💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › petr-kropotkin-communism-and-anarchy.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 13:21:19. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Communism and Anarchy
Author: Pëtr Kropotkin
Date: 1901
Language: en
Topics: anarcho-communist, classical, history
Source: Retrieved on February 25th, 2009 from http://flag.blackened.net/daver/anarchism/kropotkin/commanar.html
Notes: Freedom: July (p30)/August (p38) 1901. Reprinted in Small Communal Experiments and Why They Fail. Jura Books

Pëtr Kropotkin

Communism and Anarchy

Editor’s Preface

Peter Kropotkin (1842–1921) was one of the greatest anarchist

theoreticians of his time. Although he admired the directly democratic

and non-authoritarian practices of the traditional peasant village

commune, he was never an advocate of small and isolated communal

experimentalism. Many people, upon reading his works, have been inspired

to found such communities, both in his own time as well as the hippies

of the 1960s (a period when Kropotkin’s major works were epublished and

influential). Kropotkin did not consider such ventures were likely to be

successful or useful in achieving wider revolutionary goals. His friend,

Elisee Reclus, who had been involved in such a venture in South America

in his youth, was even more hostile to small communal experiments. It is

a pity that some of the founders of the many hippy communes in the 1960s

(nearly all of which faded rather quickly) did not read Kropotkin more

carefully. Unfortunately, they made the same mistakes as many

anarchists, communists and socialists had made a century before them. In

the anarchist press today one still finds adverts for prospective small

and isolated anarchist colonies. Also, many commentaries about Kropotkin

still misrepresent him as having had a vision of society consisting of

unfederated and independent village-like settlements and of advocating

small communal experiments as a means of achieving an anarchist society.

The following speech and two ‘open’ letters, which have not been in

print for a century, clearly show, that although not emotionally opposed

to such ventures, he was highly sceptical about their chances of success

and generally believed them to be a drain upon the energies of the

anarchist movement. Despite his warnings, these articles also contain

much good and practical advice to those who are still tempted to found

small experimental communes in the wilderness, or perhaps, those tempted

in some future era to colonise space.

Graham Purchase

Many Anarchists and thinkers in general, whilst recognising the immense

advantages which Communism may offer to society, yet consider this form

of social organisation a danger to the liberty and free development of

the individual. This danger is also recognised by many Communists, and,

taken as a whole, the question is merged in that other vast problem

which our century has laid bare to its fullest extent: the relation of

the individual to society. The importance of this question need hardly

be insisted upon.

The problem became obscured in various ways. When speaking of Communism,

most people think of the more or less Christian and monastic and always

authoritarian Communism advocated in the first half of this century and

practised in certain communities. These communities took the family as a

model and tried to constitute “the great Communist family” to “reform

man,”. To this end, in addition to working in common, they imposed the

living closely together like a family, as well as the isolation or

separation of the colony from present civilisation. This amounted to

nothing less than the total interference of all “brothers” and “sisters”

with the entire private life of each member.

In addition to this, the difference was not sufficiently noted as

between isolated communities, founded on various occasions during the

last three or four centuries, and the numerous federated communes which

are likely to spring up in a society about to inaugurate the social

revolution. Five aspects of the subject thus require to be considered

separately:

after the model of the present family?),

Individual in a Communist society.

An immense movement of ideas took place during this century under the

name of Socialism in general, beginning with Babeuf, St. Simon, Fourier,

Robert Owen and Proudhon who formulated the predominating currents of

Socialism, and continued by their numerous successors (French)

Considerant, Pierre Lerous, Louis Blanc; (German) Marx, Engels;

(Russian) Chernychevski, Bakunin; etc, who worked either at popularising

the ideas of the founders of modern Socialism or at establishing them on

a scientific basis.

These ideas, on taking precise shape, gave birth to two principal

currents: Authoritarian Communism and Anarchist Communism; also to a

number of intermediary schools bent on finding a way between, such as

State Capitalism, Collectivism, Co-operation; among the working masses

they created a formidable workers’ movement which strives to organise

the whole mass of the workers by trades for the struggle against

Capital, and which becomes more international with the frequent

intercourse between workers of different nationalities. The following

three essential points were gained by this immense movement of ideas and

of action, and these have already widely penetrated the public

conscience:

machinery, the State, which helps to maintain economic slavery.

On these three points all are agreed, and even those who advocate

“labour notes” or who, like Brousse, wish all “to be functionaries,”

that is employees of the State or the commune, admit that if they

advocate either of these proposals it is only because they do not see an

immediate possibility for Communism. They accept this compromise as an

expedient, but their aim always remains Communism. And, as to the State,

even the bitterest partisans of the State, of authority, even of

dictatorship, recognise that with the disappearance of the classes of

today the State will also cease to exist.

Hence we may say without exaggerating the importance of our section of

the Socialist movement — the Anarchist section — that in spite of all

differences between the various sections of Socialism (which differences

are, before all, based upon the more or less revolutionary character of

the means of action of each section), we may affirm that all sections,

by the voice of their thinkers, recognise the evolution towards Free

Communism as the aim of Socialist evolution. All the rest, as they

themselves confess, are only stepping-stones towards this end.

It would be idle to discuss these stepping-stones without an examination

of the tendencies of development of modern society.

Of these different tendencies two, before all, merit our attention. One

is the increasing difficulty of determining the share of each individual

in modern production. Industry and agriculture have become so

complicated, so riveted together, all industries are so dependent one

upon the other that payment to the producer by results becomes

impossible the more industry is developed, the more we see payment by

piece replaced by wages. Wages, on the other hand, become more equal.

The division of modern bourgeois society in classes certainly remains

and there is a whole class of bourgeois who earn the more, the less they

do. The working class itself is divided into four great divisions:

These divisions represent four degrees of exploitation and are but the

result of bourgeois organisation.

In a society of equals, where all can learn a trade and where the

exploitation of woman by man, of the peasant by the manufacturer, will

cease, these classes will disappear. But, even today, wages within each

of these classes tend to become more equal. This led to the statement:

“that a navvy’s day’s work is worth that of a jeweller”, and made Robert

Owen conceive his “labour notes”, paid to all who worked so many hours

in the production of necessary commodities.

But if we look back on all attempts made in this direction, we find that

with the exception of a few thousand farmers in the United States,

labour notes have not spread since the end of the first quarter of the

century when Owen tried to issue them. The reasons for this have been

discussed elsewhere (see the chapter: The Wage System, in my book “The

Conquest of Bread”).

On the other hand, we see a great number of attempts at partial

socialisation, tending in the direction of Communism. Hundreds of

Communist communities have been founded during this century almost

everywhere and at this very moment we are aware of more than a hundred

of them, all being more or less Communistic. It is in the same direction

of Communism — partial Communism, we mean to say — that nearly all the

numerous attempts at socialisation we see in bourgeois society tend to

be made, either between individuals or with regard to the socialisation

of municipal matters.

Hotels, steamers, boarding houses, are all experiments in this direction

undertaken by the bourgeois. For so much per day you have the choice

between ten or fifty dishes placed at your disposal at the hotel or on

the steamer, with nobody controlling the amount you have eaten of them.

This organisation is even international and before leaving Paris or

London you may buy bons (coupons for 10 francs a day) which enable you

to stay at will in hundreds of hotels in France, Germany, Switzerland,

etc., all belonging to an international society of hotels.

The bourgeois thoroughly understood the advantages of partial Communism

combined with the almost unlimited freedom of the individual in respect

to consumption, and in all these institutions for a fixed price per

month you will be lodged and fed, with the single exception of costly

extras (wine, special apartments) which are charged separately.

Fire, theft and accident insurance (especially in villages where

equality of conditions permits the charge of an equal premium for all

inhabitants), the arrangement by which great English stores will supply

for 1s. per week all the fish which a small family may consume, clubs,

the innumerable societies of insurance against sickness, etc., etc..

This mass of institutions, created during the 19^(th) century, are an

approach towards Communism with regard to part of our total consumption.

Finally, there exists a vast series of municipal institutions — water,

gas, electricity, workmen’s dwellings, trains with uniform fares, baths,

washing houses, etc. — where similar attempts at socialising consumption

are being made on an ever increasing scale.

All this is certainly not yet Communism. Far from it. But the principle

of these institutions contains a part of the principle of Communism: for

so much per day (in money today, in labour tomorrow) you are entitled to

satisfy — luxury excepted — this or the other of your wants.

These forays into Communism differ from real Communism in many ways; and

essentially in the two following;

If, however, the idea, the tendency of these institutions were well

understood, it would not be difficult even today to start by private or

public initiative a community carrying out the first principle

mentioned. Let us suppose a territory of 500 hectares on which are built

200 cottages, each surrounded by a garden or an orchard of a quarter

hectare. The management allows each family occupying a cottage, to

choose out of fifty dishes per day what is desired, or it supplies

bread, vegetables, meat, coffee as demanded for preparation at home. In

return they demand either so much per annum in money or a certain number

of hours of work given, at the consumers’ choice, to one of the

departments of the establishment: agriculture, cattle raising, cooking,

cleaning. This may be put in practice tomorrow if required, and we must

wonder that such a farm/hotel/garden has not yet been founded by an

enterprising hotel proprietor.

It will be objected, no doubt, that it is just here, the introduction of

labour in common, that Communists have generally experienced failure.

Yet this objection cannot stand. The causes of failure have always to be

sought elsewhere.

Firstly, nearly all communities were founded by an almost religious wave

of enthusiasm. People were asked to become “pioneers of humanity;” to

submit to the dictates of a punctilious morality, to become quite

regenerated by Communist life, to give all their time, hours of work and

of leisure, to the community, to live entirely for the community.

This meant acting simply like monks and to demand — without any

necessity — men to be what they are not. It is only in quite recent days

that communities have been founded by Anarchist working men without any

such pretensions, for purely economic purposes — to free themselves from

capitalist exploitation.

The second mistake lay in the desire to manage the community after the

model of a family, to make it “the great family” They lived all in the

same house and were thus forced to continuously meet the same “brethren

and sisters.” It is already difficult often for two real brothers to

live together in the same house, and family life is not always

harmonious; so it was a fundamental error to impose on all the “great

family” instead of trying, on the contrary, to guarantee as much freedom

and home life to each individual.

Besides, a small community cannot live long; “brethren and sisters”

forced to meet continuously, amid a scarcity of new impressions, end by

detesting each other. And if two persons through becoming rivals or

simply not liking each other are able by their disagreement to bring

about the dissolution of a community, the prolonged life of such

communities would be a strange thing, especially since all communities

founded up to now have isolated themselves. It is a foregone conclusion

that a close association of 10, 20, or 100 persons cannot last longer

than three or four years. It would be even regrettable if it lasted

longer, because this would only prove either that all were brought under

the influence of a single individual or that all lost their

individuality. Well, since it is certain that in three, four or five

years part of the members of a community would wish to leave, there

ought to exist at least a dozen or more federated communities in order

that those who, for one reason or other, wish to leave a community may

enter another community, being replaced by new comers from other places.

Otherwise, the Communist beehive must necessarily perish or (which

nearly always happens) fall into the hands of one individual — generally

the most cunning of the “brethren”.

Finally, all communities founded up till now isolated themselves from

society; but struggle, a life of struggle, is far more urgently needed

by an active man than a well supplied table. This desire to see the

world, to mix with its currents, to fight its battles is the imperative

call to the young generation. Hence it comes (as Chaikovski remarked

from his experience) that young people, at the age of 18 or 20,

necessarily leave a community which does not comprehend the whole of

society

We need not add that governments of all descriptions have always been

the most serious stumbling blocks for all communities. Those which have

seen least of this or none at all (like Young Icaria) succeed best. This

is easily understood Political hatred is one of the most violent in

character. We can live in the same town with our political adversaries

if we are not forced to see them every moment. But how is life possible

in a small community where we meet each other at every turn. Political

dissent enters the study, the workshop, the place of rest, and life

becomes impossible.

On the other hand, it has been proved to conviction that work in common,

Communist production, succeeds marvellously. In no commercial enterprise

has so much value been added to land by labor as in each of the

communities founded in America and in Europe. faults of calculation may

occur everywhere as they occur in all capitalist undertakings, but since

it is known that during the first five years after their institution

four out of every commercial undertakings become bankrupt, it must be

admitted that nothing similar or even coming near to this has occurred

in Communist communities. So, when the bourgeois press, wanting to be

ingenious, speaks of offering an island to Anarchists on which to

establish their community, relying on our experience we are ready to

accept this proposal, provided only that this island be, for instance,

the Isle de France (Paris) and that upon the valuation of the social

wealth we receive our share of it. Only, since we know that neither

Paris nor our share of social wealth will be given to us, we shall some

day take one and the other ourselves by means of the Social Revolution.

Paris and Barcelona in 1871 were not very far from doing so — and ideas

have made headway since that time.

Progress permits us to see above all, that an isolated town, proclaiming

the Commune, would have great difficulty to subsist. The experiment

ought, therefore, to be made on a territory — eg, one of the Western

States, Idaho or Ohio — as American Socialists suggest, and they are

right. On a sufficiently large territory, not within the bounds of a

single town we must someday begin to put in practice the Communism of

the future.

We have so often demonstrated that State Communism is impossible, that

it is useless to dwell on this subject. A proof of this, furthermore,

lies in the fad that the believers in the State, the upholders of a

Socialist State do not themselves believe in State Communism. A portion

of them occupy themselves with the conquest of a share of the power in

the State of today — the bourgeois State — and do not trouble themselves

at all to explain that their idea of a Socialist State is different from

a system of State capitalism under which everybody would be a

functionary of the State. If we tell them that it is this they aim at,

they are annoyed; yet they do not explain what other system of society

they wish to establish. As they do not believe in the possibility of a

social revolution in the near future, their aim is to become part of the

government in the bourgeois State of today and they leave it to the

future to decide where this will end.

As to those who have tried to sketch the outlines of a future Socialist

State, they met our criticism by asserting that all they want are

bureaus of statistics. But this is mere juggling with words. Besides, it

is averred today that the only statistics of value are those recorded by

each individual himself, giving age, occupation, social position, or the

lists of what he sold or bought, produced and consumed.

The questions to be put are usually of voluntary elaboration (by

scientists, statistical societies), and the work of statistical bureaus

consists today in Distributing the questions, in arranging and

mechanically summing up the replies. To reduce the State, the

governments to this function and to say that, by “government”, only this

will be understood, means nothing else (if said sincerely) but an

honourable retreat. And me must indeed admit that the Jacobins of thirty

years ago have immensely gone back from their ideals of dictatorship and

Socialist centralisation. No one would dare to say today that the

production or consumption of potatoes or rice must be regulated by the

parliament of the German People’s State (Volksstaat) at Berlin. These

insipid things are no longer said.

The Communist state is an Utopia given up already by its own adherents

and it is time to proceed further. A far more important question to be

examined, indeed, is this: whether Anarchist or Free Communism does not

also imply a diminution of individual freedom?

As a matter of fact, in all discussions on freedom our ideas are

obscured by the surviving influence of past centuries of serfdom and

religious oppression.

Economists represented the enforced contract (under the threat of

hunger) between master and workingman as a state of freedom.

Politicians, again, so called the present state of the citizen who has

become a serf and a taxpayer of the State. The most advanced moralists,

like Mill and his numerous disciples, defined liberty as the right to do

everything with the exception of encroachments on the equal liberty of

all others. Apart from the fact that the word “right” is a very confused

term handed down from past ages, meaning nothing at all or too much, the

definition of Mill enabled the philosopher Spencer, numerous authors and

even some Individualist Anarchists to reconstruct tribunals and legal

punishments, even to the penalty of death — that is, to reintroduce,

necessarily, in the end the State itself which they had admirably

criticised themselves. The idea of free will is also hidden behind all

these reasonings.

If we put aside all unconscious actions and consider only premeditated

actions (being those which the law, religious and penal systems alone

try to influence) we find that each action of this kind is preceded by

some discussion in the human brain; for instance, “I shall go out and

take a walk,” somebody thinks, “No, I have an appointment with a

friend,” or “I promised to finish some work” or “My wife and children

will I be sorry to remain at home,” or “I shall lose my employment if I

do not go to work.”

The last reflection implies the fear of punishment. In the first three

instances this man has to face only himself, his habit of loyalty, his

sympathies. And there lies all the difference. We say that a man forced

to reason that he must give up such and such an engagement from fear of

punishment, is not a free man. And we affirm that humanity can and must

free itself from the fear of punishment, and that it can constitute an

Anarchist society in which the fear of punishment and even the

unwillingness to be blamed shall disappear. Towards this ideal we march.

But we know that we can free ourselves neither from our habit of loyalty

(keeping our word) nor from our sympathies (fear of giving pain to those

whom we love and whom we do not wish to afflict on or even to

disappoint). In this last respect man is never free. Crusoe, on his

island, was not free. The moment he began to construct his ship, to

cultivate his garden or to lay in provisions for the winter, he was

already captured, absorbed by his work. If he felt lazy and would have

preferred to remain lying at ease in his cave, he hesitated for a moment

and nevertheless went forth to his work. The moment he had the company

of a dog, of two or three goats and, above all, after he had met with

Friday, he was no longer absolutely free in the sense in which these

words are sometimes used in discussions. He had obligations, he had to

think of the interests of others, he was no longer the perfect

individualist whom we are sometimes expected to see in him. The moment

he has a wife or children, educated by himself or confided to others

(society), the moment he has a domestic animal, or even only an orchard

which requires to be watered at certain hours — from that moment he is

no longer the “care for nothing,” the “egoist”, the “individualist” who

is sometimes represented as the type of a free man. Neither on Crusoe’s

island, far less in society of whatever kind it be, does this type

exist. Man takes, and will always take into consideration the interests

of other men in proportion to the establishment of relations of mutual

interest between them, and the more so the more these others affirm

their own sentiments and desires.

Thus we find no other definition of liberty than the following one: the

possibility of action without being influenced in those actions by the

fear of punishment by society (bodily constraint, the threat of hunger

or even censure, except when it comes from a friend).

Understanding liberty in this sense — and we doubt whether a larger and

at the same time a more real definition of it can be found — we may say

that Communism can diminish, even annihilate, all individual liberty and

in many Communist communities this was attempted; but it can also

enhance this liberty to its utmost limits.

All depends on the fundamental ideas on which the association is based.

It is not the form of an association which involves slavery; it is the

ideas of individual liberty which we bring with us to an association

which determine the more or less libertarian character of that

association.

This applies to all forms of association. Cohabitation of two

individuals under the same roof may lead to the enslavement of one by

the will of the other, as it may also lead to liberty for both. The same

applies to the family or to the co-operation of two persons in gardening

or in bringing out a paper. The same with regard to large or small

associations, to each social institution. Thus, in the tenth, eleventh

and twelfth centuries, we find communes of equals, men equally free —

and four centuries later we see the same commune calling for the

dictatorship of a priest. Judges and laws had remained; the idea of the

Roman law, of the State had become dominant, whilst those of freedom, of

settling disputes by arbitration and of applying federalism to its

fullest extent had disappeared; hence arose slavery. Well, of all

institutions or forms of social organisation that have been tried until

this day, Communism is the one which guarantees the greatest amount of

individual liberty — provided that the idea that begets the community be

Liberty, Anarchy.

Communism is capable of assuming all forms of freedom or of oppression

which other institutions are unable to do. It may produce a monastery

where all implicitly obey the orders of their superior, and it may

produce an absolutely free organisation, leaving his full freedom to the

individual, existing only as long as the associates wish to remain

together, imposing nothing on anybody, being anxious rather to defend,

enlarge, extend in all directions the liberty of the individual.

Communism may be authoritarian (in which case the community will soon

decay) or it may be Anarchist. The State, on the contrary, cannot be

this. It is authoritarian or it ceases to be the State.

Communism guarantees economic freedom better than any other form of

association, because it can guarantee wellbeing, even luxury, in return

for a few hours of work instead of a day’s work. Now, to give ten or

eleven hours of leisure per day out of the sixteen during which we lead

a conscious life (sleeping eight hours), means to enlarge individual

liberty to a point which for thousands of years has been one of the

ideals of humanity.

This can be done today in a Communist society man can dispose of at

least ten hours of leisure. This means emancipation from one of the

heaviest burdens of slavery on man. It is an increase of liberty.

To recognise all men as equal and to renounce government of man by man

is another increase of individual liberty in a degree which no other

form of association has ever admitted even as a dream. It becomes

possible only after the first step has been taken: when man has his

means of existence guaranteed and is not forced to sell his muscle and

his brain to those who condescend to exploit him.

Lastly, to recognise a variety of occupations as the basis of all

progress and to organise in such a way that man may be absolutely free

during his leisure time, whilst he may also vary his work, a change for

which his early education and instruction will have prepared him — this

can easily be put in practice in a Communist society — this, again,

means the emancipation of the individual, who will find doors open in

every direction for his complete development.

As for the rest, all depends upon the ideas on which the community is

founded. We know a religious community in which members who felt

unhappy, and showed signs of this on their faces, used to be addressed

by a “brother”: “You are sad. Nevertheless, put on a happy look,

otherwise you will afflict our brethren and sisters.” And we know of

communities of seven members, one of whom moved the nomination of four

committees: gardening, ways and means, housekeeping, and exportation,

with absolute rights for the chairman of each committee. There certainly

existed communities founded or invaded by “criminals of authority” (a

special type recommended to the attention of Mr. Lombrose) and quite a

number of communities were founded by mad upholders of the absorption of

the individual by society. But these men were not the product of

Communism, but of Christianity (eminently authoritarian in its essence)

and of Roman law, the State.

The fundamental idea of these men who hold that society cannot exist

without police and judges, the idea of the State, is a permanent danger

to all liberty, and not the fundamental idea of Communism — which

consists in consuming and producing without calculating the exact share

of each individual. This idea, on the contrary, is an idea of freedom,

of emancipation.

Thus we have arrived at the following conclusions: Attempts at Communism

have hitherto failed because:

considering a community simply as a means of economic consumption and

production,

leisure time, and

having for an aim the fullest possible emancipation of the individual.

Communism, being an eminently economic institution, does not in any way

prejudice the amount of liberty guaranteed to the individual, the

initiator, the rebel against crystallising customs. It may be

authoritarian, which necessarily leads to the death of the community,

and it may be libertarian, which in the twelfth century even under the

partial communism of the young cities of that age, led to the creation

of a young civilisation full of vigour, a new springtide of Europe.

The only durable form of Communism, however, is one under which, seeing

the close contact between fellow men it brings about, every effort would

be made to extend the liberty of the individual in all directions.

Under such conditions, under the influence of this idea, the liberty of

the individual, increased already by the amount of leisure secured to

him, will be curtailed in no other way than occurs today by municipal

gas, the house to house delivery of food by great stores, modern hotels,

or by the fact that during working hours we work side by side with

thousands of fellow labourers.

With Anarchy as an aim and as a means, Communism becomes possible.

Without it, it necessarily becomes slavery and cannot exist.