💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › miguel-amoros-primitivism-and-history.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 12:26:46. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Primitivism and History
Author: Miguel Amorós
Date: March 2003
Language: en
Topics: anarcho-primitivism, history, philosophy, indigenous
Source: Retrieved on 8th May 2021 from https://libcom.org/library/primitivism-history-miguel-amor%C3%B3s
Notes: Translated from the Spanish original: http://www.bibliolibertaire.org/catalogue_des_textes_en_espagnol.htm

Miguel Amorós

Primitivism and History

1. The Sect of the Dog

Back in the middle of the Fourth Century B.C., a vagabond philosopher

lived in Athens and Corinth, a philosopher who employed extravagant

gestures and a provocative attitude to preach the rejection of all

civilized conventions and a return to nature and spontaneity. Diogenes

the Cynic, originally from Sinope, a city on the shores of the Black

Sea, practiced what he preached: he lived in a clay jar, he neither

voted nor participated in any other way in a citizen’s duties, he had no

fixed occupation and attended to both the “matters of Aphrodite” (sex)

and the “matters of Demeter” (eating) in public. He went about with his

staff and his coarse blanket, which served as his clothing by day and

his bedding by night, and a wallet containing the simple items of his

frugal diet that he acquired by begging, which never included cooked

food. Criticizing the false idols that ruled the lives of his

contemporaries, or the democratic institutions that had been perverted

by tyrants and demagogues, or the social hypocrisy concealed behind

allegedly sacred values, he opposed the laws of nature to those of

society and chose the animals as his model, seeking freedom in a life

without encumbrances outside the confines of the polis, far from its

laws and prejudices. He laughed at exile, the worst punishment that

could be inflicted on a Greek, and proclaimed that he was a citizen of

the world; he said, “the only true commonwealth is that of the

universe”. He also rejected property and the family and advocated the

community of goods, women and children: “What I possess is not mine.

Relatives, friends, family, fame, familiar places, lifestyle, all these

things are foreign to me.” [I was unable to locate an English-language

source text for this quotation; it appears to be a

paraphrase—Translator’s note.] Under the law of nature, men, women and

animals were equals, and therefore all varieties of incest are legal (a

minor detail of free love), because they are natural, and even

cannibalism is legal (“because all elements are contained in all things,

and pervade everything”). Violence, however, the source of all evils,

was not legal under the law of nature, nor was the idea of the

fatherland or money. Harmony with the universe would be the necessary

result of the abolition of war and warriors, and of money and

patriotism. Along the same lines, Epicurus, the founder of a later

school of thought, discouraged his disciples from submitting to the

regular Greek educational curriculum and condemned participation in

politics. Like Diogenes, he was addressing the cosmopolitan individual,

that great invention of the Greek world, and proposed that individuals

withdraw from the public realm and live a quiet life surrounded by

friends and lovers, based on a simple diet, the satisfaction of natural

desires and the enjoyment of genuine pleasures, that is, wisdom and the

absence of pain.

The teachings of the philosophical school of the Cynics, which include

the teachings of Diogenes, therefore constituted the first primitivist

critiques of civilization. Their appearance at the end of the classical

period of Greece, in the midst of the full-blown crisis of the polis,

reflected the contrast between the letter of the law and the dreary

reality of everyday life. The civil wars between Sparta and Athens led

to the collapse of the values of Greek civilization. The meanings of

words changed and the civic virtues were transformed into their

opposites due to the greed for power and partisan politics. Corruption

and partisan conflicts had free rein. According to Thucydides: “Thus

religion was in honour with neither party; but the use of fair phrases

to arrive at guilty ends was in high reputation. Meanwhile the moderate

part of the citizens perished between the two, either for not joining in

the quarrel, or because envy would not suffer them to escape” (The

Peloponnesian Wars). Shortly before this era, during the early period of

Hellenism, the Greek cities suffered under the oppression of organized

power and the favored classes. At that time, no one felt that the laws

protected them and therefore no one felt like a member of a civil

community. Hegel said that, “for philosophy to arise among a people, a

rupture must take place in the actual world.” Man takes refuge in

thought when public life no longer satisfies him, when moral life has

dissolved. The Greeks began to think about nature when they lost all

interest in their world and everything around them was turbulent and

unhappy. This phenomenon is not at all surprising. The Greeks did not

conceive of man as emancipated from the universe or separated from

nature, and thus they perceived no opposition between nature and man.

The universe was an ordered world, the source of just relations, a model

in which one could discover the social order “that is in conformance

with nature”. The works of men could not be superior to the works of

nature; at most, they could approach perfection to the extent that they

inserted themselves into nature and reflected its order. With regard to

this question, Epicurus said: “If you do not on every occasion refer

each of your actions to the ultimate end prescribed by nature, but

instead of this in the act of choice or avoidance turn to some other

end, your actions will not be consistent with your theories.” The polis

was a system based on the cosmic laws, a natural system that had been

perverted, and had become something foreign, or “barbarous”. It was

therefore “more Greek” to return to nature. Given the absence of the

historical dimension of time among the Greeks, the end was only the

beginning. The Romans experienced this same state of mind when the

Republic fell. During the subsequent stage, that of the Roman Empire,

the primitivist refusal underwent a resurgence as a myth in literature

and as a reality in the periphery of the empire.

2. The Golden Age

During the Third Century B.C., Zeno the Stoic began his career with a

description of a society in which there were no differences of personal

status, or racial distinctions, or party politics, a kind of egalitarian

world community devoted to sun worship. Ever since the time of Hesiod

there was a primitivist tendency in Greek thought that conceived of life

as it was lived in the distant past as the reign of Pan, a golden age of

abundance, innocence and happiness. The poets sang of the Happy Isles

inhabited by “heliopolitans”, and thanks to the historian Diodorus

Siculus we know that flowers and fruits were plentiful there, and that

nothing was owned by anybody; that everyone took turns using land, food

and tools, and it goes without saying that promiscuity was generalized.

Theocritus situated the pastoral scene in Sicily, but it was a rugged

and inhospitable region of central Greece, Arcadia, that ultimately came

to embody the myth of the original happy condition. Virgil, in his

Eclogues, describes Arcadia as containing lush vegetation, perfect for

meditation, in eternal spring, without suffering, where everything is

leisure and love: “Far from discord and weapons, the land that is so

prodigal for justice provides an easy living…. Man has to do no more

than pick the fruit from the branches and farmland is produced for his

benefit spontaneously. He enjoys a repose without disturbance and an

existence that is rich in various resources.” [This appears to be a

paraphrase rather than a quotation from the Eclogues—Translator’s note.]

Ovid, in his Metamorphoses, provides a similar version of the beginnings

of history, of the times “before Saturn was deposed by Jupiter”: “when

Man yet new,/No rule but uncorrupted reason knew:/And, with a native

bent, did good pursue./Unforc’d by punishment, un-aw’d by fear,/His

words were simple, and his soul sincere;/Needless was written law, where

none opprest…./The teeming Earth, yet guiltless of the plough,/And

unprovok’d, did fruitful stores allow.” Saturn had to take refuge in

Italy with its first inhabitants and according to Pompeius Trogus, “The

first inhabitants of Italy were the Aborigines, whose king, Saturn, is

said to have been a man of such extraordinary justice, that no one was a

slave in his reign, or had any private property, but all things were

common to all, and undivided, as one estate for the use of every one….”

The aspiration for happiness derived not from the impossible idea that a

new society could be built, but from the evocation of a primeval

paradise that would recur at the conclusion of a cycle that was

characterized by decline and ruin. For the Roman Empire, this cycle

began in the Third Century. From then on Gaul and Spain experienced

massive uprisings of outcasts known as the bagaudae that could not be

suppressed by large armies. The bagaudae were fugitive slaves, military

deserters, impoverished dependent farmers, and city dwellers fleeing the

destruction of the cities, who fled to the forests seeking the freedom

that they could not enjoy in civilization. There, they formed gangs that

expropriated landlords and besieged the cities, managing their internal

affairs by means of a “natural” justice that was unrelated to that of

the Empire, without magistrates or governors. In a dialogue that has

been preserved from that era (Querolus), a citizen asks his lares to

guide him to a place where he can be happy. They responded by telling

him to go to the Loire Valley, the territory of the bagaudae, because

“Men live there under natural law. There is no suffering there. Capital

sentences are proclaimed under the oaks and are engraved in bone. There,

even the country people speak and the ordinary people pass judgment. You

can do as you please….” This is an account of the first primitivist

revolt in history.

Neither the disintegration of the Empire nor the Germanic invasions

destroyed the Greco-Roman world. It was the radical transformation with

regard to how the world was viewed that was propagated by Christianity

that was really responsible for the destruction of the Greco-Roman

world. The gods abandoned the universe, which was now the exclusive

creation of God, and cosmic harmony was broken for the benefit of man,

who was made in God’s image. The anthropocentrically interpreted world

was devalued and reality lost its substance in favor of the beyond. This

was a transitional place, an episode in the transcendent drama of

salvation. Spirit and the world, man and nature, were irremediably

separated. This dualism prevailed in the West until the continuing

development of the material and spiritual conditions of medieval society

provoked the emergence of tensions and conflicts that led to the

elaboration of two different approaches to the problem: one, that

originated among the theologians, based on the disenchantment of the

world pursued to its most extreme consequences; the other, inspired by

the intellectuals, based on the exaltation of the culture of antiquity

and the rediscovery of nature through observation and experience. Reform

and Renaissance.

3. The Millennium

Religious reform rejected the doctrine of salvation by way of the

sacraments, and left man alone to face the consequences of his actions

and forced him to rationalize his conduct. The world—and therefore

civilization—was as a result even more deprecated than was the case

under Catholicism. One more step in this direction led to the appearance

of sects that turned their backs on the “world” and avoided any

relations with non-believers. Attachment to the world was an impediment

to the revelation of faith by the Holy Spirit, and therefore to the

overcoming of irrational subjectivity (of the primitive state of man).

In an attempt to adopt the lifestyle of the primitive Christians, the

sects preached the community of goods and followed the Bible literally,

rejecting any interpretation. Among the adepts of the Free Spirit, a

sectarian movement that, under various names, spread during the 13^(th)

century across a large part of Europe, the spiritual emancipation of man

was pursued by way of the identification of God and the radical

rejection of private property. One of the members of this sect, Johannes

de Brünn, preached to his followers: “Leave, leave, leave your homes,

your horses, your possessions, your land, leave it, remember that

nothing is yours, you possess everything in common….” At first, however,

the call to return to a lost Golden Age, to a natural egalitarian

condition that could be realized in the present, a state that the Church

Fathers had interpreted as the prelapsarian paradise, did not find many

supporters, but when the message was propagated among the poor peasants

and the impoverished people of the cities, as was the case in Flanders,

Picardy and England (the revolt of John Ball), the idea became a

revolutionary myth of the masses. Dissident preachers like John Wycliffe

championed it and spread it throughout Europe, triggering revolutions in

Bohemia, Germany, Holland, etc. (the Hussite revolt, the peasant wars,

the Bundschuh, the Anabaptist movement). With the feudal world in full

disarray, alongside the Protestant reformers an apocalyptic plebeian

party announced the immanent arrival of the Holy Spirit and the return

of 1,000 years of primal paradise, a classless and totally free society,

in which authority would be abolished; the society lost since the Fall

of Man, that is, since the advent of civilization. While the Protestant

reformers prepared the world for capitalism, the plebeian party attacked

“Babylon” (the commercial cities) and burned books. Although only a few

radical factions actually practiced the community of goods—the Adamites,

the extremist Taborites, certain groups of Anabaptists, etc.—all of them

proclaimed the imminence of a kingdom of equality, where all will enjoy

all the goods of nature, of river and forest, of fish and game, in

common, and where all will receive what they need and where there will

be no distinctions of status or estate and everyone will be like

brothers and sisters; a kingdom that will be inaugurated at the end of a

battle of extermination against the Anti-Christ and his hosts, that is,

against the State, the Church and the ruling classes. As the agitator

Thomas Müntzer proclaimed: “On! On! On! Let not your sword grow cold,

let it not be blunted. Smite, cling, clang, on the anvil of Nimrod, and

cast the tower to the ground...”, calling for the most complete social

destruction. Nimrod was the builder of the Tower of Babel and was

considered to be the first creator of cities, the inventor of private

property and of class distinctions, that is, the destroyer of the

primitive State of Nature.

The analysis made by Engels (The Peasant War in Germany) of these

revolutions is erroneous. He judges that they were only capable of

formulating a communist program in a “fantastic” form that could not be

realized given the limited productive forces of that time. Not only does

he succumb to the mistake of blaming them for not knowing things they

could not have known, but he also judges them on the basis of ideas that

had not even been conceived yet. Thus, by scorning the real content of

the revolts he condemned himself to misunderstanding them, and under the

appearance of “historical materialism” he simply asserted the debatable

view that communism only became possible with the total development of

the proletariat, or, which amounts to the same thing, with the full

unfolding of the bourgeois conditions of production. It is true that,

far from being primitive and chimerical elaborations of a

nineteenth-century emancipatory project, those uprisings pursued the

abolition of the feudal world via the extremist realization of the

Christian ideal. The millenarianism of the peasant and urban plebs was

precisely what they wanted it to be. It was not a movement against

history because it remained on the terrain of the myth of the earthly

paradise and was alien to the Protestant bourgeoisie. Its goals—the

destruction of the Church and of the power of the princes, and the

realization of the Millennium—were perfectly possible under those

historical conditions, and they did not require any other language for

their expression.

4. The Diggers

During the decline of the Middle Ages a sentiment began to be expressed

in literature that reflected a yearning for the simple pastoral life and

the dream of natural happiness, which represented, that is, the bucolic

ideal, which revealed a vital desire for pleasure. The Ancient World was

not so distant. In the particular conditions of the Italian cities, one

of which was the existence of an educated class, a culture linked to

antiquity flourished that awakened an interest in, and a desire to

understand, nature. This attitude restored to nature the reality that

Christianity had taken from it. The world was no longer represented as a

rigid sphere with God—or the Earth—at the center, and was revealed to be

infinite. Religion ceased to be the instrument that made the world

intelligible and yielded this role to the testimony of the senses and

experience. Religion no longer served as a veil for existence and nature

became the field of action for human experience. But it must be recalled

that this change of perspective, which was generalized at the end of the

16^(th) century, affected only the educated class of the cities, that

is, the core population of the bourgeoisie. The uneducated classes that

comprised the majority of the population were unaffected by this

intellectual ferment and expressed their ideas in religious terms. As

late as the time of the English Revolution we can still contemplate the

attempt to use the Gospels to overthrow society. Gerrard Winstanley, the

leading personality among the Diggers, a faction of the Levelers,

replaced the word “God” with “Reason”, because “… I have been held under

darknesse by that word, as I see many people are”. This Reason is a

revealed Reason; a voice told him the news: “work together and eat bread

together, doth advance the law of Reason and Righteousnesse,” but it

also told him that hell does not exist and that heaven is within men. He

referred, like all the rest of his predecessors, to a primal Golden Age.

“In the beginning of Time, the great Creator Reason, made the Earth to

be a Common Treasury, to preserve Beasts, Birds, Fishes, and Man, the

lord that was to govern this Creation; for Man had Domination given to

him, over the Beasts, Birds, and Fishes….”. The egoism of some men,

however, created authority and servitude, and led them to appropriate

the natural wealth that was the common property of all, especially the

land, inventing arbitrary laws to justify their usurpation. The

“Diggers” based freedom on the free enjoyment of the land and proclaimed

that they must “lay the Foundation of making the Earth a Common Treasury

for All, both Rich and Poor, That every one that is born in the land,

may be fed by the Earth his Mother that brought him forth, according to

the Reason that rules in the Creation”. They advocated an economy

without money, organized around public storehouses where everyone would

bring the products of their labor and from which everyone could take

what they need. In practice, they broke down fences and occupied common

lands and the lands of the nobility in order to cultivate them, carrying

on the tradition of previous peasant rebellions by acknowledging the

slogan of an unpartitioned land, without property lines or fences. They

also refused to pay the tithe, they did not respect the rules regarding

Sundays and they demanded the rule of natural justice and Reason without

the mediation of judges and priests. Borrowing the words of Debord that

were less justifiably applied to the peasant wars, we can say that the

struggle of the Diggers was a “revolutionary class struggle speaking the

language of religion for the last time, which is already a modern

revolutionary tendency that as yet lacks the consciousness that it is

only historical”. This shortcoming was the result of the separation

between the educated and the uneducated classes, between spiritual and

material necessity, since the popular classes, primarily the peasants

(the English “yeomanry”), were trapped between the bourgeoisie and the

aristocracy. It would be a constant feature of history that obliged the

representatives of the bourgeoisie to clothe themselves in the vestments

of the apocalypse. Even in the middle of the 19^(th) century Georg

Büchner wrote to his friends in the Young Germany group: “Reform society

by ideas? Impossible! Our epoch is altogether materialistic; if you were

to act in a strictly political manner, you would soon reach the point

where reform comes to an end on its own (….) And the majority class

itself? For it, there are only two levers, material poverty and

religious fanaticism. Every party that knows how to manipulate these two

levers will be victorious. Our time needs steel and bread—and only later

a cross or something else….”

5. The Noble Savage

In 1493 Columbus sent a letter to the Secretary of the Catholic Kings,

Luis de Santángel, summarizing the results of his voyage to “the

Indias”: “Hispaniola is a marvel. Its hills and mountains, fine plains

and open country, are rich and fertile for planting and for pasturage,

and for building towns and villages. The seaports there are incredibly

fine, as also the magnificent rivers, most of which bear gold. The

trees, fruits and grasses differ widely from those in Juana (….) The

people of this island and all the others I have found or been informed

of go about totally naked, men and women, naked as the day they were

born, although some women cover one place with a leaf or a piece of

cotton cloth they make for that purpose. They have no iron, nor steel,

nor weapons, nor are they fit for them, because although they are

well-made men of commanding stature, they appear extraordinarily timid

(….) It is true that since they have gained more confidence and are

losing this fear, they are so unsuspicious and so generous with what

they possess, that no one who had not seen it would believe it. They

never refuse anything that is asked for. They even offer it themselves,

and show so much love that they would give their very hearts. Whether it

be anything of great or small value, with any trifle of whatever kind,

they are satisfied.” The accounts of the Spanish and French explorers

provide ample material for the reconstruction of the figure of the noble

savage, an image of freedom that had been fragmented by the shattering

of the unity of the Church, the State and earthly life. When Montaigne

wanted to study “the human condition”, a very unusual topic for that

era, he read the travelers’ accounts published in Francia Antarctica:

“what we now see in those nations, does not only surpass all the

pictures with which the poets have adorned the golden age, and all their

inventions in feigning a happy state of man, but, moreover, the fancy

and even the wish and desire of philosophy itself; so native and so pure

a simplicity, as we by experience see to be in them, could never enter

into their imagination, nor could they ever believe that human society

could have been maintained with so little artifice and human patchwork.

I should tell Plato, that it is a nation wherein there is no manner of

traffic, no knowledge of letters, no science of numbers, no name of

magistrate or political superiority; no use of service, riches or

poverty, no contracts, no successions, no dividends, no properties, no

employments, but those of leisure, no respect of kindred, but common, no

clothing, no agriculture, no metal, no use of corn or wine; the very

words that signify lying, treachery, dissimulation, avarice, envy,

detraction, pardon, never heard of. How much would he find his imaginary

republic short of this perfection?” (Essays). Montaigne thought it

fitting to call them barbarians if they were judged by reason, but not

if the standard of judgment would be a comparison with the civilized,

who exceed them in barbarism. He did not even hesitate to claim that

their language, of such an agreeable sound, recalled the accents of the

ancient Greeks. He concluded by referring to the response that one of

the indigenous people, who had been brought to France, gave to King

Charles the Ninth. Asked about how people lived in his country, he

shockingly raised the issue of the leveling of conditions: “… they had

observed, that there were among us men full and crammed with all manner

of commodities, while, in the meantime, their halves were begging at

their doors, lean and half-starved with hunger and poverty; and they

thought it strange that these necessitous halves were able to suffer so

great an inequality and injustice, and that they did not take the others

by the throats, or set fire to their houses.”

The myth of the noble savage would be put to use as a political weapon

of reason. In The Adventures of Telemachus, Fenelon would revisit the

theme of “natural man” and would point to the latter’s antagonism with

civilized man: “We look on the manners of these people as a beautiful

fable, and they must needs look upon ours as a monstrous dream.” In

describing the delights of “Betica” he was actually talking about

certain idealized Canadian aborigines. Its inhabitants live in tents,

all together, without any possessive attitude towards the land, where

there are gold and silver mines, although “the inhabitants, plain and

happy in their plainness, do not even deign to reckon gold and silver

among their riches; they esteem nothing but what really subserves the

wants of man.” Furthermore, “[a]s they had no foreign trade, they had no

occasion for money. They are almost all shepherds or husbandmen. There

are in this country few artificers, for they tolerate no arts but those

which subserve the real necessities of man….”. Superfluous goods are for

wicked men, slaves of the false needs upon which they mistakenly believe

their happiness depends: “They have no need of judges, for every man

submits to the jurisdiction of conscience. They possess all things in

common; for the cattle produce milk, and the fields and the orchards

fruit and grain of every kind in such abundance that a people so frugal

and temperate have no need of property.” And, thanks to the fact that

they flee from vain wealth and deceitful pleasures, they can remain

united, free and equal, peaceful, monogamous and proud of their way of

life: “[t]he Beticans would forsake their country, or choose to die,

rather than submit to servitude. It is therefore as difficult to subdue

them, as they are incapable of desiring to subdue others.” The content

of this work follows a clear purpose: Fenelon contrasted the corrupt

society of Louis XIV with a natural communism, showing, on the one hand,

the incompatibility between the bourgeois world and absolutism, and, on

the other hand, the political weakness of the incipient French

bourgeoisie.

The expansion of the horizons of the world and of the possibilities

inherent in it posed the problem of how man would live; the discovery of

the American tribes contributed to the construction of a theory of the

natural origin of society and the State that could be used to refute the

contrary theory of divine origin. While in France this theory revolved

around utopian constructs, in England, the country where royal power had

been battered by a revolution, bourgeois formulations were much more

carefully tailored. In 1609, Garcilaso de la Vega ordered that his Royal

Commentaries be printed, in which he described the birth and development

of the Inca state of Peru. He maintained that the Inca provided the

proof of the existence of an almost perfect State that ruled, “in

accordance with the teachings of reason and natural law”, every minute

of every day of the lives of its subjects. The Incan Empire had arisen

from the primitive state of nature, free and egalitarian, thanks to the

cities of a mythical founder, Manco Capac. The work was translated into

French and English, and was influential among the enemies of absolute

monarchy, especially John Locke. Thus, from the ranks of the Whig party,

the bourgeois party that disputed power with the English monarchy and

the aristocrats after the revolution, Locke defined the state of nature

as “a state also of equality, wherein all the power and jurisdiction is

reciprocal, no one having more than another; there being nothing more

evident than that creatures of the same species and rank, promiscuously

born to all the same advantages of nature, and the use of the same

faculties, should also be equal one amongst another without

subordination or subjection….” (Of Civil Government: The Second

Treatise). According to Locke, this state was altered by the

transgression of natural law that was brought about by the greed to

possess more than what was necessary and the unwillingness of some

people to work, which obliged the inhabitants to construct a

contract-based society. The people, seeking protection, renounced part

of their individual freedom and submitted to a superior power created by

general agreement. The rationalist philosopher called “natural” what was

in fact only “historical”. Natural law was nothing but the idealist

formulation of the bourgeois social norm.

6. Natural Law

If the “geometrical” consideration of nature characteristic of

rationalist philosophy (such as that of Descartes or Spinoza) deduced

enormous potentials for man within the confines of nature, expressed in

the idea of the perfectibility and progress of civilization, for other

authors (such as Pascal), the disenchantment of the world by science and

reason revealed an infinite cosmic void, foreign to the human being,

provoking an existential disorder in man, who was now lost in a little

corner of the universe. This latter perspective led to the renunciation

of the world and to religion. As the contradictory side of civilization

began to be revealed, doubts arose regarding the guarantees of freedom

and happiness that the progress of science and the arts was supposed to

bring in its wake. The great debate of the century of the Enlightenment

was that of nature or civilization, progress “of the arts” or moral

progress. For some, one could be happy in ignorance; culture caused

inequality and was the source of error, unhappiness and poverty. For

others, exactly the opposite was true. Modern thought, however, was

irremediably separated from the idea of God and gravitated towards life,

for which contemplative retirement could not be the solution. According

to Abbe Raynal the study of the lives of primitive peoples must have the

purpose of making “the ignorance of the savage shed light in some way on

the civilized peoples.” In the discussions of the savage, therefore,

three positions can be delineated. One followed the path of utopia. In

1753 Morelly’s Wreck of the Floating Isles, or Basiliad of the

Celebrated Pilpaï was published, which was an apology for natural

anarchy and a veritable manual of primitivism. On a blessed isle there

lived an innocent and free people who knew how to reject the temptations

of laziness and wickedness and attended to nature’s harmonious message,

which rather than hindering, actually enhance passions and desires. On

this isle there was neither property, nor marriage, nor religion nor

privilege. Luxury and the accumulation of wealth were forbidden.

Society, formed without an explicit contract, was composed of small

communities that practiced agriculture and the arts and engaged in

mutual aid, obeying no other law than nature. As for culture, they only

needed one book that covered everything. Another position, which is

indebted to Hobbes, paints the life of the savage in the most somber of

colors. According to this view, the primitive man, far from being happy,

suffers from hunger and countless afflictions that make him a ferocious

and cruel being, and that drive him to a perpetual state of war against

all other men. To escape such a risk-filled condition he had to enter

into an agreement not to harm the others and to help them when they

needed help. Holbach maintained that the savages, because they were

deprived of reason, cannot be free, and that freedom in the hands of

beings without either culture or virtue was like a knife in the hands of

a child: “The Savage Life or the state of nature towards which some sad

thinkers have wanted to drag mankind, the golden age that was so highly

praised by the poets, is actually only a state of poverty, of

imbecility, and of irrationality. Inviting us to participate in such a

life means that we are being told that we should return to our infancy,

that we should forget everything we know, that we should renounce the

enlightenment that our minds have been able to acquire: meanwhile,

unfortunately for us, our reason is still quite underdeveloped, even in

the most civilized nations” (Système Social). Freedom therefore depends

on a society ruled by law that is inspired by nature, whose goal must be

human happiness. Abbe Marly, halfway between Holbach and Morelly,

suggested the happy medium was “perfect equality” obtained by means of

the community of goods, since property engendered avarice and ambition,

passions that the legislator had to combat (On Legislation or the

Principle of Law). Marly advocated Spartan equality, the enemy of

science and the arts, since the latter had separated man from the state

of nature, and Athenian freedom, based on the total transfer of

authority to the social body. A third position, that of Rousseau, who

followed in the footsteps of Locke, simultaneously rehabilitated the

egalitarian primitive community and also consecrated the State with the

popular will and the “contract”. This is the content of the Discourse on

Inequality. For Rousseau inequality did not exist in the state of

nature, it only made its appearance when man emerged from that state,

when he formed society: “The moment one man needed the help of another;

as soon as it was found to be useful for one to have provisions for two,

equality disappeared, property appeared, work became necessary, and the

fast forests changed into smiling Fields that had to be watered with the

sweat of men, and where slavery and misery were soon seen to sprout and

grow together with harvests.” This period corresponds with the

introduction of agriculture and metallurgy. From the cultivation of the

land one arrived at the division of the land and from there at property.

The arts brought with them an endless series of needs that seized upon

man. Then, as a corollary, came exploitation and wars, laws and

institutions. As a result, civilized man has lived under the constraints

of superfluous desires and artificial passions. But “When savage man has

eaten, he is at peace with all nature and the friend of all those like

him (…) since savage man desires only things which he knows and knows

only things which he is capable of possessing or which are easy to

acquire, nothing should be as tranquil as his soul and nothing as

limited as his mind.” With regard to the balance sheet of advantages and

disadvantages, the civilized world was in the red, because we never

found a savage who wanted to become civilized but there were many cases

of civilized people who went to live among the savages. The novel

explanation for this fact was that happiness had nothing to do with

reason but with feeling. Finally, by considering freedom as a gift of

nature and property as a social convention, Rousseau provided a decisive

argument for egalitarianism, and exercised more influence than any other

author on the French Revolution, Romanticism and Socialism.

The publication of Bougainville’s Voyage Round the World in 1771 gave

rise to discussions concerning the state of nature and the image of the

savage. Once again, the depiction of a natural and happy world was

transformed into the mirror where civilized society could identify its

malaise and its misfortune. Tahiti, with its voluptuous nature and the

sexual freedom of its inhabitants, became the focal point of the moral

preoccupations of the era. The savage continued to be the cause of the

nostalgic dream of a virtuous and happy life in harmony with nature.

Diderot would express this better than anyone else in his “Supplement to

the Voyage of Bougainville”: “How far we are from nature and happiness!

The empire of nature cannot be destroyed. However much you handicap it

with obstacles it will endure (….) How short the code of nations would

be if it conformed rigidly to the law of nature. How many errors and

vices man would be spared!” Civilized taboos will never be able to

eradicate man’s natural inclinations, at most they can dissimulate them,

to his misfortune: “Would you like an abridged account of almost all our

wretchedness? Here it is. There existed a natural man. There was

introduced into this man an artificial man: and a civil war, enduring

the whole of life, arose in the cavern. Sometimes the natural man is the

stronger, sometimes he is struck down by the moral and artificial man.

In either case the poor monster is pulled about, pinched with tweezers,

tortured, stretched on the wheel.” Diderot resolves the dilemma of

whether one should civilize man or abandon him to his instincts in the

following manner: “If you aspire to be a tyrant, civilize him…. Do you

wish him to be happy and free? Then do not meddle in his affairs.” For

Diderot the history of political, civil and religious institutions was

nothing but the history of tyranny over the human species. In the final

analysis, if you have to choose between civilization and nature, “Really

I cannot say. But this I know. Townsmen have several times been seen to

strip themselves and return to the forest. The woodsman has never put on

clothes and come to the town.” The enlightened man did not renounce

civilization, nor did he seriously consider the advisability of putting

an end to progress. The opposition between nature and reason was

insuperable using only the instruments of reason, but the philosophy of

the 18^(th) century was absolutely unaware of this. What Marx called

“eighteenth century Robinsonades” were in reality an anticipation of the

bourgeois society that had been in gestation since the 16^(th) century.

In this society based on contract, each individual was dispossessed of

all natural bonds, bonds that in the medieval era had made him an

integral and indivisible part of society. The savage was the

idealization of the isolated individual that was a product of the

dissolution of the feudal world. The idea of the savage was an outcome

of history rather than the starting point of history.

7. Equality

During the French Revolution, the specifically bourgeois current as well

as the “sans culottes” constantly invoked nature and its designs,

swearing by Rousseau or Marly. The agitator Anacharsis Cloots, a

self-proclaimed “citizen of humanity”, claimed to have discovered his

political system, “The Republic of the Human Race”, by consulting

nature. Taking an example at random, the oration of the Abbe Fauchet

before the “The Friends of Truth”, we read: “Man was originally a

product of nature in the fullness of his existence and in society; he

was established in the midst of its realm in order to enjoy the good

things of life, to take from it what he needs to survive, to sweeten and

to embellish his existence, and to accumulate by means of his personal

efforts the goods supplied by nature (….) He got enjoyment out of his

existence; he took possession of his domain; he identified the gifts

that were destined for his use; he increased his pleasure by the

exercise of the faculties that enabled him to make constant

improvements: labor was not a punishment for him; it was an agreeable

elaboration of his power and his genius. He was happy as a result of the

serenity of reason and the sweet society which doubled his happiness by

the help of his neighbor; he was happy due to the generosity of the

earth and the simple efforts that multiplied his pleasures; such was the

state of man in the golden age of nature…. Man was born free; this

beautiful faculty was given to him so that he could rise to the

challenge of his destiny and in order to second the intentions of

nature, which was so favorable for him….” By living in society man

separated himself from nature and turned his back on its principles, and

suffered tyranny and injustice. Man can never return to the golden age

but something of that age can be reproduced if society were to be

ordered in such a way that “all have something, and each does not have

too much”, in brief, if it can be ordered in accordance with the ways of

nature: “It is upon natural law that legal institutions must be based

for the first time. The model is neither ancient Greece nor ancient

Italy; it is immutable nature: the social order must adapt to nature, or

else the human race will be eternally miserable (….) Opinion rises to

the level of nature: men want to be happy and just; and they will be

because their will is totally united in favor of happiness and justice.

No power can resist them when nature is on their side, when they march

freely under its commands….” According to Marat, man in nature, in order

to defend himself from the oppression and injustice inflicted on him by

others, has the right to rebel, rob, subjugate and kill if necessary.

The unrestricted exercise of this right would have led to a permanent

state of war and in order to escape this fate man renounced some of the

advantages of nature in favor of the advantages of living in society:

“he renounced his natural rights in order to enjoy his civil rights”; in

short, he signed a social contract. “Thus, the rights of nature

acquired, by means of the social contract, a sacred character. Because

men all received the same rights from nature, they must have equal

rights in the social condition.” But the contract may be broken if there

are privileged persons who enjoy themselves at the expense of the poor:

“justice and wisdom demand that at least part of these goods should be

destined, by way of a judicious allocation, to be shared out among the

citizens who have nothing; for the honest citizen abandoned to poverty

and to hopelessness by society, returns to the state of nature and

therefore has the right to demand with weapons in hand not only the

benefits that he had not renounced but to obtain other greater benefits

as well” (“The Constitution”). This was a unique expression of the right

to insurrection, which Marat called, in accordance with the political

jargon of the era, “the return to nature”. The French revolutionaries

were becoming more and more aware of the danger posed by the inequality

of fortunes, or, which amounts to the same thing, class differences. The

most radical among them suggested compulsory equalization, a leveling of

property that pointed towards the idea of common property, but their

proposals were at first limited to subordinating property rights to the

interests of society, thus undermining its basis. For the deputy from La

Meuse, Harmand, “equality of rights was a gift of nature and not a favor

granted by society”. For the Republican Antonelle, “nature did not

produce property owners, just as it did not produce the nobility; it

only produced beings with nothing, equal in their needs as in their

rights.” The struggle for equality was the crowning moment of the

Revolution and its most enduring demand, but the appeal to communism

took place on the occasion when the bourgeoisie separated itself from

the plebeians and persecuted them ruthlessly. For the conspirator

Babeuf, too, property was not a natural right; to the contrary, “the

condition of community is the only just condition, the only good

condition, the only condition that is in conformance with the pure

sentiments of nature and outside of that condition peaceful and truly

happy societies cannot exist”. In order for the dispossessed to believe

that communism is more than just a dream they will have to recognize

that “the fruits of labor are for all and the land is owned by no one”.

Primitivist communism was the last upwelling of the French Revolution

and the first form that expressed the future emancipatory ideology of

the proletariat, the last class produced by history.

8. Terra Incognita

The rational understanding of the world created the foundations for a

new freedom at the same time that it unleashed the forces that would

hinder its realization. The domain of nature, far from achieving freedom

for man, subjugated him more completely than religious despotism.

Science and reason were no better than revelation and the divine will.

The advent of industrial civilization, offspring of applied science and

technical progress, with its long train of destructive consequences,

entailed the worst slavery: wage labor. The instrumental fruits of

Reason gave birth to a monstrous civilization in which both man and

nature were devastated. The opposition between the city and the

countryside grew more pronounced than ever. The people of the

countryside saw how the new laws passed by the bourgeoisie deprived the

majority of them of their means of subsistence, and they were expelled

and concentrated in the most pestilential quarters of the cities. The

cities grew in size and became more and more ugly at the cost of an

enslaved mass of human labor power and prisoners of misfortune. The

individual experienced, in the form of boredom and neurosis, the

disparity between his abstract freedom and the social repression of his

impulses. The confrontation between the ever-narrowing world and the

hypertrophied individual took the form of a unique ideological product:

Romanticism. The Romantics set feeling and passion, or nature, against

reason and progress, or society. Chateaubriand formulated the individual

drama: “Let us listen to the voice of our conscience. What does it tell

us about Nature? ‘It is free.’ And about Society? ‘It rules’.” They

directed their curiosity towards the past, towards the adolescence of

man, to unknown epochs. For Victor Hugo primitive man was not separated

from the divine and that is why his way of thinking was composed of

dreams and his language was poetry: “Before the epoch which modern

society has dubbed ‘ancient,’ there was another epoch which the ancients

called ‘fabulous,’ but which it would be more accurate to call

‘primitive’…. In primitive times, when man awakes in a world that is

newly created, poetry awakes with him. In the face of the marvellous

things that dazzle and intoxicate him, his first speech is a hymn

simply. He is still so close to God that all his meditations are

ecstatic, all his dreams are visions. His bosom swells, he sings as he

breathes. His lyre has but three strings—God, the soul, creation; but

this threefold mystery envelopes everything, this threefold idea

embraces everything. The earth is still almost deserted. There are

families, but no nations; patriarchs, but no kings. Each race exists at

its own pleasure; no property, no laws, no contentions, no wars.

Everything belongs to each and to all. Society is a community. Man is

restrained in nought. He leads that nomadic pastoral life with which all

civilizations begin, and which is so well adapted to solitary

contemplation, to fanciful reverie. He follows every suggestion, he goes

hither and thither, at random. His thought, like his life, resembles a

could that changes its shape and its direction according to the wind

that drives it. Such is the first man, such is the first poet. He is

young, he is cynical. Prayer is his sole religion, the ode is his only

form of poetry. This ode, this poem of primitive times, is Genesis.”

(Preface to Cromwell). This spirit gave rise to an unusual interest in

traditions, legends and popular songs, but also in virgin, mysterious

nature, situated on the edge of the world, in “terra incognita”: “The

memory of a distant country overflowing with an abundance of all the

gifts of nature, the image of a wild and lush vegetation, reanimated and

fortified the spirit; oppressed in the present, we take delight in

getting away from our condition in order to enjoy that simple grandeur

that characterized the infancy of the human race” (Alexander Von

Humboldt, The Legend of El Dorado). Exotic countries, especially “the

Orient”, became the focus of interest (“Spain was still the Orient”). A

feverish passion developed for virgin islands (Robinson Crusoe and Paul

and Virginia were set on islands). Imagination was set above reason,

emotion above logic and intuition above experience. The lost connections

with nature—and with divinity—could not be reconstituted with the help

of reason. Freedom was the most valuable good of man that society could

not guarantee; it was sought outside of society, on its margins, among

the fugitives, the bandits, rebel peoples and savages. Society was

irremediably corrupt. An Indian Chief said: “I began to grasp that this

hateful mixture of ranks and fortunes, of extraordinary opulence and

excessive poverty, of crime without punishment and sacrificed innocence,

forms what in Europe is called society. That is not how it is with us:

among the longhouses of the Iroquois there are no great or small men, no

rich or poor, but hearts at peace and freedom of man everywhere.” Nature

not only appeared as the dream of freedom, rooted in a natural community

held together by feeling, but also as the goal towards which society

itself had to aim: “Can it be otherwise than that the highest degree of

civilization connects with nature?” (Chateaubriand, The Natchez). The

absolute liberty that was proclaimed and the society that existed could

not be more irreconcilable; Shelley said that if men were created by

Jupiter, they could also destroy him. The solution appeared to lie in

revolution, but the Romantics were more tourists than revolutionaries.

In any case, the solution did not lie in civilization; returning to

Chateaubriand: “Civilisation has reached its highest point, but a

materialistic barren civilisation, which can produce nothing, since one

can only create life through morality; one can only forge nations by

Heavenly means: railroads only carry us more swiftly towards the abyss.”

The present was no longer seen as a beginning but as an end; the

Romantic generation had become pessimistic and simply looked back to the

past. The multiple faces of disillusionment transformed the Romantic

ideology into an idealization of the past and a defense of archaic forms

of authority, reflecting the new form of post-revolutionary rule, the

fruit of the alliance between the bourgeoisie and the backward classes

that were in decline. In this spiritual atmosphere naturalist theories

suffered a profound setback at the hands of German idealism. By seeking

to situate man within historical becoming, that is, at the end of a long

series of civilizations, Hegel definitively ruined enlightenment

political thought and its Romantic heirs. Later, the Hegelians Marx and

Bakunin would proclaim to the four winds that freedom and equality were

social rather than natural facts, and that the proletariat, oppressed

humanity, must seek them among the debris of bourgeois civilization and

not in untamed nature.

9. Freedom

This change of perspective that Hegel’s works meant for the 19^(th)

century was total and was completely absorbed by socialist thought,

forcing the latter to break not only with the Christian metaphysic and

bourgeois positivism but also with the Rousseauian ideology of the

Revolution. It is often forgotten that Bakunin came of age in the

Hegelian left and that the origins of anarchism are incomprehensible

without taking this into account. Bakunin considered Rousseau to be the

worst of all the bourgeois ideologists on the basis of the assumption

that a social contract legitimized the State, a brutal and primitive

form of social organization. It was assumed that before the advent of

the State man was free but Bakunin thought otherwise about natural

freedom: “It is nothing but the absolute dependence of the ape-man under

the permanent pressure of the external world.” The freedom of primitive

man depended on his solitude: “The freedom of one of them does not

require the freedom of any other; to the contrary, every one of these

individual liberties is based on itself alone, it exists on its own, and

therefore the freedom of each necessarily appears as the negation of the

freedom of all the others, and all of them, should they meet, must limit

and restrict each other mutually, they must contradict each other and

destroy each other….” Up to this point Bakunin is repeating what Holbach

said; but now he parts company with him completely: “Man does not really

become man, he does not conquer the possibility of his internal

emancipation unless he manages to break the chains of the slavery that

external nature imposes upon all living beings.” Humanity was born the

slave of nature and its freedom begins when humanity is emancipated from

nature, that is, when it becomes civilized. From that point on a series

of historical circumstances determine man: “Man does not create society;

he is born within it. He is not born free, but enslaved, the product of

a particular social environment created by a long series of past

influences, of historical developments and events (….) It could be said

that the collective consciousness of any society, embodied in both the

great public institutions as well as in all the details of its private

life upon which all its theories are based, forms a kind of environment,

a kind of intellectual and moral atmosphere, one that is harmful but

absolutely necessary for the existence of all its members.” Freedom and

individuality itself were not natural facts but historical products

created by human society: “Society, far from reducing and limiting, to

the contrary creates the freedom of human individuals”; and further,

“the freedom of individuals is not an individual but a collective fact,

a collective product”, which argument he uses to refute the

individualist workers, whom he defined as “false brothers”. Marx said

the same thing: “Man is, in the most literal sense, a zoon politikon,

not just a social animal, but an animal that can only become an

individual within society” (Grundrisse). The cosmopolitan Bakunin

imagined man living outside of all society, in a desert, and concluded:

“If he does not miserably perish, which is the most probable result, he

will become nothing but a boor, an ape, lacking speech and thought”. He

even criticized the communitarian spirit of pre-bourgeois societies

which he called “natural patriotism”, even though the solidarity of

trades and communities was decisive in the first stages of the workers

movement: “The less civilization prevails in human communities, the less

complicated and the more simple is the very basis of social life and the

more intensely is natural patriotism expressed. Whence we may deduce

that natural patriotism is inversely related to civilization, that is,

to the triumph of humanity….”. However, it was “the barbarians who

represent, today, the faith in the human destiny and the future of

civilization, while the civilized can no longer achieve their salvation

except in barbarism.”

Even so, in socialism the victory over primitivism was not total. In his

Origins of the Family, Engels started from the basis of the primitive

community: “At all earlier stages of society production was essentially

collective, just as consumption proceeded by direct distribution of the

products within larger or smaller communistic communities.” At the

beginning, then, was the state of nature, the golden age that was

perverted according to Engels by the division of labor, which

successively gave rise to livestock raising, agriculture, metalworking

and trade. Then came private property, the accumulation of wealth, and

finally, the formation of classes in conflict, and then the State was

born in order to maintain a balance in the class struggle. This was a

reading of Rousseau and Hobbes in a socialist key, accompanied by a

quantity of data from historical and ethnographic research. Kropotkin,

for his part, would try to prove solidarity as a social principle by

looking in nature, which contains abundant examples of animal solidarity

(Mutual Aid). He would introduce an authentic theoretical breakthrough

by reducing anarchism to a mere Darwinist sociology and by making the

methodology of the natural sciences the guiding procedure of social

analysis. After Kropotkin, the roots of Bakunin’s thought would fall

into oblivion and it was normal to read Rousseauian discussions in

anarchist publications. Working class socialism, meanwhile, had become

reconciled to bourgeios society as a necessary but inevitable evil and,

as a result of this positive evaluation of the historical role of the

bourgeoisie, it was only a short step to the rehabilitation of the idea

of progress and the embrace of science and economic development. The

proletariat, by renouncing its own past, by forgetting that its movement

had made its debut with a bloody struggle against industrialization that

did not hesitate to destroy machines, factories and commodities, and by

ignoring the fact that its own interests demanded the destruction of the

labor market rather than its control, took this step. The bourgeoisie,

on the other hand, became more and more stratified, and became more

reactionary as a result of its position in the hierarchical class order,

and restricted its actions to defending its privileges and forgetting

about the general interest. As the bourgeoisie abandoned all the

reformist whims that previously, when it was revolutionary, had formed

its own patrimony, the proletariat, socialist as well as anarchist, made

those same demands its own. Anarchism, for example, constructed an

entire field of culture out of them: the idea of progress,

individualism, education for all, opposition to war, defense of nature,

family planning, birth control and the other themes of women’s

liberation, sexual freedom, health and nutrition, the dissemination of

scientific knowledge, etc. But despite the fact that the emancipatory

project of the workers had been enriched with new concrete contents that

were previously the property of the bourgeoisie, it nonetheless

experienced a setback. Social democracy became a reformist movement.

Revolutionary Marxism and anarchosyndicalism were the two attempts to

overcome this setback.

10. Nowhere

The worker of one hundred years ago could be defined by his dependence

on machinery. The machine had split the artisan into technology and

worker. The goal pursued was the rationalization of labor and the

principal consequence, the ejection of the worker from the process of

production. This process having reached its limit with automation, we

obtain a producer expelled from production (with a totally depreciated

wage) and a consumer who is absolutely dependent on machines. The

collective use of machinery changed nothing with regard to the worker’s

condition, and thus changed nothing with regard to the nature of his

exploitation, but only changed the leadership of the process, which was

now in the hands of experts or managers. As a result, the proletariat

that was thus split in two could not overcome itself, that is, free

itself, by way of the development of the machine or its communist use,

but by way of its disappearance. It is true that in some socialist

currents there were complaints about a “working class” civilization

conceived as a copy of the bourgeois civilization, but they were few and

only influenced a minority. It is significant that, as if acknowledging

the unlikelihood of the realization of their proposals, they presented

their theories in the form of utopian narratives. For example, in The

American Anarchist City [1914] by the anarchist Pierre Quirole, we read:

“It is true that everything that exists, the product of labor, must

belong to the workers. But the latter are deceiving themselves if they

want to ‘continue’ rather than ‘innovate’; for we must not imagine any

concept of a new society made in the mold of the current one; if we did,

it would not be worth the effort to move one little finger to help bring

it about. Everything that exists must be replaced by something more

rational and in conformance with real human needs. And Super denied that

coal mines, and the dreadnoughts of the sea, and the fiery dragons of

the rails, and the herculean automatons of the steelworks, are factors

that contribute to human well-being, happiness and freedom; he denied

that the electric trolleys that fill our streets represent progress;

that the tunnels and underground railways are necessary; or that the

great electrical generation plants that give us power and light

represent a benefit for mankind….” All of these creations born of a sick

civilization are condemned to disappear with the victory of the real

revolution because, “to continue exploiting the mines, to keep the

trains and electric trolleys running, to keep the lights on as we did in

capitalist society, to keep the factories and workshops in operation, to

take advantage, in short, of everything that currently exists, all these

sources of profit, regardless of what is done to perfect the machines

and the means of production, for the purpose of alleviating and

relieving the burden of labor, and to act on behalf of the condition of

the producers charged with their management, will always amount to

accepting the existence of an army of slaves eternally chained to the

same amount of demoralizing and unrewarding labor….” Therefore, the idea

of the expropriation of the bourgeoisie, as such, implies consequences

that are opposed to the libertarian goal. The legacy of a social

organization that was complicated, regimented and centralized by

technology was a poisoned legacy.

For his part, the socialist William Morris conceived of the free society

as the result of a process of reversing the ruin and depopulation of the

rural villages brought about by capitalism: “People flocked into the

country villages, and, so to say, flung themselves upon the freed land

like a wild beast upon his prey; and in a very little time the villages

of England were more populous than they had been since the fourteenth

century, and were still growing fast (…) People found out what they were

fit for, and gave up attempting to push themselves into occupations in

which they must needs fail. The town invaded the country; but the

invaders, like the warlike invaders of early days, yielded to the

influence of their surroundings, and became country people; and in their

turn, as they became more numerous than the townsmen, influenced them

also….” (News from Nowhere). In both cases a kind of return to

pre-capitalist conditions is advocated, but this return is to be

accompanied by the experience gained by fighting against capitalism. A

conscious return that does not reject the knowledge acquired in the past

and rather than establishing limits to technology, it oriented its use

to the achievement of a free society of equal producers.

11. The Country of Naturia

In fin de siècle Paris a certain Henri Zisly lived, an anarchist

railroad worker, a contributor to various magazines such as Temps

Nouveaux, an editor of L’Etat Naturel and the author of a Voyage to the

Beautiful Country of Naturia [Voyage au beau pays de Naturie, 1900]. He

was the first person to champion the cause of a nature that was enslaved

by industrial progress. For the anarchists generally, nature was made

for all free and equal men and the transgression of its laws was the

source of all social evils. Bakunin’s coffin had been sealed with seven

seals. In nature harmony reigned, that is, it lacked contradictions.

Anarchy was its norm. The social revolution meant the abolition of the

divorce between man and nature and the return to the natural life, via

the natural association of producers. The peculiarity of Zisly resided

in his disagreement with the standard view when it came to the means to

be employed. For most anarchists, firm believers in progress, the

separation between man and nature would be overcome thanks to science

and reason. For them, the natural organization of society was the same

thing as the scientific organization of society. Humanity was advancing

towards freedom arm in arm with science and the antagonism between

civilization and nature would be abolished. Zisly, however, did not

believe in the beneficent powers of science or in those of industrial

civilization; “our science is the science of life, the science of

nature”. With great foresight he blamed technological progress for the

disappearance of the forests, the disasters of pollution, climate

change, and the illnesses and degenerative conditions affecting plants,

animals and humans. “Civilization is evil and Nature is good”, he

concluded, and that is why he fought “against the monster of

civilization and for the advent of Integral Nature”. He recognized that

the emancipation of the working class was a prerequisite for a return to

the natural state. For the emancipation of the working class involved

the reconstruction of the natural state of the earth that had been

corrupted by civilization and a return to a primitive state of humanity.

How could this be achieved? By obeying the laws of nature. Avoiding

trade and industry. Abolishing private property and anti-natural needs.

Happiness would come from the satisfaction of basic needs like food,

drink, clothing, shelter, labor, love…. In his list of the things we can

do without, we find artificial lighting, stoves, bicycles, the

gramophone, wine, blouses, and windows and sheet metal. In the “normal

life” amidst the full enjoyment of “freedom in Integral Nature” the

whole world goes on foot and lives in cabins or at the most in houses

made of stone, without dancing, theater, auto races or bullfights.

Zisly was the first advocate of the naturist current in the libertarian

milieu, and far from devoting our attention to the silliness of his

claims or the simplicity of his alternatives, we shall interpret his

role as that of a defender of nature in harmony with man, a precondition

of his emancipation. Zisly and his friends had a better understanding

than anyone else of that time of the fact that the destruction of the

natural environment was the consequence of the technological

colonization (or artificialization) of society, or to put it another

way, of the domestication of man by machines. The exploitation of nature

was the other side of the coin of the exploitation of man. The

bourgeoisie identified progress with economic development. This progress

meant that nature was exclusively the stage for the unfolding of the

productive forces and the backdrop for wage slavery. The degradation of

nature proceeded in tandem with the degradation of the worker.

Anarcho-naturism, an eminently pedagogical tendency, contributed to the

program of social redemption the demand for a balance between nature and

humanity without which equality and freedom would be impossible. While

nature had to be humanized, man had to be naturalized. The influence of

anarcho-naturism is demonstrated by the policy statement on libertarian

communism of the 1936 Zaragoza Congress of the CNT: “… those communes

which reject industrialization, the naturists and nudists, for instance,

may agree upon a different model of coexistence and will be entitled to

an autonomous administration released from the general commitments.

Since such naturist/nudist communes (or communes of some other sort)

will be unable to satisfy their own needs, however limited these needs

may be, their delegates to congresses of the Iberian Confederation of

Autonomous Libertarian Communes will be empowered to enter into economic

contacts with other agricultural and industrial communes.”

12. Potlatch

The disenchantment of the primitive by ethnography, anthropology and

archaeology must shed light on the crossroads before which the civilized

world stands, rather than confuse it with nebulous ideologies.

Contemporary primitive societies employ little time in labor that is

necessary for survival; thus, they are not the false primitives who are

forced to engage in a constant search for food, for they never work more

than is necessary to meet their needs, that is, they are anti-work

societies. They are not subsistence societies; they are capable of

accumulating a surplus of food above and beyond their needs, but they

only do so in order to consume it or waste it, rather than use it for

trade. The kind of relations that govern their societies are not based

on exchange or barter because scarcity is unknown, but on the “gift”.

They are therefore societies without markets. This detail might be

useful for those who desire to recover the advantages of primitive life

for the free and civilized society. The indigenous peoples of the

northwest coast of North America engaged in contests of sumptuary

gift-giving in order to humble, challenge or compel their rivals, which

they called “potlatch”. This was an explosion of totally unproductive

wastefulness, whose goals were prestige and glory. It was on the basis

of this practice that Georges Battaille offered his suggestion about how

to overcome the conflict between civilization and savagery. From this

perspective the excesses of technology can be rectified. What technology

builds, man destroys. Technology acquires a new role, that of extending

the possibilities of dilapidation. Civilization cannot survive unless it

destroys itself in one gigantic potlatch. The social revolution was the

highest form of potlatch. Civilization’s only historical justification

was its revolutionary overthrow, when its surpluses would have to be

liberated for destruction. This scorn for wealth and rejection of the

fruits of labor was the real luxury, the luxury of the poor and the

refutation of the work ethic preached by domination. The permanent

revolution received a surprising theoretical confirmation. Ultimately,

this competitive destruction was not just a natural form of leveling,

but was also the finally discovered procedure that would permit the

reconciliation of man and the world. It might be objected that the

dynamic of destruction and construction is precisely what characterizes

capitalist civilization, but there is one important difference: the

active subject is different in this case. And the meaning of the process

is logically different, and indeed the opposite.

The primitivist critique of civilization must be of interest to those

who believe that the human ends—freedom and happiness—can only be

achieved with the dismantling the apparatus of production,

de-urbanization and life in community. We cannot, however, overlook the

danger that an erroneous formulation of the problem entails, with the

elevation of nature to a supreme principle (for example, nature equals

anarchy), for this would transform nature into a weapon to be used

against thought and against freedom. The abdication of the human spirit

in favor of nature, or the reduction of man to pure nature, would imply

a degradation of thought into irrational forms. To proclaim the

superiority of primitive man by situating paradise in the Paleolithic

era and original sin in the appearance of symbolic language, as John

Zerzan does in his Future Primitive, does not help clarify the problem

either, since the roots of human unhappiness are not to be found in

language nor can human unhappiness be cured by means of a return to

archaic times. The hunter-gatherer of the primitivists is nothing but an

idealized reflection of the atomized and déclassé individual of mass

society produced by late capitalism.

Nature is not the repository of the truth, only of the wild side. And

civilization is not simply the locus of the lie; it is also the locus of

history. Both have been subjugated by the independent power of the

economy, which is why they are both intertwined and form part of each

other. Dispossessed, separated from his works, submerged in alienation,

man is just as alienated from nature as from civilization, but the

latter is his battlefield. By making civilization his own, he will also

make nature his own. As a result, it is not a matter of man escaping

from civilization, but of creating a situation where civilization cannot

escape from man’s control. Nature will recover its proper status only

when man is free, and he will be free only when he controls his labor,

that is, when the powers he has created which have become independent of

him—the State, the economy, etc.—are destroyed. And then the knowledge

that primitive societies were societies without economies and without

States, because they did not allow the formation of any kind of separate

power, since they could not even conceive of the existence of desires

for wealth, power or domination within them, might prove useful.