Inuit, shamans âheld the threat of witchcraft over others and were, for
the main part, not highly susceptible to vengeance because of their
presumed supernatural immunitiesâ (Damas, 33).
In Inuit society there is no-one who can be called a ruler â a person
who can order others to obey him, having behind this order an exclusive
right to employ physical force to compel obedience. Leadership is
informal and the role of leadership only loosely defined. The commands
of a leader can be ignored with impunity, but this could be dangerous,
especially in connection with a malevolent shaman. In a community major
issues are . openly discussed in informal gatherings. Consensus
regarding a course of action may result, usually being an approval of
the suggestions made by influential men. However, if unanimity of
opinion is not forthcoming, the disagreeing parties may merely go their
own way.
The Inuit case points to the potential pitfalls of a system in which
there is no formal leadership and where anarchy prevails. As we have
noted, a shaman can exert considerable power by inducing fear of his
supernatural powers, so that he could enhance his position, although he
would not thereby enhance his prestige. Damas says they were more feared
than respected (33). A related problem which arises in Inuit society is
the man who chooses to reject community morality and assert his personal
strength in acquiring whatever he wanted. Often such men are able to run
roughshod over others in a community, but inevitably must ultimately
come to a violent demise themselves. They might be dispatched by a
revenge killing. Or in vigilante fashion, a number of men, sometimes the
offenderâs relatives, would plan the execution. A less permanent
solution is to drive the individual out of the group. In any case some
form of diffuse sanction is the only means employed to overcome such
threats.
All forms of leadership, including that of shaman, are achieved statuses
in Inuit society. As one earns status, so one might also lose it. Loss
of position could come with the appearance of what is recognised as a
better leader, hunter or shaman or as a result of the failure of
shamanic powers.
Alleged wrong-doers could be ostracised and in some cases driven out of
the village, or, as we have already mentioned, in extreme cases they
might be killed. Gossip and argument are effective techniques for lesser
offences. Occasionally a severe crime might go entirely unpunished.
Ordinarily the kinsman of a murdered man sought revenge and feuds of a
limited sort have not been unknown. Inuit frequently settle disputes
through competitive trials between opponents, with the audience deciding
who is victorious and therefore winner in the dispute. Two disputants
might therefore engage in a wrestling match, or they might compete with
one another in composing songs which, among other things, attempt to
outdo each other in insult. Shamans contest with each other by
demonstrating their marvellous powers in grand spectacles which could be
the highlight of an otherwise dreary and dark winter.
An Inuit woman could not be considered as fully equal to a man, yet she
has a liberty and influence which exceeds that of women in most. other
societies. It is sometimes argued that the high position of Inuit women
results from their crucial role in the economy. An adult male Inuit
requires assistance in maintaining a household; he cannot survive
without an adult female fulfilling her role. So necessary are women to
the household that if a man is unable to find a single woman to take as
his wife, he may even indulge in polyandry and marry a woman who already
has a husband. It is true that in a difficult land, such as the Arctic,
one would expect the co-operative interdependence of a family group to
have greater significance than it might under less severe conditions.
Thus the economic importance of the womanâs role elevates her status in
such a society. On the other hand, among hunters and gatherers elsewhere
women are known to provide over 50% of the food supply in their
gathering activities, in addition to filling other crucial economic
roles in society. Yet these women do not have the freedom or equality of
their Inuit counterparts. The Australian Aboriginals are a case in
point. Inuit may well award women more equality and freedom in part
because of their important economic role, but, in fact, the position of
these women derives mostly from an emphasis upon self-reliance which is
instilled in every Inuit. A self-reliant person must be given a greater
degree of freedom. This emphasis also, I think, helps explain why
children in Inuit society are treated as distinct persons with specific
inalienable rights. In contrast, many other peoples see children at best
as mere extensions of the person of their father. Again, in the
environment of the Inuit, co-operative activity is crucial, but
self-reliance, learning to get along on your own, is mandatory if one is
to survive.
In the arid zones of southern Africa there are peoples collectively
referred to as Bushmen or by their close relatives, the Hottentots, as
. Most of them have long since abandoned a hunting-gathering way of life
to become employed as servants by neighboring Negroid groups or European
farmers. A small handful, numbering in the hundreds, have at least up
until a scant few years ago persisted in the old traditions in the
refuge of to desert areas of Botswana and Namibia.
The San are organized into bands or camps which are loosely structured
groups composed primarily of related individuals (often patrilineally
related to a common male ancestor) and dwelling in a territory
identified with the band.
San have no formal leaders, neither headmen nor chiefs, but bands do
have leaders or persons of influence. These are invariably âownersâ of
the lands which surround a water hole and represent the band territory
or the area which provides its general needs. âOwnersâ comprise the core
of related persons, usually siblings or cousins, in the band who have
lived around its water hole longer than anyone else and are therefore
recognized as collective owners, as âhostsâ of the territory to whom
anyone from outside the group is expected to request permission on
visiting the area. This kind of ownership passes from one generation to
the next as long as any descendents remain within it.
One who is not an âownerâ may seek to achieve leadership status by
marrying a woman in another band who is an owner. Yet ownership alone is
insufficient to place one in the forefront. Other attributes of
leadership include being the older within a large family with many
children and grandchildren. Moreover one should possess several personal
qualities. Thus, one who is a powerful speaker is respected. It helps
also to be recognized as a mood mediator. Under no circumstances should
a leader be âarrogant, overbearing, boastful, or aloof.â (Lee, 345). Lee
notes that these characteristics of the leader are also stressed among
Australian aboriginals.
Camp leaders are preeminent in decision making, mediation and food
distribution. Yet one !Kung San in response to a question as to whether
his group had headmen replied: âOf course we have headmen! In fact we
are all headmen ... each one of us is headman over himselfâ (Lee, 348).
Another more recent kind of leader has arisen among âBushmen as a
consequence of contact with neighboring Blacks, peoples who have a more
hierarchical social system. Such leaders are brokers or liaison agents
with the outside non-San peoples and have their position because of
their ability to deal with foreigners and carry on entrepreneurial
affairs. Such individuals are rarely camp or community leaders.
There are also medicine men whose sole role is the curing of illness,
receiving no special privilege because of this position. The San lack
sorcerers and witches. Throughout the society men are dominant, a factor
Marshall attributes partly to their superior physical strength, but also
to their prestige role as hunters and thus as those who provide the meat
for the community (despite the fact that plants collected by women
supply the bulk of the food). Lee, however, has noted that some women
become recognized camp leaders.
San fear fighting and desire to avoid all hostility. At the same time
fights do arise and sometimes lead to killing. Most conflicts are in the
nature of verbal abuse and argument relating to food and gift
distribution or accusations of laziness and stinginess. When actual
physical combat is provoked those around the combatants, most often
close kin or supporters of one of the protagonists, immediately seek to
separate the participants and to pacify them. Extended discussion may
ensue but the antagonists remain silent. âThe trance dance that
sometimes follows a fight may serve as a peace-making mechanism when
trance performers give ritual healing to persons on both sides of the
argumentâ (Lee, 377). It is considered particularly important to
intervene in a fight involving men between ages 20 and 50 since they
have a monopoly on the poisoned arrows. Thus were they to lose all self
control and physical combat among these people is likened to a state of
temporary insanity â someone would surely die.
Although San do not engage in ritual murder or sacrifice they sometimes
âCarry out revenge killings. Yet even these may be avoided. for fear of
escalating the violence. On some occasions killers have been âexecutedâ
through the mutual agreement of a group of men. According to Lee a
goodly number of those who are killed in fights are non-combatants,
being usually persons who seek to intervene to stop a fight or
occasionally a by-stander. Any severe conflict is usually resolved by
the group splitting up.
According to Lee a camp persists as long as food is shared amongst its
members, but once this is discontinued the group ceases to exist. There
are specific rules concerning the distribution of wild gaÎźie. The bulk
of any kill must be distributed initially by its âownerâ, the man who
owns the arrow which first entered the animal. So a hunter who shoots an
arrow loaned to him by another is merely shooting for that person. Meat
is first distributed amongst a small group, including the hunters and
the owner of the arrow. This group in turn distributes portions to a
wider circle of individuals and they to still a larger group.
Consequently, members of the sharing group are involved in a reciprocity
system which obligates those who receive to return gifts of meat in
future distributions.
Because groups are small, nearly all social relations are actually
guided in terms of kinship concepts. There is no organisation or
integration of San beyond the band level. One retains band membership
throughout life, along with the associated rights to its resources. Yet
members do leave their home band and join others. They may still return
at a future date.
Children are treated permissively by parents. Marshall affirms the
latter are especially fond of younger children and gentle in their
treatment of them. â!Kung children are never harshly punished. One
father said that if he had a boy who was quarrelsome or who disobeyed
the rules â for instance, the absolute rule of the !Kung against
stealing food or possessions â what he would do about it would be to
keep the boy right with him until he learned sense. The children on
their part do not often do things that call for punishment. They usually
fall in with group life and do what is expected of them without apparent
uncertainty, frustration, or fear; and expressions of resistance or
hostility towards their parents, the group, or each other are very much
the exceptionâ (Marshall, 264).
The traditional
hunters dwell in the rain forests of the interior of Zaire living in
small nomadic bands. There is neither formalised leadership nor are
there formal group councils, although outstanding men and women are
recognised in each band. No-one, however, wishes to take it upon himself
to make judgments or impose punishments on others. Rather, the
maintainance of order is a co-operative affair, or something left up to
superntural forces. â ... Pygmies dislike and avoid personal authorityâ,
says Turnbull, âthough they are by no means devoid of a sense of
responsibility: It is rather that they think of responsibility as
communalâ (1962, 125). The Pygmies told Turnbull they had no leaders,
lawmakers or government âbecause we are the people of the forestâ; the
forest âis the chief, the lawgiver, the leader, the final arbitratorâ
(1962, 126).
When a theft has occurred there is a detailed discussion of the case by
an assembly of the whole encampment. When consensus has been reached as
to the guilty party, all those who feel so inclined collectively
administer a sound thrashing to the offender. The most outrageous
offences, it is believed, are so terrible that they result in
supernatural punishment. Minor disputes and alleged offences are often
left to the litigants who either settle them through argument or a mild
fight. Such encounters may, however, escalate and soon the whole band
may be involved in arguing the case. Turnbull writes that if you lose
patience with your wifeâs nagging, you call on your friends to assist
you in trying to put her in her place. Your wife will do the same, so
that the entire camp is drawn into the argument. âAt this point someone
â very often an older person with too many relatives and friends to be
accused of being partisan â steps in with the familiar remark that
everyone is making too much noise, or else diverts the issue onto a
totally different track so that people forget the origin of the argument
and give it upâ (1962, 124).
Other techniques of diffuse sanctions employed commonly by Pygmies
include the use of ostracism and ridicule. In most bands there is a
young bachelor with some repute as a hunter. He assumes the role of the
clown and lampoons the disputants in a conflict. The process of
decision-making in everyday community affairs is similar to the
technique for dealing with disputes. Affairs are dealt with in a casual
and informal way and without the appearance of individual leadership. In
deciding on a hunt, each adult male is involved in discussion until
agreement is reached. Women, too, participate by offering their
opinions.
Pygmy society is strongly communal in its orientation and the emphasis
on co-operative action is such that when compared to the Inuit these
Arctic dwellers seem very individualistic indeed. Pygmies probably
approach the anarchist ideal more closely than most other groups. While
others have the form of anarchy, Pygmies appear to have captured some of
the spirit as well.
There is an attempt to avoid leadership by one or a few, to arrive at
decisions by full communal participation and consensus. Pygmies, like
the Inuit, minimise discrimination based upon sex and age differences.
, like that of other hunters, is organised on a band basis. Several
families traditionally hunted and camped together and claimed a
territory for economic exploitation and as a ritual and totemic centre.
These families were related and for the most part through the male line,
usually to a common paternal grandfather or great grandfather.
Australians have often been described as the most primitive people in
the world â or as having the simplest culture. But such descriptions
contribute more to confusion and misunderstanding of Australian cultures
than they do to clarification. It is true that few people known to
modern society have possessed a more rudimentary and limited technology.
An Australian could readily .. carry all his earthly possessions under
his arm. Spears and throwing sticks were his most elaborate form of
projectile; he did not know the use or manufacture of the bow and arrow.
In technology Australians did not elaborate on a wide range of different
types of tools, rather they concentrated on the development of a great
many styles within a few kinds of tools. Thus, one finds a wide variety
of throwing sticks or of spears.
Similarly Australians did not experiment with many different social
structures; their social organisation was based on the single principle
of kinship. Yet, they managed to invent a variety of kinship structures.
Indeed, they played upon a single theme â that of dual division- in such
a way as to create several complex kinship patterns. The most elementary
form of dual division is to cut a society into two groups (moieties)
which engage in mutual exchange, including the exchange of women, so
that wives are derived from the opposite group. Australians elaborated
this dual principle so as to create four and eight âsectionâ systems
which determined incest rules and the persons whom one might marry. To
the outsider, such as the introductory anthropology student, these
systems become extremely complex conundrums. Australian mythology and
ceremony and their attendant art forms are similarly by no means simple
or crude. On the contrary, they must be recognised as rich and highly
developed. In sum, Australians seem to have taken a minimum number of
simple principles and woven them into a complex web of variant Patterns.
Further, they seem to have been highly concerned with the realms of
kinship, mythology and ceremonial and uninterested in technology. In
contrast, western society has been interested primarily in the latter
while innovation- in kinship and ceremonial verges on being tabooed.
Thus arises the misleading notion that Australians are âprimitiveâ (in a
pejorative sense), crude and simple.
Australian political organisation requires no complexity and it has
none. Their political system has been called a âgerontocracyâ â by which
is meant a rule by old men. More.correctly, for Australia it means that
older men are the most influential and their opinions are accepted
because of the prestige of their elderly positions. Further, oneâs
elders are oneâs grandfathers, so there is the moral force of kinship
behind their words. One accepts the decision of the elder males also out
of fear of public opinion, believing all others in the band would
disapprove of any dissent. Further, older men are considered to have a
certain sanctity, since it is they who are the repositories of all the
sacred wisdom of the group. Among the Murngin, for example, each clan
has ceremonial leaders who know all the rituals of that clan. The
position is inherited from father to son. By control of the ceremonial
system these leaders also control who may be initiated into which
ceremonies and at which time. This is extremely crucial to the Murngin
male, who, in order to be a fully fledged member of society, must in the
course of his life pass through several rites of passage from one age
group to another. These rites reveal knowledge which is held to be
necessary to group survival. Life is a process of being initiated into
various ceremonies and, thus, secrets of life, and its climax is the
ultimate initiation into âthe final mysteries of life by seeing the most
esoteric of the totemsâ (Warner, 132). The main force available to the
elders, then, appears to be a supernatural sanction: the threat of
withholding admission to certain knowledge deemed essential to success
in life. Additionally, elders may turn public opinion against a person.
Within a band the elders are the ones concerned with dealing with
strangers and the ones responsible for organising blood feuds or
instigating others to impose a punishment on malefactors. Elders,
however, have no power as a police force to enforce law. They can only
encourage physically stronger men in the community to try to impose a
punishment on an alleged culprit.
Supernatural sanctions form an important part of the Australianâs
techniques to maintain order. Bone pointing is well known and one does
not have to be a particular specialist in order to use it. In this
technique a magic bone is pointed in the direction of oneâs enemy, who
is, of course, informed that this has been done. Consequently the victim
is supposed to become ill and die. As Cannon long ago pointed out, this
âtechnique does achieve results. Victims appear to die because they
simply resign themselves to death. Like the Inuit the Australians have
part-time religious specialists or shamans. These undergo special
initiations, often under the direction of a group of shamans who
constitute a kind of rudimen1ary guild of craft specialists. Shamans
have the power to counteract the magic of an enemy. They can also
destroy another man. This they are a major force for mobilising and
influencing public opinion and, according to Warner, they are as
effective in this respect as ceremonial leaders (242).
Australian society represents a political system with somewhat more
structure and formality than characterised the Inuit and Pygmy. Indeed,
gerontocratic features are more common to African horticulturalists.
Australians, nevertheless, function according to diffuse and religious
sanctions. The control by the older men of access to those ceremonial
initiations deemed essential for attaining full male status, approaches
a rudimentary government. Yet since Australian groups are communities of
kinsmen and these elders are kinsmen, addressed and treated as such,
their position is more clearly that of grandfather than that of governor
or policeman. In addition, elders in no way have any monopoly on the
uses of violence to impose their commands an and this, of course, is the
keystone of a governmental structure.
One could continue with a catalogue of most hunting-gathering societies
as soeieties without government. For the most part they follow the
pattern characteristic of the foregoing peoples: leadership is informal
and largely achieved; it may be invested in technicians such as the good
hunter among the Inuit or Northern Athabaskan Indians, or in the shaman,
or, as in Australia, ascribed to the older men of the community; rules
are enforced through diffuse and religious sanctions and egalitarianism,
at least within a given age-sex group, prevails.
Some hunters and gatherers have the rudiments of governmental forms,
such as the warrior societies among Plains Indians. Others are ârankedâ
societies, which nevertheless have the characteristics of functioning
anarchies. The Indians of central and northern California had a very
simple rank system, while those of the Northwest Coast had a complex
one.
Of the Californians let us briefly consider the
. They were fishermen and seed (acorn) gatherers as well as hunters. The
Yurok constitute small rather permanent communities composed of
patrilineally related families centred around a senior male â âthe rich
manâ. The ârich manâ office is essentially the senior rank in the
community. Its holder is overseer of the groupâs wealth. He directs
activities at salmon weirs and on acorn grounds and could draw upon the
wealth of the community to pay bride wealth or blood money. He maintains
his position through his âinfluenceâ and displays characteristics deemed
proper for a Yurok man of prestige, particularly through demonstrations
of his great generosity and, hence, wealth. Any decisions he might make
could only be enforced by withholding his generosity or threatening to
do so. Obviously, he could do greater favours for those whom he saw as
the most obedient and loyal.
The Yurok possess an elaborate set of regulations concerning offences,
but the technique employed to enforce these rules is not one of law
enforcement, but rather one of mediation. Disputants in a case choose
âgo betweensâ or âcrossesâ who cross back and forth between the
conflicting sides carrying offers and counter offers until an agreement
is reached. The go-betweens are expected to be completely impartial and
to bring forth an agreement which is fair to both sides. They gather the
evidence and make a judgment about damages on the basis of a scale which
forms part of Yurok traditional regulations. Individuals judged as
offenders by the go-betweens are expected to pay fines in accord with
these regulations. Thus a manâs life is valued as equal to the bride
wealth paid for his mother.
Hoebel considers that these circumstances constitute a court of law (196
1 , 25). However, Kroeber clearly indicates that the opposing parties
involved have to agree to the decision of the crosses (1953). They are
therefore not judges with the power to compel obedience by force. They
are negotiators with the moral backing of society. This is a kind of
non-governmental system of dispute settlement which one finds widely
dispersed throughout the world and one which we will encounter again in
the descriptions to follow. That it is so common and widespread may
indicate that it has proven a most successful mechanism for maintaining
peace. It should be noted that the main aim of this form of justice is
not to assess guilt and gloat over rights and wrongs, but rather it is
to re-establish communal peace and group harmony.
Yurok depend upon other important devices such as gossip and sometimes
ârash youthsâ attempt to form a kind of vigilante committee to settle
disputes, thus transforming a minor issue into a major conflict and
possibly a blood feud.
In the
, the Indians developed one of the most elaborate cultures known for a
hunting-gathering people. It was based largely upon fishing and whaling.
These people were the great potlatch givers. They developed a complex
ceremonial system of. gift giving and partying by which individuals
sought to outdo and so shame or âflattenâ others by their generosity.
Through potlatching one could earn various named and privileged ranks.
Thus society was divided into three groups: those who held one or more
ranks; freemen who held no rank but who were kinsmen of those who did
and were expected to assist in amassing wealth for potlach party
engagements; and, finally, at the bottom there were slaves. These were
persons captured in warfare or others given to pay damages for an
offence. This ranking system should not be confused with a class system.
Ranking involves differential status of individuals; class involves
differential status of groups. Thus among the Northwest Coast Indians a
man might acquire many titles and be of highest rank. Yet other members
of his family might well not have this status at all. An eldest son
would inherit ânobilityâ from his father, while the youngest son was
little more than a commoner. There are differences in wealth and sharp
competitions for prestige and for the limited number of ranked
positions. Yet the competition involved has sometimes been misunderstood
as some flagrant, individualistic form which would be dear to the heart
of the laissez faire capitalist. Actually, that which existed between
rank holders vying for yet more exalted positions depended upon wealth
which was provided by the co-operative group activity of the kinsmen of
the rank holder. If competition existed at all levels of the system¡ it
would have . been totally unworkable. This is something few of those who
worship at the altar of competition see, namely, that co-operation is
fundamental to all human activity, even to being able to compete.
The man with the highest rank in a village is often referred to as the
âchiefâ. However, as in other instances of this kind, this usage is
misleading. A senior ranked ânobleâ was called a chief because he was
senior and consequently had priyileges which were not shared with
others. Thus among the Nootka the chief or senior ânobleâ of several
local settlements had certain prior rights to the salmon streams and
ocean waters for fish and sea mammals; he owned important root and berry
patches and the salvage materials which landed on the shores of his
territory.
The chief was expected to demonstrate liberality, generosity and
leadership. Yet he had little or no authority to impose his will by
force. He was not a chief in the sense of executive officer with police
powers.
Among the Carrier of the British Columbia interior, when families
quarrelled the âchief called all the people to his house where he
covered âhis head with swanâs down, the time honored symbol of peace,
and dance(d) before them to the chanting of his personal song and the
shaking of his rattleâ. After the dance he delivered an oration on the
wealth he and his clan-phratry had expended to get titles. He exhorted
the disputants to settle their quarrel and warned of the troubles which
would come if it continued (Jenness, 518). This was the limit of his
contribution to settling disputes. The phratry chief among the Carrier
ordered murderers to fast for twenty-five days and he presided at a
ceremony in which the murderer and his clanâs people handed over a blood
price.
Writing of the West Coast Indians in general, Drucker reports that âin
the rare instances when blood was shedâ within a kin group âusually
nothing was doneâ since the group could not take revenge upon itself or
pay itself blood money (1965, 74). Revenge was resorted to when a person
of one kin group murdered one in another. Among most of the Coastal
people (except for the Kwakiutl and Nootka) the alternative to a revenge
attack in the case of intergroup murder was for one person from the
offending group to be asked to âcome forth voluntarily to be slainâ.
Witches accused of practising black magic were often slain and these
killings went unavenged.
Northwest Coast societies seem to represent cases of marginal anarchy,
where the âchiefsâ or ânoblesâ , as men of clear rank and privilege,
held more âlegitimateâ authority than others. Yet the situation was
still sufficiently ambiguous for such chiefs to have no monopoly of
force and most social control mechanisms were clearly of a diffuse or
religious nature.
Inuit data are derived from Birket-Smith, Damas and Spencer (see
Bibliography). San materials are from Lee, Marshall and Thomas. Turnbull
is the source for the Pygmies while Elkin, Sharp, Spencer and Gillin,
and Warner are the main sources for the Australians. The Northwest Coast
description is from Drucker and Jenness while that on the Californians
is from Kroeber. For other American Indian groups see Hallowell for
Ojibwa and Honigmann for Northern Athabascans.
Horticultural societies depend primarily upon gardening activity for
food supply. This differs from agriculture which entails extensive
cultivation. employing animal or mechanical draft power in cultivating
large fields. In horticulture only human labour is used and the digging
stick or hoe is the chief implement rather than the plough.
Horticultural peoples practice slash and burn, or shifting cultivation,
in which an area is burned over and cleared of brush and forest. Then
the field is planted year after year until the unfertilised soil no
longer yields a good crop, at which time the place is abandoned and the
gardeners shift to another one. This means that although
horticulturalists are ordinarily a sedentary people, especially.
compared to. most hunter-gatherers, they are occasionally forced to move
their dwellings and villages in order to be near their gardens.
Horticulturalists usually specialise in a limited number of crops. In
North America there was a corn, beans and squash complex; New Guineans
rely upon a considerable variety of different kinds of yams. Garden
foods are often supplemented by resorting to hunting and gathering
activities, which in some cases provide as much. as the gardens
themselves. Another food source is domesticated animals. New Guineans,
particularly, spend great energy and time in swine husbandry; roast pork
is central to any feast or ceremony. In Sub-Saharan Africa, gardeners
often keep cattle, sheep and goats. Among American Indians, however,
animal husbandry was never of any importance and practically all their
animal protein was derived from wild game.
This kind of subsistence provides a platform for launching a variety of
cultural innovations not found among hunter-gatherers. Some African
horticulturalists were able to develop stratified,class-based societies
with specialised craftsmen and full-time religious specialists, all on
the basis of highly productive gardens cultivated by the use of the iron
hoe. In America, the Aztecs, Mayans and Incas did the same without metal
implements. In both areas there was a relatively heavy density of
population and in West Africa this entailed the development of cities as
well. Enduring, aggressive empire states arose and. fell and true
warfare was common.
For the most part, however, horticultural societies remain with a simple
division of labour according to age and sex. Although some, such as in
Polynesia, evolved formal ranks and chiefs or rulers, probably the
majority are âegalitarianâ . A great many horticultural societies would
fall into Serviceâs âtribalâ type. The tribe is âa body of people of
common derivation and custom, in possession and control of their own
extensive territory. But if in some degree socially articulated, a tribe
is specifically unlike a modern nation in that its several communities
are not united under a sovereign governing authority, nor are the
boundaries of the whole thus clearly and politically determined. The
tribe builds itself up from within, the smaller community segments
joined in groups of higher order, yet just where it becomes greatest the
structure becomes weakest: the tribe as such is the most tenuous of
arrangements, without even a semblance of collective organisation. The
tribe is also uncomplicated in another way. Its economics, its politics,
its religion re not conducted by different institutions specifically
designed for the purpose but coincidentally by the same kinship and
local groups: the lineage and clan segments of the tribe, the households
and villages, which thus appear as versatile organisations in charge of
the entire social lifeâ. This is a decentralised, functionally
generalised, and segmentary society (Sahlins, 1968, viii) . Most of the
horticultural societies having anarchic characteristics are tribal and
egalitarian societies. Yet some are ranked societies, as Fried would
call them, or âchiefdomsâ in Serviceâs language.
Examples of anarchic horticulturalists can readily be drawn from Africa,
Southeast Asia and South America. Sub-Saharan Africa provides numerous
cases of anarchic polities organised along tribal lines as defined
above. Most New Guinea societies are also cases of functioning anarchy,
but here the social organisation, though basically of the chiefdom type,
has certain âtribalâ characteristics as well.
Scattered throughout the continent south of the Sahara are dozens of
anarchic societies, some of which are the most populous of all anarchic
communities. For horticultural people the main¡ concentration is the
Volta River area of West Africa, the plateau of central Nigeria and a
band across mid-Africa just north of . the equator. A few are found in
southern Africa while a major concentration is among pastoral peoples of
East Africa (see Chapter V).
The anarchic horticultural societies of Africa are primarily limited to
the more equatorial zone of the continent â the area of greater
forestation and rainfall. The savannah grasslands to the north have
proven more amenable to the establishment and expansion of empire
states. Here in the open country, free of tsetse fly infestation one can
better keep cavalry and deploy them as devices for domination. Closer to
the equator, savannah gives way to dense forest and eventually to
tropical rain forest, neither of which are suitable for horse keeping
and in both of which it is easier t.o conduct defensive warfare with
bows and arrows â the âdemocraticâ weapon of warfare since anyone can
have one. Thus, anarchic systems have been able to survive until
recently adjacent to predatory states (Goody, 1971) .
African anarchic polities are invariably characterised by the presence
of slavery and sometimes of debased pariah castes. Neither include very
large numbers, nor are they of much importance in the total social
system. Slaves are mostly war captives and pawns and there is little
slave trading. Nevertheless, these institutions along with the normal
inferior position of women and prevalence of patriarchal authority
hardly make such polities oases of freedom, even though they may have no
government or state. Africa affords, in its myriad of anarchic and near
anarchic societies, innumerable cases of transition between anarchy and
archy. Especially important for the rise of the state and decline of
anarchy in many of these societies is the role of secret societies and
of age grading. In West Africa secret societies are important. They may
be voluntary organisations. or ones designed to initiate the entire
adult male population. A major part of their function is to enforce
community rules and punish those believed to be wrong doers. This then
represents, depending on oneâs point of view, a kind of
institutionalised vigilante committee, or a rudimentary police force. In
the case of the Ibo who are discussed below, the age grades assume a
governmental function in an otherwise anarchic polity. Part of the
responsibility of those initiated into the younger grade is to act as
policemen and enforce the rulings of the village courts which are
presided over by members of the middle age grade.
Over a third of a million Lugbara dwell in southern Uganda and northern
Zaire. As horticulturalists they grow chiefly eleusine and sorghum, but
they also keep some cattle. The Lugbara live on open rolling plains in a
highland area of 4â5,000 feet elevation. They, like their neighbours,
are politically decentralised, traditionally having no chiefs and the
fundamental form of social organisation is the segmentary lineage.[7]
The basic social grouping is the family, either some type of joint
family or a nuclear group. Families related through males and dwelling
in a neighbourhood comprise a âfamily clusterâ or minimal lineage of
three to four generations depth. The cluster might also include
individuals who are not members of the lineage group, such as a sisterâs
son or daughterâs husband. It might also have âclientsâ residing within
it. These are persons who escaped from their own homes in times of war
or famine, or who had been expelled for some offence. Except for those
clients who had not married into the cluster, the residents are subject
to the elder of the group, who is its genealogically senior member. His
authority is primarily ritual in that he can invoke the ancestral
ghosts, who have influence only on their descendents.
The lineage owns the territory within which its members reside and the
elder allocates use rights within it as well as the rights to its
resources, including daughters of the lineage. Further, he is in control
of the use of livestock. Within the minimal lineage the elder is
responsible for settling disputes. He may also initiate hostile
relations with other groups.
Related minimal lineages form yet another lineage segment (minor
lineage), which in turn is consolidated into larger segments (major
lineages) and these in turn constitute sub clans which consolidate to
form clans. However, the number of levels of segmentation among the
Lugbara varies. The following diagram of the levels of segmentation
within a Lugbara tribe shows on the right side the various segments as
territorial units, beginning at the lowest level of the family cluster
and culminating in the subtribe. On the left side of the diagram is the
segmentary system in terms of descent groups, commencing with the
smallest segment, the minimal lineage, whose personnel is roughly
equivalent to the territorial unit, the family cluster. (It will be
recalled that some residents of the family cluster are not agnatic
kinsmen.) Correspondingly each higher level of segmentation of the
descent groups has an approximate correspondence to equivalent levels of
territorial groups. Again, the rough correspondence results from the
fact that while . territories are identified with a given descent group,
they may include residents not belonging to that descent group.
[]
[]
The major lineage comprises a most strategic segment within Lugbara
society since it is within this group that marriage and fratricide are
prohibited and kinship terms are used as forms of address. The major
lineage is the feud unit: the body that presumably unites to engage in
hostilities against other equivalent segments and within which feuding
is not supposed to occur, although it does occasionally.
Within the minor lineage only fighting with sticks and fists is
permitted: no bows and arrows or spears can be used since there is no
technique, ritual or otherwise, by which the group can deal with the
fratricide which might result. We have encountered this notion before:
that fratricide, that is, murder carried out within a closely related
group, is so horrendous that the community has no established means to
deal with it. Nevertheless, a Lugbara killer would marry his victimâs
widows and donate a bull to the victimâs motherâs brother, but still
this does not repair the injury done. A killing between minor segments
of the same lineage is also a heinous deed, but compensation in the form
of cattle is considered payable to re-establish group harmony. A
homicide involving two major lineages entails no compensation, but
rather retaliation may be resorted to. Such fighting can go on between
groups for some time. Eventually, when everyone gets tired of
hostilities, elders from both sides, in addition to elders from related
but uninvolved lineages, gather and negotiate a peace. Should the
parties continue to fight the elders may invoke a collective curse upon
them. In the curse those ancestral ghosts common to the conflicting
parties are asked to bring sickness upon all those who disobey.
Killings within a tribe and between its subclans are compensated for,
but beyond this level there is no compensation and the fighting that
goes on between tribes continues until third parties are able to
intervene successfully, or until the matter is forgotten.
As is usual in other systems of this sort, the most intense feelings of
identification, and the most active functioning in terms of mutual
interrelationship, is at the minimal level. This gradually decreases as
one ascends to encompass larger and larger groups and numbers of people,
until one can say that the tribal level has little or no significance.
Nevertheless, all Lugbara have the belief that they are all kin. They
express their own social relations by speaking of groups which are juru,
wherein potentially hostile relations obtain, and those which are
oâdipi, which include all those within a groupâs direct social relations
which are not juru. Ordinarily oâdipi refers to the agnatic descendants
of a common ancestor, often a manâs major lineage. Thus, as with the
latter, among oâdipi there is supposed to be no fighting, no
intermarriage and any girl is called âsisterâ. At any given time a group
may be regarded as juru and later it may become oâdipi.
The chief form of sanction in Lugbara society is religious. Ancestral
ghosts may themselves directly impose their vengeance through sickness.
Otherwise the elder may invoke the power of the ghosts against
individuals, including his own dependants within the family cluster. The
power of the ghost invocation by an elder extends as far as there are
common ghosts. Non-agnatic kin may curse one another for breaches of
kinship ties. Witchcraft accusations are directed against neighbours.
Within the community of kin and neighbours, order is maintained through
these several supernatural sanctions, all of which form a single
mystical system. The rainmaker is a powerful figure in Lugbara society,
as he is in many neighbouring groups. Among the northern Lugbara, where
he is the senior member of the senior line of the senior major lineage
of a subclan, he is able to bring an end to hostilities by calling
people together to prohibit fighting on pain of his cursing those who do
not obey. In some areas wrongdoers may find a sanctuary in-his person.
Other important men in Lugbara society are âmen whose names are knownâ.
These are invariably wealthy men, but they also have admirable character
and thus attract a following. Their influence may spread over several
tribes and their status is neither attached to the lineage system nor is
it hereditary. They carry white staves as symbols of their position.
Like the rainmakers they can curse combatants in a feud and may act as a
sanctuary for a refugee and as a mediator in quarrels. For a short
period, first in 1895 and again in 1910 âprophetsâ appeared among the
Lugbara and had some influence.
The Lugbara have unmistakable anarchic characteristics. Yet there exist
certain specific kinds of persons â rainmakers and âmen whose names are
knownâ â who have a superior cursing power which sets them off as
privileged individuals. Here we have the beginning of a
proto-governmental structure.
The
number about 50,000 people and reside in northern Togo where they are
chiefly grain farmers raising sorghum, millet and yams. They have a
typically African segmentary lineage system based on patrilineal descent
(cf, Lugbara example). Konkombaland is divided into several tribes each
of which in turn segment into several clans. Each clan rarely has more
than 250 members and is the basic unit occupying, and being identified
with, a specific territory that is its own. Clans divide into two or
more lineages. The oldest man in, a lineage is its head, while the clan
head is the senior of all the several lineage heads. Mutual assistance
in work occurs within the clan and more commonly among members of the
lineage segment of the clan. The clan is also a church or a parish of
the prevailing fertility religion, the members of which are responsible
for major rituals associated with sowing and offerings to the sacred
land. Not only is the clan defined by economic, religious and kinship
functions, but it is the primary mechanism of social control. Within the
clan, disputes are to be settled by mediation and no violence is
tolerated. Disputes with individuals outside the clan require no
obligatory arbitration and one may resort to force or threat of
retaliation. Within the clan the elder demands observance of the rules,
but he has no power to enforce his decisions. The power he has is of a
ritual and moral nature rather than judicial. As the chief and oldest
kinsman his fellow clansmen owe him a moral obligation which is
reinforced by the fact that as the eldest he is nearest the sacred
ancestors. In addition he is guardian of the land. Within the clan,
infractions are dealt with by ostracising a culprit, or by assessment of
fines. For the latter there is no means to compel payment, aside from
the expression of disapproval by fellow clansmen and the feeling of a
moral-ritual obligation to conform. We must appreciate, however, that in
a small closely-knit community, in which everyone âbelievesâ and where
there are no cynics or atheists, such sanctions are extremely powerful.
As was noted with the Pygmies, the most horrendous crimes are not
punished by men at all, so with the Konkomba, if a man kills a fellow
clansman he would himself die. âGodâ, say the Konkomba, âwill not suffer
to live one who has killed his brother and there is no ritual or
medicinal protection for the fratricideâ (Tait, 1950, 275). Tait,
however, believes that murder of fellow clansmen does not actually
occur.
Aside from the elders within a clan, another man of influence is the
diviner, who may build up a reputation which extends over a wide area.
Ordinarily the relationship between clans is one of relative hostility,
but those which are neighbours and others which may co-operate in ritual
affairs have harmonious relations . Such groups do not feud, especially
those with close ritual ties. Clans which have, or claim to have, a near
kinship relation are also not supposed to indulge in feuds.
Nevertheless, Tait reports two closely-related clans whose feuding with
one another was so notorious that it was widely remembered among
Konkomba 30 years later.
Clans within the same tribe which engage in feud may formally end
hostilities by negotiation and ritual burial of the arrows of war. But
feuds between clans of different tribes are âendlessâ and there appear
to be no formal means to bring peace. Apparently, those involved might
eventually get tired of fighting.
The tribe among the Konkomba is an amorphous entity. It has a name and
is associated with a territory in that it is the sum of the lands
âownedâ by its several clan components. Face marks usually indicate a
personâs tribe. But tribes have no elders, ritual leaders or chiefs. In
inter-tribal fighting, clans of the same tribe come to the aid of their
brethren.
Konkomba, in sum, exemplify a highly decentralised polity organised
along typical segmentary lines. They represent about as clear cut a case
of anarchy as one can find among African horticulturalists.
The
are somewhat similar to the Konkomba, but more structured in their
social order. Over a million live in central Nigeria on a rolling plain
extending to the banks of the Benue river. Population density is well
over a hundred people per square mile. Like the Konkomba, Tiv are also
subsistence farmers engaged in grain and yam cultivation. They have few
cattle due to the problem of tsetse flies. Their settlements are
composed of rather dispersed compounds, each consisting of a ring of
huts and connected to other compounds by paths. The segmentary
patrilineal system is the fundamental principle of social organisation.
Every Tiv identifies himself with a tar, a term like âcountryâ, which
refers to a given place associated with a patrilineage. Most men reside
in their own home tar, but most tars have individuals dwelling in them
from others. âIn time of war, Tiv say, a man must return to his tar in
order to assist his ityo (patrilineage)â (Bohannan, L, 41).
The ityo is split into further segments. The ultimate unit is the
compound of a family â usually an extended family. Within it the senior
male, who is normally also an older man, is responsible for the members
and their actions. One who is seen as a continual trouble-maker may be
expelled from the compound by the elder. The elder devotes himself to
the daily problems of keeping peace and settling quarrels. He must
possess the necessary knowledge for peace keeping and, therefore, should
know the jural customs, the genealogy and history of his kinsmen, the
health and fertility magic, and be in âpossession of the witchcraft
substance, tsav. Legitimate power depends on possession of a mystical
quality which ensures peace and fertility.
Bohannan lists four relationships in which there is âdefinite authorityâ
among the Tiv. Three of these are kinship roles: the position of the
senior member of the compound mentioned above, the father-son
relationship and that of husband and wife. A fourth relationship
involving the role of police and judges in the market-place is discussed
below.
In addition, there are also men of prestige or influence among the Tiv.
These are often elders, but they could be others as well. They possess
wealth and demonstrate generosity and astuteness. They were once able to
purchase slaves and build up gangs which were used to sell safe conduct
to strangers and to rob others. Such individuals were difficult to
control. Witchcraft and magic in the hands of the elders were the only
effective means of restraining those who were not elders. However, men
of prestige who were also elders controlled these supernatural powers
too, thus nullifying such attempts to curb them. Therefore travellers
seem to have been faced continually with a protection racket.
Elders within a lineage could be called together in assembly to deal
with various problems such as occur in connection with witchcraft,[8]
magic and curses. These include deaths, sickness, dreams, barrenness,
and âbad luckâ. The meeting discusses the matter but has no means to
enforce settlements. Good âjudgesâ are those who get the litigants to
concur in a solution which accords with Tiv custom. An elder can only
suggest settlement and must work to bring all parties to an agreeable
resolution. He is a mediator, not a judge. Witchcraft accusation is very
common among the Tiv and it is seen as a cause for innumerable different
kinds of events. The elders are invariably reluctant to call a moot to
discuss accusations against a man of prestige. In such cases, then,
members of a victimâs age set, and afterwards members of his own
lineage, approach the elders and request an inquest.
For other problems there is no moot or inquest. Rather, the persons
involved seek out an elder and ask him to mediate. If a thief has been
caught, the victims may go directly to the thiefâs compound head and
demand compensation. In cases of negligence the victim may go directly
to the culprit.
The lineage group is not the only source of protection for the
individual. Tiv are divided among age sets. Every young man is initiated
into a given set and throughout his life he passes or graduates along
with his set mates through several grades, each of which is associated
with certain communal responsibilities. The age set acts as a peer group
mutual aid association, cutting across lineage lines and consolidating
individuals from different lineages, but of similar age. Thus a man asks
his age set for protection against witches and witchcraft accusations.
He may seek assistance for land clearing and other farm work or in
financial matters. If oneâs lineage for any reason withdraws its
supernatural protection, a man has his age set as protector. Age sets
may assemble to inquire into the health of one of their members.
Among the Tiv the age set system is nowhere near as elaborately
developed as among many other African peoples; in fact with the Tiv it
is a rather amorphous form of organisation. It appears to be most
important to the young adult males as a device for mutual aid and
protection. Young men have reason to be wary of the supernatural power
and especially the malevolent powers of witchcraft allegedly resting in
the hands of the older men. Thus their solidarity at this stage becomes
crucial. About age 40, as men pass into eldership roles, the age set
function changes to one of protecting the vested interests of eldership
against the jealous and resentful. After age 50 the set members
constitute a sentimental association: they are no longer competitors.
Between lineage segments there is often feuding and between larger
segments fighting can become fierce. But the Tiv also have treaty and
pact-making mechanisms. Lineage segments desirous of being able to
conduct peaceful trade make treaties with other segments aimed at safe
conduct, where otherwise as strangers they would be captured or killed.
These treaties âforbid shedding of blood of contracting . parties and
any act which might lead to it (such as shaving)â (Bohannan, L, 62).
Market pacts secure order in the major local trading centre. This is a
market associated with the tar which owns the land and controls the
market-place. The lineage segment controls the market magic important to
securing peace in the market-place, but it also provides market police
and judges, all for keeping order. Thus we have within this anarchic
polity a circumscribed and restricted area of governmental-style polity.
However it should be emphasised that this police power is restricted to
the market-place and time and is not generalised outside those
boundaries. It suggests that Tiv found traditional techniques of social
control inadequate for handling breaches of peace in the market-place
and so introduced the police. The Konkomba, too, have markets, each of
which is under the control of the clan on whose land the market is
located. They, however, do not invoke police. Rather, the market elder
has ritual control over a market shrine and he may invoke its
supernatural power. Konkomba believe an unconfessed thief would be stung
to death by bees which inhabit the trees around the shrine. On
confessing his guilt, a thief provides the market elder with a guinea
fowl which is sacrificed on the shrine.
The Tiv represent one of the largest and most densely populated of
acephalous societies. As with the Konkomba, the segmentary system is of
fundamental importance to the political order. This suggests that most
of that order is conceived in kinship terms. Yet the Tiv depend upon a
number of ancillary systems for maintaining peace. Age sets are
important devices for protecting the interests of peer groups. There are
treaties and pacts and a rudimentary governmental structure in
connection with markets. Underlying the whole system is the power of
religious sanctions, which is a power diffused especially in the older
members of the community.
Tiv society is one of intergenerational strains: of elders enforcing
their authority and younger men resenting it. But when the younger
graduate to eldership they too are concerned about maintaining and
extending their positions of dominance. As with any age grading system,
the individual may find himself in an inferior position, but also has
the satisfaction of knowing that eventually, with the passage of time,
he too will ultimately graduate to the top of the pile.
The Plateau Tonga are a matrilineal people living in southern Zambia.
They number well over 150,000 with a population density of more than 60
people per square mile. The Tonga keep considerable herds of cattle and
are also shifting cultivators, raising corn, millet and sorghum.
The population dwells in tiny villages, from four to eight comprising a
neighbourhood cluster. Both because of the poor soil and the shifting
cultivation, the location of a village is often changed and there is
also some considerable movement of individuals from one location to
another in order to establish a new residence.
In addition to residential ties, each Tonga is affiliated to a
matrilineal clan, the members of which are scattered throughout the
land. These clans have a highly amorphous character: they are not
corporate groups; living members never meet as a group and they have no
leaders. From the Tonga point of view, however, they are held together
by a mystical bond with the ancestral ghosts. Their function seems to be
limited to regulating marriage one cannot marry within the clan â and
establishing joking relationships with the members of several other
clans. In this way the clan serves as a social control mechanism, since
such a relationship prescribes that an individual does not become mad at
his j oking relative. He engages in an easy-going, light-hearted
association and presumably avoids conflict and open expression of
hostility. The joking relationship, like that of avoidance, is designed
as a technique to promote peace in a relationship which might ordinarily
be seen as prone to conflict.
A Tonga also belongs to a matrilineal group within the clan. This is
also a dispersed population, but more localised than the clan
membership. Thus, a given village will tend to have a high proportion of
members of one kin group. The Tonga system should not be seen as a
matrilineal counterpart of the patrilineal segmentary system we
encountered among the other African peoples. The Tonga are not much
interested in genealogical reckoning. There is no internal segmentation
or differentiation between the children of one woman within the group
and those of another. It is also not at all difficult to become absorbed
into a matrilineal group, although, theoretically, membership is based
on verifiable descent through the female line. The group also has
corporate characteristics. That is, members are jointly responsible for
providing bride wealth for their members and for defending their own in
feuds. At the same time they share bride wealth received for married
daughters and are responsible for taking collective vengeance when one
of their number has been murdered, robbed or injured. Inheritance is
also governed by matrilineal group membership and there are mutual
ritual obligations associated with it as well.
Each Tonga is involved in a complex pattern of relationships and
obligations with those in other kin groups beside his own. Thus, one
becomes an honorary member of oneâs fatherâs matrilineal clan. Every
household is in some . important way a matter of concern not only to the
husbandâs matrilineal group, but also to the matrilineal groups of his
wife, his father and his wifeâs father.
We have also said that each Clan is exogamous, but there are other
marital regulations which have the effect of requiring that marriages be
contracted with a wide variety of different groups, thus cementing
alliances with a maximum number.
The neighbourhood in which one lives places on one still further
obligations with yet other, unrelated people. Neighbourhoods control
land use and exploitation of hunting, fishing and other resources. They
obligate residents to a system of mutual aid in a wide variety of
activities. Each neighbourhood has its own shrine and constitutes a
local âchurchâ. In connection with this church the entire neighbourhood
becomes a congregation for mourning the death of fellow residents,
praying for rain and good crops, purifying the land after homicides and
celebrating harvests.
Aside from residential and kin ties, the Tonga have an amorphous age
grouping system which serves to strengthen intragenerational ties within
a neighbourhood. A man may also loan some of his cattle out to others.
This establishes new social ties; it also helps minimise the number of
stock he might lose from an epidemic or raid. Finally, there are
brotherhood pacts which guarantee peaceful movement, especially for
trading activity between and among different contracting neighbourhoods.
Villages and neighbourhoods both have headmen and the neighbourhood
headman is also priest of the local shrine. Of less significance are
leaders of the matrilineal groups. Finally, there are various religious
specialists including diviners and those through whom the spirits of the
rain speak. A man can compound his importance by acquiring several of
these positions. Nevertheless, Tonga leaders are always of local
importance; there are no leaders or chiefs for all the Tonga.
Positions of prestige and influence are acquired through proving oneâs
reputation as a worthy man. Leadership positions are precarious in the
sense that leaders can readily be abandoned by their followers. Headmen
act as advisors, mediators and coordinators. They might intervene in a
dispute, but, like the other mediators we have encountered, they have no
authority to enforce their views. At best they might resort to
supernatural invocations. Feuds are carried on between clans and between
different cult neighbourhoods. They can be brought to an end through
agreement to pay damages. The Tonga never act together as a single
consolidated unit. No means exist for such a mobilisation. Tonga are
apparently not eager to provoke hostilities. They, like other anarchic
peoples, âstress the importance of personal restraint in the interests
of avoiding any possibility of raising hacklesâ. Colson states that
Tonga âattempt to sidestep issues, are reluctant to allow their fellows
to drag them into a dispute, and try to vanish from the scene if those
in their vicinity seem intent on pursuing a quarrel. Or close
supporters, who inevitably will be identified with the combatants
attempt to restrain them, taking from their hands any weapons or tools
which can be used for injury, applying gentle pressure, and murmuring
soothing words about the advisability of cooling the combat for the
moment. They do not want to take sidesâ or draw the wrath of a vengeful
person (1974, 39).
The central mechanism of social control in Tonga society is the fact
that any given individual is a member of a number of different groups,
which in turn are part of a network of further obligations so that any
negative action against an individual or group resulting from one set of
relationships has its counter restraining effect resulting from
affiliation with other groups and individuals. Let us recall that
everyone has close ties with his own matrilineal group, that of his
father, his motherâs father and his fatherâs father. This then
establishes a connection with up to four clans. These clan relations are
extended through joking relationships and marriage alliances. Further,
one belongs to a neighbourhood which draws in still others who are not
otherwise part of oneâs social network. Additionally, one establishes
links through cattle loans and brotherhood pacts. By one connection or
another a person would ordinarily find that effective restraining
measures are built up to cover all the important social relations one
might have. The fine mesh of counterbalancing obligations serves to
integrate and give order to Tonga society which on the surface at least
appears as a society without form. Through such means the Tonga turned
âchiefsâ, as well as centralised authority and integration, into
redundancies.
It is a common misconception that matrilineal societies make women equal
to men. But matriliny is not matriarchy. Reckoning descent through
females is not rule by females. Of the latter there is no record and for
matrilineal societies, such as the Tonga, we find still that men are
dominant and have rights and privileges denied the women. It is of
course true that in matrilineal societies women often have more leverage
than otherwise, since property and status are inherited through
affiliation with females. Matriliny, it is sometimes observed, provides
a far more unstable kind of social organisation than does patriliny,
because inherent in the former is a conflict between inheritance through
females, on the one hand, and control of the social order by males, on
the other. This conflict often leads to strong pressures towards
patriliny, as is testified by African examples, including the Tonga. For
the Tonga have deviated from the âpristineâ matrilineal type in
practising virilocal residence[9] and in ascribing no little influence
to the fatherâs kin group.
If the Tiv and Lugbara award certain powers to a man without making him
a king, the Anuak of the southern Sudan perhaps institute the status of
king with its symbolic trappings but stripped of its powers. These
horticultural people live in villages each of which has a headman who
holds a âcourtâ and keeps sacred emblems of the village such as drums
and beads. He is approached by others with signs of respect such as
obeisance and the use of a special vocabulary. Although his house is no
better than anyone elseâs, the fence posts are decorated with the skulls
of animals killed to provide for the feasts he offers his people. While
he has the trappings of kingship, the headman has in fact little power
and is largely at the mercy of fellow villagers. As long as he can
provide feasts he has good standing and his villagers will see to it
that everyone shows the proper respect to the headman in his âcourtâ. He
is, with the help of other third parties, able to persuade both the
killer of a fellow villager to make compensation and the victimâs kin to
accept it.
Anuak, however, do not believe a man should hold the headship for very
long and, definitely, one who can no longer properly feast his followers
deserves no support. He will then find his followers deserting him. A
major faction opposing the headman and no longer respecting him will
arise and install a rival who must be the son of some previous headman.
Such an event leads to fighting in which the old headman may be deposed.
Despite the quarrelling and intrigue which surrounds the headman office,
it does operate as a unifying force in village affairs, which are
otherwise defined by a segmentary lineage form of organisation similar
to that already discussed. Although different factions may appear in a
village, they are not revolutionary ones: no one seeks to abolish the
position of headman.
In south-eastern Anuak headmen are drawn only from a ânobleâ clan, which
apparently comes from outside the Anuak country. Necklaces, spears,
stools and drums are emblems of the office and there is much struggle,
intrigue and fighting to obtain possession of them. The holder has, as
elsewhere in Anuakland, little authority in his own village, but if he
can mobilise an armed force he could sometimes extend his influence and
even gain a usually tenuous control over neighbouring villages.
Thus, among the Anuak, we see the beginnings of a centralisation of
authority, based initially upon a ceremonial and symbolic role and
expanding in the south-east into a recognisable predatory form of
organisation.
Another example of rudimentary governmental structure is the Ibo, the
second largest ethnic group in southern Nigeria. They presently number
some seven million and have traditionally been village-dwelling
horticulturalists. Some Ibo, however, have been town dwellers. Marketing
and trading are major activities of these people, who are noted for
their aggressive business-like activities and their individualism.
Throughout lboland there are at least two different kinds of polity.
Thus, some Ibo towns have âkingsâ and a governmental structure which is
intrusive and not typically Ibo. Over most of lboland the traditional
highly decentralised and acephalous political system has prevailed.
Much of Ibo social life is dependent upon participation within a
segmentary lineage structure, the fundamental unit of which is the
compound under the supervision of its senior male. Related and
neighbouring lineage segments and compounds comprise a village which is
ordinarily the maximal unit of social integration and control. Within
the village complaints and legal proceedings are undertaken by compound
heads, or by groups of mediating third parties each of whom may be
called upon to settle a dispute. But such mediators âhave no power to
impose their decisions. Thus, if one is not satisfied by this procedure,
one appeals to other institutions. The elders within each village, who
form a specific age grade, comprise a deliberative, legislative,
judicial and executive body to whom an injured party may appeal. The
elders do not act unless they are called upon to do so. They function as
a court, deciding guilt or innocence and assessing fines and
punishments. Punishments are meted out by the young members of the age
grade association. That is, like the Tiv, Ibo have age grades with
responsibilities associated with each grade. The members of the younger
grade are, among other things, responsible for bringing witnesses and
culprits to the village court and for executing punishments decided by
the court. Someone found guilty of stealing, for example, may be tied up
for days on end without food, or, if he is caught red-handed, he is
carried around the village along with what he has stolen and those on
the streets curse him, spit on him and ridicule him. There is no power
of capital punishment, but a murderer is expected to hang himself if
caught.
Aside from this governmental technique, Ibo society has other methods of
imposing sanctions. There are associations of titled men which exert
considerable influence. These organisations offer various titles which a
man may purchase and so acquire prestige. Religious sanctions are
imposed by dibia associations which are for religious specialists. There
are associations for herbalists, for diviners or medicine men; each
requires a considerable initiation fee and leads to a memberâs
ordination as a âpriestâ within the association. Most important among
such individuals are the oracles through whom the gods speak, making
predictions, answering questions and, thus, operating as a major force
in directing peopleâs behaviour.
Ibo society, to use Bohannanâs term, has a multicentric power system:
there are several distinct loci of power. Clearly it has a government,
but this government is sovereign only over a small population and area
and even within it is a diffuse and decentralised arrangement. In
addition Ibo society is a stratified society. At the bottom there are
slaves, individuals who were captured in warfare and a slightly higher
status of cult slaves who are persons who have been dedicated to a
deity. Above the slaves are âpawnsâ, usually young girls, who are pawned
to pay for debts. The vast majority of Ibo are freemen, but they are
divided between commoners and members of elite groups. Among the latter
are senior males of the minor lineages who are empowered to carry wooden
club-like objects which are symbols of authority. Others in the upper
echelons are the members of the title societies and the various dibia
societies. Thus, these upper levels of the Ibo world comprise both those
who have achieved an elite status by their wealth (title societies) and
their learning ( dibia societies) and those to whom high status has been
ascribed as senior lineage males.
Traditional New Guinea is a Tower of Babel of hundreds of different
language groups and of thousands of culturally distinct, autonomous
villages perched on tropical mountain sides or hidden in secluded
valleys. The people raise a variety of tubers and roots and keep pigs.
Much energy is devoted to ceremonial and feasting, to carrying on blood
feuds and attempting to settle them. The village is a basic social unit.
It is composed of several hundred inhabitants, most of whom claim
descent through the male line from a common ancestor and so constitute a
lineage group.
(There are a few matrilineal groups among New Guineans as well.) Members
of such lineage groups make marriages with individuals of other lineages
in neighbouring villages and so consolidate alliances with them. Within
any given village there are important men of prestige referred to in the
literature as âBig Menâ. They acquire followings of dependants â
individuals who are in some way in the big manâs debt. The Big Mali is,
in Serviceâs language, a âchief redistributorâ of wealth, the âchiefâ in
control of a redistribution centre.
The lineage system is an important mechanism of social control in New
Guinea as in Sub-Saharan Africa. Yet, within this island, there is
probably more variety in the system than there is in all of Africa.
These New Guinean varieties should not be equated with the typical
African segmentary lineage system and they diverge from it in the
following ways: a) In much of New Guinea political organisation is a
network of inter-village relations, the focus of which is a village.
Villages of one ethnic group, situated on the margins of that groupâs
territory, will have the same kind of relationship with those in other
ethnic groups as it does with its own; b) New Guinean lineages and clans
sometimes do not have a common ancestor or at higher (maximal) levels
may not even claim unilineal descent; c) In New Guinea the largest
groups which may be considered polities are groups within which no war
takes place. But such a unit often does not correspond to other kinds of
important maximal social uriits organised for events such as pig
exchanges and initiations. Further, it is sometimes difficult to
determine what uniting for war may mean. Thus, among the Siane, there is
no war within a phratry. If a clan chooses to go to war outside the
phratry, at best it can only be sure that fellow clans will remain
neutral. It cannot ¡rely on fellow clans supporting it actively. Clan
and lineage in New.Guinea are better conceived of as âparameters within
which activities are instigated and points of reference fixed to
identify individuals and sub groups within publicsâ (Langness, 1973, 142
ff) . There is no automatic alignment of clan, subclan or even lineage
behind a man who has been wronged; d; The individual is not seen as the
jural representative of lineage or clan. Thus, kin groups are not
clearly corporate groups. In these ways New Guinea systems deviate from
the African segmentary lineages which are more sharply defined in
structure and function and possess a more clearly corporate character.
Lineage groups are important aspects of the New Guinean political system
since they carry on blood feuds and settle them. They are also the
groups which, through their adult male members, maintain internal order
and peace.
Politically, the most important individuals in a New Guinea community
are the Big Men. This too is another contrast with the normal African
plan which invests power in the ascribed role of male elder and in .the
usually achieved roles of religious specialists. The Big Manâs
leadership accrues from his wealth, his personal charisma, and sometimes
from his sheer physical power and size. An example of the latter comes
from the Tairora of the Eastern Highlands. They¡ tell a story of Matota
who was not only a despot but a fearsome killer as well. Yet he had some
reputation as a peacemaker since he had several trading partners and his
many wives gave him numerous affines. So he had a wide circle of
contacts, acquaintances and presumably friends. On seeing a desirable
woman Matota was known merely to motion to the womanâs husband and
proceed to take her into the bushes. He ordered villagers around with
impunity and it was considered that everything in the village belonged
to him. He was a symbol of individual initiative, boldness and male
machismo â all respected and desirable values among the Tairora.
Ultimately he met his own demise in an ambush â the only way such a man
could be controlled in this society.
Even in his prime Matota was never despot over more than 2,500 people.
His influence and control could not extend far, since not only was it
based on a meagre technology of communication and transportation, but it
depended as well purely on personal ties and his physical prowess. It
could also not lay the basis for creating an hereditary dynasty, since
the role of Big Man had to be achieved; it was not inherited. It is
likewise a question as to whether Matota himself was conceived of as
âlegitimateâ , or as just a big muscle man. Watson is not sure whether
the Tairora case suggests a society which has a leaderless political
morality occasionally interrupted by despotism â such as that of Matota.
Or does it have a political ideal of the strong leader, but considerable
ambivalence about one once he arises? (Watson , Tairora, 224 ff.) The
case does seem to suggest that where a social system which values
individual initiative, male assertiveness and aggressiveness, also lacks
control or curbs on such behaviour, despotism must occasionally appear.
Under such circumstances there seems no other way to get rid of the
despot but to kill him.
Of the Gakuku-Gama, the name for several tribes in the Central Asaro
Valley of the Eastern Highlands, Read says that authority is ordinarily
achieved and in lieu of any formal political institution âorder is
maintained largely through self-regulationâ. There are strong men who
have capabilities as warriors and orators and who have proven ability in
business, since they own many pigs and contribute considerable amounts
to communal feasts which accompany marriages, deaths and other events.
Men are admired for their strength and the strong man is a boastful,
aggressive person who demonstrates his superiority over others. But to
be a strongman also means economic success: one cannot have any debts
and must have reciprocated all the gifts made at oneâs marriage. After
this one must acquire sufficient wealth to be able to lend it out to
others so as to build up a wide following of debtors. Such persons not
only owe the return of the principle, but also a considerable interest
as well.
Among the Mari11g, the Big Man is a physically strong and attractivâe
adult male with a fighting manâs temperament and business ingenuity. But
Big Men vary according to their ability to communicate with the
ancestors. One of the most important positions in Maring society is that
of the âFight Medicine Manâ who has control of âfightâ magic in time of
war. Thus religious âpowerâ Is also associated with the Big Men.
Similarly among the Wogeo, who inhabit an island off the northeast coast
of New Guinea, the leaderâs influence is derived in large part from his
supernatural control of the weather. Wogeo believe he can bring rain or
sunshine and hence provoke abundance or famine. Like other Big Men he
too provides great feasts and entertainments and so makes others
indebted to him. Through his joint religious and economic powers he
acquires the right to mediate disputes, although he could do no more
than shame individuals into making a settlement (Hogbin, 1979).
Sahlins summarises the Big Man characteristics as personal power,
achieved status, an ability to attract a loyal following and to get what
he wants done by haranguing his followers; he is not so much a leader as
a hero and is able in war, magic, oratory and gardening. One might also
add that he is ordinarily a capable mediator. The aim of his economic
and political manipulations is to amass goods and distribute them in
ceremonies and feasts so as to bring him prestige as a generous man
(1963). Perhaps the Big Man is not far removed from Max Stirnerâs ideal,
or the hero in an Ayn Rand novel.
This New Guinean system has close parallels with a laissez faire
capitalism, but one practised with limited resources. As Sahlins says,
it is a highly unstable system: The Big Man reaches a certain stage in
his career when he searches for greater and greater renown and is thus
driven to press his debtors and other followers for greater production;
he in turn delays reciprocities owed to his followers, so that he
eventually encourages an âegalitarian rebellionâ which he may try to
hold off as long as possible by use of his charismatic and oratorical
skills (1963).
Several peoples in the Philippine Islands have anarchic polities. The
Ifugao are probably the best example. They live on the island of Luzon,
cultivating mountain gardens and raising chickens and pigs. Their
extensive terraces for irrigated rice production are well known.
Probably less well known is the fact that this complex system of
cultivation is accompanied by a social order in which there is no
government, no courts, no judges or constitutional or statutory law.
Ifugao social organisation is extremely simple. As with ourselves, kin
relationships are reckoned bilaterally, so that aside from the family
household a person identifies with a cognatic group of relatives. while
the basic and stable unit is a family centred around its most important
member, one is also obligated to go to the defence of any whom one
considers within the circle of kinship. Villages hardly exist; rather
houses are scattered, sometimes with a cluster of a dozen or so in one
place.
Another important aspect of Ifugao social organisation is the division
into social strata. At the top is a small group of wealthy men who could
at least claim someone in this class, called kadangyang, as an ancestor.
Admittance to the stratum is achieved by acquiring sufficient wealth to
sponsor feasts and become a man of note and influence. The great
majority of the Ifugao are either in a middle stratum where a family
owns sufficient rice fields to sustain itself, or in a lower class of
the poor who have no rice fields.
The kadangyang are the leaders of the Ifugao. They are asked to act as
go-betweens, that is third party mediators, in disputes. They bring to
any negotiations both their own reputation and the power of their own
kin group. Particulai-ly favoured are those with a reputation as head
hunters. The go-between is employed in a variety of circumstances: in
buying and selling operations, borrowing money, marriage proposals, the
collection of debts, demands for damages, buying back heads lost in war,
ransoming of the kidnapped and making peace. He is responsible to both
parties to a dispute and must be impartial, carrying from one group to
the other the proper and correct offers and payments. âHe wheedles,
coaxes, flatters threatens, drives, scolds, insinuatesâ in trying to
bring the parties to an agreement so that he may receive the fee due
him. He âhas no authority. All that he can do is to act as a peace
making go-between. His only power is in his art of persuasion, his tact
and his skillful playing on human emotions and motivesâ (Barton, 87).
However, a go-between can compel a defendant to participate in
negotiations. If a man tries to run away from, or shows defiance of, an
accusation, the go-between seeks him out and with his war knife
prominently displayed, therefore forces him to participate. In this
aspect we have then a true legal sanction and police authority. We may
also understand why an eminent head hunter is preferred for the
position.
Besides exacting a fee for his services the go-between also builds his
reputation and prestige with every successful settlement so that he will
be asked more frequently, acquire more in fees and build his wealth.
Most cases are settled by the assessment of fines. These are determined
in part by the nature of the wrong, but there is also a differential
scale based on a personâs social class. The go-between likewise
considers the reputations and positions of the individuals and groups
involved. Where fines are to be paid the two parties must first agree on
the amount of the payment. Ordinarily the party of the defendant
recognises an obligation to pay some indemnity; it mainly tries to
reduce the exhorbitant demands of the plaintiff. But, if one side
refuses to pay the fines that are assessed, the wronged party may then
proceed to attempt to seize property such as gongs, rice wine jars,
caraboas, gold beads, children, wives, or rice fields from the culprit.
Sentence of death applies to extreme cases such as murder, sorcery and
the refusal to pay a fine for adultery. It is ordinarily carried out .
by the wronged party. But any âexecutionâ can have adverse repercussion,
since it too may be avenged.
Where an accused denies his guilt he may be asked to undergo the boiling
water ordeal. Of course, if he refuses he is considered to be guilty.
The go-between acting as an umpire, observes the accused put his hand in
a pot of boiling water and remove a stone which has been placed in it.
Where two mutually accuse each other their hands are placed side by side
and a hot bolo knife is laid on them by the go-between, supposedly only
burning the guilty. Wrestling matches and duels are also resorted to.
Duels may commence with two opponents throwing eggs, leading to their
throwing spears and sometimes to others joining in on the fray. Feuding
is endemic, arising out of the desire to avenge alleged wrongs to oneâs
kin. The taking of the head of an enemy is an important part . of the
raiding between groups. This prize gives its possessor supernatural
power including that of the murdered man. Feuds are sometimes settled by
intermarriage and marriage is, in general, a means by which one can
extend the network of friendly relations. In addition pacts are made
between individuals which guarantee oneâs safety while in the home
district of a pact partner.
Ifugao men and women have fairly equal relationships. This arises in
large part from the practice of bilateral kinship. Both man and wife
bring to their marriage an equal amount of property and they also work
side by side in the fields.
Brief mention might also be made of yet another southeast Asian people:
the Land Dayaks of Sarawak in Borneo. They number about 50,000 and are,
like the Ifugao, wet rice fâ!rmers who also keep pigs and chickens. âThe
Land Dayaks are anarchists to the extent that no one amongst them is
strong enough to force the others to do anything which they do not wish
to do. In this classless society there are no true chiefs. Each village
has a headman, nowadays confirmed in office by the Government, but he
leads only when the people agree to be led. The way he gets his office
and the way he uses it ensure that he will not become a dictatorâ
(Geddes, 21). A relative of one who was once a leader is usually
favoured to fill the post. A headman is confirmed in his position by
general consensus. He should be a man of some wealth, but riches alone
do not suffice to make one a great man. A headman, at least, should also
be gentle and wise and one who will not seek to rule arbitrarily,
forcing his own will on others. Once again we have the man of influence
who, if he is tactful, can encourage others to follow his desires.
Any important decisions of the village are decided at a general meeting
called by the headman. Here everyone is free to speak and various
viewpoints are enunciated with great vigour. A headman observed by
Geddes âchose his words carefully, left them unclouded by argument, said
them at the right times, and kept them few . Thus, his comments stand
out, clear as beacons in the general debateâ (Geddes, 22). Since no
decision is final unless there is a consensus, occasionally a single
stubborn individual can obstruct action which is advocated by everyone
else. âIn such a case the unanimity which closes the meeting is an
agreement to do nothingâ (Geddess, 22) . Ordinarily agreement is reached
in part because public opinion is a strong force which only the most
thick-skinned can ignore.
In most villages there are one or two older men who know a sufficient
amount about the genealogies of their neighbours to settle any of the
rare disputes which do arise concerning land. The Land Dayaks also have
quasi-specialist religious leaders. Some of these lead ceremonies
connected with the veneration of ancestors and others are shamans who
tend to concentrate on the diagnosis and cure of illnesses, most of
which are believed to be caused by demons.
Like the other groups discussed in this essay, there is no overall
political integration of the Dayak society. Each village is an
autonomous and independent entity which may have either friendly or
hostile relations with its neighbours.
The sub-tropical and tropical regions of South America were home to a
multitude of differing cultural groups. Most of them were small in
population with no political integration beyond a local level. Some were
clearly anarchic; others were not.
Dole points to several examples of South American forest Indians wherein
a hereditary chieftainship was extremely powerful. A Sherente headman
was obeyed when he ordered several other men to kill a man who had
repeatedly abandoned his wife. Apinaye headmen ordered the execution of
alleged sorcerers. A Shavante headman held five men to be dangerous to
communal well-being and had them executed. The Cashinahua headman
visited every family in his village each day and gave out orders for the
dayâs activities. His permission was also required before a marriage
could be contracted.
Dole suggests that perhaps many of the known anarchic tribes in South
America were once much less so and considers in some detail the case of
the Kirikuru, a small group of about 145 persons who live in central
Brazil.
They have âheadmenâ who have no authority or power, although they once
had more before recent demographic and social disturbances. Disease has
reduced the population of many groups to the point where they can no
longer function as self-sufficient and separate entities. Consequently
various remnant groups consolidate. Thus among the Kirikuru there are
people from at least four different âtribesâ. Headmanship was normally a
kind of hereditary office through the male line, but a man often dies
before his eldest son matures so that one from another family is
therefore appointed. This man himself may be from a family which had
provided headmen in another tribe. Thus leadership is distributed among
various families producing claims to succession in several patriliries
so that the position becomes weakened. Dole argues that the strength of
headmanship is tied to lineality because it provides a standardised and
exclusive channel for the exercise and transmission of authority. Where,
as with the Kirikuru, this disappears, the authority of the headman is
undermined.
In lieu of any chiefly power Kirikuru rely upon a number of diffuse
sanctions. There is gossip, complaining, and ostracism. Alleged
sorcerers and witches are killed; guilt in connection with a crime or
evil is determined by divination. Any woman who looks on the secret
flutes of the tribe is punished by gang rape.
Lowie presents examples of the chiefly role among other South American
tribes. The Caraja chief is wholly dependent on his villagersâ goodwill.
If they are dissatisfied with him they will only abandon him. The Tapuya
chief was highly respected when he was leading his warriors, but at home
he was not so honoured. The modern Taulipang âheadman has very little to
say until hostilities break out with another groupâ (Lowie, 1949, 341).
The Jivaro likewise emphasise chieftainship only in time of war. Indeed,
they have no term for chief in their vocabulary and their war leaders
are only of a temporary kind. Actually over the long term a shaman may
be the most influential man in a Jivaro community. He is a curer, a
maker of love potions, a diviner of enemy activity and interpreter of
omens of defeat or victory in war. At the same time he may also be the
war leader.
The more anarchic of the South American polities are made up of groups
of kinsmen so that social relationships are kinship relationships. The
chiefly role as Lowie sees it, entails acting as peacemaker,
representing the group in foreign relations, welcoming visitors,
directing economic activities and indulging in admonishing harangues
(Lowie , 1949, 343).
Pierre Clastres has focussed on the more anarchic tribes in South
America. He asks why the chief should have no power. He recognises the
chiefâs importance as a peacemaker and mediator, but argues that these
functions should not be confused with the nature of chieftainship. To
explain this nature we must turn to the relationship of the chiefly role
to reciprocity. The chief is involved in an exchange entailing women,
words and wealth. Most of these Indians practise polygyny. The chief is
always the man with the most wives; often the only polygynist in the
group. At the same time the chief is expected to enthral the group with
his oratory â no speech, no chief. He must sponsor feasts, support the
community in hard times and always demonstrate his magnanimity and
generosity. Through these mechanisms the chief continually strives to
validate and revalidate his position. But such demonstrations are not,
as one might think, proper reciprocations to the community¡.for the
excess of wives or the position the chief has. Women are of s11tt:h
âconsummateâ value that all the words and all the gifts provided by tpe
chief are insufficient to qualify the situation as a reciprocal, that
is, equal exchange. As such the chief in his position defies
reciprocity, that basic law of social relations. Such an asymmetrical
relatibnship is identified with power and that in turn with nature. In
opposition to them stand reciprocity,[10] society and culture. People in
archaic societies, realising this conflict and the contradiction of the
fundamental social law, see power as enjoying a privileged position. It
is therefore dangerous and in need of restraint:; in fact âpowerâ should
be made âimpotentâ . The final synthesis in this dialectic is
paradoxical. The chiefâs most unreciprocal acquisition of multiple wives
puts him in a condition of perpetual indebtedness to his people, so that
he must become their servant.
Clastresâ argument is both plausible and logical. Yet reason and logic
alone are clearly insufficient grounds for accepting a theory. For the
more empirically-minded, Clastresâ explanation, like other structuralist
explanations, seems strangely detached from the solid earth. The use of
hard evidence to demonstrate the theory is lacking. We Me given no idea
of what the individuals involved may think. But then the structuralists
argue that these things are superficial appearances, not the world in
reality, the deep, underlying structure. Structuralism, like
Freudianism, Jungianism and, to a lesser extent, Marxism, suffers from
the problem of testability. A scientific hypothesis or theory should be
so constructed that it is falsifiable. It should be subject to empirical
test such that different investigators should be able to analyse the
same phenomenon and validate the hypothesis by independently coming to
the same conclusions. Strangely enough both LeviStrauss and Clastres
have investigated the chiefly role in South America according to
structuralist principles, but have apparently reached different
conclusions about it. In contrast to Clastres, Levi-Strauss offers the
usual conservative explanation that a true reciprocal relationship is
involved. (Levi-Strauss, 309). Clastres correctly expresses concern
about the ethnocentrism inherent in much political anthropology and in
cultural evolutionary doctrine. He also calls our attention to the
opposition and tension between reciprocity and leadership.
The following are the main sources used for African peoples: Lugbara,
Middleton; Konkomba, Tait; Tiv, Laura and Paul Bohannan; Tonga, Colson;
Anuak, Evans-Pritchard; Ibo, Green and Uchendu. The New Guinea materials
are from Berndt and Lawrence, Hogbin, Langness, Pospisil, Read, Sahlins,
and Watson. The Ifuago are based on Barton and the Dayak on Geddes.
South American Indians are from Clastres, Dole, Lowie, and Steward and
Faron.
Our third kind of society concerns those people who specialise in the
rearing of livestock. This does not include those who, as in our
society, specialise in producing livestock for sale in a market, but
only those who rely on domesticated animals as their chief mode of
subsistence. Indeed, marketing such animals is viewed by some pastoral
peopte as almost sacrilegious.
Pastoralism possibly originates as a speciality in agricultural village
life. Early farmers â five or six thousand years ago in the Near East â
may have initially sent their livestock out of the village each day, or
for longer periods, to graze under the direction of herdsmen. In the
course of time the latter separated from the village so that they¡
commenced keeping their own animals, utilising as grazing grounds the
marginal lands which were not good for agriculture. Eventually the
pastoral specialty spread through central Asia and large parts of Africa
outside the rain forest zone. Wherever it developed it was readily
adapted to local conditions, so that several types of pastoralism
survive to this day.
Pastoral peoples rely upon a few varieties of livestock. In all cases
their animals are grazers and browsers which are on the move cropping
grasses and shrubs. These animals include: equids (donkey and horse) ,
camelids (camels and llamas) , bovids (cattle yaks and buffalo), ovids
(sheep and goats) and cervids (reindeer) . Thus pastoralists may be
divided as:
1) Llama herders in highland regions of western South America
2) Reindeer herders of Arctic and Sub Arctic Eurasia.
3) Central Asiatic herders of mixed stock including, sheep, goats,
horses, cattle and sometimes camels and yaks. For the Central Asians
sheep and goats are the cornerstone of the economy, except in Tibet
where yaks are of most crucial importance.
4) Middle Eastern herders of sheep, goats and camels, with horses and
donkeys in a minor role. For some, camels are paramount; others, as in
eastern Turkey and Iran, have camels, but sheep and goats are more
important.
5 Herders of the African savannah grasslands depend on cattle, but sheep
and goats are also kept and in a few cases so are donkeys and horses.
Except among reindeer and llama herders, livestock is mainly the
provider of milk and other dairy products. Indeed, aside from the donkey
and llama, all the animals used by herders are milked in at least one
place or another. The herds contribute to the economy in other ways as
well. The larger animals are important as means of transportation â for
movement of both baggage and person; they provide the meat that is
consumed at all festive and cere monial occasions. Their hair, wool and
hides are used for making clothing, shelters, containers, harness and
many other things. Even their urine and manure is important among some
pastoralists.
Most pastoralists engage in activities other than herding for a
livelihood. Nearly all indulge in a somewhat indifferent cultivation,
providing chiefly grain. Some are occasional fishermen, while hunting
and gathering are of minor importance. One of the distinguishing
features of pastoralists, especially in the Middle East and to a lesser
extent in Central Asia and Arctic Eurasia, is the symbiotic tie to a
sedentary cultivating and town-dwellling population. The close
interaction with these peoples often affords an opportunity to acquire
wealth by raiding, warfare and extortion. In the latter case there is a
kind of protection racket, wherein sedentary villagers and townsmen pay
tribute to the pastoral tribe to avoid being raided. Furthermore, most
pastoralists depend upon townsmen for much of their manufactured goods
and other supplies and on peasant villagers for agricultural products.
Many pastoral systems are then, as Kroeber called them, âpart culturesâ
, not fully self-sufficient entities either in terms of material
productivity, or in terms of the ideological and spiritual aspects of
life.
Nearly all pastoral peoples are in part at least nomadic. There are
those who live their entire lives in dwellings which are readily
transportable and they move in a seasonal round over a tribal territory
following their grazing herds. Others may spend part of the year in
nomad encampments and part in fixed village houses, while some such as
the Nuer, to be considered below, send their herds off with all the
young people as herders during the extended dry season while the elders
remain at home in the village.
The tribal form of social organisation described in the previous chapter
prevails among herders. The chief exception is among some of the
reindeer keepers of northern Eurasia, especially the Samek who have
essentially a band type organisation like that of hunter-gatherers. The
tribal structure entails a segmentary patrilineal kind of organisation.
But in many cases this has evolved into a kind of incipient state
structure with distinct social classes and a military organisation which
undertakes true warfare.
Pastoralism ordinarily supports relatively large and dense populations
and in some cases, for example, Genghis Khanâs Mongols, has allowed for
the creation of extensive, though ephemeral, empire states. In part
because of the marginal nature of their enterprise and because they are
motivated to increase herd size and so expand grazing areas,
pastoralists, especially in southwest Asia and Africa, have acquired
reputations as warriors and predators.
There are some herders who have perpetuated a segmentary patrilineal
âtribalâ system without government and as such exemplify the practice of
anarchy. Clearly the most famous example is the Nuer, an Nilotic people
presently numbering probably 400,000, who reside in the swampy Sudd area
of the White Nile and its vicinity in the southern part of the Republic
of Sudan.
We have encountered the segmentary lingeage system several times before
and the Nuer system is basically no different from that of the Lugbara
or Konkomba. There are local villages which are identified with lineage
segments and inhabited largely by members of that segment, but there are
outsiders in a village as well. In addition, members of the lineage
associated with a given village will be found dwelling in other
villages. Members of the clan segments are likewise dispersed. Village
territories identified with given lineages combine to form larger
territorial units associated with yet larger segments (subclans and
clans), until one encompasses a tribal domain which is inhabited by
members of the tribe.
A tribe may have between 5â45 ,000 people. Each is economically
self-sufficient, having all its own pastures, water supply and fishing
places. Within the tribe disputes between members ought to be settled by
mediation and members ought to unite against other tribes and
foreigners. If a Nuer leaves his own tribal domain and settles in
another he thereby changes his tribal affiliation and becomes a member
of the tribe within whose territory he now lives. This is because
hostilities between tribes are endemic and there is no obligation to
mediate. On the other hand, one may move from one lineage territory
within the same tribal domain to another without changing oneâs lineage
affiliation.
In addition to the lineage structure, Nuer have age grades which cut
across lineage affiliations and tribal membership, uniting individuals
of the same sex and approximate age. It is a much weaker structure than
may be found among many other Africans, including the Tiv, and is
largely a device for noting the rites of passage between childhood,
youth, adulthood. Women also have a parallel organisation to that of the
men. Age grades have no political function and aparently do not even act
as mutual aid associations.
The feud between segments of the same complementary level of the system
is the primary political mechanism among the Nuer. Thus, if a man kills
a member of a different subclan, a feud situation would exist between
the subclans of the aggressor and his victim. However, the feud in fact
will involve only close kinsmen on both sides. the more inclusive the
segments become â that is, the higher one goes among groups in the
levels of segmentation â the more difficult it becomes to settle a
dispute, so that conflicts between members of primary or secondary
tribal sections often lead to intertribal fights (see diagram under
discussion of Lugbara above).
Disputes, including feuds, are regulated and usually ultimately settled
through the mediation of a man known as the leopard skin chief. As
Evans-Pritchard has noted, the title âchiefâ is misleading since he has
no true chiefly powers but is rather a ritual specialist who belongs to
one of a limited number of lineages. The leopard skin chief is much like
the Lugbara rainmaker. Someone who commits a murder first goes to the
chief whose residence is a sanctuary. The chief cuts the arm of the
murderer as a mark of Cain. He may then act as a mediator between the
kin of the killed and of the killer. He insures that the latter are
willing to pay blood money so as to avoid feuding and then persuades the
other group to accept compensation. The leopard skin chief collects the
blood money in the form of cattle, from 40â50 animals, and takes them to
the dead manâs home. The chief does not act as judge, although he may be
very insistent and even threaten to curse the dead manâs kin if they do
not accept compensation. But threats are invariably made, because that
group must preserve its honour and so appear reluctant to accept. What
is of paramount importance is the âmoral obligation to settle the affair
by the acceptance of a traditional payment and the wish, on both sides,
to avoid for the time being at any rate, further hostilitiesâ
(Evans-Pritchard, 1961 , 292).
âThe leopard skin chief does not rule and judge, but [is a] mediator
through whom communities desirous of ending open hostilities can
conclude an active state of feudâ (Evans-Pritchard, 1961, 293) . He may
also mediate in disputes concerning ownership of cattle. In any case all
the leopard skin chief can do is ask the parties to discuss a conflict
and only if both sides are agreeable to mediation can the matter be
settled. The ultimate power of the leopard skin chief, as with that of
the Lugbara rainmaker, is to curse those who will not agree to a
suggested settlement. This is indeed the nearest the Nuer come to any
governmental structure and for someone who firmly believes in the power
of the curse it possesses, therefore, a similar authority and force to a
policemen in our society ordering someone off to jail at the point of
his pistol. On the other hand, the curse, unlike the policemanâs pistol,
is not a weapon legitimately confined to the leopard skin chief alone,
for others as well have the power to invoke the supernatural, though it
may not be as potent a force. Furthermore, the power of the chief is
apparently only legitimate within the narrow limits of accepting the
results of mediation. Its authority does not extend to other areas of
social control.
The leopard skin chief incidentally decides appropriate compensations in
accord with well-established Nuer custom, but as Evans-Pritchard makes
clear, this does not make a legal system âfor there is no constituted
and impartial authority who decides on the rights and wrongs of a
dispute and there is no external power to enforce such a decision were
it givenâ (1961, 293).
Aside from the leopard skin chiefs, the most important men among the
Nuer are the local heads of extended families. These are older men, but
above all they are men rich in the number of cattle and men who have the
kind of personality respected by all Nuer. They also belong to what
Evans-Pritchard refers to as aristocratic clans. Such groups are those
which predominate within a given tribe. The term âaristocraticâ seems
inappropriate since such a clan has prestige, but no special privilege
and does not even have prestige outside of its own tribe. These
influential individuals lack any clearcut status. âEvery Nuer ...
considers himself as good as his neighbour, and families and joint
families, whilst co-ordinating their activities with those of their
fellow villagers, regulate their affairs as they please. Even in raids
there is very little organisation and leadership is restricted to the
sphere of fighting and is neither institutionalised nor permanentâ
(Evans-Pritchard, 1961, 294).
The Nuer do have several different kinds of ritual specialists: The Man
of the Cattle, totemic specialists, rainmakers, fetish owners,
magicians, diviners. Yet none has any political status or function,
except that some do become prominent and are able to scare others by
their alleged supern=atural powers.
As with the Lugbara, âprophetsâ appeared as an additional political
force among the Nuer in the late 19^(th) century, probably provoked by
the Mahdist phenomenon in the Sudan. The early prophets seem to have
been ritual specialists â healers and shamans â and later to have
acquired roles as mediators of disputes within their own districts. Some
prophets were able to imbue a sense of tribal unity, with themselves as
symbols of that unity, by inciting the several factions of their tribe
to united action in war against some enemy. It was the prophets who
organised the tribes to which they belonged to fight both Arab and
European incursions. But they never integrated any group larger than
their own tribe and even these efforts were short-lived.
Harold K Schneider argues the thesis that there is a significant
relationship between egalitarianism and dependence upon cattle
pastoralism . Focussing on East Africa, he finds that those societies
which have a high ratio of cattle to humans (more than one per person )
are egalitarian and stateless, with social systems which are either
primarily organised around the segmentary lineage concept or around age
grading. Hierarchy and the state tend to appear more commonly amongst
people with fewer cattle. He believes reliance upon cattle production by
its nature inhibits the growth of hierarchical organisation. Cattle
herds provide a highly mobile source of wealth which can grow rapidly
and can also as rapidly be wiped out. Where cattle rearing is the
primary focus of the economy and involves the participation of all it is
difficult to monopolise the main source of wealth or bring it under the
control of the few. âIt is difficult ... to centralise cowsâ (
Schneider, 219).
In addition, Schneider emphasises the widespread importance of stock
associations in which cattle are lent out to other men. Consequently
every man becomes involved in a network of relations in which each is a
lender and a borrower of cattle. This has the manifest function of
minimising losses from raids and disease. It builds goodwill with
others, lessens pressures on grazing land and spreads the burden of
work. At the same time it helps to disguise oneâs own wealth. But more
importantly, these stock associations lend reinforcement to the
hierarchy-inhibiting features of cattle raising, by engaging each man in
a multiplicity of equal and mutual bonds with others. Egalitarian
systems are such because they provide âmultiple opportunities for
acquiring new wealth, so that men of substance, big men as opposed to
chiefs, were seldom able to translate wealth into power since those whom
they sought to dominate had resources, derived from multiple
opportunities and wide ranging systems of stock association credit in an
atmosphere of rapid capital formation, which allowed them to escape
submissionâ (Schneider, 210). Egalitarianism always ârests upon an
economic base which is such that by its nature (and sometimes perhaps by
legal arrangement) it cannot be monopolisedâ (Schneider, 219).
It is interesting that Schneider places considerable emphasis upon stock
associations (and possibly correctly) , but the Nuer which we have
discussed above are invariably taken as the example of the typical
cattle pastoralist, egalitarian society and they do not seem to depend
to any extent on this mechanism. They do have an institution called math
or âbest friendâ in which two men formally establish a bond of
friendship by exchanging or loaning cattle (Howell, 198) . I have not
found math described in any published source in any detail. Either it is
not of much importance to the N uer or, as may very well be the case,
Evans-Pritchard and others who have studied the Nuer never recognised
its significance.
In his book Schneider does not address the question of why pastoral
peoples outside of East Africa tend more often to have hierarchical
systems and proto-states, if not full blown states. Central Asian
stockmen from Turkestan to Mongolia not only depended upon large herds
of sheep, but also on herds of cattle and horses as well. They also
organised some very substantial states and hierarchical systems. Arab
Bedawin and Iranian pastoralists also seem much more oriented to systems
far less egalitarian than East African herders. Yet one important
difference between Asiatic and African pastoraJists is that the former
have always dwelt in close proximity to large states (China, Iran and
the Indian states) . Perhaps, then, the evolution of hierarchical
structures amongst the Asiatic peoples is a response to this
circumstance. Notables among the pastoralists acted as intermediaries
with the giant states and were central figures in the very important
trade activity between China and the West. Through such channels, then,
pastoral notables were able to enhance their power and create states.
Schneider also does not consider the many African cultivators, many of
whom have few livestock of any kind, who have egalitarian, anarchic
social orders (eg, Konkomba, Tiv, etc) . One is led to wonder,
therefore, whether the basis for egalitarian and acephalous systems is
not so much dependence upon a highly mobile and reproductive form of
wealth (cattle) as it is dependence upon a cultural pattern which
induces a maximal dispersal of counterbalancing social bonds, and
creates an atmosphere in which monopoly is impossible. Monopolies can be
created with cattle and monopolies may be made impossible with other
forms of wealth. One might compare the Mongol herders on the one hand
with the Konkomba cultivators on the other.
Reindeer herding in the European sub-Arctic is in sharp contrast to the
lanky Nuer pasturing his cattle in the torrid southern Sudan. Yet these
peoples share not only pastoral life, but an individualistic world view
and anarchic social structure as well. While the Samek have generally
shown a remarkable tenacity in maintaining their unique culture in the
face of centuries of intimate contact with Europeans, they have
nevertheless modified their political and religious systems as a
consequence of this contact. For 300 or more years it can be said that
the Samek have been subject to the rule of one or the other of the
Scandinavian or Russian states and they have likewise been subject to
either Lutheran or Orthodox Christian churches. It is therefore somewhat
difficult to reconstruct the more âpristineâ, pre-contact social order
of the Samek.
For one thing it is obvious that the Samek never had any overall
political integration. They were a people divided among many small
herding bands, each of which was an independent and autonomous entity.
The band is still important among the Samek. Despite the fact that the
Samek are a pastoral people, this basic social unit, the band, is
similar to that which characterises most hunting-gathering people. Thus
the Samek band consists of a few dozen people, most of whom are related
to one another. This relationship is bilateral; it may be either through
the father or the mother. Indeed, Samek kinship, like that of the Inuits
and of Europeans, is quite non-lineal. Members of the band have use
rights to a certain territory; thus, it could be said that the territory
is the collective property of the group. Band members have the exclusive
right to hunt and fish in the area and of paramount importance is the
right to pasture their reindeer.
Band membership has a rather fluid character in that it is perfectly
possible for one to withdraw from a group and seek membership in
another. It seems that at one time the band was an exogamous group and
thus engaged in the cementing of alliances with other similar groups
through the exchange of women as wives.
Internal affairs are managed by what some writers have called a council.
Since this body included in its membership the heads of every family,
the term âcouncilâ is in fact somewhat misleading in its connotation of
formal organisation and delegation of power. Group decisions are
actually the collective responsibility of the adult male population as a
whole â a common feature of the other anarchic polities which we have
encountered.
There is in addition a band leader. This is a position for life and is
often hereditary, passing to the eldest son. But sometimes the leader
might be selected by the group. It is even possible for a man to marry
into a situation where he can eventually become leader because the
present one is his father-in-law, who has no sons to succeed him.
Ordinarily a leader should be wealthier than any of his colleagues. Band
leaders are essentially chief herdsmen of the group in that their
authority over other individuals encompasses their relationship to the
reindeer herds. The band leader is then co-ordinator of the groupâs
major economic activity. âIt is he who determines which kin groups
within the band shall furnish personnel for a herding expedition. It is
he who sets migration dates, accepts or rejects an applicant for band
membership, and directs herd movements. It is he who gives some
continuity and stability to the loosely organised Lapp band since his
successor is usually chosen from among his sons or sons-in-law. â
Outside the sphere of herd management the role of the leader âis
ambiguous and he is frequently overruled in group decisionsâ (Pehrson,
1077).
âMaster of the bandâ is the literal translation of the Samek title and
âmistress of the bandâ is the equivalent term for the wife or mother of
the band leader. She has a considerable amount of influence within the
group. Indeed, Samek society like that of the Inuit, Ifugao or Dayak
awards a much more equal position to women in general. Women inherit
equally with men; they could transmit property the same as men; they
participate fully in the economic activities of the group and male
leadership of the band itself could be transmitted through a woman.
Another source of power in the Samek community in preChristian times was
the shaman. Details of Samek shamanism are not well known, but it seems
safe to say that such individuals, being the most skilled in
communicating with the supernatural, in curing illness and in divining
future events, were ones to be listened to and respected. It is hard to
believe that they did not sometimes seek to use their powers to enhance
their own personal positions within a neighbourhood.
Modern times have been accompanied by the expansion of individual
property (enlargement of herds, acquisition of modern technology such as
snowmobiles, etc) and this has tended to increase the individualism
within Samek society. At the same time the governments of Sweden,
Norway, Finland and the Soviet Union have instituted formalised
techniques to foster more direct control over Samek social affairs.
The chief source for the Nuer is Evans-Pritchard. Other African
pastoralists with acephalous political systems, some of which approach
the anarchy of the Nuer are the Barabaig (see Klima); Dinka (see
Lienhardt) ; Jie (Gulliver) ; Karamojong (Dyson Hudson); Turkana
(Gulliver). For the Samek see Pehrson and Vorren and Manker.
Almost by definition one would not expect examples of anarchic polities
among agricultural peoples. Among the reasons for this is the fact that
agriculture entails permanent cultivation of large tracts of land so
there is an incentive to accumulate this important resource as property.
Further, agriculture from its inception was, and still today is, widely
associated with irrigation. Due to the complex problems of water
distribution, irrigation can easily lend itself to bureaucratization or
at least it has often done so. Consequently, it is easy for a stratified
and politically centralized society to arise within the context of
agriculture. Agricultural peoples include those who share a peasant way
of life, which is followed today probably by a good minority of
humankind. In addition, modem industrial societies fall into this
category as well, so that altogether over 90% of the worldâs population
is presently encompassed in this type.
Although no pristine examples of anarchy seem to be traditionally
practiced by any agricultural people, there are interesting cases of
highly decentralised confederations which border on anarchy and whose
governmental institutions are of the most ambiguous kind.
Consider ancient Iceland. This bleak island was settled in 864 by
Norsemen, no small number of whom moved because they were outlawed in
Norway or were dissatisfied with conditions there. One must remember
that nearly all the settlement of Iceland occurred before Norway
developed any system of a unified or centralised state and monarchy.
Settlers did bring with them the Germanic-Norse conception of âlawâ , an
important ingredient of which was the notion of the assembly of free
adult males to legislate and pass sentence upon criminals, all by a
system of consensus.
The new settlers in Iceland introduced the stratified social system of
Scandinavia. There were the freemen who laid claim to homesteads in the
new land and there were hired hands or bondsmen (thralls). From the
freemen were drawn 36 chiefs (godhis) who, with their families,
constituted the aristocracy. Each chief was the senior man in his given
area, which in the early period would have included barely 1 ,000
inhabitants. He protected those dwelling in his territory and helped the
freemen in securing their rights. He was the main decision-maker to whom
people deferred; he also attempted to mediate disputes and punish
culprits. It might be said that his sword was feared not necessarily
because it was wielded by the most able fighter, but because there was
attached to it an aura of legitimate authority. But while there was then
a vague legal sanction associated with the godhi, he was basically a man
of influence who was successful in imposing his will to the extent that
he could convince his followers to accept him as their first among
equals. When the community withdrew its goodwill the chief was
powerless. He had no police force to support him, only the public
opinion which he tried to rally to his support. Thus a good chief was
one respected and admired by his followers so that they supported him. A
bad chief would find his will frustrated, his following declining and
ultimately his own gory demise. Individual freemen who disliked their
chief might renounce their allegiance to him and accept another. Because
of this, a given chiefdom was not characterised by a true notion of
territorial sovereignty, since a given territory identified with one
chief might actually be dotted with farms whose owners adhered to
another.
From very early times, in Iceland all the habitable lands in the island
were occupied and claimed as homesteads, the owners of which were
associated with one chief or another. The Icelandic hinterland, a land
dominated by icefields and live volcanoes, was a refuge for those who
rejected the system or who were outlawed by the rest of society.
The local political unit then was a chiefdom which lacked a clean cut
sovereign territory. There was no real executive power and diffuse
sanctions were the primary means of social control. A chiefdom was not a
sovereign state, but was rather a voluntary contractual relationship
between chief and freeman which could be broken at will by a freeman.
Beyond this local chiefdom, the only form of political integration in
early Iceland centred around the âThingsâ. These were voluntary
judiciary assemblies of freemen led by the chiefs âwhere mutual problems
were discussed according to orderly traditional proceduresâ (Thompson,
165). There were regional Things and one Al thing for the whole island.
The latter met annually and here participants were reminded of the
customary âlawâ ; they also legislated new regulations and performed as
a court. But none of the Things were truly governmental institutions
since they had no power to enlist a military force, nor had they any
means, aside from urging diffuse sanctions, to enforce what was decided.
The most common punishments entailed outlawry (banishment from civilised
society for a set number of years) and confiscation of a manâs property.
The enforcement of outlawry depended entirely on the publicâs
willingness to see that the man was banished. And as the Sagas tell us,
a banished man invariably found supporters who would aid him, so that
banishment was by no means the harsh punishment one might imagine in a
place like Iceland. Furthermore it seems from the Sagas that
implementation of banishment was left up to those who belonged to the
wronged party; other individuals were at best indifferent regarding
enforcement (cf. Saga of Gisli, Saga of Grettir the Strong).
In the other form of punishment â the confiscation of property â it was
necessary for a number of men from the Thing to take it upon themselves
as a collective whole to visit the homestead of the condemned and
declare the property confiscated. The men assuming this responsibility
appear also to have been the aggrieved individuals and their friends. If
no such group took up this task the judgement of the Thing remained
unenforced. When there was an attempt to confiscate property it
frequently led to feuding and acts of vengeance. A chief who was found
guilty of an offence by the Thing might defy the sentence and this too
usually resulted in blood feud.
Icelandic Things had no executive officer. The Althing, for example,
appointed a man for a three year term as âlawmanâ whose responsibility
it was to recite one third of the law each year and also to act as a
moderator at the Althing meeting, a position similar to that of a
moderator of a New England town meeting â as a ânon-partisanâ who merely
calls upon various individuals who wish to speak.
Social order in ancient Iceland rested upon the voluntary contractual
agreement with a godhi and upon judgements of an assembly of all adult
freemen in which enforcement depended upon voluntary collective or
diffuse sanctions. But one might also resort to blood feud and sorcery
to obtain justice and order. Even if the Althing passed judgement on a
man for murder, the honour of the murdered manâs kinsmen required
revenge and thus feuds seem to have been very common and only stopped
when cooler heads sought to intervene and begin a process which would
bring the issue to a Thing for settlement. Sometimes this settlement was
cause for renewed bloodshed.
A man also defended his honour and pride by duelling, the consequences
of which likewise provoked feuding. Both men and women could obtain a
reputation as powerful magicians so that their manipulation of
supernatural forces was greatly feared.
While there were men who obtained reputations as mediators of disputes
in Iceland (such as Njall in The Burnt Njall) the institutionalisation
of mediation was primarily in the Thing.
Laura Thompson described the ancient Icelandic commonwealth as â... in
actuality not one state but rather a confederation of independent,
politically equal godord associationsâ (Thompson, 163). Of course it
must be remembered that one of the reasons for this situation was that
the several chiefs were jealous of their own realms of power and
influence and so attempted to curtail centralisation of authority.
However the struggle between chiefs even eventually led to the supremacy
of fewer and fewer of them. Finally one chief became dominant and made
Iceland a Norwegian dependancy. Iceland was thus being rapidly divested
of its old decentralist, headless and anarchic characteristics â
characteristics which, to contemporary Europeans, were rather incredible
âbarbarismsâ .
Throughout the Middle East there are several different ethnic groups
which have been referred to as âinhabiting lands of insolenceâ because
they live in defiance of centralised government authority. They are
âtriballyâ organised, with patrilineages and highly decentralised,
acephalous polities. Imazighen who dwell in northern Algeria and in the
Moroccan highlands probably demonstrate the more anarchic of these
peoples. A most appropriate example is the so-called âKabyleâ â
Imazighen farmers of northern Algeria and a group noted with favour by
Kropotkin.
The fundamental social unit in Kabyle society is the family household.
Several adjacent households comprise a neighbourhood within a village
and this is equivalent to a common patrilineage, although it may include
persons who are not true kinsmen. The patrilineage, in sum, is a
constituent of a clan. Ordinarily there are two clans in a village each
identified with a sof or moiety â that is, one particular half of the
village. Villages are independent entities. From ten to 20 comprise a
tribe, but this has no effective function , being at best a voluntary
association or alliance called into being on rare occasions for mutual
defence. About a dozen tribes are to be found in Kabylia.
Each lineage in a village has a chief spokesperson who participates in a
village council which deliberates on all matters of communal importance:
legislating, mediating and judging. The council is expected to defend
the honour of the community and to see to it that its decisions are
carried out. Here, as in other cases encountered in this survey, we may
note the weakness of true governmental features since there are no
specific policemen. Rather the council usually seeks to mediate between
disputants trying to find some basis for compromise and exhorting them
to reach an agreement. Once again the aim seems to be not so much to
determine guilt as to re-establish group harmony. The council is, in
fact, the voice of public opinion and communal sanctions, since it is
composed of representatives of each kin group, also because it acts only
when agreement is unanimous, that is, by consensus. The two primary
forms of punishment which may be imposed by this body are banishment
from the village and ostracism. The council, as has been said, is
essentially the voice of village public opinion and if it chooses to
ostracise a fellow villager, all others tend to fall in line to enforce
the punishment which is seen as a symbolic putting to death. Similar
diffuse and collective sanctions operate in banishing a member.
The collective oath is resorted to as a final resort, when every other
method of settlement has failed. This entails the members of a group
jointly swearing to the truth of their claims on pain of the wrath of
God if perjury is committed. Thus a refusal to swear is an admission of
guilt.
Aside from the council of the whole village, the males of a lineage on
occasion may meet as a body, but more important is the council of the
clan which controls the time of commencement of various seasonal
activities such as the beginning of ploughing, harvesting and other
communal labour, as well as the religious festivals. Throughout,
councils always operate on the basis of a well-known collection of
customary regulations peculiar to the village. These delineate the
recognised âcrimesâ and their appropriate punishments. In addition
councils are guided by a Kabyle code of honour.
Bourdieu calls the Kabyle system a âgentilitial democracyâ since it is a
group of kinsmen who administer their lives through an assembly of all
the âfathersâ in the village. Yet it seems to lack some essential
attributes of democracy. First, the majority does not rule: consensus is
the basis for decision-making. Secondly, ideally at least, power is so
decentralised that every kin group in the community is represented.
Delegation of authority, a characteristic of democracy, can hardly be
said to exist. Thirdly, enforcement of decisions is not through
policemen and the council is not a judicial body so much as it is a
mediatory one. Ultimate power rests in the expression of the diffuse
sanctions of the community. Finally, the social intercourse is more in
the nature of a relationship between kinsmen than it is a political
affair. In these respects then we have an institution which seems more
anarchic than it is democratic.
Among Moroccan Imazighen a patrilineage system along with the respective
councils is also characteristic. Yet the structure at the higher levels
of integration is more distinct and powerful, such that tribal councils
are clearly in evidence as governing bodies. A tribal council consists
of the patriarchs from each of the several clans which make up the
tribe. These patriarchs, who are similar to Big Men, often constitute a
kind of nobility from which the higher nobility or chiefs are drawn and
these are entrusted with the affairs of the whole tribe. If the council
cannot agree on a chief, one is selected by lot.
In some parts of Morocco an important political device is the alliance
in which a patriarch and his followers, who include members of his
extended family as well as those who may not be related to hm, affiliate
with others as a lift. Feuding within the tribe can be controlled, since
if one clan attacks another, this would be the call for the members of
the alliance to come to the aid of their brethren. And of course members
of the same alliance do not feud with each other. As long as the
alliances remain strong, a tribal chiefs power is curtailed since booty
acquired in fighting has to be shared by all members of an alliance.
Occasionally a tribal chief is able to secure an adequate following with
sufficient fire power so that he can impose his will on his tribe and
extend it over others. This invariable entails his being able to gain
control of the two alliances, and to assassinate rival chiefs as well as
to provoke local conflict which he might manipulate to his advantage.
After gaining domination over an area he could then seek to reinforce
his position by being appointed a qaid (agent) by the Moroccan sultan.
Whether or not he is able to ascend this far on the ladder of political
success, his autocratic rule is usually short-lived. Establishing a
dynasty is next to impossible due to the fact that the chief is faced
with constant revolt which ultimately becomes successful and returns the
system to the old decentralised anarchic order. In any event, the system
creates the rudiments of government and a tenuous autocratic state
structure. It provides an historical process of cyclic oscillation
between archy and anarchy.
Some Moroccan Imazighen have an interesting mediation technique. While
minor disputes are left to the local chiefs and councils, major disputes
involving members of differing tribes are submitted to âholy menâ or
Igurramen. These hereditary saints are ideally descendants of the
Prophet and so possess baraka or holiness. They have magical powers and
are known to be good and pious men. They do not fight, or engage in
feuds or litigation, but are non-combatants and permanently neutral
pacifists who comprise their own separate patrilineages. They are the
mediators between potentially hostile groups. Aside from this task they
supervise the election of chiefs among the several tribes in their
vicinity, provide sanctuary, protection for strangers and act as centres
of information.
An important part of their mediator judicial role is to witness
collective oaths. As was mentioned for the Kabyle, the collective oath
is deemed effective because one swears on pain of divine punishment
should perjury be committed. But Gellner suggests that this is not
ultimately the reason for the effectiveness of this method of
adjudication, since individuals do perjure themselves. To Gellner the
effectiveness of the collective oath is that if a group wishes to stand
behind one of its own it will be able to do so ; it will swear
collectively to the innocence of the alleged culprit. But it can also
use the mechanism to punish one of its own who is too much of a
trouble-maker, by some or all of his kinsmen refusing to take the oath
in which case the plaintiff wins.
The saints are mediators of disputes, not judges, since they cannot
enforce their decisions, but depend upon the acceptance of the verdict
by those involved . Those who refuse to abide by a verdict face
considerable danger due to the moral authority of the saints. Public
opinion and especially that of the saints and their clients would be
turned against such persons.
In addition to the fact that Imazighen society may be characterised by a
hierarchical structure which distinguishes prestigious tribal council
members from lesser lights, there is a more clear cut class or even
caste-like division. Thus Imazighen have a small population of slaves.
In addition tiny communities of Jews have resided in the land and these
too have been a subordinate âpariahâ caste. Among some Imazighen, such
as those of the desert oases, there has existed a Haratin caste of serf
cultivators, usually having distinct Negroid physical features.
In sum, Imazighen style societies are hierarchical, yet in many respects
egalitarian . They exhibit anarchic characteristics and also give birth
to autocratic regimes. They are suggestive as well of interesting
non-governmental techniques for social control. Recent decades, in part
because of improved military technology, have brought all Imazighen much
more under the direct control of central governments.
Several million people in India have been traditionally classed as
âtribalâ . This means they belong to those minority ethnic communities
which neither observe the caste system nor accept the ideology or ritual
of Hinduism. They are egalitarian and ordinarily organised into
exogamous patrilineal clans. Tribal people are found scattered
throughout India living as village agriculturalists. Their egalitarian
ideology and decentralised social system in some cases suggests an
anarchic order.
The Santals, at least, have only the barest indication of any
governmental system. Numbering over 3,000,000 they live in eastern
India, largely in the state of Bihar. In the Santai village life is
ordered by oneâs own kin group (his family and clan) and by the village
council and headman. Headmanship is an hereditary position, normally
passing from father to son, but nevertheless requiring the approval of
the villageâs household heads. It is an office for life. A headman is
seen as the main protector and repository of tradition, which is greatly
treasured by Santai. He may be referred to as the âbig manâ, in other
words, a man of considerable influence. He is also seen as a man of
wisdom and learning. Nevertheless, he is at best a first among equals.
âPublicly he is little more than the voice of consensus, though
privately his influence is that of an especially respected and powerful
manâ (Orans, 21). The headman receives certain tributes and privileges
for his role, including rent free lands, a portion of each animal slain
on a communal hunt and a central place at all weddings. There are six
other offices in a village and these are by appointment and for life.
These include village priests and an assistant responsible for public
morals.
The council comprises all household heads in the village. It assembles
regularly and under the chairmanship of the headman. While he ordinarily
calls meetings, anyone in the village can make a request that one be
held. Apparently, in Santai tradition there is strong emphasis upon open
and free meetings which guarantee every member the right to express his
views fully. The aim of any meeting should be to achieve consensus, but
if this unanimity is not forthcoming, the support of the overwhelming
majority is accepted. Usually final decisions follow the recommendations
of the headsman.
According to Somers, Santai village life is so structured that it
prevents concentrations of power. Thus, the seven village office holders
are never able to constitute a special power clique because council
meetings are held frequently and are open and free. Santai also do not
take kindly to the secrecy which would be required for a clique to
operate. The village has different foci of power such that they
counterbalance the power of the headman. While each institutionalised
social segment has authority over its members, there is nevertheless
considerable tolerance for individual autonomy. It seems that Santai
have a healthy distrust for power and have therefore not only developed
techniques to minimise its concentration, but have been diligent in
preserving and enforcing them.
Local village affairs are the responsibility of the council and headman.
Conflicts between persons of two different villages necessitate
settlement through the offices of elders of the village involved. A
group of between ten to 20 villages constitutes a territorial
confederation and this is the largest unit of political integration in
Santai society. This confederation also has a council composed of elders
and headmen from member villages. There is no formalised technique for
selection of members. One of the members, usually a headman of a
village, is elected permanent chairman of the group. This assembly is a
âcourt of last resortâ and is concerned with intervillage affairs. Here
also no decisions are made unless consensus of an overwhelming majority
has been achieved.
In their adjudications village councils seem primarily to assess fines
and order ritual purification as judgements. The aim is to restore peace
rather than to punish. Fines are often used to provide a feast and drink
for the council and in one area both complainant and accused contribute
to such a feast, although the accused gives more.
Apparently for certain offences one could be administered physical
punishment (cf. Culshaw) . This clearly suggests legal sanctions.
Physical punishment and fines are, however, only imposed by the
collective meeting of household heads and are arrived at mostly by
consensus so that such sanctions are in fact more in the nature of
diffuse sanctions. They are not those enjoined by the force of a select
elite.
The most awesome punishment which could be imposed on an individual or
group is ostracism, which is, of course, one form of diffuse sanctions.
This seems largely to be imposed by the council of the confederation and
in connection with infractions of marital regulations. A person or a
group declared ostracised is first lampooned by the whole community.
Then the guilty will be shunned and treated as if non-existent. The
sentence of ostracism may be permanent or temporary. In the latter,
return to the community may depend on the personâs willingness to change
his ways, his demonstrated repentence and payment of the costs of
purification ceremonies.
Members of Santai society are concerned about concentrations of power
and the need to preserve an egalitarian society which gives some free
rein to individual expression. There is at the same time a strong
dedication to tradition; religious sanctions are both powerful and
important. With the emphasis upon consensus of the total community,
diffuse sanctions rather than legal sanctions seem to prevail and thus,
at the least, Santal society exemplifies a condition of marginal
anarchy. Yet, with the imposition of British colonial rule and, more
definitely, with the creation of the Indian republic, Santai society has
been radically modified and more clearly integrated into and subjugated
to the national state. For example, confederational councils have
apparently not acted among the Santai since 1947 and local headmen are
now responsible to authorities of the central government.
Another social and cultural milieu upon which Kropotkin looked with
considerable favour was the medieval free city commune. He leads us to
believe that in its early form it was a society without the state and a
community of free men. But how free was it? Did it in fact lack
government?
Kropotkin argues that the medieval free city had its origin in the
village community and in the notion of the fraternity or guild. âIt was
a federation of these two kinds of unions, developed under the
protection of the fortified enclosure and the turrets of the city.â In
some places this was a ânatural growthâ , in others, especially in
Europe, it resulted from revolution. â(I)nhabitants of a borough ...
mutually took the oath to put aside all pending questions concerning
feuds arisen from insults, assaults or wounds, and they swore that
henceforth in the quarrels that might arise they would never again have
recourse to personal revenge or to a judge other than the syndics
nominated by themselves in the guild and the cityâ (Kropotkin, 1943,
19).
The Encyclopaedia Brittanica says: âIt would be very wide of the mark,
however, to imply that the communes were democracies. The life of all
the towns was characterised by a struggle for control, as a result of
which the wealthiest and most powerful citizens (patricians) were
usually more or less successful in monopolising power. Within the
communes oligarchy was the norm.â
The liberal characteristics of these communes did vary considerably,
however not only from place to place, but also the same city might
experience a period of relative liberality and, then, ultimately decline
into tyranny. Indeed, the latter seems to be the historic process of
most of them.
The residents of the medieval commune, as Kropotkin notes, swore a
collective oath to follow the decisions of the cityâs elected judges.
However, this collective oath was not always freely given; residents
were often forced to make it. In addition, it soon became only a
perfunctory act. Judges and other city administrators were chosen, often
in a popular assembly, from the wealthy and influential families who
were precisely those most interested in having a free city â free of the
interference of neighbouring dukes and kings so they might better pursue
their business interests. Not only did this situation then create a
ruling body of oligarchs, but it enhanced the class differentiation
already present.
Kropotkin overlooks the class oriented and exploitive nature of the
European guild system. Ostensibly one might say members of a guild
gradually progressed from one status to a higher and more responsible
one â that the ultimate aim of guild membership was graduation to the
rank of master. This then is no different from the ideal of any rational
educational system in which the student has the potentiality of becoming
equal in knowledge to his or her teacher. However that might be, in the
guild system, masters were the rulers and indeed dictators. The
apprentices at the bottom were treated hardly better than common slaves.
They had to be especially submissive and obedient if they wanted to
advance to a higher rank of journeyman, since that depended upon the say
of the masters. All power in the guild was vested in the masters and the
majority of members could only act as âyes menâ to them. Also the free
cities acquired an increasing population of wage working proletarians
who had no decision making role in the guilds, or in any part of the
economy or polity.
From the point of view of the serf on the feudal estate, the free
commune of the medieval period might have seemed like a haven of
freedom. And even from the vantage point of a 19^(th) century European
the free commune must have stood out as a laudable oasis in a desert of
authoritarianism. But there is little justification for Kropotkinâs
treating it as if it were some worthy example of early anarchy.
It is interesting to note the occasional close relationship between
views which are ordinarily diametrically opposed. Sometimes indeed,
opposite views are so opposite to one another that they converge in
similarity. Obviously fascism and anarchism have diametrically opposed
ideals â particularly about the morality of the state and the role of
the individual. Yet, as was suggested early in this essay, the anarchist
description of the nature of the state is not always that divergent from
the fascist one. The difference, which is crucial and fundamental, is
that while the anarchist sees the state as morally wrong, the fascist
sees it as right and good. Fascism and anarcho-syndicalism also share a
common historical tie to the corporate system allegedly associated with
the medieval commune.
Rather ironically a myth of the medieval communeâs social organisation
seems to have been used as a model for both fascist corporative theory
and the anarcho-syndicalist idea of federalism. Presumably the
administration of medieval cities was by an assembly of representatives
of the several corporations or guilds which constituted the city.
In anarcho-syndicalist theory the free commune myth becomes transformed
into an administration by levels of presumably voluntarily confederated
bodies representing the various crafts and trades. The top level is
either a national or world federation. In fascist theory, which draws
not only on the medieval mythic model, but on anarcho-syndicalism as
well, the nation state is conceived as a corporation just as the
medieval city was viewed as a corporation. Similarly it was to be
governed by an assembly of representatives of the several corporations
within the state. In fascism this means one segment representing the
working force through its syndicates divided according to craft and
another segment representing management. The state is seen, in Hobbesean
fashion, as the grand arbitrator, ameliorating these forces in the
public interest. (Of course, in actual operation the interests pursued
were those of the clique controlling the state and secondarily those of
business management.) The Soviet system might be seen as a modification
of the syndicalist and fascist models. It is certainly closer to the
latter since in effect the Soviet system absorbs the corporations of the
workers and the capitalists into the state bureaucracy.
In the United States the Catholic Worker movement has for years carried
on a campaign for a new society which combines Roman Catholicism with
communalism, anarchism and pacifism. It is, however, clear to anyone who
has read the Catholic Worker and other materials published by their
followers that the movement seeks a return to medievalism, a criticism
made of the movement almost 40 years ago by the Communist Daily Worker.
The anarchism of the Catholic Worker is a romanticised and nostalgic
notion of a medieval free commune. Their model amounts to a variation on
an authoritarian corporative one: the church becomes the state.
Kropotkin, in his essay on the origin of the state, mentions the
Anabaptist movement as an example of anarchism, although present day
members of
sects and atheist oriented anarchists would undoubtedly be a little
disturbed at such an association. Modern legatees of Anabaptism are the
Mennonite, Amish and Hutterite sects. Basic to their teaching is the
âtwo Kingdomsâ theology, which has its roots ultimately in Augustineâs
City of God. To Augustine there are two cities: the earthly city of self
love and contempt for God and the heavenly city of love of God and
contempt for self. The latter, or city of God, manifests itself on earth
in the church. Since the church has elements both of the heavenly and
earthly cities, it should not be identified as the city of the God. The
state corresponds to the earthly city. A true Christian state works in
close relation with the church, promotes the church and secures the
peace. Church and Christian state are inextricably bound together in
mutual dependence and obligation.
This scheme, which became the model for the medieval conception of
church state relations was modified by the Anabaptists. Thus the earthly
city or kingdom represented by government and the state is seen as
âworldlyâ and un-Christian. There can be no such thing as a Christian
state or government since it is founded upon the principle of the
legitimate use of violence to compel obedience to law. Since violence
cannot be used by Christians, they therefore cannot participate in
government or in the administration of the state. Furthermore,
Christians being right-minded individuals and members of the church, and
therefore of the Kingdom of God, have no need for governments.
Governments as institutions of the kingdom of this world are for
worldly, evil-doing people. As long as there are the latter, governments
are necessary. Christians must stand aloof from them to avoid
participation in their operation. At the same time they should be
obedient to them where it is within their conscience to be so. They
should render unto Caesar. Such rendering, however, does not include
being a member of a military organisation or a police force. Nor does it
mean holding political offices or voting for them or serving on juries,
which may send men to prison or to their death.
The true Christian is a member of the Kingdom of God through the earthly
organisation of the kingdom, which is the church. This in turn, is the
community of believers and of those who practice the teachings of Christ
in everyday life. In lieu of secular government, believers are under the
guidance of congregations of which they are full, equal and voluntary
members. The church is a voluntary contractual association; one does not
have to belong. The member is expected to live according to the doctrine
and the rules of the church. Such doctrine and regulations are not
determined by an elite body of hierarchs, but represent the collective
product of the total religious community.
There are, however, clergy who are elected by lot from among the members
of the congregation and they lead the church rituals and take a major
role in interpreting church doctrine and in dealing with alleged
wrongdoers. The ministers and bishops are the men of influence in the
community who are at least readily able to sway a large part of a
congregation, if not all, to their way of thinking. They do not have the
power to make decisions arbitrarily by themselves, however. When a
member of a congregation is accused of wrongdoing his or her case is
heard by the whole membership and decided by it. The ultimate punishment
is âdisfellowshipingâ in which the errant member is expelled from
membership, which in the close knit highly integrated order of the
Anabaptist congregation has always meant a serious punishment. Before a
person is given such a sentence, however, he is encouraged to make a
public confession before the assembled congregation and ask for
forgiveness. Such a request is invariably granted and the matter is
ended. Refusal to do so is considered a defiance of the entire church
and this defiance of the community ultimately, then, becomes the most
serious offence. Disfellowship means not only that one is expelled from
membership, but also that one is totally shunned by all the church and
cannot share in the religious services. It is in this general manner
that Hutterite colonies and Amish congregations operate today. They have
no police or courts and do not apply to them, but settle their dispute
within their own communities in a system without government or the
state, but founded, of course, on the ultimate sanction of Godâs
disapproval. Such a system, as much as others we have discussed,
requires firm belief in the power of the supernatural sanctions. It
demands such a dependence upon the community of believers that shunning
and disfellowship are perceived as excruciating punishment and so are
effective deterrents to deviant behaviour. Some so punished would not
find it easy to continue in defiance of the congregation and at the same
time continue residing among its members.
Unlike the other communities described thus far these Anabaptist groups
exist within states, so that they have always been ultimately subject to
the law and force of a given government, although as far as they are
concerned this would not in any way make their system of social control
for themselves any different than if they were not subjects of nation
states. Many such groups, for example, the Hutterites, have the
characteristics of intentional communities which are discussed below.
On ancient Iceland see Durrenberger, Gjerset and Thompson. On the
Imazighen see Bourdieu for the Kabyle, Gellner, Hart and Vinogardov for
others. See also Munson. Regarding the Santai, see Mukherjea, Orans and
Somers. Materials on the medieval free cities were drawn from Clarke,
Hughes, Lodge, Martines, Pirenne, Previte-Orton and Rorig. For the
Anabaptists see Friedmann and Hostetler.
In the modem world there have been a few isolated attempts at creating
the anarchist commonwealth. One type of experiment is the institution of
anarchy within a major region or entire country. Another is the small
scale communal experiment â the âutopianâ or intentional community
established within the existing larger society. In both we are dealing
with a set of circumstances different from what has been encountered so
far. For here we have selfconscious efforts to establish anarchy by
individuals committed to the anarchist ideology of 19^(th) and 20^(th)
century Europe and America. This implies not only a rejection of the
state and government, but also of church and patriarchy, male dominance
and all dominance by elders. It also involves deliberately planning a
social order based upon voluntary co-operation.
There are two cases of attempts to institute anarchy at the regional or
national level. One is from the Ukraine during the Russian Revolutian
and the other from Spain during the Revolution or Civil War, 1936â39.
Unfortunately, the circumstances in both are muddled because of the
prevailing war conditions and therefore cannot provide an adequate idea
of an anarchist society in ânormalâ times.
Not only did the Ukrainian case occur during the great revolutionary
upheaval after 1917, but it was also a short-lived affair. Nestor
Makhno, leader of anarchist revolutionary forces in the Ukraine,
initially directed his energies against the Czarist army. But for a
short period between late 1918 and June 1919, he gained sufficient
control of the cities of Ekaterinoslav and Aleksandrovsk, along with the
surrounding countryside, for some implementation of anarchist communal
ideas to be achieved.
In the rural areas, followers of Makhno expropriated farm lands,
livestock and implements from the landed estates as well as from wealthy
small holders, leaving their owners, according to Makhno âtwo pairs of
horses, one or two cows (depending on the size of the family), a plough,
a seeder, a mower and a pitchfork ... â With this expropriated property
the peasants organised communes. It is alleged that the communes were
âcreated freely, by a spontaneous impulse of the peasants themselves,
and with the help of a few good organisers, for the purpose of providing
the necessities of life for the working peopleâ. Everyone was expected
to work while administration and co-ordination of affairs was placed in
the hands of those of their number who were deemed most capable, such
administrators returning to their ordinary workplace with the other
peasants when these duties had been accomplished. Thus there seems to
have been an attempt to minimise differences between the workers and the
co-ordinators so as to avoid development of a bureaucracy (Voline, 105
ff). According to Voline, the Makhnovist partisan soldiers never exerted
any pressure on the peasants.
Makhno himself declared that in the communities members âapplied
themselves willingly to the taskâ. There were communal kitchens and
dining halls, although a member could eat with his or her family in its
own quarters without objection. Apparently each member was expected to
take a responsible attitude towards food and inform the commune how much
was required before taking it. Sundays were days of rest, but if members
informed their work mates ahead of time they could leave the commune at
other times as well. Overall management of the commune was by a regular
meeting of all members.
Makhno reports that there were four of these communes within three or
four miles of Gulyai Polya and many more in the surrounding district. A
commune apparently had from 100â300 members, each being allotted
sufficient land by âdistrict congresses of land committeesâ. Yet a
majority of the population of the region was not involved in the
anarchist communal movement and even within the communes only a minority
were anarchists. The great majority of villagers did not join the
communes, âciting as their reasons the advance of the German and
Austrian armies, their own lack ¡of organisation, and their inability to
defend their or_der against the new ârevolutionaryâ and
counter-revolutionary authoritiesâ (Avrich, 132) . In the urban areas
there seems to have been little organisation along anarchist lines. Only
a minority of the workers were supporters of Makhno and, unlike the
peasants, they had little ex p erience in âmanaging their own affairsâ
and âwere lost without the guidance of supervisors and technical
specialistsâ(Avrich, 25) Peasants could also barter produce whereas
workers depended wholly on wages.
During this short period, several regional congresses were held by the
peasants, workers and partisans of the region . While they were
presumably established to co-ordinate a regional economic and social
programme, they devoted most of their time to the pursuit of the war,
initially against the Czarists but eventually against the Bolsheviks as
well. One congress organised a Revolutionary Military Council which was
supposed to carry out all decisions of the congresses, but had itself no
power to legislate. Makhno claims that âonce the resolutions of this
Second Congress were made known to the peasants of the region, each new
town and village began to send to Gulai-Polya, en masse, new volunteers
desiring to go to the front against Denikinâ (general of the White Army)
(Voline, 109).
These rather ambiguous descriptions by Makhno and Voline of the actual
practice raise more questions than they answer. One wonders how many of
these army volunteers were truly volunteers. One may ask to what extent
individualism in the commune was tolerated. One may question the
technique of âexpropriatingâ property, especially from small holders.
Then, too, Makhnoâs own proclamations have an all-too-familiar ring:
âAnyone convicted of counter revolutionary acts or of banditry will be
shot on the spotâ. Persons refusing to accept Soviet, Ukrainian or any
other kind of money âwill be subject to revolutionary punishmentâ. âAll
individuals who attempt to hinder the distribution of this declaration
will be regarded as counter-revolutionariesâ (from Proclamations of the
Makhno Movement, 1920 in Avrich, 134).[11] Makhnovist conceptions of
justice and freedom seem to have been closer to those of the Bolsheviks
than to anarchy. At best it would appear that Makhno and his cohorts
sought to initiate a kind of decentralist military democracy which was
soon nipped in the bud. Although there were attempts to prevent the
development of a differentiation between the bureaucrat and the worker,
we might expect that even if the Makhnovist society had survived, that
difference would have soon appeared and a red bureaucracy established,
as in the Soviet Union as a whole (cf Luciano Pellicani). But the Makhno
experiment had so little time and was continually harrassed by Czarist
and Bolshevik alike that it probably should not be judged too harshly.
The second example of the attempt to establish an anarchist society in
this century occurs in Spain â beginning in 1936. Yet again we have an
equivocal situation: is this an attempt to establish a decentralised
collectivist democracy or anarchy per se? In writing of the situation
Sam Dolgoff, Vernon Richards and other anarchists have considered the
movement and the society âanarchistâ . Gaston Leval, who observed many
of the collectives directly, prefers to call the movement âlibertarian
communismâ or ârevolutionary libertarianismâ even âlibertarian
democracyâ.
The Spanish Civil War, which ultimately brought down the Republic and
established the Fascist regime of Francisco Franco, is also seen by
members of the left and, especially the libertarian left, as a Spanish
Revolution. It was considered a revolution because during the period
from July 1936 until March 1939, widespread fundamental changes were
introduced into the social and economic life of much of Spain. Most
important to our interest is the establishment of new social
institutions by anarchists.
Spain in 1936 had the largest anarchist movement in the world. In- deed,
possibly more than half of all anarchists in the world were Spaniards.
This was the precipitate of a well-established tradition which carried a
popular anarchist movement back to 1872. The Spanish movement was
essentially Bakuninist in that it favoured an organisation of society
into localised collectives which would federate into local federations
and in turn form broader federations.
An important feature of Spanish anarchism was its mass support both from
rural and urban areas. Indeed, anarchist writers such as Rocker and
Murray Bookchin have argued that the traditional Spanish peasant
community perpetuated a tradition amenable to anarchist collectivism.
Bookchin even claims anarchism is âembeddedâ in the life of the Spanish
people. What this seems to refer to is the pre-capitalist collective and
mutual aid practices in the village in addition to individualist values
held by the Spanish peasants. This combination of mutualism and
individualism is not unique to the Spaniards. It seems to be a common
feature of peasant peoples. Certainly the neighbours of the Spaniards,
the Imazighen and Arab peasants, might be so characterised. Anarchism
might not be so much embedded in the life of the Spanish people, as a
certain predisposition to it may be embedded in peasantry and this
because of the general character of the peasant situation. Even so, such
an observation as Bookchinâs does not adequately take into account the
authoritarian side of Spanish life, such as the influence of the church
and the fact that fascism had some appeal among Spaniards.
Clearly, however, the support for Bakuninist federalism among Spanish
peasantry, especially suggests that that milieu when faced with the
radical social-technological upheaval of the last 100 years, was a
fertile ground for anarchism.
It is not my purpose here to enter into any details of the organisation
and operation of the Spanish anarchist collectives, other than to raise
some questions concerning the role of authority within them. The ideal
of all the communes was to institute a free collective characterised by
communal ownership of means of production, voluntary membership and
right of withdrawal without punishment, full and equal participation in
the decision-making process, free choice of occupation, equal pay, free
education, medical care and pharmaceuticals, and the replacement of
money by ration or credit cards and an intercommune barter system.
The collectives in Spain, like those in Makhnoâs Ukraine, operated only
during a period of intense hostilities and open warfare. This had the
obvious adverse effects of creating shortages of all kinds, and of
disrupting communications, effective social intercourse and trade. But
it also had the positive effect of continually motivating all members as
a united force against a common enemy: it was a fight for survival such
that many normal problems, which might have caused conflict in ordinary
times, were set aside and overlooked. Not only did the adverse war
circumstances affect the system, but within the short span of less than
three years it can be questioned whether there was sufficient time for
the development of the kinds of oligarchic and bureaucratic arrangements
Michels or Machajski, for example, might have predicted as part of the
dynamics of such a situation. Finally, it is also worth bearing in mind
that in almost all the collectives the dedicated anarchists were
invariably in a minority. In most of them, socialists and others not
particularly committed to the principles of decentralism, equality and
freedom, were a majority.
Reviews such as those of Leval or Dolgoff show that collectives did
implement the principle of communal ownership. In the agricultural
collectives the land, livestock and implements were the property of the
commune. Business appears to have been conducted with maximum
participation by members. There were frequent meetings and open
discussions. There was an honest attempt to introduce some equalisation
in wages for all. Free education, medicine and pharmaceuticals were
universal and some collectives went further to provide free housing,
electricity and bread.
Nevertheless for a presumed anarchist experiment some important
questions arise â again similar to those which come to mind with regard
to the Makhno experiment. First, it appears that in their meetings few
communes operated according to the principle of consensus, but instead
relied on majority vote. Now this may be an appropriate anarchist
technique if it is not utilised as a mechanism to oppress a minority
point of view. This means in effect that issues of fundamental principle
cannot be very easily decided. Further, whatever the case, the minority
must always have the right either not to follow the majority will, or to
withdraw.
The right to withdraw seems to have been recognised by the Spanish
collectives, yet someone who left stood a good chance of thereby losing
any contribution to the collective on joining. More important what
happened to those people who did leave or for that matter to those who
did not wish to join any collective? Presumably one had the choice of
belonging to a collective, or remaining an independent worker. In
agriculture this meant one was limited to a holding which did not
require hired wage labour to operate, since that was forbidden. Leval
tells us, in some of the ambiguous terminology of the left, that
âthrough the intermediary of the collective their[12] activities were
co-ordinated with the general plan of workâ . What they produced was
sold to the collectives. One is led to wonder in what manner wage labour
is forbidden and how the activities of non-collective farmers were
âco-ordinatedâ. Was there an âanarchist police forceâ? Or, in a
tradition more amenable to anarchy, were diffuse sanctions such as
ostracism or boycotting imposed?
Another questionable grey area is suggested by the mention of committees
of collectives which were elected to manage the groupâs affairs.
Collectives quite commonly elected three or so of their number to act as
an executive or managerial committee or âadministrative commissionâ , to
which seemed to be delegated no small amount of authority. They decided
hours of labour and payment to be made; they decided whether or not to
expel a member. On the âlibertarian communismâ in Alcorn village we hear
that â(t)he Committee is the paterfamilias. It possesses everything, it
directs everything, it deals with everything. Each special desire should
be submitted to it. It is, in the last resort, the only judge. One may
object that the members of the Committee run the risk of becoming
bureaucrats or even dictators. The peasants have thought of that too.
They have decided that the Committee should be changed at frequent
intervals so that every member of the village should be a member for a
certain periodâ (quoted in Dolgoff, 144). Yet is such a total delegation
of authority anarchy? It might better describe a democratic arrangement
in which terms of office are short and limited to one term per person.
These questions and criticisms should not be interpreted as an attempt
to belittle the Spanish effort. For these libertarian collectives were,
despite their faults, brave, novel and bold experiments in living.
Because of their anti-authoritarian bias they were probably the only
truly radical large scale efforts at change thus far in this century.
Intentional communities are in no sense sovereign entities, but quite
the contrary, they are communities within and upon the land of sovereign
states. They are attempts to initiate anarchic communities âwithin the
shell of the oldâ . Thus, for example, the several anarchist communes
established in the United States all have had to conform in some fashion
to United States law and in many cases have been forced to close down
largely because they have not so conformed. Any anarchy in such
communities becomes highly circumscribed and is applicable to the
internal affairs of the group itself, where even here the long arm of
the law may sometimes reach. Any such commune finds itself an integral
part of the political and economic system of the state whether it wants
to be or not.
Further, individual members themselves. have been reared in the cultural
traditions and values of that state and have only the greatest
difficulty divesting themselves of their delecterious effects. In
communes which do survive more than a few years, the children do not
have the same desires, motivations and emotional problems as their
parents. Children reared in communes will not have the devotion to them
and the same ideals as their parents. The charisma of the first
generation is succeeded by the routine of the second. Nor can the
commune easily shield the young or any others from the formidable
âattractionsâ of the outside. How to keep them down on the commune is
another major problem. In short, from the start, any such project as an
anarchist intentional community has an overwhelming chance of failure
because of the odds against it which emanate from the external world.
Anarchic communal experiments have always comprised small populations.
Indeed, the great majority hardly ever reached 100 permanent members and
they have been family-like affairs. Moreover, they are invariably not
self-sufficient economically. Some, or most of the members, obtain
employment outside in order to sustain the community. While the
anarchist experiments have often been based on a communal ownership of
the land, full communism, in the sense of a pooling of wealth and
labour, has been less common than among other kinds of experiments.
Most of the anarchist intentional communities have been located in the
United States and Great Britain. Probably the first which might be
characterised as anarchic was founded by Josiah Warren. He was not only
one of the great creative thinkers within the anarchist movement, but
was also an inventor of gadgets and a social experimenter as well. For
most of his life he was interested in the intentional community movement
and indeed he lived during its hey day in America â the first three
quarters of the 19^(th) century. Warren took part in Owenâs Harmony
community and left it in 1826 believing that its mam problems were a
lack of individuality and failure to encourage self-reliance. Warren was
an individualist anarchist who did not wish to introduce communism, but
advocated a system of free contract in which each would receive
according to the time he devoted to his labours. In his Equity Store he
tried to implement his ideas by a system of goods excha ng e based on
labour notes, each worth the time in labour devoted to produce an object
or to provide some services.
In 1831, Warren, with others, organised a co-operative industrial
community in Ohio called Equity. Here it was hoped Warrenâs ideas on
education and social order would be instituted. The basic principle of
anarchy was adopted: that one might do as one pleased but always at
oneâs own cost. The experiment however soon failed, not because of
internal problems of the community, but because the region was infested
with malarial bacteria, making it impossible to carry on after 1835.
Warren did not endeavour to found another community until several years
later when he established Utopia, again in Ohio. Here each family
purchased its own house an lot and engaged in the equal exchange of
labour through notes which were used in all internal community
transactions. The economy was primarily industrial, as members engaged
in grinding corn and manufacturing wood and iron products. At one time
there were almost 100 residents. To Warren, at least, Utopia was
designed primarily to demonstrate the practicality of a free community;
permanent survival was secondary. And the colony did prosper and
operated successfully according to anarchist principles. It eventually
suffered from the Civil War and from the attraction of members and
potential members to the cheap land in the west. In the end it seems to
have disappeared by merging into the local scene as another American
community. While there were apparently still a few of the original
members around in 1875 most of them had moved on to Minnesota and
cheaper land some 25 years before.
Finally, Warren was instrumental in establishing a third community,
Modern Times. on Long Island, not far from New York City. Beginning in
185 1 , up to three acres of land were sold to an individual and on this
each settler built a house. The chief economic activity was market
gardening. Members largely engaged in growing fruits and vegetables for
the New York City market. Here as well emphasis was placed on voluntary
co-operation, exchange of labour notes, and a system of education which
stressed self-reliance, freedom and the acquisition of manual arts. By
1854, 37 families resided at Modern Times and it was proving to be a
successful experiment, both economically and politically. Because of the
publicity and easy accessibility to New York City, the colony received a
large number of curious visitors, many of whom decided to stay on. The
community refused to adopt rules which might prevent individuals from
settling within it. Consequently a variety of eccentrics came to live in
Modern Times. While they never constituted a very significant number,
they gave the colony some adverse publicity. This notoriety, however,
was not sufficiently detracting to inhibit the growing success of the
place, in contrast to some other communes which were practically
destroyed by bad publicity. The Civil War with its economic hardships
ultimately put an end to Modern Times as an experiment in voluntary
co-operation and mutualism.
What is most noticeable about these three communities is the fact that
none of them failed because of their anarchism; all ceased to exist
entirely because of external factors â conditions which would have
crushed any community.
Another anarchist communal experiment was established at Home,
Washington about 20 miles west of Tacoma. The Mutual Home Association
was formed in 1898 and acquired land, the use rights to which it sold to
members in the form of one to two acre plots. Membership was open to
those who sought âthe personal liberty to follow their own line of
action no matter how much it may differ from the custom of the past or
present, without censure or ostracism from their neighboursâ and âthe
placing of every individual on his or her own merits, thereby making
them independentâ ( quoted in Le Warne, 171).
The communitarian aspects of Home were extremely limited. A cooperative
for food supplies, a school, library and a variety of classes and clubs
for art, Esperanto, Oriental philosophy, music and physical culture were
available. In addition, there was neighbourly mutual aid. Communal
property included a meeting hall, a sea wall, sidewalks and a cemetery.
As in the Warrenite communities, most activity was left up to an
individualâs own enterprise.
Membership increased from 54 in 1899 to 213 by 1910 â its largest size.
A year later the Home Grocery Association, a co-operative, collapsed
amidst a bitter law suit and factional dispute. And by 1917, as a result
of a court case, the Home Association itself was dissolved and placed in
receivership. One faction claimed the other had usurped the organisation
by making crucial changes in the constitution of the organisation
without the approval of the other faction.
In Great Britain, during the last decade of 19^(th) century, at least
eight anarchist communes were organised. Two of these were influenced
primarily by Kropotkinâs views, while six were Tolstoyan. They were all
extremely small operations, rarely having more than a dozen members.
They also had only small acreages with market gardening as the primary
economic endeavour. The Purleigh Colony became a centre for the
publication of Tolstoyâs works which were translated by Aylmer Maude, a
member of the colony. It was one of the largest colonies, at one time
having at least 65 members.
Within a year or two after its organisation in 1896, the colony was
involved in internal conflict over how to select candidates for
membership and how to market the Tolstoy translations without becoming
overwhelmed by commercialism and profit-seeking. Apparently Purleigh was
eventually dissolved as members left, many to join the Dukhobor
communities in Canada.
One tiny colony, the Brotherhood Workshop originally established in
Leeds and in the course of time moving to E several different locations,
has managed to survive until the present day.
The Ferrer Colony founded near New Brunswick, New Jersey in 1915 was
named after the Spanish anarchist-educator, Francisco Ferrer. It was
organised by New York anarchists who continued to commute to work in the
city from their communal homes. At the same time they raised vegetables
and poultry, but the most significant communal enterprise was the
âmodern schQ.2!â, attended mainly by children of colony families, but
also by boarders as well. The school like the community was presumably
operated according to anarchic principles of freedom and individuality
and managed to suniive until the Second World War. While the colony had
distinct problems with internal dissent and conflict, the actual factor
which caused its demise was external. The United States army constructed
Camp Kilmer right next door and this created many critical problems with
which the colonists found it eventually impossible to cope. Theft and
personal safety seem to have been the main issues and the situation
encouraged members to move out. Yet Veysey claims that the military
intervention probably only speeded a process of already existent slow
disintegration anyway.
Joseph Cohen, who had been a member of the Ferrer colony, was
instrumental in the attempt to found an anarchist-communist commune in
Sunrise, Michigan in 1934. This lasted until 1937 and, as his
description suggests, it was an experiment which was harrassed by
internal conflict from the beginning. Indeed, the failure of the colony
may be seen in part as a justification of anarchist theory since its
major problems were organisational. There was an excessive delegation of
authority; administrative committees formed cliques and proceeded to act
arbitrarily and privily. In addition, this was an agricultural community
in which few of the members knew anything whatever about farming.
Finally, at Sunrise all property was held in common. This creates a more
intense and binding set of social relationships than the loose ties
characteristic of some of the experiments already discussed and so
creates a situation more vulnerable to conflict.
The 1960s were accompanied by a revival of the intentional community
movement. This recent development is probably of far greater proportions
than was experienced in the previous wave of communal experimentation
between 1820 and 1860. What is more, the types of community which
stressed individuality and personal freedom are more noticeable in the
recent wave, than in the earlier one. Literally hundreds of anarchic
communes have sprung up and disappeared with a few surviving for several
years.
As was mentioned above, any intentional community faces great odds from
the outset in terms of a variety of external factors which threaten
group success. However, the fact that some communes have succeeded in
face of these odds indicates there are characteristics internal to the
community which are of strategic significance regarding success or
failure. Some of these might be the following:
1) Minimisation of adverse publicity and external interference
Communities which have practiced eccentric sexual and dress habits, or
indulged in the use of drugs and at the same time have openly advertised
their behaviour, obviously invite failure by the sanctions of the
greater community and police interference. The community which is the
least unusual has the best chance of surviving at the hands of the
outside world. While it has been difficult for any community to
disappear from the view of the state, today this is almost an impossible
achievement.
2) Screening of members Much of communal success depends on the building
of a congenial group of members and this is enhanced to the extent that
persons applying for membership are adequately tested. This, of course,
sets up a âclassâ distinction between those who have the power to test
and admit or reject and those who are the applicants â a condition which
has not always been appealing to libertarians. Nevertheless, a survey of
communal experiments indicates how often a major cause of failure has
been an inadequate control over admission to membership. On the other
hand, the most successful communal movement of all, the Hutterites, has
the most stringent admission requirements and practically never admits
members from outside.
3) Individual responsibility Many a community has failed because of the
lack of sufficient numbers of mature and responsible members and a
surfeit of what some would call selfish, little kids. , It bears
repeating that anarchy depends upon the extent to which each member
assumes a conscientious, personal responsibility and a sense of self
reliance . Riesman refers to such individuals as being âinner directedâ
and I suspect that the successful anarchist commune is composed mainly
of these kinds of people. Many of the more enduring anarchist
experiments have been among those whose cultural milieu was nineteenth
century, English and Protestant â an inner directed type. Many Spanish
anarchists were as well. At least they often embraced an atheist
âpuritanismâ which opposed alcohol, bullfights and sexual promiscuity
(see Hobsbawm, 82, and Brenan, 157) . Brenan also saw parallels between
Spanish anarchist gatherings and revivalist meetings. There is a
relationship between âpuritanismâ and inner directedness since self
discipline among other things is basic to any âpuritanismâ . This is not
to say, however, that one must be a puritan in order to be
self-disciplined. It would be interesting to determine the extent to
which an association between inner directedness and an anarchic polity
occurs outside of the European milieu, among the other people which have
been discussed in the preceding pages.
4) Technical capability The most common ideal for a community has been a
rural, subsistence farming colony. In some regions of marginal economic
value, these communities have been a qualified success and have even
contributed to a modest economic revival of the area. Yet more
frequently, they have been economic disasters because members are
unfamiliar with either farm or rural life. Failure is most certain when
members are not only ignorant of such life, but persist in naive
romantic notions about it.
5) Communality To maximize the extent of communal life â communal
property , communal eating, communal housing, etc, â tends also to
intensify certain problems of conflict. Drawing people of varying
backgrounds together and so tying them to one another, engenders
trouble. Hutterites have been reasonably successful in a communal
venture in good part because they have tried to insure maximum cultural
homogeneity of all members. They have strictly controlled the
indoctrination of members from the cradle to the grave. At the same time
they have a tradition which is nearly half a millenium old. Those
anarchist communities of the 19^(th) and 20^(th) centuries which have
had some degree of success were âlooselyâ structured with a minimum of
communal property, communal eating, communal housing , etc â they were
neighborhoods of like-minded individuals who were not so intimately
involved with each other. There was a broad leeway for individual action
and autonomy, yet at the same time mutual aid was always available on
call and, of course , economic differences were absent.
On Makhno and the Ukrainian movement see Avrich and Voline. Material on
the Spanish Revolution is derived from Brenan, Dolgoff, Leval and
Richards. On the anarchist intentional communities see Martin for
Warrenâs experiments, LeWarne for the Mutual Home Association, Hardy for
the English communes, Veysey for the Ferrer Colony and Cohen, Joseph for
Sunrise.
Almost all hunting and gathering societies of which we have any record
are egalitarian and anarchic, having no government or state. A small
minority â typically those of the Northwest Coast of America and of
northern California â are rank societies, which nevertheless frequently
lack any governmental system. Among horticulturalists the extent of
egalitarian and anarchic polities is still widespread, but less so than
among hunter-gatherers. On the other hand, probably a minority of
pastoral societies and hardly any agricultural ones, fall into this
category. Among the latter, societies are characterised by
stratification and the state.
The egalitarian quality of any polity, anarchy included, it must be
remembered, is to be seen within the context of same sex and general age
or generation. True sexual equality is a rarity and societies which
approach it are, like the Ifugao or Dayaks, more often than not those
which have a bilateral kinship system. With it there is a lack of
differentiation or preference regarding relatives through either parent;
there is an equality or an approximate equality in terms of inheritance
through either parent and by members of either sex. Husband and wife
will tend to bring to the new household equal amounts of property. This
bilateral situation usually sets the stage for relatively equal
participation within the economic sphere (eg, Ifugao, Inuit, Samek).
Matriliny sometimes appears inferior to bilaterality in its ability to
provide the most secure basis for a relative sexual equality. This is
because in it, males are often motivated to neutralise the principle of
inheritance through females by asserting their own dominance.
Anarchy correlates with âfolkâ or gemeinschaftlich characteristics. It
is easiest where the population of the maximal effective social group is
small â probably up to 200 individuals. In it âface to faceâ relations
prevail and thus the typical diffuse sanctions of gossip, ostracism and
the like can operate most effectively. Anarchy is easiest where the
population is homogeneous and undifferentiated. Among other things this
means there is only a minimal division of labour and specialisation of
task. Such a situation where people are much the same, reduces or
minimises the opportunities for differences of opinion, sharp cleavages,
and conflict, and maximises what people have in common so that even if
there is disagreement there is still immense pressure to conform and
keep the system going. Numerous bonds of commonality bind the dissident
to the group and prevent total alienation.
Some may interpret these conditions as rigidly curtailing freedom.
Freedom, it may be said, is measured by the number of choices open to an
individual. And there are obviously fewer choices open to members of
these small scale societies. But perhaps we should question how much
less freedom exists in such societies if all the members are unaware of
a greater number of alternatives and if the same few alternatives are
available to all. How, indeed, would such societies compare to those
more âmodernâ ones in which there are presumably so many more choices,
but in fact they are not freely available to everyone?
While it may be said that anarchy occurs most frequently in a small
group situation and is probably easier to perpetuate in this condition,
this is not to say that it is impossible in a modern more complex
context. Rather it is more correct to say that it is not very probable.
Yet we do have examples of anarchic polities among peoples such as the
Tiv, Lugbara, Nuer and Tonga, numbering in the hundreds of thousands and
with fairly dense populations, often over 100 people to the square mile.
Such social orders may be achieved through a segmentary lineage system
which as we have seen already has certain parallels to the anarchist
notion of federalism. Or, as among the Tonga and some East African
pastoralists, large populations may be integrated by a more complex
arrangement which affiliates the individual with a number of cross
cutting and bisecting groups so as to extend his or her social ties over
a wide area. In other words, individuals and groups constitute a
multitude of interconnected loci, which produce the integration of a
large social entity, but without any actual centralised co-ordination.
Even within Western civilisation we have cases of large acephalous
organisations. Studies of recent social movements in the United States
have led students of such phenomena to speak of segmented polycephalous
idea-based networks (SPINs). âAn organisation chart of a SP(I)N would
look like a badly knotted fishnet with a multitude of nodes or cells of
varying sizes, each linked to all the others either directly or
indirectlyâ ( Hine, 19) . SPINs have no single leader, but each segment
has its leaders although none has any authority. Leadership is based
upon ability and persuasiveness alone. What holds the various autonomous
segments together and prevents disintegration is a wide range of
âhorizontal linkagesâ and most important of all, an ideological linkage.
That is, there is much overlapping of membership so that one person
belongs to several groups within the whole movement. There is
considerable interaction between leaders of the participating groups or
cells and leaders themselves may lead in one group and be ordinary
members in another. There is also much ritual activity in the form of
demonstrations, rallies and the like which draw all together. The real
glue of the movement is ideological: a deep commitment to a very few key
and basic tenets which are shared by all. Hine suggests that the
biological analogue of a SPIN is the earthworm. But another may be the
brain within which there is co-ordination of a myriad cells without any
ârulerâ.
SPINs are purely instrumental and pragmatic, when the idea which spawns
one loses its influence, either because it has been won, or lost, or
made obsolete, the SPIN changes or disappears. It is probably
significant to anarchist and other propagandists that SPINs do not
emerge as a result of rational planning, but âemerge out of functional
necessityâ ( Hine, 20). The parallel of SPINs to Tonga and other like
forms of social organisation is obvious. A free society modelled along
such lines may prove to be the most resistant to the growth of oligarchy
and hierarchy.
Anarchists have frequently also referred to other examples of systems
which do work without any head. Thus, we have the European railway
system, composed of several independent national rail lines, which
co-ordinate their activities so as to allow for efficiellt passage of
goods and passengers amongst several different countries. It is a system
without a head. The United States railways are owned and directed by
several separate companies which co-ordinate their operations by means
of voluntary associations of companies so as to provide for travel
throughout the country. The international postal system is of the same
acephalous nature.
It is somewhat ironic that certain defenders of a powerful national
state are at the same time advocates of an economy which not only lacks
a centralised control at the international level, but also has none at
the national level. The old liberal capitalist notion that .an economy
is, or ought to be, a self-regulating system controlled only by the
demands of a free market, is in its essence an anarchist notion.
However, it no longer remains one when it becomes a guise for exploiting
and oppressing others. In any case these several examples are what
Bohannan has referred to as âmulticentricâ power systems.
It is clear that large, relatively complex social systems or
relationships can function efficiently in an anarchic fashion. It is,
however, noticeable that none of the ethnographic cases available
suggest the operation of anarchy where there are major urban
agglomerations. Except for the brief Spanish and Ukrainian experiments,
wherever anarchy obtains it is in a rural context. Still, if anarchy can
function in a densely populated rural area, there is again the
possibility that it could operate in cities as well.
The fact that there are few anarchic polities among complex social
structures may mean that the centralised state has appeared to be a more
practicable mechanism by which to maintain social relations in such a
milieu. It may also mean that certain individuals with power are able to
anaesthetise the populace into believing their authority is
indispensable and that life is easier by abdicating responsibility to
them. The ruled are instilled with the notion that government knows
best; it is the most efficient vehicle for providing services to the
community, while the ordinary folks are neither qualified nor capable.
Like any successful institution, government also prospers by inculcating
its necessity in the populace. Once power has been accumulated into a
few hands it is more difficult to get rid of it. It has a savage
appetite and the habit of a cancer, ever expanding and enlarging. As we
have suggested elsewhere in this essay there has been, over the decades,
a gradual erosion of self-help and voluntary co-operative institutions
in our society , an erosion which has favoured an increasing
encroachment of government into the lives of all. This is not only to be
criticised as a threat to liberty, but it is equally a threat to the
everyday practice of voluntary co-operation, of self-reliance and mutual
aid between ânaturalâ groups in society.
Even if we set aside the real possibility that the masses have been
drugged by those who achieve power, we might consider that peopleâs
weighting of human values have too often been such that they elect
security over freedom, order over liberty and efficiency over
individuality. The plain fact is that anarchy requires work ,
responsibility and a big gamble. Especially today , the majority of
people are content to abdicate responsibility to government â perhaps
because they are too lazy and because they have been happily mesmerised
by those in power; perhaps, also, because their self-confidence has been
undermined by the powerful.
In Nationalism and Culture Rudolf Rocker explored the hypothesis that
wherever there is a state, there is an inhibition of human cultural
develpment and, correlatively, wherever political integration is weak
and limited to small groups cultural âprogressâ occurs. By culture
Rocker refers to the various arts: architecture, painting, music,
literature, philosophy. Unfortunately he fails to make any systematic
analysis of cultural contents or to disengage the subject from the most
subjective level. He makes only personal judgements about the value of
Roman literature or of Greek sculpture, for example. Obviously, this is
an area in which objectivity could hardly be achieved. An equally
serious problem is that Rocker seems to view with approval the ancient
Greek city state, the early Spanish commune and the small principalities
of 17^(th) and 18^(th) century Europe. It is not clear then whether he
is critical of the state or critical only of big states. Whatever the
case might be, the argument that cultural florescence is suffocated by
the state is a fascinating question, but one replete with too many
pitfalls to be answered in any convincing way.
To pursue properly Rockerâs question we would require a more precise
conceptualisation of the state and above all we would need an objective
technique by which evaluation of art forms in different cultures could
be made. This formidable task I have no intention of pursuing. A L
Kroeber in Configurations of Culture Growth attempted something of this
sort. He made no evaluations of art forms, but used the names of noted
persons as indices for plotting the rise and decline of the several arts
and sciences in the major civilisations of the world.
His aim was to determine regularities in the growth of intellectual and
aesthetic endeavours in the course of time and from one major
civilisation to another . His technique is by no means beyond reproach.
And in his conclusions, unlike others such as Spengler or Toynbee,
Kroeber finds no grand pattern or patterns, no historical universals. He
finds no significant interrelationships between the climaxes of
particular configurations, whether these be in the natural sciences,
philosophy or arts. Nor are there connections between culmination in a
given art and a total cultural climax. The crest of a scientific wave
may come before, with, or after that of a literary wave and so on.
Cultures often have great climaxes in some arts and sciences and none at
all in others. More directly as a response to Rocker, Kroeber finds
configurations and their culminations are not particularly related to
such factors as the lack or extent of political integration. Both
Kroeber and Rocker are only concerned with literate civilisations . One
wonders how Rocker, for example, would have looked upon the cultural
development among the anarchic polities discussed in this essay,
compared to others which have states.
For one thing, we have noted that in such governmentless societies there
are nevertheless numerous oppressive features which would seem to
inhibit free creative expression. What is more, the atmosphere of
freedom in and of itself is insufficient for cultural florescence. The
free do not create in a vacuum. It is sometimes pointed out that the
Australian aboriginal hunter has much time to think and create, but the
end product is not that impressive. Aside from freedom, one requires the
appropriate stimulation. The accumulation of knowledge is a certain spur
to that stimulation. As one gathers more data oneâs understanding is
eventually enhanced. New connections and relationships are seen; greater
insight is achieved and new hunches or intuitions flash into oneâs mind.
The specialisation of task is a major factor in producing a creative
atmosphere, because there is the opportunity for a number of individuals
interested in the same specific problem to exchange ideas, work together
and so inspire each other. Such inspiration is accelerated as one has
easy and free communications around the world with others of like
concerns. Now historically , specialisation of task in the division of
labour â the building up of a community of scholars or artists â is
invariably associated with some urban development and the creation of a
leisured class. This suggests, then, a stratified society which has
little place for anarchy.
No one can deny that some degree of personal freedom and individuality
is essential for innovation and cultural florescence. But contrary to
Rocker it seems that cross cultural analysis and history tell us that
humans can be creative under quite dissimilar circumstances. The
quantity of freedom which may be essential is highly variable. Certainly
no one can argue that the various anarchic polities will have greater
developments in the arts simply because they have no state.
Freedom and individuality as enunciated in the anarchist movement are
European, if not bourgeois, values which grew out of the Protestant
Reformation and have roots further back in Greek cultural tradition.
Most of the people with which we have dealt maintain an anarchic system
and display certain individualist traits but do not commonly explicate
philosophical thoughts on freedom. As a matter of fact we may well be
valuing these peoples for reasons important to us, but not to them (cf.
Colson, 1974, 62 3).[13]
A society may be free of governors, policemen, jails and law â the whole
apparatus of government â but this by no means guarantees it will be a
free and egalitarian society. The reliance of anarchic polities upon
diffuse and religious sanctions may lead to tyranny. The taunts, the
gossip, the ostracism and the physical violence which form part of such
sanctions often appear unyielding, unforgiving and cruel. And as we know
from our small town life there is little place of refuge from such
sanctions, so long as one desires to remain within the community.
Diffuse sanctions are often difficult to control and can readily get out
of hand, as with the vigilante committees of the Old West. What is more,
they may be a force of conservatism, stupidity and intolerance.
Nevertheless, we who dwell in state dominated societies not only must
submit to diffuse sanctions but also the overwhelming power of the state
as well. And in our age of sophisticated technology, particularly in the
realms of communication, transportation and electronic surveillance, the
state has access to an incredibly awesome power. The real tyrannies in
this world have been and are state tyrannies.
Anarchic techniques for maintaining order stress self-help and
self-regulation, which from the point of view of an American or European
may sometimes appear like a perpetual resort to violence in the form of
the feud. Lee has addressed the question of relative homicide rates
amongst San as compared to the United States and other areas. He
calculated the San rate at 20.3 per 100,000 person years. In the United
States there are 9.2 homicides per 100,000 population while a study of
23 Ugandan peoples showed a range of between 1 . 1 and 1 1 .6 per
100,000.with a mode of four to six. The U.S. figures would be far higher
if it medical facilities were as rudimentary as those of the San.
Moreover, it is noted that many automobile and other accidents in the
United States are intentionally homicides but are not counted as such.
Far more important is the number murdered in warfare and none are
counted in the homicide rate. Consequently Lee revises the American
figures and estimates the proper rate in the United States to be about
100 per 100,000. He also figures British, French, and German numbers
would be equally as large. However, I would suspect that his estimates
are too high. Nevertheless, his conclusions are valid, namely, that San
homicide rates are probably quite a bit less than those in the United
States and that while the state may be effective in reducing certain
kinds of violence such as individual fights, it creates new forms such
as war (Lee, 398â399).
Our survey of anarchic polities shows how widespread is the presumed
reliance upon the feud, which can be so wasteful of life in its apparent
senseless murder and mayhem. What is more, the feud provokes a prolonged
state of anxiety and psychological turmoil. However, it is well to bear
in mind that the destruction of the feud in an anarchic polity is hardly
likely to approach that of the warfare which is conducted between
states. While there are no available comparative figures, there is at
least one basic difference between feuding and the nature of war which
helps substantiate this conclusion. That is, feuds aim at evening a
score. The operating thesis is an eye for an eye. They do not aim at
annihilation of an enemy or unconditional surrender of the opponent.
Often, once someone has been injured in a feud, the fighting stops. At
least active peace negotiations will be initiated because of the
priority of the maintenance of group harmony. It is essential in any
conflict to restore that harmony as soon as possible. Litigation of any
kind is not aimed at finding blame for blameâs sake, but in satisfying
disputants and bringing peace. This entails a central role for third
party mediators or go-betweens. These respected men consult with
opposing sides until some compromise can be reached. The success of such
ventures depends on the ability of the mediator and on the sense of
moral obligation to play the game on the part of the parties involved.
Elizabeth Colson believes, however, that it is not so much actual
feuding, but fear of provoking a feud, that is an important mechanism of
social control in acephalous societies. She refers to recent reviews
made independently by E. Adamson Hoebel and Sally Falk Moore which
conclude that there is not a great deal of evidence for feuding as such,
but a great deal of evidence for fear of the feud. In anarchic polities
everyone becomes very much aware of the potential consequences of rash
behaviour. Each person learns the need for self-restraint. â ... (S)ome
people live in what appears to be a Rousseauian paradise because they
take a Hobbesian view of the situation: they walk softly because they
believe it necessary not to offend others whom they regard as dangerousâ
(Colson, 1974, 37) . âThere is âpeace in the feudâ as Gluckman has said,
but it is a peace based on the prevention of the first act rather than
on the force which leads to the final settlementâ (Colson, 1974, 43).
It has been suggested that people in anarchic polities have less to
quarrel about because there is less property and much homogeneity and
equality. But perhaps again restraint is important because ofthe fear of
consequences, so that there appears to be less quarreling (Colson, 1974,
43).
An obligation to play the game is elemental to the functioning of any
anarchic polity. And, of course, it is readily enforced by fear of
diffuse and religious sanctions. Nevertheless, those who are used to
living in a society governed by policemen and legal sanctions often fail
to appreciate the significance of the sense of obligation to play the
game as a motivating force for social order even within their own
society. We must not forget that in all human societies most members
chose to follow the rules because they want to and because they believe
in them. They would resist any attempt to lead them into non-conformity.
In any society, sanctions of whatever kind are for the tiny minority.
Were all law enforcement to be removed tomorrow there would probably be
an initial burst of crime, but after the novelty wore off it would
dissipate. At the same time, the vast majority would not be involved,
but would go about its business¡ as usual. To hold, as some apparently
do, that were the law to be removed there would occur some momentous
explosion of brutish and murderous behaviour among all the populace is,
in the first place, grossly to overestimate the present power of the
police. More importantly, it is grossly to underestimate the years of
conditioning about right and wrong to which all have been exposed and
the power of the internalised censor or conscience.
In those cases where traditional techniques for social control have been
removed suddenly or greatly relaxed, two consequences are noteworthy.
One is the extent to which voluntary mutual aid spontaneously appears
and spreads â people begin helping each other. The other consequence is
the opposite response â the one . the âlaw and orderâ supporters would
predict. That is, there is âi! rioting, looting and mayhem. But the
reason for this reaction is not because there is no police to keep
order. The reason is suggested by the kinds of people who engage in such
behaviour. These people are definitely not the members of society who
have prospered from it, nor are they the ones in positions of prestige,
power and influence: On the contrary, they are always from the ranks of
the disadvantaged and frustrated. And the revolt â which is what it is â
is an attempt at catharsis, to relieve pent up aggression and hostility
generated by a system perceived to be oppressive (whether it is âin
factâ oppressive is beside the point; it is seen to be such and that is
what counts).
It is an error to think of humans as ânaturallyâ good; it is equally
erroneous to condemn them as monsters. And radicals, of all people,
should appreciate the extent to which people are conformists.
Some criticise anarchy because its only cement is something of the order
of moral obligation or voluntary co-operation. But democracy, too,
ultimately works in part because of the same cement. And it works best
where the cement is the strongest. That is, democracy ultimately does
not operate only because of the presence of a police force. The free
elections and two-party system could never survive if they depended upon
the army and the police to enforce them. They survive because
participants have a belief in the system and a feeling of obligation to
play according to the rules. Hocart has said that government depends on
âspontaneous and incessant goodwill ... Without it governments would
collapseâ (129).
De la Boetie, Machiavelli and Spooner among others would add however,
that in any system of government submission is induced by fear and
fraud. In The Politics of Obedience: The Discourse of Voluntary
Servitude Etienne de la Boe tie devotes himself entirely to the question
of why people submit to rulers. He makes the following points:
1) People submit because they are born serfs and are reared as such.
2) People are tricked into servitude by the provision of feasts and
circuses by their masters and because they are mystified by ritual
practices and religious dogmas which aim to hide the vileness of rulers
and imbue reverence and adoration as well as servility.
3) The âmainspringâ of domination is not physical force so much as it is
a chain effect: the ruler has five or six who are his confidants and
under his control; they in turn control 600 and these in their turn
control 6,000. âThe consequence of all this is fatal indeed. And whoever
is pleased to unwind the skein will observe that not the six thousand
but a hundred thousand, and even millions, cling to the tyrant by this
cord to which they are tied. According to Horner, Jupiter boasts of
being able to draw to himself all the gods when he pulls a chainâ (78).
Also suggestive of why people obey is Lysander Spoonerâs classification
of âostensible supporters of a constitutionâ: knaves, dupes and those
who see the evil of government but do not know how to get rid of it or
do not wish to gamble their personal interests in attempting to do so.
In anarchy there is no such delusion for there is a priority placed upon
individual freedom which is absent in democracy. Democracy â granted its
concern for liberty and individualism â nevertheless like any other
system of rule, puts its ultimate priority in the preservation of the
state. When in a democracy one group threatens to withdraw â to secede â
there is always the final recourse to a âwar measuresâ act to compel
compliance and suppress ârebellionâ. To summarize, order in the anarchic
polity, is founded in diffuse sanctions. It is maintained through
self-help, self-regulation and self-restraint and these devices are
channelled by fear as well as by the motivation to make the system work
and to play the game with a minimum of friction.
Part of the democratic myth is the sanctity of majority vote. That every
so many years each voter goes to the polls and chooses a leader by
majority, and the secret ballot is the most sacred ritual of democrats.
Anarchists have argued that this is no true indication of liberty.
Rather, again as de la Boetie might have observed, the election of
rulers by majority vote is a subterfuge which helps individuals to
believe that they control the situation. The voter, in fact, chooses
from a pre-selected group and invariably there is no choice between
contrasting ideologies. The difference between major parties â those
that have a chance of victory â in any western country today is no
greater than the difference between. factions within the Communist party
in the Soviet Union or China. No one could seriously argue that there is
any ideological or any other enduring traditional philosophical contrast
between the major parties in the United States or in Canada. In addition
electors might be reminded that they are selecting individuals to do a
task for them and they have no guarantee that it will be carried out as
they desired. Above all, this job in its essence is one of forcing
obedience. Electing men to public office is like being given a limited
choice of your oppressors.
Quite often election by majority does not even occur. A candidate for
office is elected because he or she has more votes than any single other
candidate and actually receives much less than a majority of the votes
cast. In addition, the number of people who donât vote â the silent
majority â .is never taken into account. Presumably a goodly proportion
of the non-voters are not particularly enamoured of any candidate. In
1976 in one American state, Nevada, voters were given the alternative in
the Presidential election of marking an X beside âNone of the aboveâ â
the nearest thing to an anarchist vote. Slightly less than three per
cent of those who voted made this choice. In addition, 40â50% never
bothered to vote.
We frequently hear the refrain: If you donât vote you have no right to
complain. Such an argument makes the false assumption that an election
provides real choices. And, of course, it falsely assumes the legitimacy
of the process itself: that an individual is required to delegate
authority to an arbitrarily chosen few, or that an individual is
required to elect his or her own jailers.
Above all, there is the fundamental moral question about the sanctity of
the majority. Democracy, in its advocacy of majority rule, attempts to
provide an alternative to the rule of one or of a few, but it often
replaces that kind of dictatorship by one of the majority or, most
commonly, of the plurality. It assumes that right and wrong, that
morality, is determined by a majority of those who bother to vote.
Ibsenâs Enemy of the People is a vivid dramatisation of some of the
consequences of relying ilpo n majorities. Yet even aside from the fact
that minorities may know better, or have right on their side, there
remains the truth that the majority compels the minority to conform.
The anarchic polities which we have considered, as well as anarchist
theoreticians, have stressed an alternative decisionmaking device â that
of consensus. An issue is argued out until everyone agrees or acquiesces
to a given solution, or, in lieu of such agreement, the matter is set
aside, usually to be taken up at a later date. The Society of Friends
(Quakers) in our own cultural tradition has long practiced this
technique as a means of conducting business. Decisions depend upon
coming to a sense of the meeting: a point when there is no further
expressed opposition to a plan of action.
There are many arguments against this approach. It invariably entails a
considerable amount of talk. Indeed, a member of an anarchist
intentional community once said that the main product of his group was
talk. But there is nothing more human than talk and as long as people
engage in it they will not engage in violence. Consensual politics is
most commonly criticised on the grounds that business could well be
hamstrung by a stubborn minority. This is sometimes the case, but this
can also occur in a democratic legislature, which can be as inefficient
and time consuming. If one wants an efficient system one would probably
do best to appoint a select committee of technocrats to plan and
expedite legislation, but this would not be a free society; it would be
Orwellâs 1984 world.
A more credible criticism of consensual politics derives from the manner
in which it tends to work out in actuality. First, consensual politics
is effective with small groups, since it depends upon full and open
discussion of issues in a kind of face to face relationship. Secondly,
in practice there is no equal participation by everyone. Rather the
people of influence in the community impress their opinions upon others
so that individuals fall in line and at least come to a tacit agreement.
Indeed the people of influence in a community may often confer ahead of
time and agree to a position for public consumption. Anyone âholding
outâ and preventing consensus is ordinarily âprevailed uponâ by
influential individuals to see the âerrorâ of his or her ways. All these
kinds of political manoeuverings are equally as common in democratic and
other politics. The advantage of a consensual system is that ideally it
is morally superior to others in protecting minority rights. Clearly it
can become an unwieldy and coercive instrument. Anarchists themselves,
in their implementation of communes and collectives, have often found it
necessary to resort to the democratic system of majority vote.
An alternative to consensus is decision by lot. Election of ministers
and other church officers among the various Anabaptist sects has often
been by this process, in the belief that one must avoid the
possibilities of strife, which might come from the partisan politics of
majority vote elections, and leave the decision up to God who presumably
expresses himself in the lot. Election by lot assumes, however, a high
degree of group homogeneity, or at least some kind of control over who
are to be the potential candidates. One can imagine what would occur if,
in the United States, one of the candidates in a lot was a Communist and
he was in fact selected.
The search for a decision-making process which is both moral and
efficient must yet continue. At least in the smallest more homogeneous
group, or in one committed to the¡ priority of group harmony, the
consensus technique seems more advantageous.
From a review of anarchic polities, different kinds of leadership and
attitudes towards leadership emerge. In most cases leadership is looked
on positively and to become a âchiefâ is an aspiration of the many.
There are, however, a minority of societies in which it is considered
impolite or unethical to strive for paramountcy in any way. Leadership
roles are deemphasised and are not quite approved. Yet, whatever the
attitude, leadership patterns in any group do emerge and we may note at
least four different types amongst anarchic polities:
1) The Big Man,
2) The Technician,
3) The Holy Man,
4) The Old Man.
The Big Man is the one who acquires a central position of influence in
the community and a following of clients as a result of his wealth, his
ability to persuade and to orate and, occasionally, because of his
physical prowess. Here is the Yurok or Northwest Coast Indian âchiefâ.
Here also is the Big Man of New Guinea.
The Technician achieves paramountcy especially in huntergathering
societies. Thus one who is a good hunter collects around him a following
which is willing to do his bidding and be fed, as among Athabascan
Indian bands of the Canadian Sub-Arctic or among the Inuit.
Modifications of this role are found among the San and Pygmies. And the
Samek headmap is a master technician for a pastoral people.
The Holy Man, through some religious ideology, is accepted as a
prestigious person to whom all voluntarily defer, particularly as a
mediator of disputes. Here we have the Nuer leopard skin chief or the
maraboutic families and lineages of the Imazighen. Also of a slightly
different order is the Inuit shaman who acts not so much as mediator,
but as a manipulator of people, often for his own ends (a role which
mixes the Holy Man and Big Man concepts).
The Old Man is the leading member of the community simply by being the
senior male member of the kin group. While the Big Man and the
Technician are more frequently achieved statuses and the Holy Man may be
either an achieved or an ascribed one, that of the Old Man is ascribed,
although even here there may be the slight element of achievement. Thus
some elders may be more pre-eminent because of ability in speech, having
more wives, more wealth, more sons, or knowledge of ceremony and
esoteric doctrine. The Old Man syndrome is characteristic of Australians
and particularly of the ¡ African horticultural societies. (Tiv,
Lugbara, Konkomba, Tallensi, etc.). Some segmentary patrilineal systems
combine the Old Man and the Holy Man syndromes, as with the Arab
Bedawin.
Earlier it was noted that authority might be considered as rational or
irrational. In connection with the above four kinds of leadership it
would appear that only the Technician represents a rational form. The
others also have clear elements of rationality, but have at the same
time irrational or arbitrary qualities. This is most true of the role of
the Old Man.
In Max Weberâs classification of types of authority, both Big Men and
Holy Men fall into the âcharismaticâ type, while Old Men combine the
gerontocratic and patriarchal attributes of âtraditionalâ authority.
Weber does not really make provision for the Technician (Weber, 324 ff).
Conservative theory holds that the tribute offered the ruler is fully
reciprocated by the services of the ruler to the people. This argument
has been challenged by persons from a broad spectrum of ideologies, from
the democrats to anarchists. Indeed, it seems only the height of
self-delusion to contend that all forms of rulership are reciprocal. How
could the relationship between an ancient Egyptian peasant and a pharoah
conceivably be seen as a reciprocal one? Where is the reciprocity in the
enormous wealth which is yearly handed over to the British royal family
and the positive services it presumably offers? Does not every ruler
acquire special privilege and an essentially non-reciprocal relationship
with clients or subjects? Indeed, we may, with Pierre Clastres, say that
another way of defining rule is as a non-reciprocal relationship. The
ruler is the paramount example of that status.
Henry Orenstein discusses two types of asymmetrical reciprocity: the
centripetal and centrifugal. The first is the leader as servant and is
best exemplified m Pierre Clastresâ analysis of South American Indian
chiefs. Here it will be recalled the chiefâs advantage is seen as a
breaking of the fundamental law of social relationships â reciprocity â
resulting in a suspicion of power and a desire to contain it.
Paradoxically, the chief is contained by his own¡ asymmetrical
reciprocity: his excess of wives places him in perpetual debt to the
community, so that he must forever be a servant of the people and can
never affirm coercive power as a true ruler. This conception of the
centripetal âchiefâ works against governmental and state organisations.
Orenstein thoroughly confuses the issue when he suggests that
centripetal leaders and rulers include such widely variant persons as a
South American Indian chief, a Roman emperor and the elected official in
a democracy. If this were in fact true, it would make the concept of
centripetality useless and meaningless. The centripetal leader is
correctly a leader within the most pristine of anarchic polities: he is
a servant whose clientele may, if they choose, ignore him with impunity.
What democratic elected official or Roman emperor could ever be ignored?
Even the command of the justice of the peace must be obeyed on pain of
punishment.
In centrifugality the ruler or leader maintains a type of relationship
which can command obedience and services. What we have called the Big
Man and the Holy Man ordinarily have centrifugal relationships. It is
out of this kind of context that we have the creation of the despot and
of government. But before exploring this issue further, I would like to
suggest that perhaps some types of leaders in anarchic polities are
neither centripetal nor centrifugal. Perhaps leaders of certain polities
only engage in the ordinary reciprocal relations of everyday people.
Consider leadership among the Pygmies. Here it seems to be only of a
temporary sort, highly amorphous and âmulticentricâ, always surrounded
by a reluctance to lead or to be aggressive. There seems to be no
special advantage to be derived from leadership and the leader is not
indebted to his people. The Pygmy leader appears to embody the best
anarchic ideal, because he minimises leadership characteristics and
retains normal reciprocal relationships with others.
As we have seen from our survey of anarchic polities, the seeds of
tyranny and government are readily observable in the performance of many
leaders. The Tiv, Lugbara and other African polities, as well as the
Australians exemplify the potential tyranny of Old Men. The patriarchal
system, it might be argued, does have a certain rationality, in that it
is the elders who have lived the longest and so presumably have acquired
the most experience in living, as well as having had the greatest
opportunity to learn the wisdom of the ancestors. But it is irrational
in that it assumes that all those in âelderâ status are automatically
always superior.
By its nature the old man syndrome alone cannot perpetuate an elite
power group as a dynasty. A man assumes power as an older person and
retains it for a few short years at which time he must yield to new
persons who were his subordinates. Indeed, in an age graded society such
as the Tiv, a man assumes leadership for a short span of a decade, when
he must retire to inactivity and now find himself in a social setting
where those who were his subordinates are now leaders. Another reason
patriarchy in this anarchic setting may not lead to government per se is
that the entire system is intimately attached to kinship. Patriarchs or
elders are always grandfathers of some kind. One is not obligated to
obey those one does not address with a paternal type kin term.
The germ of state development might find a more fertile location in the
role of the Big Man. In New Guinea this leader acquires a body of
clients which he is able in some cases to command. Mair has contended
that the foundation of a state could be in this development by a leader
of a dependent and loyal body of supporters. Slightly different is the
individual among the Inuit who is able to lord it over a community by
his own physical force or use of dreaded supernatural powers.
With the Big Man, anarchy can then degenerate into tyranny. What
sometimes occurs may be seen as an abortive attempt to introduce a
governmental-state system. It is invariably a failure because there is a
definite ambivalence within the community towards authority, so that if
established it regularly inspires rebellion and the Big Man who tries to
be the bully is most often murdered. Thus, the situation returns to an
acephalous or more anarchic condition. In addition, there is no
precedent for establishing a succession pattern so as to perpetuate a
dynasty. It is also clear the New Guinean and other systems do not
develop permanent states out of their Big Man leadership pattern because
there is no adequate economic, technological or organisational base. The
New Guinea Big Man is limited by the productive capability of his
dependents and this is inhibited by lack of a more complex technology.
Nor can one expect to control extensive territories with the available,
very simple, methods of communication and transportation. At the same
time the Big Manâs power is maintained and extended only through a
network of personal contacts. There is no organisation of loyal
bureaucrats to sustain the realm. The difference between king and Big
Man is fundamental: kings receive tribute and submission; Big Men must
rely on support (Schneider, 207) . âRather than being a stage in the
evolution of government, the state, or rather the monarchy, is but a
point on one end of a spectrum whose other end is stateless societies
containing only big menâ (Schneider, 207).
Leaders among the Ifugao represent yet another type of Big Man. In their
role as go-betweens they have the legitimate right to command contending
parties to mediate, on threat of violence. Government then, in a most
limited sense, has been instituted.
Clastres believes that the state cannot rise out of the âchieflyâ role,
but this view requires some modification. First, it is least likely to
arise in those cases which clearly fit the qualifications of centripetal
leadership. Here it does not arise because the community is vigilant in
restraining the chief. Nevertheless the Anuak village chief exemplifies
a leader of this sort who, under certain circumstances can apparently
expand his authority. Secondly, the sort of anarchic leadership
characterised by the Pygmies is even less conducive to state
development. Not only does the community frown upon any vigorous
exercise of authority, but individuals have been conditioned to avoid
the aggressive affirmation of leadership. Thirdly, the state as a
permanent institution has difficulty in appearing in those centrifugal
systems such as in New Guinea for reasons we have just enumerated. On
the other hand, a governmental institution may be more likely to appear
in connection with certain kinds of mediator roles as among the Ifugao.
But, also significant in this regard are the roles of Holy Men. To be
sure, Clastres sees these as different from his centripetal style chiefs
and recognises the possible emergence of government in the role of
prophet among the Guarani Indians in South America.
Hocart has argued that the earliest government-like functions were
assumed by ritual specialists, some of whom, in the course of time,
become fully fledged rulers of states as part of the general process of
increasing specialisation in the division of labour. In Marxist theory
power derives primarily, if not exclusively, from control of the means
of production and distribution of wealth, that is, from economic
factors. Yet, it is evident that power derived from knowledge â and
usually âreligiousâ style knowledge â is often highly significant, at
least in the social dynamics of small societies. The Australian leader
derives his power by his control of esoteric ceremonial knowledge, the
Inuit shaman by his control of curing techniques and the manipulation of
the dark arts. The Nuer leopard skin chief has the power of the curse as
do the elders and rainmakers among the Lugbara. The foundation and
legitimacy of the Anuak chiefs roleâ is in its ritual and supernatural
significance. Economic factors are hardly the only sources of power.
Indeed, we see this in modem society as well, where the capitalist owner
does not wield total power. Rather technicians and other specialists
command it as well, not because of their economic wealth, but because of
their knowledge. For the anarchic polities we have looked at it is clear
that the functionaries with knowledge are often entitled to invoke
sanctions which at least border on the legal. As was just noted above
the Ifugao case as well as the Nuer and Lugbara suggest that the germs
of government often first appear as the mediator role is transformed
into a judiciary one, which also has ancillary police-like powers. A
separate and distinct police force would presumably be a later
development.
Countless authors agree that the state arises with social
differentiation . and increasing social complexity. Such views often
implicitly argue that the state becomes a necessity as an integrative
device. This is apparently the thesis of Wittfogel, who in his hydraulic
theory of state origin correlates the rise of the state with the
development of extensive irrigation systems. The latter necessitate
co-ordination and the state is the grand co-ordinator. Much data has
been assembled to demonstrate that complex social arrangements, whether
irrigation works (eg, the Ifugao) or the international postal system,
are co-ordinated in lieu of the state. In addition, of course, the fact
that the state does appear constantly in connection with highly complex
social arrangements does not mean that it must occur, nor that it ought
to appear.
Oppenheimer among others argued that the state originates out of
conquest. The expansion of one group so as to conquer another gives rise
to an apparatus aimed at maintaining dominatiqn. The major drawback to a
conquest theory of state origin is that before a group embarks on the
war path it has already become a state. The examples Oppenheimer
presents are of social entities which were states when they commenced
expansion.
Anarchic polities engage in hostilities which are best not confused with
warfare, but rather should be called feuding. This is because, among
other things, true warfare entails the organisation of armies with a
chain of command and with the intent of subjugating an enemy and
occupying his territory. For those societies we have
Investigated above, it is apparent that some have the germs of
governmental organisations, but they engage in neither real warfare nor
in conquest. In other words, some kind of governmental structure is
perhaps an essential prerequisite to engaging in the true warfare
necessary for conquest. One requires at least the rudiments of an
administrative system to order new subjects about. At the same time the
truth of Oppenheimerâs theory is that pursuit of warfare and conquest
invigorates a burgeoning state and helps elaborate the administrative
hierarchy. State and conquest are best seen as mutually interdependent
phenomena which âfeed backâ on each other.
Intrasocial conflict affords another explanation of state development.
The Marxist theory of class conflict is the most notable of such
theories. It argues that where there is an economically dominant class
there is a state and where there is no state there is no class system.
Marxist theory identifies property accumulation with the evolution of
the state. And such a correlation was made as well by anarchists.
Kropotkin and Bakunin both believed the abolition of capitalism â
private property â was a prerequisite to the building of an anarchist
society. Proudhon, however, saw that private property, which is used to
intimidate, exploit and subdue others was in truth âtheftâ and
incompatible with anarchy, but individual property not so employed was
not. Our survey of anarchic polities seems to substantiate Proudhonâs
view. The societies we have encountered recognise individual ownership
of important resources and where, as in New Guinea, those resources are
frequently used as devices to create a body of dependents we have âBig
Menâ who take on a more tyrannical character than leaders in other
anarchic polities who do not seek to acquire economic control over
others. [14]
The Marxists Barry Hindiss and Paul Hirst have claimed that with âthe
primitive and advanced communist modes of productionâ there is no state
because there are no social classes. Such a view ignores the
bureaucratic-managerial elite as a class, thus unveiling one of the
weaknesses of Marxist theory. That is, the bureaucrats as non-property
holders are not seen as a social class and so are not seen as worthy of
further consideration. Yet they are nevertheless a potent social force
which perpetuates the division of society into the powerful and the
powerless. Such observations are not intended as a demonstration of the
falsity of a class theory of state origin. Rather they are intended to
question the absoluteness and dogmatism with which this theory is
sometimes enunciated. Neither government nor social class can be
developed to any extent without the other also appearing. The case of
ancient Iceland demonstrates that social classes can exist without the
state, but not for long. Governmental functions restricted to the local
headman as a kind of proto-state require no class of rulers, but a full
blown state with government applied to extensive areas and large
populations does. And those who control and own the societyâs wealth
will certainly be part of the ruling class.
Often leaders in stateless societies have been transformed into
governmental officials as a consequence of contact with already existing
nation-states. It was noted above that people bordering on Chinaâs
northern frontier no doubt created states as a consequence of the role
of their notables as intermediaries, especially in the trading activity.
Among Afghan tribes men of influence assume the role of chief liaison
agent between their own people and a neighboring state. Increasingly
they come to accumulate the trappings of governmental authority
themselves and so help create states. Similarly, European colonial
powers in the process of their territorial aggrandizement on contact
with people in stateless societies recognized certain individuals as
âchiefsâ of the âtribeâ and insured for them formalized power positions.
Thus, stateless societies are either transformed into states themselves
or are absorbed into existing states.
All the relevant case material presented here concerns societies which
for the most part exhibit only rudimentary forms of government and
social class. They suggest, then, that in what might be seen as the
earliest phases of state development there are alternate paths of social
change. Ronald Cohen has written: â... [T]here is no clear cut or simple
set of causal statements that explains the phenomenon of state
formation... The formation of states is a funnel-like progression of
interactions in which a variety of pre-state systems responding to
different determinants of change are forced by otherwise unresolvable
conflicts to choose additional and more complex levels of political
hierarchy.â Once this is achieved there occurs a convergence of forms
towards the early state (142). Yet clearly involved in the beginnings of
state formation is an inter-dependent development of government and
social class tied to an economy which is able to provide the means to
sustain an elite class. Hierarchy, submission and tribute are
characteristics of any fully-developed state and these cannot properly
bloom until society has the proper wherewithal, economic and otherwise
âto deliver the goodsâ
Even more fundamental ingredients for state formation are the individual
will to power and the creation of a division between leaders and led.
From these basic elements we have noted several different paths for
further elaboration in the direction of the state. Thus leaders, in
their capacity as mediators may acquire authority to impose legal
sanctions, first possibly in a restricted sense and eventually
broadening the realm of control. Other kinds of leaders may build a
loyal body of dependents who in turn legitimise the use of force by the
leader. In these cases wealth and knowledge are important bases for
establishing oneâs credit as a ruler. Menâs associations may assume
governmental functions and if these are in the hands of age grades we
might expect the system to be more democratic. In some instances we have
encountered, such as New Guinea, the seed of statism has been planted,
but has never truly germinated. In others, as the Tiv or the Ibo, there
is only the most limited growth; there is an anomalous condition with
the barest rudiments of the state. State development may be a subtle and
insidious process by which the distinction between leader and led is
transformed into one between ruler and ruled. In looking at anarchic
polities one can only discern at best the very beginnings of this
development â the prelude and first lines of the first act in the drama.
I suspect that one of the most common scenarios for state (and class)
development commences in the initial anarchic polity with the existence
of some kind of âbig manâ who was at one and the same time a recognized
mediator of disputes, an impressive manipulator of supernatural forces
and above all a central figure in a redistribution system in which he
held impressive feasts for and made loans to a considerable number of
individuals who consequently became his dependents and retainers. As the
big man thus enhanced his wealth and power, trade increases, labor
specialization becomes more widespread and populations increase,
particularly as a consequence of improved productivity. The social order
then becomes more heterogeneous, composed of groups with increasingly
divergent interests and outlooks so that intergroup conflict becomes
more common and more important. Thus, the mediator and mystagogue roles
of the âbig manâ are augmented. He can turn some of his dependents and
retainers into armed guards and enforcers abandoning his role as
mediator for that of arbitrator-ruler. Thus, human societies which once
were all egalitarian, acephalous and anarchic entities are transformed
into hierarchic, authoritarian states. At the same time some of the more
favoured henchmen of the âbig manâ, through their own machinations and
especially through being able to establish themselves as centers of
lesser redistribution systems are able to increase their own wealth and
power so that they are increasingly differentiated from the rest of
society. An elite class of controllers of wealth and power with the âbig
manâ at the top is created over a subordinate class of producers of
wealth.
Finally, Pierre Clastres has made an interesting observation on the
phenomenon of state formation, although he might slightly overstate the
case. He maintains that the shift from huntinggathering to Neolithic
agriculture is not a decisive revolutionary change since old patterns of
social organisation were not altered that radically. In addition the
Middle American states were dependent upon an agricultural system of the
same technical level as the anarchic âsavagesâ of the forest. The real
revolution is the rise of the state and of âhierarchical authorityâ ,
not economic transformation. â... (P)erhaps one must acknowledge that
the infrastructure is the political, and the superstructure is the
economicâ (171) . Thus, is Marx turned on his head.
Whether anarchy has any future requires us first to consider how to
dispense with the state which now prevails everywhere. Secondly, we may
inquire into the general pattern of historic and cultural trends
regarding state development and the prospects for a libertarian age from
that vantage point.
Three general techniques for abolishing the state and government have
been most commonly proposed by anarchists. One advocates undermining the
state by the creation of a multitude of voluntary associations whose
functioning will make the state superfluous. Another favours violent
revolutionary overthrow. A third approach is non-violent direct action,
which includes such a syndicalist technique as the labour strike. Why
anarchists avoid electoral politics should be obvious from what has
already been said about anarchism. But, in short, anarchists have no
faith in such a technique because they do not believe one can defeat an
enemy by joining him.
The attempt to make the state superfluous was popular amongst the early
19^(th) century anarchists. Proudhon hoped to initiate at least the
decline of the French state by a proliferation of mutual associations
which would loan money interest free. Several Americans including Josiah
Warren had similar ideas, particularly entailing monetary reform and
mutualism, which were seen as paths to the free society. Much later,
Gustav Landauer wrote: âThe state is not something which can be
destroyed by a revolution, but it is a condition, a certain relationship
between human beings, a mode of behaviour. We destroy it by contracting
other relationships, by behaving differently.â
Another approach along these same lines is the intentional community ..
Indeed, Josiah Warren saw his communities as demonstration experiments
which people would be able to observe, be impressed by and copy. Always
the anarchic intentional community is an attempt to âcontract other
relationshipsâ , to âbehave differentlyâ and find alternatives to the
state.
But many who seek to âbuild the new within the shell of the oldâ are
essentially indifferent to the ultimate fate of the state. For many who
have participated in intentional communities the motivation is a
personal one: of finding immediately a different, and presumably better,
life for themselves and their families. They are unconcerned about its
potential consequences upon the state, or at least that is of very
secondary significance. Yet, some who are interested in building mutual
associations in part as devices to undermine the state, simultaneously
pronounce the obvious anarchist truth that the state is an institution
which will not voluntarily abdicate its power. Those in power would
never come to see themselves as superfluous and, as they have done on
countless prior occasions, they will act to suppress any perceived
threat to their positions. The state in a modern capitalist society, as
in Canada and the United States, may readily tolerate, even encourage,
credit unions and co-operatives and any number of other mutualist
voluntary associations. This support would soon turn to suppression if
such movements became a threat to the banking and corporate interests of
the country. In addition, such organisations readily tend to become
âestablishmentâ oriented. Rather than having a modifying effect upon
their environment, it is the environment which modifies them in a more
conservative direction. Co-operatives, for example, are notorious for
becoming as large, as bureaucratic and nearly as capitalistic as the
more traditional organisations. Do not misunderstand. I am all in favour
of mutual associations and of Landauerâs call to contract other
relationships. However, such techniques are extremely limited and it is
hard to see how, by themselves, they can produce a transformation to a
stateless society because, by one means or another, no state will permit
it to happen.
Another course of action suggested by anarchists is violent overthrow of
the state. We have seen the use of violence as a diffuse sanction
amongst various anarchic polities. Yet this seems inconsistent with an
ideological commitment to the doctrines of anarchism. Violence is the
technique of the state and the ultimate form of coercion. Those who
adopt it as a means cannot help but be tainted by its use. A main reason
for the anarchist rejection of participation in the governmental process
is that it will have a corrupting effect upon individuals, turning them
into politicians seeking power and personal glory. No less can be the
case for those who take up violence in the attempt to find justice. Yet
the strongest arguments against anarchist resort to violence is that any
effective violence necessitates a military structure which must clearly
be the most anti-anarchist form of organisation conceivable. Can one
imagine an army organised on anarchist principles of voluntary
co-operation and consensus? The implications and logical consequences of
pacifism would seem to be anarchism. The view of some Quakers that there
can be a non-violent state or government is self-contradictory since the
state is by definition based upon violence. Otherwise it is not a state
and must be a polity based on other than legal sanctions. Conversely
anarchists who would be the first to recognise this inherent nature of
the state, have often justified war and in this sense have sought to use
statist methods to abolish the state.
Bakunin expected the revolutionary zeal of the masses to be spurred on
by a group of selfless devotees who had no care for themselves or their
own glory. They were to be a body of strong, educated personalities who
would not seek to lead, master or direct the masses. Instead, they would
learn what the people desired, articulate it and, with their broader
knowledge and understanding, better be able to aid in pushing the
revolution towards the goals set by the masses. This vanguard would be
an anonymous and invisible body blended into the background. Thus, in
part is the justification for Bakuninâs romance with secret
conspiratorial groups. The revolutionary vanguard Bakunin saw being
drawn from the large number of âdeclassed intellectualsâ and middle
class students, âchildren of peasants or the lower middle class, the
children of unimportant civil servants and bankrupt gentryâ â any who
have no chance of pursuing a career or position (Lehning, 189). Lenin
was influenced by this Bakuninist idea, but as a ârealistâ his vanguard
had lost all the high-minded altruism which Bakunin, in his romantic and
naive way, held to be imperative. In contrast to the fascists, whose
elite is a vanguard of heroes, Bakuninâs is a vanguard of saints.
In general, any proposal to build the barricades is today a purely
romantic notion which is strategically stupid. Military technology has
become so sophisticated and expensive that only governments can invest
in it and support it. A guerrilla army would find itself faced with
overwhelming odds and its only hope would be to incite the military to
join the revolution â a most unlikely event.
The third technique, that of non-violent direct action, is the viable
alternative to violent revolution. It requires much self-discipline and
patience, demanding that one be satisfied with miniscule successes and
slow transformation. Certainly this, coupled with the. movement to build
voluntary, mutualist associations, is the only approach having much
feasibility. Yet no prospects can be promising, particularly when one
looks at the general trend of history.
The anarchic polities we have discussed in this essay are largely
phenomena of the past. Anarchies have been transformed into subject
entities by colonialist states and then gobbled up by third world
nations. Their old social structure has been modified so as to
accommodate to the proper functioning of the modern state. The lineage
elder is now a âchief, who may call upon the local constabulary for aid;
the mediator becomes the judge who now commands. âIndigenousâ anarchies
are a dying breed, an endangered species. This process seems to support
the contention that the main thrust of history is towards the creation
of states and authoritarian forms. It is a movement from
decentralisation to centralisation, from small to big. While we may cite
case after case of the growth of states out of an earlier anarchy and
have noted the several germs of statism in our examples, the evidence of
anarchy evolving out of the state is next to non-existent. Indeed, not
only is the trend towards state organisation but it is towards bigger
and fewer states enveloping the world.
Recently Robert Carniero showed how the number of polities (of all
kinds) in the world has, since at least 1000 BC, continually declined.
âAnd not only has there been a decrease in the number of autonomous
political units in the world; the tendency has accelerated. It is quite
clear that the rate of decrease in the number of independent political
units between Ab 500 and AD 1976 was much greater than it was between
1000 BC and AD 500â (Carniero, 214). Overall, during the 3,000 year
period from 1000 BC to the present, he estimates the decline has been
from several hundred thousand polities to 157 in 1976. We may cavil that
the latter figure is too small since it includes only the worldâs
nation-states and fails to take into account the fact that in many parts
of the world there are cultural groups which persist as autonomous
political entities despite the claim of some nation to the territory.
Still the decline is dramatic and, what is more, it would be yet greater
for anarchic polities since we must assume that a high proportion of
societies in 1000 BC were of this type, while few if any are today.
Carniero attempts to project the approximate time we must anticipate the
creation of a single world state. He arrives at, not 1984, but about
2300. Such projections can be discounted as rather fanciful, but what
cannot be overlooked is the clear major trend towards fewer and bigger
states. The usual argument against anarchy runs something like this:
people are not perfect; they require constraints; the bad need to be
confined in jails. The moment one institutes a free society based on
voluntary co-operation there will arise people who will seek to take
advantage of the situation and accumulate power themselves. Further, as
societies become larger and more dense in population and more
heterogeneous, the problems of order and decision-making become too
complex to be left to consensual techniques and diffuse sanctions. So
from this vantage point as well there are pressures to centralise,
institutionalise and formalise authority patterns. Anarchist
theoreticians have long warned of the dangers entailed in the assumption
of power even by the most idealistic. Bakunin particularly attacked
Marxism along these lines. He was rightly somewhat more than suspicious
of the âdictatorship of the proletariatâ and correctly predicted that it
could be ânothing else but despotic rule over the toiling masses by a
new, numerically small aristocracy of genuine or sham scientistsâ (Maxim
off, 287) . Later W Machajski, a Polish participant in the Bolshevik
Revolution, came to similar conclusions about the Soviet Union, for as
he saw it the proletarian revolution had been transformed into a
dictatorship of the party hacks. Arguments along these lines were
further expanded by Max Nomad.
In 1911 Roberto Michels published his Political Parties in which he
expounded the âiron law of oligarchyâ . This law states that all
organisations develop in the direction of increasing authoritarianism,
bureaucratic and oligarchic rule. Whoever says organisation says
oligarchy. To demonstrate his thesis Michels analysed the history of the
several European political parties. Later Seymour Lipset and others
sought to refine Michelsâ interpretation by studying a labour union, the
International Typographers Union, which did not seem to follow the
pattern of the inevitable move towards oligarchic rule. From this
investigation Lipset and his cohorts suggested some conditions which
might preclude a bureaucratic and authoritarian development.
Interestingly enough they entail little an anarchist theoretician might
not have told him: small units, a variety of autonomous local voluntary
associations, several interest groups none of which can control or
monopolise power, no great differences in socio-economic status and a
general state of economic security for all, an educated population and
one which shows a high degree of participation in communal affairs, a
high sense of group solidarity, and leaders who are not given much
salary or status difference. In other words, âchiefsâ must be servants â
impotent co-ordinators in a centripetal relationship. I would also
suspect that a conscious will of the membership to preserve a free
society is no small factor in this process.
Perhaps the Industrial Workers of the World is another example which
deviates from Michelsâ law and for reasons similar to those Lipset found
for the typographers. Yet while we may scout about looing for
exceptions, the prevailing directions seem in accord with the âiron law
of oligarchyâ. Thus, among labour unions, for the one or two which have
avoided this direction there are 100 which have not.
Aside from the general trend for complex organisations to develop
internal changes which produce oligarchy, there is yet another type of
observable trend which commences with voluntary associations and ends as
well in an authoritarian structure. This pattern was pointed out by Bert
Buzan in a paper on âVoluntary Co-operation and Social Democracy: The
Case of 20^(th) Century Neo-Populismâ delivered at the International
Symposium on Anarchism (1980). Buzan reviews the history of the
farmer-populist movement in the United States between 1880 and 1920 and
notes that it originated with various apolitical voluntary mutual aid
associations. The most important of these were co-operatives aimed at
marketing farm products. These, however, met with the concerted
opposition of vested economic interests. Thus railroads refused to carry
their goods; land and buildings were not available for sale or rent for
grain elevators and warehouses. Because of this sabotaging by capitalist
enterprises the members turned increasingly to electoral politics
spawning the Peoples Party, FarmerLabour Party and Non-Partisan League.
In their devotion to seeking reform through government, they moved away
from voluntary co-operation to depend more on formal legislation. At the
same time, of course, the co-operative organisations themselves became
large, bureaucratic and political lobbying groups (in line with Michelsâ
predictions). Thus, in addition to an internal dynamic which pushes an
organisation towards oligarchy, there is the external process which
propels individuals to abandon those voluntary associations they have in
favour of dependence upon bureaucratic and governmental ones.
Now the question arises, perhaps the movement towards centralised
oligarchy is only part of a long term historical process of oscillation
between decentralisation and centralisation. Yet it is difficult to find
examples of trends towards decentralisation â at least of a libertarian
nature. Periods of so-called cultural or organisational decay in history
may suggest this sort of trend. But what trends do occur in these
situations is the creation of a number of petty despotisms out of one
which had existed before. Decentralisation is not accompanied by
freedom. The revolutions and revolts of history and the decay of social
systems have invariably entailed the replacement of one kind of
despotism by an another. Or what is a process of decay of one polity is
the basis for the creation of another, so that, for example, the
appearance of Clovisâ Frankish kingdom and of the Umayyad caliphate
follow on the heels of the decline of Rome. Power abhors a vacuum. A few
South American Indian societies referred to above appear to have become
anarchic as a consequence of a general process of tribal disintegration.
Yet this situation seems uncommon and is limited to extremely tiny
polities. Those few societies such as the Pygmies, which provide not the
slightest hint of embarking upon the course towards a governmental or
state organisation, are also small and highly homogeneous without any
specialisation of task. They exemplify that rarity wherein members have
been diligent in restraining the forces of authority and wherein events
have been such that members have not been detracted from that noble
pursuit. Perhaps one must conclude that the main thrust of history is
towards centralised states with occasional minor âpulsationsâ of
reaction â slight and temporary reversals or people running off on
alternate paths. Perhaps also the last decade and a half has experienced
a feeble resurgence of this kind in parts of the Western world. Thus,
there is not only the enormous increase in the number of communal
experiments, but there is the movement of individuals âback to the
landâ, to simplification of life and revolt against the establishment.
More important has been the appearance of mass social movements based
upon âsegmented polycephalous idea-based networksâ . Unfortunately these
several activities remain largely confined to the offspring of
middle-class white society alienated from the values of their parents.
Back in 1963 Paul Goodman in People or Personnel pointed out how
centralisation has now made industry inefficient, creating excessive
congestion and problems of transportation and communication. With the
diffusion of electric power it is possible and more sensible to
decentralise production. This theme has been reaffirmed continually.
Schumacher harks back to Kropotkin and Goodman, noting how âsmall is
beautifulâ. Recognition that small group operations and decentralisation
can be more productive and obviously more humane, is coupled today with
some growing recognition of the inefficiency and alienating effects of
large impersonal, centralised organisations. Recently Marshall McLuhan
offered a mixed prediction for the 1980s. It was mixed in the sense that
part foresees greater decentralisation by the expanded use of the home
computer, TV, telephone and other âelectric softwareâ. But it is not
necessarily a prediction of individual liberation in that with this
expansion of new technology McLuhan sees a further disappearance of
personal identity â the disembodiment of individuals and a new form of
government by âpollstergeistsâ.
In spite of the various ârecognitionsâ, hopes and predictions, and in
spite of the movements into the intentional community or out to the
land, states continue to become more powerful and centralisation goes on
essentially unabated. Certain biological species are reputed to have
become so specialised that they cannot adapt to changed environmental
conditions and so become extinct. Perhaps there is a parallel to the
potential fate of those social systems which become so utterly complex
and overburdened with top down administration that they collapse.
Hopefully, out of the remains might arise, like a Phoenix, a simplified
and decentralised system. But would this only generate its own tyranny?
Humans as intelligent beings have some control over their own destiny.
As they increase their knowledge and understanding in the world and,
particularly, of their own behaviour, they should better be able to
manipulate their environment and modify their social order so as to make
life more agreeable. Yet knowledge and understanding are intimately tied
up with values and priorities of values. They are circumscribed as well
by the apparent fact that humans appear to be rather conservative beasts
willing to change from the known to the unknown and the untried only in
the direst emergency. Therefore, while presently there may be a greater
realisation of the possibility of a â1984 worldâ, other priorities than
freedom and individuality may have precedence. Further, this possibility
is not perceived as an immediate and overwhelming threat. When we
consider the numbers who persist in such a simple thing as cigarette
smoking, in spite of the overwhelming evidence of its relation to
cancer, how can we expect people to be concerned about such more
abstract and apparently less obvious matters as threats to personal
freedom?
Not only is anarchy unlikely to be achieved because of the improbability
of dispensing with the state, but even given the abolition of that
institution, the prospect for subsequent modes of organisation remaining
decentralised, autonomous and free is as doubtful as the likelihood of
the participants being truly dedicated to âfreedom, equality and justice
for allâ.
I have already earlier in this book suggested the kind of free society
which might be more durable and resistant to corruption. Namely, it
would be one in which each person and group was involved in a complex
web of mutual relations such that each bond within the web would act as
a counter-balancing force to every other. In this way every participant
would be constrained and unable to expand his or her realm at the
expense of any other.
Proudhon saw human societies as being engaged in a struggle between
âfreedomâ (anarchy) and âauthorityâ. But he was imbued with the rather
naive 19^(th) century notion of progress and optimism. He had faith in
the eventual victory of the forces of freedom. An Australian group â the
Sydney Libertarians â has, one might say, adapted Proudhon to the latter
part of the 20^(th) century. They envisage a perpetual struggle between
âfreedomâ and âauthorityâ; neither one of which will be annihilated.
It appears, indeed, that we are left with a politics of perpetual
protest. There cannot be any point at which those dedicated to liberty
can sit back in security and assume the world is in peace, harmony and
freedom. That a truly free society may never be attained or, if
achieved, would have the most tenuous life is clearly no excuse to
abandon the struggle. If we resign ourselves to what is, there would
hardly be much point in living. And, even if anarchy were to be
achieved, eternal vigilance would be the bare minimum price for even a
modicum of success. Despite what the international anthem of the
revolutionary class might say there is no final battle. The battle is
forever.[15]
AVRICH, PAUL (ed), The Anarchists in the Russian Revolution, Cornell,
1973.
BARCLAY, HAROLD B, âSegmental Acephalous Network Systemsâ, The Raven,
II, 3 , 1989, also Guru Nanak Journal of Sociology, VIII, 1 ,1987.
BARTON, RALPH , Ifugao Law, University of California Publications in
American Archaeology and Ethnology, XV, 1919.
BERNDT, RONALD and p LAWRENCE (eds), Politics in New Guinea, University
of Western Australia, Perth, 1971.
BICCHIERI, MG (ed) , Hunters and Gatherers Today, Holt, Rinehart and
Winston, 1972.
BIRKET-SMITH, KAJ, The Eskimo, Methuen, 1959.
DE LA BOETIE, ETIENNE, The Politics of Obedience, Black Rose Press,
Montreal, 1975.
BOHANNAN , LAURA, âPolitical Aspects of Tiv Social Organizationâ in
Middleton, John and David Tait.
BOHANNAN, PAUL , Social Anthropology, Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1963.
ââThe Tiv of Nigeriaâ in Gibbs, James
â âYou Canât Do Nothingâ , American Anthropologist, LXXXI I, 3, 1980.
BOURDIEU , PIERRE , The Algerians, Beacon, Boston, 1962.
BRENAN, GERALD , The Spanish Labyrinth, Cambridge, 1962.
BUBER, MARTIN , Paths to Utopia, Beacon, Boston, 1958.
CANNON , WALTER, âVoodoo Deathâ, American Anthropologist, XLIV, 1942.
CARNIERO, ROBERT L, âPolitical Expansion as an Expression of the
Principle of Competitive Exclusionâ in Cohen and Service.
CLARKE, MV, The Medieval City State, Methuen, 1926.
CLASTRES , PIERRE, Society Against the State, Urizen, New York, 1977.
COHEN, JOSEPH I, In Quest of Heaven, Sunrise History Publ. Comm., New
York, 1957.
COHEN , RONALD, âState Foundations: A Controlled Comparisonâ in
Cohenâ˘and Service.
COHEN , RONALD and ELMAN SERVICE (eds) , Origins of the State, Institute
for the Study of Human Issues, Philadelphia, 1978.
COLSON , ELIZABETH , The Plateau Tonga of Northern Rhodesia: Social and
Religious Studies, Manchester University Press, 1962.
â Tradition and Contract: The Problem of Order, Aldine, Chicago, 1974.
CONDOMINAS, GEORGE, âThe Primitive Life of Vietnamâs Mountain Peopleâ,
in Manâs Many Ways, Richard A Gould (ed) , Harper and Row, 1973.
CULSHAW , WJ , Tribal Heritage, Lutterworth Press, London, 1949.
DAHRENDORF, RALF, Class and Class Conflict in Industrial Society,
Stanford, 1959.
DAMAS , DAVID , âThe Copper Eskimosâ, in Bicchieri, MG.
DENTAN, ROBERT, The Semai: A Nonviolent People of Malaya, Holt Rinehart
and Winston, 1962,
DOLE, GERTRUDE, âAnarchy Without Chaos: Alternatives to Political
Authority Among the Kirikuruâ in Swartz, Turner and Tuden.
DOLGOFF, SAM (ed) , The Anarchist Collectives, Free Life Editions, New
York, 1977.
DRIVER , HAROLD , Indians of North America, Chicago, 1962 .
DRUCKER , PHILIP, Northern and Central Nootkan Tribes, Bulletin of
Bureau of American Ethnology, Washington, 1951.
â Cultures of the North Pacific Coast, Chandler, San Francisco, 1965.
DURRENBERGER, E . PAUL , âStratification without a state: the collapse
of the Icelandic Commonwealthâ, Ethnos, Liii, 3â4, 1988.
DYSON-HUDSON, NEVILLE, Karamojong Politics, Oxford, 1966.
ELKIN, AP, The A ustralian Aborigines, Angus & Robertson, Sydney, 1961.
ENGELS, FREDERICK, The Origin of the Family, Private Property and the
State, Pathfinder, New York, 1972.
EVANS-PRITCHARD , EE, The Political System of the Anuak of the
Anglo-Egyptian Sudan, London School of Economics, Monographs in
Anthropology, 1940s.
â The Nuer, Oxford, 1940b.
â Nuer Religion , Oxford, 1956.
â âThe Nuer of the Southern Sudanâ in Fortes and Evans-Pritchard.
FIRTH, RAYMOND, Essays on Social Anthropology and Values, Athlone,
London, 1964.
FORTES, MEYER, and EE EVANS-PRITCHARD , African Political Systems,
Oxford, 1961 .
FRIED, MORTON , The Evolution of Political Society , Random House, 1967.
FRIEDMANN, ROBERT, Hutterite Studies, Mennonite Historical Soc . ,
Goshen, Ind. 1961.
FROMM, ERICH , Man for Himself, Rinehart, 1947.
GEDDES, WR, Nine Dayak Night, Oxford, 1961 .
GELLNER, ERNEST, Saints of the Atlas, Weidenfeld & Nicolson, 1969.
GIBB S , JAMES (ed) , Peoples of Africa, Holt, Rinehart and Winston,
1965.
GJERSET, KNUT, History of Iceland, Macmillan, 1925 .
GLUCKMAN, MAX, Politics, Law and Ritual in Tribal Society, Aldine, 1965.
GOODMAN, PAUL, Drawing the Line, Random House, 1946.
â People or Personnel, Random House, 1964.
GOODY, JACK, Technology, Tradition and the State in Africa, Oxford,
1971.
GREEN, MM, Ibo Village Affairs, Praeger, 1964.
GULLIVER, PH , The Family Herds: A Study of Two Pastoral Tribes in East
Africa: The lie and Turkana , Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1955.
ââThe Jie of Ugandaâ in Gibbs, James.
HALLOWELL , A IRVING , Culture and Experience, Univ. of Pennsylvania,
1955.
HAMMOND, PETER B (ed) , Cultural and Social Anthropology, Macmillan ,
1964.
HARDY, DENNIS , Alternative Communities in Nineteenth Century England,
Longmans, 1979.
HART, DAVID , âClan, Lineage , Local Community and the Feud in a Riffian
Tribeâ , in Sweet, Louise ( ed) , Peoples and Cultures of the Middle
East, Natural History Press, 1970.
ââRejoinder to Henry Munson Jr. â American Anthropologist, XCI, 3, 1989.
HINDES, BARRY and PAUL HIRST, Pre-Capitalist Modes of Production,
Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1975.
HINE, VIRGINIA, âThe Basic Paradigm of a Future Socio-Culture Systemâ ,
World Issues, II 1977, pp. 19â22.
HOBSBAWM , ERIC J, Primitive Rebels, Manchester University Press, 1959.
HOCART, AM, Kings and Councillors, Chicago, 1970.
HOEBEL, E ADAMSON, The Law of Primitive Man, Harvard, 1961.
â Man in the Primitive World, McGraw-Hill, 1958.
HOGBIN, IAN ( ed ) , Anthropology of New Guinea, Melburne University
Press, 1973.
â The Leaders and the Led: Social Control in Wogeo, New Guinea, Melburne
University Press, 1979.
HOLMBERG, ALAN, Nomads of the Longbow, Smithsonian Institution,
Washington, 1950.
HONIGMANN, JOHN J , Ethnography of the Fort Nelson Slave, Yale, 1946.
â Culture and Ethos of the Kaska, Yale, 1949.
HOSTETLER, JOHN A, Amish Society, Johns Hopkins, 1963.
â Hutterite Society, Johns Hopkins, 1974.
HOWELL , P . P . , A Manual of Nuer Law, Oxford, 1954.
HUGHES , DIANE, âKinsmen and Neighbors in Medieval Genoaâ in Harry A
Miskimin, David Herlihy and AL Udovitch, The Medieval City, Yale, 1977.
JENNES S , DIAMON D , The Carrier Indians of the Bulkley River: Their
Social and Religious Life, Bulletin of the Bureau of American Ethnology,
1943.
KLIMA , GEORGE, The Barabaig: East African Cattle Herders, Holt,
Rinehart and Winston, 1970.
KROEBER, ALFRED L , Handbook of the Indians of California, California
Book Co, 1953.
â Configurations of Culture Growth, Univ. of California, 1944.
KROPOTKIN , PETER, Mutual Aid: A Factor in Evolution, Heinemann, London,
1902.
â The State: Its Historic Role, Freedom Press, London, 1943.
LANDAUER , GUSTAV, For Socialism, Telos, St Louis, 1978.
LANGNESS, LL, âTraditional Political Organizationâ in Hogbin, Ian, 1973.
ââBena Benaâ in Berndt and Lawrence.
LEE, RICHARD B, The Kung San: Men, Women and Work in a Foraging Society
, Cambridge University Press, 1979.
LEHNING , ARTHUR ( ed. ) , Michael Bakunin: Selected Writings, Grove
Press, New York, 1973.
LEVAL , GASTON , Collectives in the Spanish Revolution, Freedom Press,
London, 1975.
LEVI-STRAUSS, CLAUD E , Tristes Tropiques, Atheneum, New York, 1964.
LEWARNE, CHARLES PIERCE, Utopias on Puget Sound 1885â1915, University of
Washington, 1975 .
LIENHARDT, GODFREY , âThe Western Dinkaâ in Middleton and Tait.
LIPSET, SEYMOUR, MARTIN TROW, and JAMES COLEMAN, Union Democracy,
Doubleday, 1965.
LODGE , EC, âThe Communal Movement in Franceâ in CAMBRIDGE MEDIEVAL
HISTORY, Vol V, 1926.
LOWIE , ROBERT, The Origin of the State, Rinehart, 1927.
â âSocial and Political Life of the Tropical Forest and Marginal Tribesâ
in Steward, Julian (ed) , Handbook of South American Indians, Vol V,
1949.
â Social Organization, Holt Rinehart and Winston, 1960.
MAINE, HENRY, Ancient Law, Murray, London, 1861.
MAIR, LUCY , Primitive Government, Penguin, 1962.
MACHAJSKI, WACLAW, âOn the Expropriation of the Capitalistsâ in
Calverton, VF (ed), The Making of Society , Random House, 1937.
MALINOWSKI, B, Crime and Custom in Savage Society, Kegan, Paul, Trench
and Trubner, London, 1932.
MARSHALL, LORNA, âThe Kung Bushman of the Kalahari Desertâ in Gibbs,
James.
MARTIN, JAMES J, Men Against the State, Libertarian Book Club, New York,
1957.
MARTINES , LAURO , Power and Imagination, Alfred A Knopf, New York,
1979.
MAXIMOFF, GP, The Political Philosophy of Bakunin: Scientific Anarchism,
Free Press, Glencoe, Illinois, 1953.
MICHELS , ROBERT, First Lectures in Political Sociology, Harper, 1949.
â Political Parties, Dover, 1959. MIDDLETON , JOHN, âThe Political
System of the Lugbara of the Nile-Congo Divideâ in Middleton and Tait.
â The Lugbara of Uganda, Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1965 .
MIDDLETON, JOHN and DAVID TAIT â Tribes without Rulersâ Routledge and
Kegan Paul, London, 1958.
MUKHERJEA, CHARULAL, The Santals, Mukherjee Co, Calcutta, 1962.
MUNSON , HENRY JR. , âOn the Irrelevance of the Segmentary Lineage Model
in the Moroccan Rifâ ; American Anthropologist, XCI, 2, 1989.
MURDOCK, GEORGE P, âThe Common Denominator of Culturesâ , in Linton, R,
The Science of Man in the World Crisis, Columbia Univ, 1945.
NADEL, SF, Black Byzantium, Oxford, 1942.
NOMAD , MAX , Aspects of Revolt, Noonday Press, 1959.
â Masters: Old and New, Black Cat Press, Edmonton, Alberta, 1979.
ORANS, MARTIN, The Santal, Wayne State University Press, 1965.
ORENSTEIN, HENRY, âAsymmetrical Reciprocity: A Contribution to the
Theory of Political Legitimacyâ, Current Anthropology, XXI, 1980.
PARETO , VILFREDO , Sociological Writings, Praeger, 1966.
PEHRSON, ROBERT N, âThe Lappish Herding Leader: A Structural Analysisâ,
American Anthropologist, LVI, 1954.
PELLICANI, LUCIANO , Red Bureaucracy, Black Cat Press , Edmonton,
Alberta, 1979.
PIRENNE , HENRI, Early democracies in the Low Countries, Harper and Row,
New York, 1963.
POSPISIL, LEOPOLD, The Kapauku Papuans, Holt, Rinehart and Winston,
1963.
PREVITE-ORTON, cw, âThe Italian Cities Till c 1200â in Cambridge
Mediaeval History, V, 1926.
PROUDHON, PIERRE J, The General Idea of the Revolution in the Nineteenth
Century , Freedom Press, London, 1923.
â The Principle of Federation, Toronto, 1979.
â What is Property?, William Reeves, London, No date.
RADCLIFFE-BROWN, AR, The Andaman Islanders, Free Press, Glencoe, Ill,
1948.
â Structure and Function in Primitive Society , Free Press, Glencoe,
Illinois, 1952.
READ, KENNETH , âLeadership and Consensus in a New Guinea Societyâ ,
American Anthropologist, LXI, 1959.
RICHARDS, VERNON , Lessons of the Spanish Revolution, Freedom Press,
London, 1953.
RITTER, ALLEN, Anarchism: A Theoretical Analysis, Cambridge Univ, 1980.
ROCKER , RUDOLF, Nationalism and Culture, Rocker Publications Comm, Los
Angeles, 1937.
RORIG, FRITZ , The Medieval Town , Batsford, London, 1967.
SAHLIN S , MARSHAL L , âPoor Man, Rich Man, Big-Man, Chief: Political
Types in Melanesia and Polynesiaâ, Comparative Studies in Society and
History, Vol V, 1963.
â Tribesmen, Prentice-Hall, 1968.
SCHNEIDER, HAROLD K, Livestock and Equality in East Africa, Indiana
University Press, Bloomington, Indiana, 1979.
SCHUMACHER , ERNST, Small is Beautiful, Harper and Row, 1973.
SCHURTZ , HEINRICH , Alterklassen und Mannerbiinde, Reimer, Berlin,
1902.
SERVICE, ELMAN, Primitive Social Organization, Random House, 1962.
â The Hunters, Prentice-Hall, 1966.
â Origins of the State and Civilization , WW Norton, 1975 .
SHARP, LAURISTON , âPeople without Politics: The Yir Yirontâ m Hammond,
Peter.
SOMERS , GEORGE E, The Dynamics of Santa! Traditions in a Peasant
Society, Abhenav Pubis, New Delhi, 1977.
SPENCER, ARTHUR , The Lapps, Crane, Russick and Co, 1978.
SPENCER , B and GILLEN, F . J . , The Arunta, Macmillan, London, 1927.
SPENCER, ROBERT F , The North Alaskan Eskimos: A Study in Ecology and
Society, Bulletin of Bureau of American Ethnology, Washington, 1959.
SPOONER, LYSANDER, Letâs Abolish Government, Arno Press, New York, 1972.
STEWARD , JULIAN, Basin-Plateau Aboriginal Socio-Political Groups,
Bulletin Bureau of American Ethnology, Washington, 1938.
STEWARD, JULIAN and LOUIS FARON, Native Peoples of South America,
McGraw-Hill, 1959.
SWARTZ , MARK, VICTOR TURNER and ARTHUR TUDEN (eds) , Political
Anthropology , Aldine, 1966.
TAIT, DAVID, âThe Territorial Pattern and Lineage System of Konkombaâ in
Middleton and Tait.
â âThe Political System of Konkombaâ in Ottenberg, Simon and Phoebe
(eds) , Cultures and Societies of Africa, Random House, 1960.
TAYLOR, MICHAEL , Anarchy and Cooperation , John Wiley, 1976.
THOMAS , ELIZABETH M, The Harmless People, Random House, 1958.
THOMPSON , LAURA, The Secret of Culture, Random House, 1969.
TREITSCHKE, H VON, Politics, Harcourt, Brace & World, 1963.
TURNBULL, COLIN, The Forest People, Doubleday, 1962.
â âThe Mbuti Pygmies of the Congoâ in Gibbs, James.
TURNER, VICTOR , The Ritual Process, Aldine, 1969.
TYLOR, EDWARD B, Anthropology , Watts, London, 1946.
UCHENDU, VICTOR , The Igbo of Southeast Nigeria, Holt, Rinehart and
Winston, 1965.
VEYSEY, LAURENCE, The Communal Experience: Anarchist and Mystical
Communities in Twentieth-Century America, Chicago, 1978.
VINOGRADOV, AMAL , The Ait Ndhir of Morocco: A Study of the Social
Transformation of a Berber Tribe, University of Michigan, 1974.
VOLINE, The Unknown Revolution, Libertarian Book Club, New York, 1955.
VORREN, O and E MANKER, Lapp Life and Custom, Oxford, 1962.
WARNER, W LLOYD, A Black Civilization, Harper, 1958.
WATANABE, HITOSHI, âThe Ainuâ in Bicchieri.
WATSON, JAMES B , (ed) , New Guinea: The Central Highlands, Special
publication of American Anthropologist, 1964.
â âTairoraâ in Berndt and Lawrence.
WEBER, MAX, The Theory of Social and Economic Organization, Free Press,
New York, 1964.
WINTER, EDWARD, âThe Aboriginal Political Structure of Bwambaâ in
Middleton and Tait.
WISSLER, CLARK, Man and Culture, Crowell, New York, 1923.
WITTFOGEL, KARL A, Oriental Despotism, Yale, 1963.
[1] See Bibliography for this and subsequent references
[2] Proudhonâs latterday ideas on federalism have recently been raised
in connection with the discussion of the nature of Canadian federalism
and thus of the Canadian nation (cf. Proudhon, 1979)
[3] The Catholic Worker newspaper allowed the appointment of a priest as
Church censor and Dorothy Day herself has said she would stop its
publication immediately if so ordered by the Church
[4] A hypothesis developed in the 19^(th) century and in the last decade
or so given some publicity by the Marxist wing of the womenâs liberation
movement, holds that in the most archaic societies men and women were
equal and that the development of âpropertyâ and agriculture led to male
domination. It is certainly true that here is greater equality between
the sexes in hunter-gathering societies than in most agricultural ones.
But this âgreater equalityâ is still within the parameters of male
pre-eminence. Two other notions which frequently appear in conjunction
with that of an ancient sexual equality are the views that the older
human society as matrilineal and that originally something called group
marriage was practised. There is no substantiation for such views in the
data of anthropology. Indeed, if nothing, the evidence is against them
oldest human societies were probably either matrilineal nor patrilineal,
but rather were bilateral (non-lineal).
[5] Some hunting-gathering societies evolved out of horticultural ones,
as for example occurred with several Amazon Forest Indian societies and
with some of the Indians of the North American Plains (eg, the
Cheyenne).
[6] As has already been mentioned, most of these societies no longer
exist, but for convenience they will be discussed in the present tense.
[7] The classical conception of the segmentary lineage system as
outlined by E. E. Evans-Pritchard in The Nuer, and as reflected in
Middletonâs description of the Lugbara has been subjected to
considerable cntic1sm over the last several years. The criticism
stresses the following points: (1) Segmentary âtheoryâ alleges that in a
segmentary lineage system any important social and political relations
are explicable in terms of lineage affiliation. Cleavages, alliances,
feuds, mutual aid are all determined by lineage affiliation. This
emphasis overlooks other types of social relationships which can be
equally important and often override an individualâs or groupâs lineage
obligations. These relationships include community membership,
fnendsh1p, ne1ghborhood and affinal ties, relationships with oneâs
motherâs kin, and relationships of work and economic enterprise.
Lineages, then, are not the solitary, close knit corporate bodies
claimed by the theory. (2) In segmentary âtheoryâ it is held that
opposition arises between segments of the same level, that is, a major
lineage opposes another major lineage but never a minor or minimal
lineage. The theory also argues that the complementary segments are
approximately equal in strength. But there are too many exceptions to
these points, especially to the latter, for them to be accepted as
invariable characteristics of the segmentary lineage. (3) Presumably
membership in a lineage within the segmentary system is based
exclusively upon kin ties through males and to a common male ancestor.
In fact, there is often manipulation and jockeying with genealogies so
that some individuals who are not so related are absorbed into the
lineage. Aside from these kinds of fictions, the alleged common male
ancestor is sometimes also only an invention. In sum we may say that the
segmentary âtheoryâ presents a peopleâs ideology about their social
system, an ideology which is only imperfectly reflected in their
everyday life and which therefore clearly tells only a biased story.
[8] Witchcraft differs from sorcery. In the latter an individual
deliberately carries out specific rituals aimed at injuring another
party. In witchcraft it is only believed that a person, alleged to be a
witch, performs malevolent ritual and non-ritual acts. Of course, such a
person also, in fact, holds a position which is feared or resented by
the believer in witchcraft.
[9] Virilocal residence occurs where a newly roamed couple live in the
household of the husband.
[10] Such emphasis upon reciprocity perhaps implicitly over-emphasises
the altruism involved, neglecting the fact that many people do not give
m the âspintâ of reciprocity so much as out of a fear of reprisal if
they do not give (Colson, 1974, 48).
[11] At a meeting discussing Makhno this writer inquired how one could
be an anarchist and at the same time order people shot for disobeying
oneâs commands. The chief response from anarchists seemed to be: âBut
Makhno organised workersâ and peasantsâ collectives as well as
educational and cultural facilitiesâ. And to this the obvious reply is
that Mussolini also made the railways run on time.
[12] ie, persons who did not belong to a collective.
[13] In their drive to build modern nation-states and ape the Europeans,
Africaâs political elites are eager to bury the archaic anarchic
elements, or to convert them into the idiom of democratic statism. Old
African anarchic decentralism becomes in their hands an example of some
ancient African tradition of democratic government and communalism.
[14] 1Modem anarchists face a dilemma if they propose the abolition and
prohibition of private property, in that in order to do so they would
seem to require an institution suspiciously like a state to ensure its
abolition and to ensure that it remained abolished.
[15] Perhaps this might be called the anarcho-cynicalist point of view.