💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › science-as-radicalism-william-gillis.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 13:50:46. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Science As Radicalism
Author: William Gillis
Date: 2015/08/18
Language: en
Topics: science, anarchism, anarcho-transhumanism, technology, critique, post-left, civilization
Source: Retrieved on 31st January 2016 from http://humaniterations.net/2015/08/18/science-as-radicalism/.

William Gillis

Science As Radicalism

It’s no secret that a good portion of the left today considers science

profoundly uncool. A slight affinity with it persists among a majority,

but few asides of scorn by the continental philosophers influential in

the contemporary leftist canon see spirited response and science’s most

prominent champions remain dated historical figures like Peter Kropotkin

and Élisée Reclus. Indeed there’s a lingering whiff of technocratic

stodginess and death that the word “science” has never quite shaken.

Those leftists most associated with it have a tendency to either be

authoritarians looking to legitimize near-fascist narratives, or

doe-eyed activists enchanted by saccharine visions of self-managed

bureaucracies and The Meeting That Never Ends. To a great many who

identify as radicals “science” appears in our lives primarily as a place

our various enemies habitually retreat to conjure the authority their

shoddy arguments couldn’t.

Taken in this light as a sort of nebulous divinity — spoken of with

explicit capitalization and the occasional flourishing exclamation mark

— “Science!” often strikes like a character in the tales we encounter

throughout our life, gradually accumulating a jumble of associations and

personality traits. Tales that are almost uniform across our society.

Everyone knows the high school story of Science! in rough terms: The

belief that the entirety of our reality can be divided up into little

atoms and facts. Gleaned from numbers, brutally harvested, and then

locked into little jars. Except — the story goes — it’s never quite

capable of successfully reducing us to these accounting sheets; all it

succeeds at is calling for xenocidal policies, unleashing catastrophes,

and, in its insane pursuit of infinite knowledge (ie domination) over

nature, consuming everything and everyone in its wake. Science! is

surely just another way of expressing the logic of empire and

capitalism. Science! is a religious institution that brokers no

alternatives. Science! is nuclear weapons, GMO killer seeds, animal

testing, bulldozers, nazi medical experiments, Jurassic Park, and

Christopher Columbus. It may have some more anodyne faces, but the

affair as a whole is inseparable from destructive hubris and cold

inhumanity.

Once you’ve seen this pattern or narrative it’s all too easy to fit

everything into it.

Chances are you don’t directly experience science in your everyday life.

But you do encounter its glossy logo incessantly. In the news stories

trolls cite against you to “prove” something about gender roles. In the

stickers on giant technological devices. If it’s not sneering Dawkins

fans telling you Science! says they’re right then it’s the horror tales

repeated incessantly by a fearful popular culture. We’ve watched

thousands of movies moralizing about “playing god” by seeking

understanding, to the point where we just assume such cinematic mistakes

are a realistic thing that totally happens. Someone says “the Large

Hadron Collider could create a blackhole” and we partially believe them

because like we’ve seen this movie before and further we immediately

leap to our Hollywood notion of a “blackhole” where it eats the earth

(rather than immediately evaporating into hawking radiation). There’s

literally a terrorist organization trying to murder graduate students

over a fear (“grey goo”) they admit they don’t understand at all. But

again, we’ve seen this movie.

Okay, sure, scientists may occasionally manage to poke their heads

through the media wall and point out that pollution is happening or that

actual neuroscience doesn’t back patriarchal narratives, but that’s

clearly just them cleaning up after their colleagues, their own

mistakes, their own colonizer logic. So many terrible people cite

science as a justification there must be something to it. And who could

deny that ozone depletion and deforestation wouldn’t have happened in

the first place if we weren’t making pencils and measuring devices for

those scientists to scribble down their findings. (Don’t talk to us

about scale or ridiculous differences in orders of magnitude! Numbers

remind us of how much math class sucked and any reference to scale

proves it’s “just a matter of degree.” And anyway all of industrial

society surely depends entirely on all the rest of it! It’s a package

deal!) Even if Science! has good parts, it surely also has a Dark Side

and dare not be let free to its own desires. At best it’s a tool capable

of some good (if tightly enslaved) and much evil (if embraced for its

own sake). But if it is just a tool it’s totally the master’s tool. And

at worst? At worst Science! is an insane power fantasy of our rulers

that has motivated and facilitated the enslavement of the entire world.

Science! is — in short — accepted on face value. It is taken more or

less as what we see called Science! almost everywhere. An unlucky few of

us are granted closer experience, stumbling into soul-sucking

engineering jobs for companies or academic sweatshops, specializing in

what boils down to optimizing a single widget. Science! is on the

nametag. Science! is on the diploma. Science! is on our report. Science!

is how our paymasters excuse the damage our widget causes in military or

economic application. Science! must surely be this.

You can tell I think this is all patent nonsense. A similar

intentionally misattributed and surface-deep tale could be told about

“Anarchy” from the newscaster desks to the Hot Topic stickers.

Yet the pull of such narratives are all consuming. And like any good

tale, they typically have a wide enough array of moving parts to make

any attempt at thorough critique prohibitively involved. Even if you

were to examine every association, assumed causation, repeated lie, and

misattribution it’s unlikely someone enraptured by this narrative would

be able to hold it all in their attention at the same time. They’d

always feel confident you hadn’t addressed enough. And in the face of

such complexity, they might as well default on whatever bundle of

associations they already have. In any case this narrative is dressed up

as a ‘critique’ of something presently in power — what? do you oppose

critiques? are you defending those in power?? surely the status quo

needs no more defenders!

As with conspiracy theories, if you hold a believer’s nose to the tricks

or holes in their tale they’ll sincerely retort that surely every other

possible story depends on equivalent slights of hand. Time and time

again I hear from hip radicals the same derision with science dressed up

as enlightenment: “All models are wrong, it’s just that some can be

useful self-deceptions.” If everything’s equally just a myth, equally

ungrounded, or politically suspect, you might as well settle on whatever

seems like it would be the most useful story given your psychology and

context.

A Context of Unending Appropriation

Among other peculiarities I have the dubious distinction of having been

raised by a true believer in “Christian Science.” If you’re unfamiliar

with the religion think less Scientology than a cranky first-wave

feminist sort of Mormonism. Which is mostly just to say a distinctly

19th century American invention with a tenuous Christian genealogy,

conservative aesthetics, and some weird twists into philosophical

idealism.

Christian Scientists are most notable for their unique response to the

problem of suffering in the presence of an omnipotent god: they respond

by disbelieving in suffering. Indeed they disbelieve in the entire

material world and sometimes even logic or math. It’s one of the cutest

tricks in the history of religion and philosophy and I feel bears some

horrified appreciation. There’s an organized religion in our world with

hundreds of thousands of followers founded on an explicit version of

immaterialism that would do even George Berkeley proud. If you break

your back or are imprisoned by a rapist you can cope by denying that any

of that actually exists. The entire material universe in fact is a

vicious lie, an error caused by the mistaken thoughts of “mortal mind.”

There is only God and Her love, everything else is a shared delusion, a

consensus reality. Thus, if you’re in suffering, disassociate. If you

face obstacles, work harder at convincing yourself they’re not a

problem. If you’re privileged, bask in the knowledge that you must be

doing something right as a matter of character. It’s basically The

Secret for 1880s housewives.

Rarely is the core of faith exposed so openly. Christian Science caters

to the poor, the mentally ill, and rich conservatives with hippie

inclinations. Washington DC is filled with them. My impoverished family

was once bizarrely taken yachting by a former assistant director of the

CIA.

So if you’re going to invent a stripped down version of Christianity

that resolves its incoherencies by claiming the universe doesn’t exist

and expressing distrust if not intense hostility to any sort of hands-on

engaging with material reality or even consistent bayesian logic — if

you’re going to become famous for letting children die rather than

concede to basic science — why adopt the label “Science”? Well put

simply, in the 1800s when the church’s founder Mary Baker Eddy was

trying to win over the world, “science” was a popular buzzword with a

lot of awe but little public comprehension. (So exactly like today.) The

founding saga of Christian Science is that a middle class schizophrenic

white girl addicted to morphine slipped and hurt herself, some doctors

allegedly told her she would never heal and in a few days she did. Bam.

New religion.

There’s a couple things to note here.

Even before Baker appropriated the term for herself, the dastardly

representatives of “science” in this story, the “doctors” (they were

actually homeopaths) had just as brazenly appropriated said mantle for

themselves. Little about practiced medicine at the time involved

anything remotely close to the kind of knowledge of root causes and

relationships that had driven the public stature of “science.” Physics

and mathematics, with chemistry and some limited realms of biology

dogging at their heels, had seen a stunning burst of conceptual

developments and dramatic evidence over three centuries. We were old

hats at advanced calculus and were sending electric signals across the

transatlantic cable — but we didn’t even really have the germ theory of

disease. Would-be doctors, like everyone else, were trying to position

themselves as inheritors and compatriots of if not indistinguishable

from physicists. Such baldfaced appropriation of anything garnering

respect is venerable tradition and those in power were well-versed long

before Baker. From the days of Newton there’ve been rich statesmen like

Francis Bacon leaping to define what those folk garnering respect were

really all about and how it could be applied to other things. In fact

the barrage of quacks, cultists, con-men, and politicians so dwarfed the

numbers of those they were emulating that very quickly they managed to

seize the mantle of “science” in the public’s eye for all manner of pet

projects. It didn’t matter that the people five-seconds prior considered

scientists emphatically dismissed nonsense like phrenology and other

such ‘sciences of peoples’ as ridiculous, the establishment showered any

halfbaked fool willing to defend patriarchy, white supremacy, and

capitalism with money and displays of respect. Neither her neighborhood

“doctors” nor Mary Baker Eddy herself (the original name she chose for

her religion was “Science of Man”) were doing anything different than

most people throughout modern history; they found something respected or

liked for whatever underlying reason and mischaracterized that reason or

offered a different explanation so they could hitch their own stuff to

it.

But Baker didn’t just ride this popular wave of appropriation, she took

advantage of the way it muddied the waters to discredit and disregard

the original scientists. The rhetorical tactics common in bible study

when I was a kid will be familiar to anyone today: Stripping merely

brilliant and unparalleled models or insights of their explicit context

and assigning them strawman pretensions as Absolute Knowledge; using the

shoddy results of appropriators to slander by association the original

endeavor; belittling anything too far outside the everyday concepts,

experiences, and concerns of those in a certain cultural/economic space…

it was a by-the-numbers affair; the same sort of rhetoric you hear from

theocrats or nihilist burnouts today. (If the ideologies that use such

defenses vary so wildly it’s because once you chuck pursuit of coherence

and the roots of dynamics you can “argue” any arbitrary position.) The

thing is, it worked. It’s one thing to latch onto a bigger phenomena in

hopes of becoming indistinguishable from it, quite another to use it as

a ladder to reach respect and then turn around and try to set that

ladder on fire.

Mary Baker Eddy’s wild success is a testament to human weakness and

oppression. People who have no power, who are trapped or locked out,

will go through all kinds of mental gymnastics to avoid coming to terms

with their reality. Minds are always looking for avenues of exploration

and the only thing more painful than being fundamentally barred is not

knowing where to start. Conscious minds can’t figure out how to live in

stasis and the result of trying is always insanity. To minimize this as

best we can we turn to escapism, we shrink our horizons, we frantically

model alternatives in hopes of finding a useful perspective. And when

that grows weak we simply deny. There’s no way they could know something

we don’t. No way our abuser or a person with more privilege could have

legitimately discovered realities by virtue of their situation. To admit

this is to come face to face with the full nature of power and either

strip us of hope or open yet another exhausting frontier of conflict.

I single out Christian Science as an illustrative example of the

disingenuousness surrounding use of the word “science” in particular

because it arose simultaneous with an array of more influential

appropriations, from “Social Darwinism” to Comte’s “Sociology” to Marx’s

“Scientific Socialism”, at a historical moment when most of the academic

categories we know today were being hashed out.

To understand the tangles of philosophical attempts over the last

century to define “science” it’s important to grasp the context

surrounding exactly who got in and who didn’t when the modern lines were

drawn. In the mid 1800s the explosive cultural force of the

Enlightenment had been mostly spent and the social prescriptions of its

political ideologues were undeniably losing cachet amid the complexities

of industrialization. Mathematics and physics were still accelerating at

a breakneck pace but the days when political theorists could pretend to

be of the same cloth were fading. Studies were moving out of social

halls and into an increasingly segmented academia. In the thereto

standard academic distinction social concerns that we’d today classify

as economics and sociology were commonsensically denoted as “moral

philosophies” — ie. inherently political — while the real drivers of

undeniable advances in knowledge like physics and mathematics were

“natural philosophies.” This distinction within academia brought a

clarity that threatened to undermine those forces looking to appropriate

intellectual authority.

Thankfully for them there were distinct aesthetic qualities to the

arguments of Enlightenment thinkers like Thomas Hobbes that resembled

the mathematical proofs and rigorous surveys of early physicists or

sought to tenuously extend models within natural philosophy into

normative social theories. That was after all the whole game of Hobbes

and company. And so eventually the term “science” was settled on as a

means by which economists, sociologists and the like could be grouped

together with the natural philosophies.

Over the previous centuries, with the decline of tradesmen and the rise

of industry, “science” had quietly shifted from an adjective describing

the individual cleverness and experiential know-how of craftsmen and

artisans to a noun mainly signifying the systematic collection of data.

“Science” thus provided an effective way to redefine what exactly was

the source of success in the early cluster of physicsy fields, and to

blend them with certain moral philosophies (usually wed to the kinds of

state power or capital that could perform extensive data collection)

into a intentionally hazy and exploitable bundle of popular

associations, primarily characterized by an air of inevitability and

absolute knowledge.

It’s this last impression that still galvanizes people today, often

quite violently.

Collecting Facts & Marking The Territory

As you might expect with stakes this high philosophers promptly spent

much of the twentieth century squabbling in direct and tangential ways

over what qualifies a statement or claim as “scientific”, or what counts

as a “scientific fact.” I’d argue that this approach, while

understandable, is ill-conceived.

The project of drawing a boundary between the inside and outside of

Science! — a project called the Demarcation Problem — has mostly played

out as contests over the mantle of science as an adjective denoting a

kind of truth value. Thus for the philosophers and demagogues who have

invested so heavily in this battle “science” is primarily viewed in

terms of its service or danger as a rhetorical weapon. As something that

might be slapped on a statement to make it a certain type of

unassailable.

It should thus come as no surprise that virtually none of the most

prominent voices in this debate and resulting commentary have been

scientists themselves (not that we haven’t had strong opinions). And

even when the intention of those involved has been good — like finding

clear definitions that get evolution and global warming accepted as

truthful but not homeopathy — the attempts invariably trend greedy in

their praise or dismissal. Either way they often end up claiming fields

like psychology and economics as being of the same primary category or

essential nature as physics. At the same time almost all of these

philosophers and demagogues have felt the need to hobble science lest it

get too uppity and say more than they want it to say. There’s a

widespread and frequently vocalized fear of science ceasing to function

as a highly limited tool and instead getting unleashed as an

orientation, motivation, or desire.

And so we get the simplistic Baconian picture taught in high schools

since the Cold War: Where a limited methodology or proceduralism is

almost entirely divorced from context or analysis and held up as the

single defining characteristic of Science!. The almost entire process of

theory or model development and comparison is handwaved away, and all

that’s left is data collection and calculation of error bars.

Under this regime science is — at least officially — limited to the

smallest of inductive steps forward. There is no space for analysis or

models that require a complicated hashing out before data collection.

The vast array of analysis of probabilities, bayesian dependencies,

contextual considerations, limits, etc. that good scientists crank

through — or any serious comparison of differing models, paradigms or

lines of investigation prior to data-collection — is waved away as not

really core to science. In the methodology picture a miracle occurs

whereby some arbitrary hypotheses emerge fully formed — each more or

less as a priori good as the next. There is no room for nuanced

contextual considerations or the extended development of analysis that

does not immediately offer experimentally falsifiable or verifiable

predictions, nor any explicitly preferred direction in the winnowing

down or comparison of such analysis. All that matters is the data

collection and everything else is ultimately treated as a kind of

handwavey excuse for it. “Signals” are then found, but how fundamental

they are is anyone’s guess. Indeed, as an exercise, it can be

illustrative to survey the notoriously horrid headlines of pop science

and see how many times phrases like “science says” could just as well be

replaced with “data says.”

This preposterously limited model of science obviously parallels the

various currents of panopticon-aspiration we know all too well today,

but it has its roots in classical imperialism — not just in the obvious

necessity of taking censuses and mapping shorelines, but in the

competitive collection of superficial “curiosities” by the upper classes

to strengthen hierarchies at home.

It’s a sadly underemphasized fact that the aristocracy pioneered aspects

of consumerism long before industrialism. In particular many fields that

came to be considered “sciences” in the 1800s like lepidoptery were

originally launched as fields of curio collecting whereby members of the

aristocracy hunted down rare items from around the world and displayed

them as one might today display a record collection. The key to

understanding this dynamic is that anything with barriers to entry and

scarcities can be used as currency to prop up a hierarchy. When the

things we might otherwise value become less scarce those invested in

social hierarchy itself respond by culturally promoting the valuing of

other scarce things.

When — as is common in the modern era — information is made the scarce

good, the resulting data collection or generation of lingo & taxonomies

need not bare any real relation or insight into what true underlying

dynamics are involved, and can happily countenance the most superficial

or limited models.

The Roots Of Science

The problem with identifying science in terms of all this is that data

collection unto itself doesn’t really signify any concept or dynamic of

substance. It’s hard to realistically speak of there being a passionate

movement or culture or ideology or idealism of data collection. And data

collection is not in any real sense descriptive of what motivated those

original scientists everyone else appropriated from. Any old pile of

data might show how particulars happen to be arranged, but alone it

offers little insight into how or why. Some statistical analysis on that

data might make for good predictions, but only within a certain given

context, whose bounds we remain entirely ignorant of. At least without a

serious sort of thoughtfulness, the contours of which are blithely

ignored by the methodology tale. Incorrect surface-level impressions and

models might well be falsifiable, verifiable, etc, yet remain

unchallenged outside a given context; how and where we search matters.

As do our motivations.

It’s easy to apply the trapping of the scientific method — even the

broader definitions of science promoted by many philosophers — and end

up with little in the way of deep insight. Indeed that’s often the point

of much that the sticker of “Science!” is slapped upon: to map the world

as it is and hide how else it might be or how it might change. Those who

are invested in existing systems have little interest in mapping

alternate possibilities. And those preoccupied with their own

situatedness have little desire to look beyond it or press beyond the

effective realm of their understanding.

Thankfully outside a few caricatures in some hilariously detached

postmodernist polemics few people widely accepted as scientists today

pursue data for data’s sake — as the sort of currency or fetishized

commodity that so attracts aristocrats, bureaucrats, middle-managers,

and hipsters. What motivates us is typically the search for deeper

insights and models that might be made clear — to hack our way through

the muddled chaos of first impressions, intuitions, and naive beliefs

and find the real underlying dynamics of a phenomenon.

This strong, persistent, and near-uniform tendency among scientists is,

I would argue, a good starting point for sorting out a clearer

perspective on the whole affair.

Sure “science” as a term was championed to facilitate a disingenuous

blurring and appropriation — a campaign that created a hazy umbrella of

uses in practice, filled with more contradictions and tensions than any

clear commonality — but a great deal of shaking-out has occurred since

the 1800s. And further many important traits of those originally

appropriated from have begun to be internalized by the appropriators.

Not enough, obviously — the journals of medicine and the social sciences

are still infamously rampant with irreproducible crap — but enough to

warrant notice. In no small part because there really was a unifying

tendency in the fields everyone else sought to steal legitimacy from.

Something deeper than a mere tactic or procedure.

Few would deny physicists are located at the dead center of whatever

‘science’ supposedly is. (Well okay, the most absurd appropriators like

Mary Baker Eddy and Auguste Comte eventually did, but their claims have

fared poorly at undermining the historical centrality of physics.) And

yet physics is also at the center of a wide and deep tradition within

science that is not motivated by shallow data collection and labeling

but by getting to the roots. Hence physicists’ uniform frustration

towards people attempting to derive general rules from surface data on

complex systems. And our fury historically at psuedosciences like

phrenology that the rest of the world happily accepted as science.

Ernest Rutherford’s famous cry that “All science is either physics or

stamp collecting!” arose deeply embedded in this context.

Our famed “arrogance” in this matter is better understood as an

annoyance at the lack of humility or diligence on the part of those

making such sweeping statements about macroscopic aggregate systems like

human beings. In practice “political science” and the like have often

functioned like cargo cult physics, and much of the literature of social

science and biology has remained in a continuing crisis as a direct

result of their failure to doggedly look for deeper root dynamics and

instead just catalog surface impressions. Not to mention their

corruption by economic interests seeking to derive useful tools or

actionable prescriptions, pressuring them to behave as technologists or

engineers rather than inquirers. And so we see within these broken

fields an attachment to the scientific method, rather than to what I

would term the heart of science. When you don’t actually really know why

and how something works, just that it in a certain context does — or

kinda does — from a bunch of data, you don’t have scientific knowledge

so much as mere empirical knowledge.

Of course there’s certainly space for speaking substantively about messy

abstractions like humans and human social relations, and data collection

can of course facilitate this. But the frequent lack of humility in the

social sciences & chunks of biology— the lack of any honest appreciation

and accountability for just how insanely hazy and attenuated most of it

is, often dealing entirely in immediate surface impressions — remains

stark. While things have certainly gotten better as the rigor of physics

and the like has leeched out (in particular see Scott Alexander’s

impassioned defenses of modern psychiatry and nutrition), significant

currents within these fields remain happy to speculate in shallow terms

and collect data without any diligent root-seeking or explicit

recognition of how tenuous and overly-simple their hypotheses are likely

to be.

Digging For The Roots

The fact of the matter is that the remarkably successful phenomenon that

the term “Science!” has wrapped itself around is not so much a

methodology as an orientation. What was really going on, what is still

going on in science that has given it so many great insights is the

radicalism of scientists, that is to say their vigilant pursuit after

the roots (or ‘radis’). Radicals constantly push our perspectives into

extreme or alien contexts until they break or become littered with

unwieldy complications, and when such occurs we are happy to shed off

the historical baggage entirely and start anew. To not just add caveats

upon caveats to an existing model but to sometimes prune them away or

throw it all out entirely. Ours is the search for patterns and

symmetries that might reflect more universal dynamics rather than merely

good rules of thumb within a specific limited context. As any radical

knows “good enough” is never actually enough.

To be sure there are naturally going to be certain tactics and

strategies that are generally quite useful in such pursuit — some in

very deep and inescapable ways — but never any single magically simple

and always efficient procedure or methodology.

Kuhn and Feyerabend pointed out half a century ago that no simple set of

rules of procedure could explain numerous important instances in the

actual history of scientific discovery. Galileo’s heliocentric model for

example was among other failings easily and immediately falsified by the

astronomical data of the time. Its greater pull lay not in perfectly

matching the data, but in an underlying conceptual critique of the

arbitrariness of the perpetually added circles-within-circles necessary

to prop up a geocentric model. That’s a meaningful critique in terms of

the free parameters and kolmogorov complexity, but it’s not reducible to

a simple and universally valid procedure or tactic.

Science, in short, is not just mere empiricism, not merely collecting

data and doing statistics. Science most critically involves an

exploration of possible models, their dependencies, and the many

possible vectors by which they might be winnowed down, all in search for

the deepest roots. The most universal symmetries, most unique patterns

and attractors in the relations of a system. Those often hidden but

least moving foundations from which everything else in all its grand

complexity can be grown. Our probings are not randomly directed, we pull

and tug on our models, see what doesn’t shift about, and re-focus our

efforts on it directly.

So for example theories that have internal logical inconsistencies

aren’t necessarily dismissed absolutely but they do get focused on far

less because such a characteristic (inconsistency) is not rare among

possible theories: there are infinitely more possible incoherent

theories than possible coherent theories. Incoherency in a theory

provides a lot of flexibility — quite a bit of freedom to wriggle it

about. Sometimes upon investigation the inconsistent theory will

entirely unravel, a phantom temporary knot, not actually a deep root.

But sometimes the inconsistency will turn out to be patchable if we give

the theory some more attention.

Similarly — in a more practical direction — if an expanse of theories

under consideration predict that it’s infinitely more likely that all

our memories are lies and we will cease to exist in another instant, we

can in some sense abandon such theories. That’s an absolutely real

example by the way. There are certain (otherwise perfectly empirically

valid models) possible in particle physics wherein it just so happens

that as a consequence of a possible model (with particular field

strengths, a geometry of spacetime, etc) it’d be infinitely more likely

for a bowl of petunias or a human brain with all of your memories etc to

be spontaneously generated out of the quantum vacuum at some point in

the infinite history of the universe than for a brain with your

memories/feelings/etc to arise in the causal fashion those memories and

feelings would suggest. This reductio ad absurdum is called “Boltzmann

Brains” and it’s engaged with quite seriously and rigorously. It may

well be that you have never existed before this moment and will never

exist after it, but if so there’s no consequence to attempting to spend

time modeling that reality or thinking in any direction really. All

desires or motivations a mind might have would instantly dead-end in

that reality. Thus we consciously mark off those possible physics models

that imply such as “not worth dwelling on”, invest our attention in

other possible models, and call a theory a certain type of ‘failed’ when

it ends up predicting that you’re infinitely more likely to be a

Boltzmann Brain than a regular one in a regular universe. But we are

explicit about that step, and this is what marks scientific knowledge:

not a claim about a single true model, but rather an understanding of

varying possibilities and their dependencies.

The atomist framework, for instance, bore a lot of fruit and so we

sought to push it as far as it could go. And yet in field theory and

string theory certain dualities make “fundamental elements” unclear —

when two different representations are exactly equivalent to each other

in results we arguably can’t speak as to which is the “correct”

portrait. The nouns we’ve wrapped as metaphors around the mathematical

relationship fall short in their description — these can be either

reveal a redundancy in our metaphorical description or a limit to our

experimental capacity. But the fundamental relations that duality

uncovers is clear as day. This requires a nuance between what the public

views as ‘reductionism’ and what many reductionists view it as. The

reductionism of scientists is not a caricature of atomism where all

simplified macroscopic layers of abstraction, intuition or practical use

are entirely erased. After all having the word “finger” doesn’t

invalidate our use of “hand” but it does help us remember that there’s

no magical emergent platonic “handness” resisting or orchestrating the

existence of fingers — it’s just useful to have language for differing

contexts or scales of abstraction. Similarly the objective of

reductionism is not to break everything into nounish-pieces or to

simplify away complexity, but to unearth fundamental relations/patterns

from which everything else can be grown. Whether for instance these

patterns take the form of particles, fields or things like symmetry

relations.

(Incidentally this is oft repeated in my circles but it really is a

goddamn crying shame that few outside of physics have any clue just how

dramatically Emmy Noether affected our field. Outsiders talk of

Newtonian and Einsteinian paradigms, but the more refined Noetherian

paradigm of the universe as a bundle of symmetry relations has ruled

physics for almost a century. This injustice to one of the greatest

mathematicians of all time is certainly a result of patriarchy but also

partially a matter of how much harder her insight is to explain to a

general public that has, through a tyrannical, alienating and deeply

anti-science education system, been denied familiarity with even basic

calculus.)

It’s ludicrous to assume that a single hammer, a single obtuse strategy

of sharply limited meta-complexity would be capable of entirely mapping

the structure of our reality much less narrowing down fundamental roots.

There will of course be complications to our search — things like the

Boltzmann Brains — that we must take into consideration in order to do

science with any efficiency. But those who want to somehow consign

science to empiricism alone do so to artificially preserve their own

domains from contact with the scientific drive, from explicitness and

analytical rigor in mapping the probabilities and dependencies of

different possibilities.

That is not to say that that experimentation, falsifiability,

verifiability, etc, don’t play quite important roles in practice, but

rather that they should be repositioned in our language as strategies

we’ve developed or come to recognize as highly useful in pursuit of

science.

The physicist approach — seen to various degrees in other fields — to

speak explicitly in terms of what gives rise to the plausibility of a

model or research branch rarely bothers with the cartoonish notion of

steps and laws taught in high schools. Physicists enjoy an excuse to

have a go at the strongest absolutes like entropy or the speed of light.

We just keep in mind the complete chain of things implying them. And so

while a few have fun going off and publishing some “let’s chuck half of

everything we know and try over in this direction” papers, even they

know it’s unbelievably more likely an experimental result indicating a

violation of the speed of light reflects a hidden wiring problem in the

experimental apparatus than a true violation of special relativity. One

can frame this in terms of induction, as “no particle yet observed has

gone faster than c”, but that’s not remotely close to how the arguments

go down in practice which take into account the root complexity of

various models, their many meta-dimensioned bayesian dependencies, etc.

This might be thought of as a kind of Feyerabend Part II. Yes, ‘anything

goes’, but to varying degrees. In ways deeply dependent upon context.

Statistically speaking there’s a strong inclination to certain

strategies and tactics, and that’s good. That’s because the radical

impulse of science is grounded in bayesian learning, an optimal approach

it turns out our neural networks also follow at the smallest level. As

in any bayesian system comparisons between models are not arbitrary

decisions hidden behind a veil of subjectivity about which we can say

nothing. Examining meta-decisions does not oblige suddenly throwing up

one’s hands and allowing charlatans free reign to claim anything about

global warming; we can still trace everything, our entire network of

assumptions and weightings, or relations. What defines science — or

rather what is the single most important and fundamental dynamic of note

within the hazy cluster of shit called “science” — is not so much the

strategies and models it has accumulated at any meta-level but the goal

of root-pursuing, a drive that hashes through the infinite possible

configuration space and gravitates towards a single locus, or sometimes

merely to more unique regions or sets of loci.

One might approach this looking for traditional philosophical claims,

and say that such an orientation assumes the existence of universal

patterns and thus is making a truth claim about reality being

consistent, but I think the orientation is better stated as an emergent

line of exploration.

If there are literally no universal consistencies then pattern searching

is useless because there cannot even be local consistencies. To give an

impression of how this works consider if 1+1=2 was only local to some

neighborhood: Then you could continuously transform to some other

neighborhood where 1+1=”duck” and then transform back. If the transforms

are always perfect pullbacks such that 1+1 continues to equal 2 upon

returning locally then you’ve exposed a universal consistency on some

meta level that has structure. If not then local consistency dissolves

entirely. (In general I abhor mere arithmetic examples as violently

misrepresenting the nature of mathematics and implicitly bundling in

certain philosophies of mathematics; “1+1=2” should be read as serving

in this context only as a loose and popularly accessible metaphor for

some manner of local consistency.) My point is that consistency or

lack-of-consistency in thought is ultimately radically infectious; there

is no middle ground. Upon any motion things either collapse in one

direction or the other. And since all intentional action explicitly

requires an assumption of some level of consistency, it implicitly

assumes a universal consistency — regardless of whether or not the agent

has full access to its nature.

We can, in a certain trivial sense, never know anything truly — in an a

priori sense. Even Descartes’ ‘cogito ergo sum’ provides no firm ground.

The qualia of the act of thought is in many substantive respects

suspect; every way we might frame it is laden with baggage of

assumptions. The formation of conscious narrative is itself an

abstraction that fails at points and dissolves under examination. Even

the recursive knowledge of the motion of our own thoughts and

self-experience doesn’t happen instantaneously, and requires an

assumption that our memory or state of mind an instant prior in the loop

of recursion is real. There is no winning epistemology. What we can do

is identify patterns, make models of dependencies.

Science in no way condemns postulating outside the assumptions that the

“external” world is real, that nature really is uniform, etc. Rather

scientific or radical thinking very quickly notes just how much of a

formless uninteresting arbitrary muck happens beyond those assumptions.

As with the Boltzmann Brains we put up a sign and move on.

Similarly the ‘problem’ of induction is only a problem if you are

interested in stating things as though they were laws rather than

symmetries, ‘absolute truths’ rather than patterns. We don’t have to

make that jump to do science. It’s a faint distinction, but one that

reveals many confusions that plague philosophy of science. The

difference is intent: between understanding/modeling a reality and

achieving an ends. Science’s goal is not so much to be useful as to give

a map of more unique, simple but descriptive, accounts of reality. We

may happily mark off some of those accounts as not useful but science

retains those accounts. And if multiple theories of similar complexity

and arbitrariness give identical predictions or no predictions then they

are of less interest than the theory that gives the same predictions but

derives such from simpler roots, with less arbitrariness.

An Artificial Distinction

I haven’t been making any real distinction so far between mathematics

and the sciences, and the above description of science as radicalism

obviously places mathematics as a science. This fits the historical arc

where “science” was adopted to more widely appropriate the prestige of

advances in physics and mathematics, but the saga goes back further. The

notion of a distinction between physics and mathematics has always been

rather ludicrous and has persisted in the west mostly as an artifact of

Greek mysticism and Christian theology. In fact this mistaken deep

division between the supposedly “a priori” patterns of math and the a

posteriori patterns of physics is arguably partially responsible for the

general paralysis of science in Europe for over a thousand years until

Newton and Leibnitz got audacious enough to challenge it. The great

advances of math and physics that started in their era on were in no

small part tied to the blurring of the two into a single tradition of

diligent radical inquiry.

Yet in the great academic reshuffling and sweeping appropriations of the

nineteenth century mathematics was rather quietly pushed out of the nest

while physics was kept. The broken language that has resulted

continually makes for very frustrating conversations. One person

declares that obviously mathematics is a science because it involves

vigorous modeling and pursuit of elegant fundamentals (in short, because

it’s radical). Whereas the other person declares that obviously math is

part of the humanities as it is not grounded in empirical

experimentation “in the physical world.”

But of course our brains are part of the physical world. Exploration of

all possible theories of formal patterns comprehensible to humans is

itself a form of experimentation — essentially a form of experimental

computer science — and data collected from such exploration is widely

taken as meaningful proof. Mathematicians for instance probe problems of

computational complexity and the meta patterns to how these explorations

have turned out has been taken as strong evidence of the complexity

classes and the incollapsibility of the polynomial hierarchy. This is

perfectly reasonable bayesian inference, but it often shocks and offends

those outside math and the other hard sciences who’ve accumulated a very

limited notion of what can constitute evidence.

And it’s worth pointing out that physicists have always taken doing math

to be both a valid realm of experimentation and the twin discipline of

physics. V.I. Arnold said it best: “Mathematics is the part of physics

where experiments are cheap.” In fact the biggest discoveries in physics

have often been mathematical reformulations of existing knowledge, from

action principles to symmetry relations to modern thermodynamics.

Physics often involves momentous discoveries that are not a prediction

of empirical data, but a restructuring of how to construct models.

Indeed the last couple decades have rapidly dissolved whatever lines had

been drawn between mathematics, computer science, and physics. These

somewhat separate academic communities are still reeling from the force

of dramatic reveal after dramatic reveal. It’s been hard for many

blindsided specialists to eat humble pie but there’s now a widespread

awareness that the three fields will have to become deeply interwoven if

not altogether indistinguishable in the future.

While there are certainly purist traditions within mathematics clinging

to the sort of Diophantine work in the tradition of the Greeks and

making snide remarks about calculus, it’s even unclear what could

possibly constitute a truly “pure” math as there are unlimited possible

formalisms or models one can work with. The inescapable fact of the

matter is that the various underlying foundations we’ve gravitated

towards choosing (like ZFC Set Theory or the increasingly popular

Homology Type Theory) are chosen because the models they generate are

better at integrating with our experiences of the world.

When John Preskill said that, “I favor the view that ‘Mathematics is

Physics’ over ‘Physics is Mathematics’,” he was expressing a relatively

common perspective from the trenches that is nevertheless shocking and

transgressive to the peanut gallery commenting on science from without.

In no small part because the division is useful to those in power.

In his work The Utopia of Rules David Graeber traced the evolution of

popular notions of “imagination” from first being seen as something

deeply tied to navigating reality to later something escapist and almost

irrelevant. Mathematics has followed a similar arc — redefined partly by

the powerful and partly in self-defense as a kind of solipsistic poetry

for the boffins whose dreaming we can’t control, regulate, or demand

immediate results from. In the end this attempt to pluck mathematics out

of the heart of science has left it as the only refuge for truly

advanced modeling, while those historical forces attempt to suppress

such everywhere else.

This artificial exclusion of mathematics from science serves a vision of

“science” that ultimately wants scientists to function as nothing more

than mechanics and sees the only meaningful exploration as that which

can be visibly embodied in a physical experiment. It wants to treat

theory as a kind of afterthought or fig leaf, and all twists and turns

in the process of theorizing as more or less equivalently suspect,

equivalently random flights of fancy. It should be no wonder this kind

of categorical framework has been gobbled up by those academics whose

experiences are largely limited to those humanities where all theorizing

away from immediate experience/experiment is often reasonably seen as

more or less equivalently tenuous, or equivalently suspect.

A Universal Current

Under this lens that I have been presenting in a certain sense

everything is science and nothing is. The radical inquiry at the core of

science doesn’t reflect a collection of claims or practices with tightly

policeable borders, but a direction, an arrow of struggle or direction

of development. And when we recenter ‘science’ on this current we find

it to be a constantly resurgent throughout human history. From the

conceptual modeling used by hunter-gatherers to some of those used by

the social sciences.

While neuroscience, for example, may not have always been consistently

scientific it’s clearly become more so over time. Appropriation is a

complicated thing; many fields that started out as absurdities have

gradually integrated the tools, instincts and ideals of those they were

appropriating from. On the other hand chemistry was a science for a long

while, and yet is increasingly turning into a technologist discipline

interested in engineering particulars, as little in the way of relevant

root dynamics remain unferreted. Science and technology have a

complicated interplay in practice, a given scientist or technologist or

a given research project or development team will sometimes have to

switch directions repeatedly. But they still denote distinct vectors,

distinct inclinations of thought. One burrows down to the roots, the

other takes the simple nutrition from these roots back out and blossoms

it into a million applied particulars.

All human thought involves induction or rather association into models.

Those instances that feedback into more engagement — rather than

defensive mechanisms of retreat to a limited context — are surely in the

scientific or radical direction, however tentatively they end up

pushing.

I could even sing a sweet song here about how love and empathy should be

properly seen as representing the spirit of science in human one-on-one

relations; constantly pursuing better models, better impressions of one

another, and updating our models of self to grow more expansive in

response. Science and love are very closely related, and a number of

jokes in physics and math reflect on the parallels between these

hungers. A longing for a deeper intimacy than a shallow surface

modeling. That many lovers and scientists shy away or abandon their

pursuit past a certain point by no means makes the point at which they

end up settling a great reflection of “science” or “love” — the point is

the general thrust of their efforts.

It’s important to note that every historical moment in every society was

alive with flickers of radical exploration, modeling, and discovery.

It’s easy to gloss over the studious play of crafting that discovered so

damn many things, but we are in many unappreciated ways standing on the

shoulders of giants. Every single society is thick with knowledge

accumulated through experimentation and record. From first hacking our

audio cortex with musical notes to developing stronger ropes.

We should be open about the fact that much of the European explosion in

science emerged not so much from the onset of a single procedure but

through the scrabbling for deeper insights, even through abortive

attempts within the tradition of magic and the occult. Those currents

that most resemble modern science in Europe, like the development of

optics and telescopes, were for a while using the term “natural magic”

like Naples’ Academy of Secrets. The core element that drove such

advances was a suspicion that nature was governed by hidden forces and

that these that could be understood. That the secrets could be pried

open, deeper underlying patterns revealed. It was this radical drive and

fervor in the fringe communities of Europe that helped drive the

scientific revolution and really flourished when they were coupled with

the printing press’ distribution of journals to tradesmen and poor

tinkerers who leapt at the chance to contribute theories and findings

back.

In resistance some have taken to demonizing everything since the

European explosion as “western science” while validating virtually any

other explanation of the world as also “science.” And while their

conclusions that the cosmological models of some random witchdoctor

confined in experience to the Kalahari are equivalently valid to those

of a modern cosmologist is absurd liberal pluralism, it can be legit to

mark both as scientific. Models generated in other cultural or

historical contexts certainly count to varying degrees as reflective of

the arrow of radicalism. Although it’s no small point that any sort of

vigilance in today’s context should quickly reveal the failings of such

models, just as it quickly reveals the failings of those early European

“natural magic” theorists. There have absolutely been many brilliant

insights around the world and the portrait where “science” doesn’t

officially start until Francis Bacon decided to lecture physicists on

what they were doing is clearly a shitty imperialist narrative.

Mary Baker Eddy’s “scientist” “doctors” were certainly far less rigorous

or vigilant than many Chinese experimenters in medicine. Indeed Iroquois

or Chinese medicine would have been arguably better than the best

western doctors of the day. The atomic and fundamental element models

postulated by both Indians and Greeks obviously turned out to be pretty

close to the mark, but given how little there was to work with back then

early Chinese cosmology deserves appreciation as an also ran — the

yin-yang and wu xing mode were valid attempts to model the world. And

Bacon’s methodology and paradigm of experimentation? Alberuni, an Indian

Arab, had pushed for this in the middle ages and the 8-18th centuries in

India saw systematic experimentation too. Three thousand years of

science in northeast Africa burnt to the ground with Alexandria (the

word “chemistry” likely has its roots in a word meaning the knowledge of

“the black land”). On and on it goes, the astronomy of the early

Chinese, the navigational techniques of Pacific islanders, the ancient

medical knowledge of sub-Saharan Africans… Upon any investigation it’s

simply impossible to paint a picture of a discrete “western science”

that is disconnected from this global tendency.

Humans have always played with symmetries and metaphors, trying to

internalize better impressions of the world. Much of scientific

reasoning is so natural to us because we’ve been constantly doing it

since we were hunter-gatherers. Primitive cosmologies like animism and

panpsychism were quite reasonable early hypotheses. We’re a social

species with brains built primarily to navigate social relations and

model psychological dynamics; of course we would search for metaphors

there. And those that did should be lauded as doing a decent job in the

limited context they had access to.

The deeper regularities immediately visible in things like astronomy

have long been interesting to hunter-gatherers, but it was civilization

that happened to provide the scope, intellectual permanence and

continuity necessary to get further in our investigations. Of course

“civilization” is an absurdly simple way of bundling a wide array of

deeply conflicting historical currents and dynamics, and what elites

emerged in most (but not all) city societies often worked hard to

suppress science. Frequently as the first step in undermining radicalism

more broadly.

We’ve covered how “curiosity” was taken by the Victorian aristocracy and

draped over shallow and exploitative consumerism. But this attempted

appropriation followed another, more dramatic reversal: It was only in

the seventeenth century that curiosity had transformed from being seen

as a vice to a virtue. Before that watershed “curiosity” had been

consistently condemned by western civilization. The Greeks were actually

highly critical of curiosity, a tendency they felt was useless,

intrusive, and disruptive. Inquiry for its own sake, the hunger for

knowledge, was correctly identified it as uncontrollable or prone to

wildness. Curiosity was a force in conflict with the ossified and

sedentary structures of their civilization. The Christians continued

this prohibition and condemnation of curiosity, the desire for knowledge

was marked as fundamentally sinful. Rejecting the hunger of inquiry is

the very foundation of the myth of The Fall, a narrative repeated in

many societies riven with power structures. Once Authority ruled divine

and the natural order was unchallenged, then some damned girl got too

inquisitive for her britches and God could no longer maintain things the

way He liked.

Today’s primitivist ideologues emerged from a long genealogy of

complaints by the elites that the masses’ inquisitive desires

constituted a horrifying monster that had to be suppressed at any cost

lest it run amok. During the “Enlightenment” Bacon made the argument to

his fellow elites that by promoting a rigid systematizing, curiosity

after the roots could be harnessed by the state. But Hobbes’

contemporaneous attack on scientists for their abstract theories and

pursuit of understanding for understanding’s sake reflected wider social

forces seeking to suppress curiosity and that repeatedly ridiculed them

as boffins.

Some scientists persisted nonetheless, but few could be so fortunate or

tolerate the poverty and ignominy that would accompany it. Many tried to

find excuses or shields against public derision, and thus many fell into

collaboration with imperial, capitalist, and aristocratic power systems.

You see currents like this again and again throughout the fight between

science and power in history, with those in power deeply opposed to

hypotheses. Only desiring details.

Physics is intimately aware of this deep and bitter conflict. The second

world war saw most of the world’s physicists either forced to work as

engineers and technologists on weapons or at best starved of funding.

And this was paralleled and followed for decades by the widespread

blacklisting of the great number of physicists who’d been inclined to

radical politics. The legacy of those who embraced their service to the

state or crumpled under its thumb has been a vicious hostility towards

too sweeping of curiosity, imagination, and extended theorizing within

STEM practice. Physicists are today still split between those who

approve of or revile the bootlicking slogan from the Manhattan Project:

“Shut up and calculate.” Variants of this hostility and anxiety towards

theory permeate STEM culture, visible in some hackerspaces in the form

of “shut up and hack.” The cowed timidity and institutional allegiances

of engineers and data collectors versus the sweeping and unrelenting

audacity of the theoreticians.

The historical arc is clearcut: Whatever complicated entanglements

momentarily emerge in their long war, science and power are unavoidably

at odds. “I would rather discover a single cause than become king of the

Persians,” declared Democritus. What science represents is the sharpest

sort of radicalism possible, a kind of thinking and a desire in-itself

that is indomitable. The externalities of scientific inquiry overturned

established power structures and created immense instability and

complexities that are hard for power structures to navigate. Those power

structures that survived did so by awkwardly clinging to certain

predictable processes of change and trying to control and divert the

development of science. But even this is often laughable and is

certainly unlikely to be sustained.

The Social Context To Our Definitions

This restructuring of how to view science is geared not just at

defending science from charges of reactionism from leftists, but at more

broadly clarifying how we might view that much looser bundle invoked by

the word “science” as a political force. Because the array of things

popularly associated with “science” is so wildly varying and hazy most

of the political claims surrounding science that don’t slice it away to

near irrelevance or neutrality as a formulaic procedure have sought to

identify underlying ideological commitments and then define “science” in

terms of them.

The problem of course has been that those undertaking this kind of

analysis (aristocrats, industrialists, liberals, marxists, & continental

philosophers) very rarely have a radical bone in their body, and so we

see writers lazily claiming that certain popular scientific models or

paradigms that emerged briefly and with attendant explicit

qualifications are in fact the core driving ideology of science. And of

course — if they even note them — the emergence of alternative

scientific models is presented as science conceding defeat or pulling

itself apart from within. But it’s not as though newtonian mechanics

were some motivating religion, rather science’s drive for the roots

ended up legitimately judging newtonian mechanics as overwhelmingly

promising for an extended period of time.

This kind of rabid preoccupation with things like positivism, atomism,

and determinism (although almost always wild strawmen thereof) is rife

among those coming from an academic or political lineage whose contact

with science is Nth-hand at best. See in particular the ongoing

cringeworthy hazy-association-fest of lazy psychology leftists have

formed around the the word “quantification.” (To be sure, as a physicist

I make the obligatory sneers and jokes about the aesthetic inferiority

of discrete math to continuous math, but come on.) There are clear

reverberations of lingering PTSD motivating these defensive obsessions

and in some sense that’s quite understandable. There has, afterall, been

a good few centuries of those in power referencing or extending popular

scientific frameworks or theories to prop up terrible ideologies. But to

characterize ‘science’ in terms of those ideologies is akin to

characterizing an elephant by the leeches, ticks and flies on its hide.

They may have swallowed some tiny bits of it, but that doesn’t make them

the elephant. And at the end of the day they don’t decide where the

elephant roams.

Yes, the political, economic, social, and cultural commitments of

scientists as a class have in many ways been largely captured and

constrained by today’s most dominant power structures; just as those

unions most critically situated at points of weakness in the system were

long ago bought off, lumpenproles defanged with welfare, artists by

commerce, etc. Although ‘pure science’ is constantly being whittled away

as capitalism attempts to reshape and replace it by more easily

predictable, controllable and overseeable fields of engineering — and

basic science education is suppressed or replaced by tradeschool-style

training — those who remain have been urged in a multitude of ways to

identify with the status quo. It’s a simple fact that fewer scientists

today face murderous repression from the establishment’s fear of

disruptive effects. For a first in history the power structures ruling

our societies have come to uneasily rely on certain predictable marches

of development (although curveballs are still strongly discouraged). And

since the creation of the modern academic system most scientists have

come to rely on government funding in deeply problematic ways that

impede a shift to alternatives. But once identified — less as a

structured procedural commitment than a cognitive inclination or

orientation of desire — science is exposed as having intense social or

political inclinations almost entirely opposed to the interests of

science’s current benefactors/enslavers.

This recognition is of profound import to anyone looking for allies and

fecund frontiers of resistance, and presents a powerful way to push back

against those corruptive or appropriative forces that have been

exploiting the situation.

I’m interested in this restructuring of our language and narratives

around science because as an anarchist I come at science from a

stridently idealistic and radical perspective and thus am attracted to

those currents within it. But also because — having consequently

developed a background in high energy theoretical physics — it’s

continually astonishing to me the vast disconnect between the analyses

of “science” popular within the left and the actual reality in the many

fields close to my own work. A lot of what I’m saying is mainstream in

physics and has been for a long long time.

While “purity” within the sciences is a widely recognized dynamic and

common joke fodder, somehow few philosophers or pundits of science have

felt any need to build any recognition of this into their definitions of

science, or even mention it. (Richard Dawid deserves special mention

here for recently taking some rarely listened to perspectives on science

not being equivalent to empiricism common among theoretical physicists

and finally giving some of our perspectives a voice in philosophy

departments.)

The abusive and unproductive wall erected after the erasure of “natural

philosophy” between science (as any immediately testable hypothesis) and

philosophy (as literally any theorizing) has pressured scientists to be

shortsighted and shallow in their theorizing and given bad philosophical

models sufficient buffer from rigor and the march of new discoveries.

And when philosophy does come up with anything concrete it’s immediately

no longer classified as philosophy! Not only is this unfair but

obviously it has a terrible influence upon philosophy!

Of course when philosophy and science aren’t defined in contrast to one

another it’s much harder to present some kind of unified Scientist

front. A definition of science centered on radical analysis would

undermine the “we’re all in this together perspective” that a lot of

science communicators have pushed to rally solidarity against attacks

and to give disparate researchers a sense of ownership or investment in

work beyond their own field. But honestly we shouldn’t have solidarity

with many people in the STEM world. We could all do with more clarity

about people’s varying underlying motivations and less fuzzy-wuzzy

collective identity. If those STEM minds in conservative, religious or

anti-intellectual contexts want to huddle around each other for warmth

they can surely do so without obscuring important distinctions over

motivations and degrees of rootedness. Our language should not be

defined in reaction to the Kansas school board.

Tackling Militant Ignorance

Yes, in some immediate sense stepping back from the shallow litmus tests

for science weakens our rhetorical toolbox when it comes to rejecting

pseudoscience. But I don’t think it’s worth risking our clearheadedness

by twisting our conceptual language just to more quickly win some short

term battles. We can still grapple with these people directly. Not with

“it was peer reviewed! 99% agree!” badgering appeals to democratic

morality, but by directly calling out the intellectual laziness of

denialists. It’s unfeasible to personally tackle each and every

anti-vaxxer, chemtrailer, or cartesian dualist; the amount of energy

necessary to generate bullshit is always orders of magnitude less than

the amount of energy necessary to refute it. There are maybe ten

thousand times more wingnuts with strong opinions about particle physics

or neuroscience than there are particle physicists or neuroscientists in

the world. We will never beat back all their diverse nonsenses

one-on-one in Facebook comment sections, and implicit appeals to social

pressure via arguments from ‘scientific consensus’ fail when a climate

change denier or quantum mystic is already subject to social pressures

of consensus within their more immediate community of fellow wingnuts.

The root problem with the people “contesting” evolution or the big bang

or whatever isn’t that they’re doing it the wrong way or using the wrong

tools of argumentation; it’s that they don’t actually care about

understanding. They care about the sensation of knowing, or the

appearance of iconoclasm, or a fantasy of the gold star they might wrest

away from the establishment. Our pluralist liberal society obsesses over

the equality of all opinions, in which my ignorance is as good as your

knowledge, and consequently in which abusers can never be pinned down

because “everything’s subjective.” We leap to find opinions and then

raise them as identity-banners. And so we bristle at the notion of

better or more objectively reachable accounts that might disrupt our

most fond self-deceptions. The ugly reality is that if people put even

the faintest effort into vigilant inquiry we wouldn’t be having these

debates.

Tackling that means tackling a huge array of social ills.

First and foremost we should be focusing on making the models or

arguments we’ve discovered more accessible. As we lower barriers

dramatically there will cease to be any excuse for the smug 37 year old

punk with a theory of gravitation as friction. Or the endless barrage of

numbskulls in the anarchist milieu — from oogles rejecting treatment for

scabies because “science is a religion” to Wolfi citing wildly off base

secondhand misaccounts of quantum mechanics and getting lauded for it.

Point them to the mappings. Quickly call out the particulars: “Okay, how

do you account for __ ?” Scientists already do this by habit.

Often however we utilize existing barriers to entry as a kind of wall

slam in people’s face. Someone repeats the well popularized woo that

quantum mechanics has anything to do with conscious “observers” or the

poorly defined notion of “consciousness” itself and we quickly snap that

quantum mechanics is a just a theory of complex probabilities, of

operators in a hilbert space, and continue rattling off mathematical

context until the wingnuts feel sufficiently browbeaten or at least

leave us be.

This is highly understandable, and often there’s no better tool

available to make the frothy nutjob or haughtily ignorant continental

philosopher go away, but it is unfortunate. Exploiting unfair existing

barriers to scientific knowledge to harangue those on the outside is

hardly in keeping with the core idealism of science.

Thankfully there are presently many projects on various levels to

restructure every aspect of science as an institution. Peer review,

journals, even colleges themselves are under constant criticism and

attack in the core of science. And while physicists led the push decades

ago to open source everything and bypass or abolish intellectual

property, it’s well past time to make that material not just available

but accessible. Doing this, replacing peer review with more organic,

open, and situationally nuanced associative networks of trust and

decentralized certification, is no simple task, but many are working on

it. Just as many are working to replace the astonishingly primitive

technology of pdfs with a richer more deeply tagged and accessible

literature, ideally leading to fields of knowledge as mindmapped wikis

where dependencies and sources are instantly visible. The solution to

people with smugly uninformed opinions is to take away any excuse for

their ignorance. To build a culture where our instincts are to just look

something up if you’re interested in it rather than to try and

accumulate ‘opinions’ from shallow data as though building a record

collection.

I’ve heard people in the left or the supposedly post-left milieu sneer

and argue that the deplorable filters of pop science reporting are the

fault of scientists, that we are complicit in the whole circus that

leads to horrid phrases like “god particle” and all the narratives that

get validated as a result. And there’s an ounce of truth to that. Not in

the sense that we scientists presently feel anything other than

murderous rage at the pop science media machine, but that there are

still many wars for us to win. Thankfully we’re clearly up for the task.

I will never forget the day the head of my old department discovered

Wikipedia. With bags under his eyes from an all-nighter editing articles

he animatedly and earnestly beseeched his statistical mechanics class

“Did you all know about this? Why are you all here when you could be at

home learning on your own? I wanna blow off my next class to adopt some

of my lecture notes! Oh! I guess this means I’m out of a job. Huh. Oh

well! Good riddance actually.” All good scientists hunger for the death

of academia, in the sense of our present institutional context, this

gross distortion, this unnaturally frozen battlefront in the struggle to

expand science to everyone. It is unfortunate our relatively recent

treaty with the state and other appropriative forces led to an abrupt

freeze in the previously exponentially increasing ranks of scientists.

We don’t always appreciate this violent pruning of science, the prison

signified by our still small numbers, but the loss is astonishing when

you plot it out.

I delight at the inevitable accusations of “imperialism!” I will receive

for the crime of desiring to persuade people or even make arguments more

accessible, but outreach does have to be nuanced. Instead of outright

declaring “you should want this” we need to go after the biggest traps

people get themselves into. I find myself having to tackle the old

“anyone can argue anything!” quite frequently: Well that’s quite a

surprisingly strong statement! How do you know every possible

perspective is perfectly and evenly mappable into all others? How can

you be so certain that when considering every possible meta structure

for ‘argumentation’ there are not emergently inferior and superior ones?

You seem to be extrapolating very vigorous results from a very small

dataset of personal experience!

But there are many more holes people dig themselves into, and some are

quite relatable.

Who You Trust Is A Legit Question

The reality is that people not trusting scientists or scientific

consensus is in many regards reasonable. What are you going to trust,

your eyes and everyday lived experience or a single teacher in school

and some nerds online?

Most arguments over catching people up to scientific knowledge usually

come down to 1) how integrated a person is with a relevant culture,

society and institutions, and 2) how unoppressed they are. There are

many other logjams and twisted arguments that can occur, but these tend

to be the most primal. If no one you know can in any meaningful way

vouch for the stranger thumping on the Particle Data Group book their

claims of peer review and the like will appear no different than a

theologian claiming to be correct because other theologians have

checked. And of course, if you’re locked in modern versions of chattel

slavery, exploring the workings of the universe is not really a good

strategy for survival; nor will your first instinct be to trust the

claimed findings of those who do have that privilege.

Honestly the only reason a good number of folk these days would sneer at

anyone saying sun goes round the earth, that Jesus rode dinosaurs, or

that the universe is 6,000 years old, or that anthropogenic global

warming isn’t real, is that they recognize these claims as cultural cues

of being on ‘the wrong side.’ It’s a not-popular thing. A shun the

“outgroup” thing. As such appealing to the spirit of social consensus

and democratic moralism is a weapon that will almost always backfire on

scientists.

To most of the kids that get shuffled into ‘radical politics’ or the

like scientists are the outgroup. The cultural divide that takes root in

college between STEM majors and humanities majors has been long cemented

and reinforced. And the few scientists in this whole affair tend to sigh

and keep their heads down rather than contest every nonsense. Meanwhile

expecting someone whose gone through the theoretical and social

conditioning of academic fields that practically define themselves by

suspicion and hostility to science — someone whose social connections

are almost certainly overwhelmingly in the same boat — to just cede

before the overwhelming consensus within the scientific community is

like telling a FOXnews troglodyte to adopt queer terminology because

everyone in San Francisco is doing it. It’s just totally disconnected

from the realities of social pressures, and it expects magic from human

trust networks.

Why on earth should you trust what one teacher says? Or wikipedia the

time you strayed over to it? You don’t have knowledge of the immense

amount of work it would take to maintain a false belief within say

mathematics journals, so both sides appear roughly equivalent. Science

appears to most as just a codification of what’s popular in certain

circles except with those people saying “it’s extra true because someone

somewhere totally tested it, whatever that means.”

Smart people come up to me and express derision or discomprehension of

science all the time. A skilled hacker asks me bemusedly at a party, “so

you actually think there’s like truth??” Brilliant girl in my high

school chemistry explains why she doesn’t pay attention in class,

“Theories in science are always changing, why bother learning one, it’ll

be totally different in two hundred years anyway.”

These express themselves as philosophical critiques and sometimes

develop into more challenging ones, but they’re grounded in a sense of

social alienation and a rebellious dismissal of seemingly arbitrary

authority.

It’s not for nothing that one of the most instinctive ways Leftists have

interacted with science has been by critiquing sources or playing games

of slander by association. “Don’t get me started about Game Theory, it

was invented by a paranoid schizophrenic who worked for the government

and feared communists.” (Nevermind its parallel discoverers or that game

theory has ultimately provided some of the strongest arguments for

anarchism and clearest insights into the landscape of challenges we

face.) Similarly it’s quite popular today to talk about “cybernetics”

and criticize anything that touches information theory by cherrypicking

the ideologies and rhetoric of associated parties — an approach that

quickly grows so disconnected from the actual reality of the material

and field that it starts to sound like conservative rants about

“cultural marxism.”

(Although quite a few authoritarians have spun out hopes that it would

provide tools for absolute control, cybernetics’ objective success in

grasping root dynamics has also revealed profound limits to the

information processing capacity of power structures and computational

neuroscience has enabled a much richer and more productive ethical

discourse. “Cybernetics” in fact is a sweeping term mostly used by its

critics. The actual fields bundled up in absurd polemics like Tiqqun’s

do not easily fit in the grand ideological narratives claimed by these

critics. Additionally, since every essay on how the ‘inherent logic’ of

cybernetics somehow inexorably saddled us with our current surveillance

state loves to point to the reactionary associations of a couple famous

researchers, let me point out that one of computational neuroscience’s

most influential early pioneers, Walter Pitts, was a homeless runaway

from a poor family who’d joined a commune of radical supporters of the

Spanish Revolution.)

There can be — of course — a sliver of relevance to who the original

discoverers are and what assumptions or constrained perspectives may get

subtly baked in, but an even remotely scientific field is quite a bit

different from say endless discourses on the writings of Heidegger;

models and paradigms in science are frequently replaced rather than

merely appended with footnotes and there are a multitude of very strong

pressures in scientific practice driving researchers toward the same

underlying root dynamics. That’s the ideal at least. But it’s a coherent

and substantive ideal that many discourses asymtotically approach and

that we are all the better for having a term for.

When alleged ‘radicals’ these days rail against science what they’re

typically arguing against — or at least what they get started rallying

against — is having to integrate with the social and institutional

structures mediating such ‘facts’. The semi-ironic embrace of mysticism

and the occult among the queer community and twentysomethings more

broadly is such a successful sociopolitical signalling game not just

because of the boogeyman of Dawkinsite atheists and the broader STEM vs

humanities culture war, but because it publicly demonstrates a rejection

of the authorities and institutions that have positioned themselves

between scientists and just about everyone else.

The error here isn’t not trusting the account of those with the right

magic words. It’s — again — not investigating more thoroughly or

proactively. A stark case of Gell-Mann Amnesia whereby people recognize

when the institutions of power appropriate and drastically misrepresent

one’s own team, but then immediately assume those same institutions and

media gatekeepers are more or less honest about everyone else.

Anarchists are happy to recognize how poorly “anarchy” is represented in

the media and how many appropriators are out there, and yet so many of

us embarassingly turn around and take representations and claimants of

“science” at face value.

Modern liberalism asks us to wrap ourselves in as many flags as

possible, to feel entitled to the sense of identity provided by a strong

opinion. Doing due diligence by looking at depth into the subject is in

no way seen as a prerequisite, and since the goal is social positioning

there’s no impetus for such investigation.

However I don’t highly trust someone’s account of a mixing angle because

it’s spoken in the magic tongue of science, but because I’ve done a lot

of looking into the social and cultural context, because I have many

points of contact with it, and thus I know how difficult it would be for

a lie to propagate or persist. Further I’ve compared theories and

considerations myself, followed them down into their nitty-gritty and

seen just how elegant and more realistic an account is.

And yes there often really is a universally accessible or “objective”

direction of “better theory.” Although it can be hard to precisely

compare two theories roughly close to each other in virtues, a broad

gradation between possible models is strongly apparent upon any fucking

due diligence.

All this is maddeningly hard to convey to people with a limited

vocabulary of experiences to draw upon. You have to go digging around in

the systemically impoverished lives of those deprived meaningful contact

with science and find the one experience that will make such dynamics

clear. Someone to whom all discussion of say ‘complexity’ is meaningless

hot air with no connection to anything in their lives cannot really be

expected to fathom any talk of scientific legitimacy outside of

experimental validation, and even that is likely to be tough going. Many

people in our world lack critical qualia, have never even experienced

basic things we take for granted, and it is fiendishly difficult to

catch them up. Try explaining turbulence to someone who has never played

with water or watched clouds fly by. I’ve listened to multiple people in

various contexts demonstrate that a system is non-linear in a trivial

way and then promptly sit back under the impression that such equates

unsolvability.

Part of the solution is obviously — as most scientists know and will

angrily rant to you at length about — destroying the prison system

masquerading as “education.” The “disgustingly boring gymnastics used

only for punitive purposes,” as a mathematical physicist I’m friends

with characterized them, that comprise all contact with supposed

“mathematics” most students ever have bares as little relation to the

actual practice as spelling bees do with literature or poetry. Of course

to merely list the myriad failings of how we are “educated” would

require the space of a book, so I won’t bother trying. But that is only

one component of a wide array of ways our present society suffocates and

denies access to deep and incredibly important concepts or experiences

regarding how the world functions that are necessary to build better

intuitions.

And even chucking those is not enough. It would not be enough to burn

this horrid system to the ground because many of the monsters impeding

access to or understanding of science have sown the ideological seeds of

their own upkeep and reestablishment.

It is, after all, not just an education or accessibility problem, it’s

also a vigilance problem.

So What’s The Hold Up?

So why do people fail to even set out on paths of exploration that would

eventually lead them to catch up and recognize science? Why do people

turn away from radicalism to reactionary perspectives?

What we must remind ourselves is that people will be prompted by their

contexts to grow into different cognitive strategies. A child that’s

beaten for exercising inquisitiveness will quite rationally decide that

thinking is a bad strategy in life. It’s often quite rational to stop

being rational, or at least to abandon intellectual vigilance. (There

are many competing popular definitions of “rationality,” some expansive

to the point where they describe literally all possible developments in

a neural net and others far more specific and aspirational, I am not

deeply wedded to any one.)

Sometimes when the goal is feeling smart rather than actually being

right, the most optimal strategies are postmodern rationalizations that

add more and more complications and slippery fallacies of association in

a kind of fractal way until it’s turtles all the way down and your

interlocutor can’t vanquish them as fast as you can generate them.

Particularly common in our society is the strategy of enforcing rituals

and spectacles of public modesty that aggressively drag yourself and

everyone else down to avoid any one of you ever being challenged.

Obviously this is the case most of the time when the outraged howls

start of “How can you claim to know anything? No one knows anything!

You’re just a confused slob like the rest of us! How dare you put on

airs!” Too frequently people in this situation start talking past each

other with entirely different notions of humility.

People are deeply afraid of science’s potency. Scratch that, it’s much

broader: People are deeply afraid of intellectual vigilance. They’re

afraid of fields they haven’t studied. They’re afraid people will come

at them one day with something from beyond their horizons that overturns

and shakes up their core perspectives or narrative of self.

The reason commentators try to fence in science, make it trivial or

incidental to our lives is because they can feel the magnitude of its

philosophical impacts lurking. There are, after all, no a priori truths.

Just deeply seeded priors that can be overruled by sufficient

conditions. Physics might very well reveal that causality or time itself

don’t work the way we develop a working assumption of at a very young

age. Physicists are unafraid of overturning the kind of intuitions

biology or our formulative experiences have built into us, but for lots

of people there’s a catastrophic sense of vertigo — and soon after,

rage. How dare you!

Yet all we humans ever do is model the world. Even logic and the most

cherished axioms are just models that have to be chosen. We see patterns

and look for stronger patterns. To discount the search for the strongest

possible patterns is to cast oneself to the winds of happenstance. And

ultimately it risks unmooring one from any good reason to even believe

in other people’s existence. If you have some kind of deep assumption

about the universe or even how you think and science reveals deep

failures of your model or better alternatives you have to postulate an

increasingly conspiratorially extended and implausible alternative

explanation of how the scientific consensus is rife with somehow

systematically unseen failures. Soon you’ve added piles and piles of

redundant or unnecessary complexities, even magical interventions. You

are pulled more and more towards solipsism.

And yes, sure, this can feel freeing. People with little agency in their

world often find any sensation of ‘possibility’ freeing, even incorrect

or deluded possibility. There’s an unlimited number of models incoherent

internally or with one’s experiences, and they’re all relatively easily

morphable into one another. This freedom of mind can be exhilarating,

but it offers a false and limited freedom, because a failure to

understand the world around you means an inability to move it.

The radical impulse is critical. It’s long been noted that people with

some basic intelligence but no deep drive often realize they can “argue”

anything and, upon such realization, stop, failing to examine the

meta-characteristics and topologies to such expanses of possible

“arguments.” Because the utility of vigilance is not immediately obvious

their instinct to rigorously examine atrophies and they get away with it

by simply upping the complexity until no one can manage to call out all

their mistakes. I once heard an 80 year old professor sincerely argue

that — never mind their individual persuasiveness or coherency — because

he had more distinct arguments for creationism it was therefore correct.

We’re playing the “how can we use words to figure dynamics out” game,

but so much of society is instinctively playing the “how can we use

words to manipulate and get what we want” game, habits that have been

adopted by the naive as well. That sort of thing is not a conversation

and it’s certainly not worth bothering with. You can always arbitrarily

increase the complexity of a stupid argument to fend off critique. The

formula is simple: start with some loud populist appeals to common

everyday abstractions, models, or language (however unfounded) and pour

on supporting claims and excuses with increasing complexity until

challenging them is too exhausting. Through this process you can marshal

armies whenever you like.

There are infinite possibilities when you abandon coherence, simplicity

and empiricism. But the infinite is boring, it’s a quagmire. What

science represents is the winnowing down of the infinite, the pursuit of

the most fascinatingly unique possibility (or possibilities).

The problem with Christian Science isn’t that it’s unfalsifiable;

falsifiability, while certainly a useful indication, isn’t absolutely

critical to science, and there’s nothing unscientific about postulating

that the entire world might be an illusion. Even though we may label

extensive thinking about it as unfruitful, we still note the possibility

and are honest about it. And — as with Boltzmann brains — there are even

fringe considerations that could have ramifications or relevance or

testability. Thinking about models involving reality being simulated,

for example, has prompted people to narrow down possible signatures

given certain assumptions regarding the hidden reality that can be

compared with experiment. The unscientific leap is just how wildly

arbitrary the claims are once you get beyond the mere statement that our

entire impression of material reality could be a lie. There’s a very

large infinity of possible configurations of hidden realities, of which

Christian Science’s claims about God etc are but one. They say suffering

is an illusion but why not claim that non-suffering is the illusion? Why

not postulate that we’re all in the dream of a cosmic green sheep? Etc.

A model with infinite arbitrary parameters is a bad model. Or at least

it’s uninteresting, or a bad model on which to predicate communicating

or collaborating with others. Hell, we need to find unique points within

the space of possible models that everyone else can identify just to be

able to meet each via those frameworks.

‘Christian Scientists’ love to claim that their conclusions follow from

a priori introspection, but the more broadly and vigilantly one engages

with the world the more one sees just how limited introspection can be

and prone to confusion or accidental self delusion. The language of

subjective experience and introspection is riddled with errors that it

alone is incapable or dramatically inefficient at recognizing. Whereas

cognitive science provides us with another useful vantage point to

integrate and rectify these mistakes. At the end of the day the

presumption of fully a priori meditation is simply not as good a

framework as the neurological model and any question you want answered

in the former can be revealed through the later as either more

efficiently and directly answerable or poorly posed and thus ultimately

unanswerable in any model. Consciousness, the self, and the ideological

edifices built in the language of subjective experience are in many ways

spooks, errors, narrative simplifications with fraying edges to their

usefulness upon any close investigation, akin to when marxists talk in

mystical ways about Capitalism or primitivists about Civilization as a

moving spirit more than the sum of its parts. The entire cartesian

assumption of an a priori vantage point is ultimately a faulty model

when examined from all angles or pushed to its breaking points.

Of course someone could retort in a Zerzan-esque vein that the only real

reality is immediate sensation and any conceptual processing of that —

any modeling of any kind — is the “abstraction.” Nevermind how easy it

is to verify things like our blind spots and optical processing defects,

our immediate sensations or qualia are not just often wrong, they have

to be heavily processed by neural columns for us to make sense of them

in any way that corresponds to the world we interact with. Indeed the

less “modeling” we do the less we’d be able to see or hear. And if you

attempt to discount those wellworn insights of neuroscience the number

of other things you must discount to do so spreads in effect quite

rapidly and dramatically. Especially if you have any instinct towards

intellectual vigilance.

There is a kind of circularity here, but it should really be viewed as a

matter of feedback. If you’re interested in parsing through your

sensations in pursuit of deeper relations, you’ll discover that any

rigorous examination reveals the superficiality of “immediate

impressions.” And conversely if you wall yourself off from such

investigations, if you champion the reactionary ideology that

immediatism is all that matters, you can ignore anything else. However

there’s a difference between these two positions. Radicalism is a stable

and attractive equilibrium, whereas reactionism is unstable under

perturbation. Once you start investigating you’re quite likely to

encounter evidence that your immediate impressions are wrong and that

deeper dynamics exist, which increases your evaluation of how useful

root-seeking is.

However the way from one equilibrium to the other is not always an easy

slide. If one revolts at the thought of searching to clarify fundamental

dynamics then one will revolt at the very idea of investigating a

definition of “science” that isn’t all-inclusive of every association,

every appropriating charlatan, and every rhetorically dressed up

atrocity. What one might call the postmodern instinct has been to reject

breaking apart conceptual bundles to identify separable sub-dynamics and

instead speak of ‘real existing science’ — the entirety of everything

its name gets slapped on — and look for fuzzy tendencies across this

abstraction. This approach takes the macroscopic abstraction as

foundational, certain rough commonalities as characteristic qualities,

and then handles any exceptions or additional complexities by means of

perpetually appending footnotes and excuses. Great for justifying

people’s preexisting impressions, opinions, or allegiances. Terrible at

better mapping the dynamics at play. As such it’s incapable of spurring

progress or meaningful change.

Conclusion

It goes without saying that we shouldn’t waste our lives fighting a war

over every preferred definition. Language is often fluid, and not every

term can be redeemed. A “language” is often really forked into many

simultaneous languages and there can be strategic and empathic virtues

in swapping between them. But it’s also important to have our terms

describe the most meaningful realities or distinct dynamics they can.

Gaping conceptual holes, unspoken or unspeakable realities in a given

language, can end up having a huge impact in our lives and impeding our

capacity to fight. Language determines what we focus on by default, what

gets left as awkward addendums, and thus what loops of debate we most

frequently retread trying to get at realities outside the terms we have

available.

When possible it’s good practice to shift our language to clearer and

more conceptually distinct and workable definitions of terms, regardless

of popular associations. This is after all the foundation of our

redefinition of anarchy. “Anarchy” is a nebulous word whose use varies

wildly. But its most widespread associations beyond the anarchist milieu

bundle in the assumption that there can be no freedom from the

oppressive dynamics of rulership, that our only speakable choice is

between fractured or unified power structures. Anarchism was founded on

a revolt against this orwellianism, and it has retained enough

distinctiveness to spur resistance to appropriation of that term by

neonazis, capitalists, and maoists as our respect has risen.

The situation with science is similar. There is a sharply distinct

subset within what gets called “science” who few would deny qualify as

science. This subset is a lot more distinct in certain ways that matter

than the “any empiricism” set and unfettered by its failings. The

present widespread identification of science with the merely anything

empirical or data-related consistently invalidates by association the

valid work of this subset, for whom there is presently no other

identifying term available besides “science.” Further this subset was

who science was originally centered on, who it appropriated from, and

it’s a subset that has vehemently and vocally resisted the wider

definition. It has accumulated various social institutions, cultures,

and other parasites around its practice but these are obviously distinct

from the core idea.

The science that lies at the core of and drives anything one might call

“science” is characterized by a radical impulse: to search for the most

deeply rooted patterns, to push beyond the existing or the immediate,

into extremes, to look for what can break and how, and to not be afraid

of throwing everything out, all in order to better grasp what is

possible.

We need to be humble about the complexity of our world, but audacious in

searching for models anyway. We must reject the traumatized mewling that

“you can’t ever know anything” or the abusive “how dare you compare

things” but also shy away from accepting shallow impressions.

This is the beating heart of science and it is what has driven its rise,

rectified its mistakes, and continually resisted its capture by power.

It is what makes it the most fecund site for resistance in our world

today.