đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș alain-pengam-anarchist-communism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 07:26:06. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Anarchist-Communism Author: Alain Pengam Language: en Topics: anarcho-communism, anarcho-communist, history Source: http://www.zabalaza.net/theory/txt_anok_comm_ap.htm Notes: contains sections
Anarchist-communism has been regarded by other anarchist currents as a
poor and despised relation, an ideological trophy to be exhibited
according to the needs of hagiography or polemic before moving on to
âserious thingsâ (the collectivisations of Spain, anarcho-syndicalism,
federalism or self-management), and as an âinfantile utopiaâ more
concerned with dogmatic abstractions than with âeconomic realitiesâ.
Yet, anarchist communism has been the only current within the anarchist
movement that has explicitly aimed not only at ending exchange value
but, among its most coherent partisans, at making this the immediate
content of the revolutionary process. We are speaking here, of course,
only of the current that explicitly described itself as
âanarchist-communistâ, whereas in fact the tendency in the nineteenth
century to draw up a stateless communism âutopiaâ extended beyond
anarchism properly so-called.
Anarchist-communism must be distinguished from collectivism, which was
both a diffuse movement (see, for example, the different components of
the International Working Menâs Association, the Guesdists, and so on)
and a specific anarchist current. As far as the latter was concerned, it
was Proudhon who supplied its theoretical features: an open opponent of
communism (which, for him, was Etienne Cabetâs âcommunismâ), he favoured
instead a society in which exchange value would flourish â a society in
which workers would be directly and mutually linked to each other by
money and the market. The Proudhonist collectivists of the 1860âs and
1870âs (of whom Bakunin was one), who were resolute partisans of the
collective ownership of the instruments of work and, unlike Proudhon, of
land, maintained an essence of this commercial structure in the form of
groups of producers, organised either on a territorial basis (communes)
or on an enterprise basis (co-operatives, craft groupings) and linked to
each other by the circulation of value. Collectivism was thus defined â
and still is â as an exchange economy where the legal ownership of the
instruments of production is held by a network of âcollectivitiesâ which
are sorts of workersâ jointstock companies. Most contemporary anarchists
(standing, as they do, for a self-managed exchange economy) are
collectivists in this nineteenth-century sense of the term, even though
the term has now come to have a somewhat different meaning (state
ownership, i.e. âstate capitalismâ, rather than ownership by any
collectivity).
In the 1870âs and the 1880âs the anarchist-communists, who wanted to
abolish exchange value in all itâs forms, broke with the collectivists,
and in so doing revived the tradition of radical communism that had
existed in France in the 1840âs.
In 1843, under the Rabelaisian motto âDo what you will!â, and in
opposition to Etienne Cabet, ThĂ©odore DĂ©zamyâs Code de la CommunautĂ©
laid the basis for the principles developed later in the nineteenth
century by communist and anarchist-communist theoreticians such as
Joseph DĂ©jacque, Karl Marx, Fredrick Engels, William Morris and Peter
Kropotkin. These principles involved the abolition of money and
commercial exchange; the subordination of the economy to the
satisfaction of the needs of the whole population; the abolition of the
division of labour (including the division between the town and country
and between the capital and the provinces); the progressive introduction
of attractive work; and the progressive abolition of the state and of
the functions of government, as a separate domain of society, following
the communisation of social relations, which was to be brought about by
a revolutionary government. It should be noted that DĂ©zamy advocated the
âcommunity of goodsâ and resolutely opposed the specifically
collectivist slogan of âsocialisation of property.â In doing so, he
anticipated the critical analysis of property which Amadeo Bordiga made
more than a century later.
Besides rejecting Cabetâs utopia, because it maintained the division of
labour â in particular that between town and country â and sought to
organise it rigidly in the name of economic âefficiency,â DĂ©zamy also
refused to insert between the capitalist mode of production and
communist society a transitional period of democracy which would have
pushed communism into the background. By seeking to establish a direct
link between the revolutionary process and the content of communism, so
that the dominant class within capitalism would be economically and
socially expropriated through the immediate abolition of monetary
circulation, DĂ©zamy anticipated what was to be the source of the basic
originality of anarchist-communism, in particular in its Kropotkinist
form. This feature was the rejection of any âtransition periodâ that did
not encompass the essence of communism: the end of the basic act of
buying and selling. At about the same time, the communists around the
journal LâHumanitaire, Organe de la Science Sociale (of which two issues
appeared in Paris in 1841) advocated a program of action very close to
that of DĂ©zamy, proposing, among other things, the abolition of
marriage. In addition, they made travel one of the principal
characteristics of communist society, because it would bring about
mixing of the races and interchange between industrial and agricultural
activities. This group also identified itself with the Babouvist Sylvain
MarĂ©chal for having proclaimed âanti-political and anarchist ideasâ.
However, it was above all the house-painter Joseph DĂ©jacque (1822â64)
who, up until the foundation of anarchist communism properly so-called,
expressed in a coherent way the radical communism which emerged in
France from the 1840s as a critical appropriation of Fourierism, Owenism
and neo-Babouvism. DĂ©jacqueâs work was an examination of the limits of
the 1848 revolution and the reasons for its failure. It was developed
around a rejection of two things: the state, even if ârevolutionary,â
and collectivism of the Proudhonist type. DĂ©jacque reformulated
communism in a way that sought to be resolutely free from the dogmatism,
sectarianism and statism exhibited by those such as Cabet and La
FraternitĂ© de 1845. DĂ©jacque spoke of: âLiberty! Which has been so
misused against the community and which it is true to say that certain
communist schools have held cheap.â
DĂ©jacque was a fierce opponent of all the political gangs of the period.
He rejected Blanquism, which was based on a division between the
âdisciples of the great peopleâs Architectâ and âthe people, or vulgar
herd,â and was equally opposed to all the variants of social
republicanism, to the dictatorship of one man and to âthe dictatorship
of the little prodigies of the proletariat.â With regard to the last of
these, he wrote that: âa dictatorial committee composed of workers is
certainly the most conceited and incompetent, and hence the most
anti-revolutionary, thing that can be found...(It is better to have
doubtful enemies in power than dubious friends)â. He saw âanarchic
initiative,â âreasoned willâ and âthe autonomy of eachâ as the
conditions for the social revolution of the proletariat, the first
expression of which had been the barricades of June 1848. In DĂ©jacqueâs
view, a government resulting from an insurrection remains a reactionary
fetter on the free initiative of the proletariat. Or rather, such free
initiative can only arise and develop by the masses ridding themselves
of the âauthoritarian prejudicesâ by means of which the state reproduces
itself in its primary function of representation and delegation.
DĂ©jacque wrote that: âBy government I understand all delegation, all
power outside the people,â for which must be substituted, in a process
whereby politics is transcended, the âpeople in direct possession of
their sovereignty,â or the âorganised commune.â For DĂ©jacque, the
communist anarchist utopia would fulfil the function of inciting each
proletarian to explore his or her own human potentialities, in addition
to correcting the ignorance of the proletarians concerning âsocial
science.â
However, these views on the function of the state, both in the
insurrectionary period and as a mode of domination of man by man, can
only be fully understood when inserted into DĂ©jacqueâs global criticism
of all aspects of civilisation (in the Fourierist sense of the term).
For him, âgovernment, religion, property, family, all are linked, all
coincide.â The content of the social revolution was thus to be the
abolition of all governments, of all religions, and of the family based
on marriage, the authority of the parents and the husband, and
inheritance. Also to be abolished were âpersonal property, property in
land, buildings, workshops, shops, property in anything that is an
instrument of work, production or consumption.â DĂ©jacqueâs proposed
abolition of property has to be understood as an attack on what is at
the heart of civilisation: politics and exchange value, whose cell (in
both senses) is the contract. The abolition of the state, that is to say
of the political contract guaranteed by the government (legality), for
which anarchy is substituted, is linked indissolubly with the abolition
of commerce, that is to say of the commercial contract, which is
replaced by the community of goods: âCommerce,... this scourge of the
19^(th) century, has disappeared amongst humanity. There are no longer
either sellers or sold.â
DĂ©jacqueâs general definition of the âanarchic communityâ was:
âthe state of affairs where each would be free to produce and consume at
will and according to their fantasy, without having to exercise or
submit to any control whatsoever over anything whatever; where the
balance between production and consumption would establish itself, no
longer by preventive and arbitrary detention at the hands of some group
or other, but by the free circulation of the faculties and needs of
each.â
Such a definition implies a criticism of Proudhonsim, that is to say of
the Proudhonist version of Ricardian socialism, centred on the reward of
labour power and the problem of exchange value. In his polemic with
Proudhon on womenâs emancipation, DĂ©jacque urged Proudhon to push on âas
far as the abolition of the contract, the abolition not only of the
sword and of capital, but of property and authority in all their forms,â
and refuted the commercial and wages logic of the demand for a âfair
rewardâ for âlabourâ (labour power). DĂ©jacque asked: âAm I thus... right
to want, as with the system of contracts, to measure out to each â
according to their accidental capacity to produce â what they are
entitled to?â The answer given by DĂ©jacque to this question is
unambiguous: âit is not the product of his or her labour that the worker
has a right to, but to the satisfaction of his or her needs, whatever
may be their nature.â
The âdirect exchangeâ theorised by Proudhon corresponded to supposed
âabolitionâ of the wages system which in fact would have turned groups
of producers or individual producers into the legal agents of capital
accumulation. For DĂ©jacque, on the other hand, the communal state of
affairs â the phalanstery âwithout any hierarchy, without any authorityâ
except that of the âstatistics bookâ â corresponded to ânatural
exchange,â i.e. to the âunlimited freedom of all production and
consumption; the abolition of any sign of agricultural, individual,
artistic or scientific property; the destruction of any individual
holding of the products of work; the demonarchisation and the
demonetarisation of manual and intellectual capital as well as capital
in instruments, commerce and buildings.
The abolition of exchange value depends on the answer given to the
central question of âthe organisation of workâ or, in other words, on
the way in which those who produce are related to their activity and to
the products of that activity. We have already seen that the answer
DĂ©jacque gave to the question of the distribution of products was the
community of goods. But the community had first of all to be established
in the sphere of productive activities themselves. Although the
disappearance of all intermediaries (parasites) would allow an increase
in production, and by this means would guarantee the satisfaction of
needs, the essential requirement was the emancipation of the individual
producer from âenslaving subordination to the division of labourâ (Marx)
and, primarily, from forced labour. This is why the transformation of
work into âattractive workâ was seen by DĂ©jacque as the condition for
the existence of the community: âThe organisation of attractive work by
series would have replaced Malthusian competition and repulsive work.â
This organisation was not to be something exterior to productive
activity. DĂ©jacqueâs communist anthropology was based on the liberation
of needs, including the need to act on the world and nature, and made no
distinction between natural-technical necessities and human ends.
Although its vocabulary was borrowed from Fourier (harmony, passions,
series and so on), it aimed at the community of activities more than the
organised deployment of labour power: âThe different series of workers
are recruited on a voluntary basis like the men on a barricade, and are
completely free to stay there as long as they want or to move on to
another series or barricade.â DĂ©jacqueâs âHumanisphereâ was to have no
hours of work nor obligatory groupings. Work could be done in isolation
or otherwise.
As to the division of labour, DĂ©jacque proposed its abolition in a very
original way. What he advocated was a reciprocal process of the
integration of the aristocracy (or rather of the aristocratic
intelligentsia) and the proletariat, each going beyond its own
unilateral intellectual or manual development.
Although he recognised the futility of palliatives, DĂ©jacque was perhaps
exasperated by the gulf between the results of his utopian research and
the content of the class struggle in the 1850s, and tried to bridge this
gulf with a theory of transition. This theory aimed to facilitate the
achievement of the state of community, while taking into account the
existing situation. Its three bases were, first, âdirect legislation by
the peopleâ (âthe most democratic form of government, while awaiting its
complete abolitionâ); second, a range of economic measures which
included âdirect exchangeâ (even though DĂ©jacque admitted that this
democratised property without abolishing exploitation), the
establishment of Owenite-type âlabour bazaars,â âcirculation vouchersâ
(labour vouchers) and a gradual attack on property; and third, a
democratisation of administrative functions (revocability of public
officials, who would be paid on the basis of the average price of a
dayâs work) and the abolition of the police and the army.
It is an undeniable fact that this programme anticipated that of the
Paris Commune of 1871, at least on certain points. But this is the weak
side of DĂ©jacque where he accepts the âlimitsâ of the 1848 Revolution,
against which he had exercised his critical imagination. The âright to
workâ appeared along with the rest, and with it the logic of commerce.
It should be noted that, on the question of the transition, DĂ©jacque
singularly lacked ârealismâ since, even if the insoluble problems posed
by the perspective of workers managing the process of value-capital are
ignored, he proposed giving not only women, but âprisonersâ and the
âinsaneâ the right to vote, without any age limit. But the transition
was only a second best for DĂ©jacque and he explicitly recognised it as
such. There was no abandoning of utopian exploration in favour of the
transition, but a tension between the two, the opposite to what was to
be the case with Errico Malatesta, with whom he could be superficially
compared.
The tenor of DĂ©jacqueâs utopia, its move towards breaking with all
commercial and political constraints, its desire to revive the
insurrectionary energy of the proletariat, and its imaginative depth
(comparable to that of William Morris) enable one to see that it made a
fundamental contribution to the critical element in anarchist-communism.
DĂ©jacque provided anarchist-communism during the first cycle of its
history with an iconoclastic dimension, the glimmers of which are not
found again until the Kropotkin of the 1880âs or until Luigi Galleani in
the twentieth century.
Working Menâs Associationâ (IWMA)
The First International, or International Working Menâs Association, was
organised in 1864 and was active for several years before splitting into
acrimonious factions in the aftermath of the Paris Commune of 1871. The
split that occurred in the IWMA was essentially over the details of
collectivism and over the ways of arriving at a âclassless societyâ
whose necessarily anti-commercial nature was never stated (except in
Marxâs Capital), or rather never played any part in shaping the practice
of the organisation. Bakunin himself, a left-wing Proudhonist for whom
the abolition of exchange value would have been an aberration, purely
and simply identified communism with a socialistic Jacobin tendency and,
moreover, generally used the term âauthoritarian communismâ as a
pleonasm to describe it.
In August 1876, a pamphlet by James Guillaume entitled Idées sur
Lâorganisation Sociale was published in Geneva. The importance of this
text lies not in its succinct presentation of the framework of a
collectivist society, but in the relation set out by Guillaume between
such a society and communism. Starting out from the collective ownership
of the instruments of production, that is to say from the ownership of
by each âcorporation of workers in such and such an industryâ and by
each agricultural grouping, and hence from the ownership by each of
these groups of their own products, Guillaume ends up at âcommunismâ, or
â since he does not employ this term â at the substitution of free
distribution for exchange. The transition to free distribution is
supposed to be organically linked to the society described by Guillaume,
even though it is a society organised around the exchange of products at
their value, because of the guarantee represented by the collective
ownership of the means of production. The essential point here is that
communism is reduced to the status of a moral norm, which it would be a
good thing to move towards, and is made to appear as the natural
development of a collectivist (and wage) society, with its rigid
division between industrial and agricultural producers, its policy of
full employment and its payment of labour power.
In making the precondition for communism a social relationship built on
wage system, and by seeing this as the basis for the state becoming
superfluous, Guillaume laid the foundation for the regression that was
to overtake anarchist-communism and of which Malatesta was to be one of
the principle representatives. According to Guillaume, the preconditions
for communism were a progressive appearance of an abundance of products,
which would allow calculation in terms of value to be abandoned and an
improvement in the âmoral senseâ of the workers to occur. This in turn
would enable the principle of âfree accessâ to be implemented. Guillaume
envisaged this train of events as being brought about by the development
of commercial mechanisms, with the working class acting as their
recognised agent by virtue of the introduction of collective property
and the guaranteed wage. What underlay all this was the implication that
the act of selling is no longer anything but a simple, technical,
transitional, rationing measure.
It was precisely in opposition to this variant of Proudhonism that
anarchist-communism asserted itself in what was left of the IWMA towards
the end of the 1870âs. In February 1876, Savoyard François Dumartheray
(1842â1931) published in Geneva a pamphlet Aux Travailleurs Manuals
Partisans de Lâaction Politique, âcorresponding to the tendencies of the
section âLâAvenirâ, an independent group of refugees from in particular
Lyons... For the first time anarchist-communism was mentioned in a
printed text.â On March 18-19^(th) of the same year, at a meeting
organised in Lausanne by members of the IWMA and Communalists, Elisée
Reclus delivered a speech in which he recognised the legitimacy of
anarchist-communism. Still in 1876, a number of Italian anarchists also
decided to adopt anarchist-communism, but the way they formulated this
change indicated their limitations as far as the question of
collectivism was concerned: âThe Italian Federation considers the
collective ownership of the product of labour as the necessary
complement of the collectivist programme.â Also, in the spring of 1877,
the Statuten der Deutscheienden Anarchischkommunistischen Partei
appeared in Berne.
The question of communism remained unsettled at the Verviers Congress of
the âanti-authoritarianâ IWMA in September 1877, when the partisans of
communism (Costa, Brousse) and the Spanish collectivists confronted each
other, with Guillaume refusing to commit himself. However, the Jura
Federation, which was an anarchist grouping that had been active in the
French-speaking area of Switzerland throughout the 1870âs, was won over
to the views of Reclus, Cafiero and Kropotkin, and integrated communism
into its programme at its Congress in October 1880. At this Congress,
Carlo Cafiero presented a report that was later published in Le Révolté
under the title âAnarchie et Communismeâ. In this report, Cafiero
succinctly exposed the points of rupture with collectivism: rejection of
exchange value; opposition to transferring ownership of the means of
production to workersâ corporations; and elimination of payment for
productive activities. Furthermore, Cafiero brought out the necessary
character of communism, and hence demonstrated the impossibility of a
transitional period of the type envisaged by Guillaume in his 1876
pamphlet. Cafiero argued that, on the one hand, the demand for
collective ownership of the means of production and âthe individual
appropriation of the products of labourâ would cause the accumulation of
capital and the division of society into classes to reappear. On the
other hand, he maintained that retaining some form of payment for
individual labour power would conflict with the socialised character
(indivisibility of productive activities) already imprinted on
production by the capitalist mode of production. As to the need for
rationing products, which might occur after the revolutionary victory,
nothing would prevent such rationing from being conducted ânot according
to merits, but according to needsâ.
Kropotkinâs contribution in favour of communism at the 1880 Congress was
the culmination of a slow evolution of his position from strict
collectivism to communism, by way of an intermediate position where he
saw collectivism as a simple transitional stage. Kropotkinâs theory of
anarchist-communism, which was drawn up in its essentials during the
1880âs, is an elaboration of the theses presented by Cafiero in 1880 on
the conditions making communism possible and on the necessity of
achieving this social form, from which exchange value would disappear.
Anarchist-communism is presented as a solution to crisis-ridden
bourgeois society, which is torn between the under-consumption of the
proletariat, under-production and socialised labour. At the same time,
anarchist-communism is seen as the realisation of tendencies towards
communism and the free association of individuals which are already
present in the old society. In this sense, anarchist-communism is a
social form, which re-establishes the principle of solidarity that
exists in tribal societies.
Kropotkinâs anarchist-communism has the general characteristic of being
based on the satisfaction of the needs â ânecessitiesâ and âluxuriesâ â
of the individual, i.e., on the right to the âentire product of oneâs
labourâ, which featured in the collectivistsâ policy of full employment
and the guaranteed wage. This satisfaction of needs was to be guaranteed
by a number of measures: free distribution of products was to replace
commodity exchange; production was to become abundant; industrial
decentralisation was to be implemented; the division of labour was to be
overcome; and real economies were to be realised by the reduction of
working time and the elimination of waste caused by the capitalist mode
of production. Kropotkin wrote: âa society, having recovered the
possession of all riches accumulated in its midst, can liberally assure
abundance to all in return for four or five hours effective manual work
a day, as far as regards production.â
Yet the question arises whether the appropriation of the instruments of
production by the producers, as consumers, and by consumers, as
producers, referred to a new legal form of property ownership or to the
abolition of property in all forms. Although the Anarchist Congress held
in London in 1881 pronounced in favour of âthe abolition of all
property, including collectiveâ, and although Kropotkin himself
contrasted âcommon useâ to âownershipâ, he still did not go beyond the
collectivist perspective of the transfer of property to a new agent
(i.e., for him, to society as a whole, rather than to industrial and
trading commercial collectives). Hence, he wrote: âFor association to be
useful to the workers, the form of property must be changedâ.
The same ambiguity is found over the related question of the abolition
of the division of labour. Certainly, the description which Kropotkin
gave of the content of communist society in this respect is perfectly
clear: integration of manual and intellectual labour; attractive and
voluntary work; and fusion of agriculture, industry and art within
âindustrial villagesâ. But a revolutionary strategy which puts forward
the corporatist slogan of âThe land to those who cultivate it, the
factory to the workersâ, presupposes maintaining the division of labour
and the institution of the enterprise and can be said not to go beyond
the establishment of a workersâ and peasantsâ society which would still
be a form of collectivism.
The organisation of the new society, in its two aspects â communist and
anarchist (in view of the necessary connection between a mode of
production and its political form) â was to be based on the âcommunist
communeâ (rather than on the âfree communeâ of the Communalists),
federalism (decentralization and economic self-sufficiency of regions or
producing areas) and neighbourhood assemblies. Kropotkin distinguished
three possible methods of organisation: on a territorial basis
(federation of independent communes); on a basis of social function
(federation of trades); and that which he gave all his attention, and
which he hoped would expand, on the basis of personal affinity. In fact,
the âfree and spontaneous grouping of individuals functioning in
harmonyâ seemed to him to be the essential characteristic of the
particular social relationship of anarchist-communism.
But the important point lies more in the forms and content of the
revolutionary process, of which all this was to be the end result. The
revolution was seen as an international process, starting with a long
period of insurrection, whose model Kropotkin found in the repeated
peasant insurrections that had preceded the French Revolution. Such a
revolutionary process would end in a phase of general expropriation,
which would mark the beginning of âthe reconstruction of societyâ:
âExpropriation, such then is the problem which history has put before
the people of the twentieth century: the return to Communism in all that
ministers to the well-being of humanity... by taking immediate and
effective possession of all that is necessary to ensure the well-being
of all.â
Immediate expropriation defined the whole logic of the revolutionary
process for Kropotkin. Basically, it is here that the essence of his
work lies. The real answer to the objection that can be made against him
(regarding his optimistic assumptions about human nature, the abundance
of products, and so on) lies in the alternatives that he posed: either
the immediate communisation of social relations or the wages system in
one form or another. If proof of the stark nature of these alternatives
was ever required, history has provided such proof in abundance. For
Kropotkin, the critique of the wages system was indissolubly linked with
the critique of collectivism (Proudhonist or Guesdist). He wrote: âThe
most prominent characteristic of our present capitalism is the wage
systemâ. Kropotkin saw the wages system as presupposing the separation
of the producers from the means of production and as being based on the
principle âto each according to their deedsâ:
âIt was by proclaiming this principle that wagedom began, to end in the
glaring inequalities and all the abominations of the present society;
because, from the moment work done began to be appraised in currency, or
in any other form of wage... the whole history of a State-aided
Capitalist society was as good as written.â
The collectivists favoured the âright to workâ, which is âindustrial
penal servitudeâ. In Kropotkinâs view, their pro-worker policy sought to
âharness to the same cart the wages system and collective ownershipâ, in
particular through their theory of labour vouchers. Kropotkin opposed
labour vouchers on the grounds that they seek to measure the exact value
of labour in an economy that, being socialised, tends to eliminate all
distinctions as far as contribution of each worker considered in
isolation is concerned. Furthermore, the existence of labour vouchers
would continue to make society âa commercial company based on debit and
creditâ. Hence he denounced labour vouchers in the following terms: âThe
idea... is old. It dates from Robert Owen. Proudhon advocated it in
1848. Today, it has become âscientific socialismâ.
Kropotkin made equally stringent criticisms of the collectivistsâ
attitudes towards the division of labour and the State. With regard to
the division of labour, he wrote: âTalk to them [the collectivist
socialists] about the organisation of work during the Revolution, and
they answer that the division of labour must be maintained.â As for the
State, it was significant that as soon as Kropotkin had come out in
favour of âdirect, immediate communist anarchism at the moment of the
social revolutionâ, he criticised the Paris Commune as an example of a
revolution where, in the absence of the communist perspective, the
proletariat had become bogged down in problems of power and
representation. Kropotkin believed that the Paris Commune illustrated
well how the ârevolutionary stateâ acts as a substitute for communism
and provides a new form of domination linked to the wages system. In
contrast to this, âit is by revolutionary socialist acts, by abolishing
individual property, that the Communes of the coming revolution will
affirm and establish their independenceâ. Further, communism would
transform the nature of the Commune itself:
âFor us, âCommuneâ is no longer a territorial agglomeration; it is
rather a generic noun, synonym of a grouping of equals which knows
neither frontiers nor walls. The social commune will soon cease to be
clearly-defined whole.â
For Kropotkin, what characterises the revolutionary process is, in the
first place, general expropriation, the taking possession of all
ârichesâ (means of production, products, houses and so on), with the aim
of immediately improving the material situation of the whole population.
He wrote: âwith this watchword of Bread for All the Revolution will
triumphâ. Since Kropotkin foresaw that a revolution would in the
beginning make millions of proletarians unemployed, the solution would
be to take over the whole of production so as to ensure the satisfaction
of food and clothing needs. First of all, the population âshould take
immediate possession of all food of the insurgent communesâ, draw up an
inventory, and organise a provisions service by streets and districts
which would distribute food free, on the principle: âno stint of limit
to what the community possesses in abundance, but equal sharing and
dividing of those things which are scarce or apt to run shortâ. As for
housing:
âIf the people of the Revolution expropriate the houses and proclaim
free lodgings â the communalising of houses and the right of each family
a decent dwelling â then the Revolution will have assumed a communistic
character from the first... the expropriation of dwellings contains in
germ the whole social revolution.â
A second characteristic of Kropotkinâs vision of the revolutionary
process was to integrate the countryside into the process of
communisation, by making an agreement âwith the factory workers, the
necessary raw materials given them, and the means of subsistence assured
to them, while they worked to supply the needs of the agricultural
populationâ. Kropotkin regarded the integration of town and country as
of fundamental importance, since it bore on the necessity to ensure the
subsistence of the population and would be accomplished by the beginning
of the abolition of the division of labour, starting from the industrial
centres. He thought that âThe large towns, as well as the villages, must
undertake to till the soilâ, in a process of improvement and extension
of cultivated areas. In Kropotkinâs view, the agrarian question was thus
decisive right from the beginning of the revolution. Kropotkinâs
exposition of the expropriation of the land for the benefit of society
(the land to belong to everyone) was not, however, free from the
ambiguity we mentioned above. To make land â as with all else â a
property question amounts to placing productive activity above the
satisfaction of needs, to inserting a social actor between the
population and the satisfaction of their needs. Property can only be
private.
This inability to break definitively with collectivism in all its forms
also exhibited itself over the question of the workersâ movement, which
divided anarchist-communism into a number of tendencies. To say that the
industrial and agricultural proletariat is the natural bearer of the
revolution and communisation does not tell us under what form it is or
should be so. In the theory of the revolution which we have just
summarised, it is the risen people who are the real agent and not the
working class organised in the enterprise (the cells of the capitalist
mode of production) and seeking to assert itself as labour power, as a
more ârationalâ industrial body or social brain (manager) than the
employers. Between 1880 and 1890, the anarchist-communists, with their
perspective of an immanent revolution, were opposed to the official
workersâ movement, which was then in the process of formation (general
Social Democratisation). They were opposed not only to political
(statist) struggles but also to strikes which put forward wage or other
claims, or which were organised by trade unions. While they were not
opposed to strikes as such, they were opposed to trade unions and the
struggle for the eight-hour day. This anti-reformist tendency was
accompanied by an anti-organisational tendency, and its partisans
declared themselves in favour of agitation amongst the unemployed for
the expropriation of foodstuffs and other articles, for the
expropriatory strike and, in some cases, for âindividual recuperationâ
or acts of terrorism.
From the 1890âs, however, the anarchist-communists, and Kropotkin in
particular, were to begin to integrate themselves directly into the
logic of the workersâ movement (reproduction of waged labour power). In
1890, Kropotkin âwas one of the first to declare the urgency of entering
trade unionsâ, as a means of trying to overcome the dilemma in which,
according to him, anarchist-communism risked trapping itself. Kropotkin
saw this dilemma in terms of either joining with the reformist workersâ
movement or sterile and sectarian withdrawal. âWorkmenâs organisations
are the real force capable of accomplishing the social revolutionâ, he
was to declare later.
Coinciding with the birth of anarcho-syndicalism and revolutionary
unionism, three tendencies emerged within anarchist-communism. First,
there was the tendency represented by Kropotkin himself and Les Temps
Nouveaux (Jean Grave). Second, there were a number of groups which were
influenced by Kropotkin but which were less reserved than him towards
the trade unions (for example, Khleb i Volia in Russia). Finally, there
was the anti-syndicalist anarchist-communists, who in France were
grouped around Sebastien Faureâs Le Libertaire. From 1905 onwards, the
Russian counterparts of these anti-syndicalist anarchist-communists
become partisans of economic terrorism and illegal âexpropriationsâ.
Certainly, it would be an âillusion to seek to discover or to create a
syndicalist Kropotkinâ, at least in the strict sense of the term, if
only because he rejected the theory of the trade union as the embryo of
future society â which did not prevent him from writing a preface in
1911 for the book written by the anarcho-syndicalists Emile Pataud and
Emile Pouget, Syndicalism and the Co-operative Commonwealth (How We
Shall Bring About The Revolution). But he saw the trade-union movement
as a natural milieu for agitation, which it would be possible to use in
the attempt to find a solution to the reformism-sectarianism dilemma. As
an alternative to the strategy of the Russian âillegalistâ
anarchist-communists, Kropotkin envisaged the formation of independent
anarchist trade unions whose aim would be to counteract the influence of
the Social Democrats. He defined his strategy in one sentence in the
1904 introduction to the Italian edition of Paroles dâun RĂ©voltĂ©:
âExpropriation as the aim, and the general strike as the means to
paralyse the bourgeois world in all countries at the same time.â
At the end of his life Kropotkin seems to have abandoned his previous
reservations and to have gone so far as to see in syndicalism the only
âgroundwork for the reconstruction of Russian economyâ. In May 1920, he
declared that: âthe syndicalist movement... will emerge as the great
force in the course of the next fifty years, leading to the creation of
the communist stateless societyâ. He was equally optimistic about the
prospects facing the co-operative movement. Remarks such as these opened
the way for theoretical regression that was to make anarchist-communism
a simple variant of anarcho-syndicalism, based on the collective
management of enterprises. Reduced to the level of caricature,
âanarchist-communismâ even became an empty phrase like the Spanish
âlibertarian communismâ of the 1930âs, to say nothing of the
contemporary use to which this latter term is put.
Kropotkinâs last contribution, not to anarchist-communism but to its
transformation into an ideology, was the introduction of the mystifying
concept of Russian âstate communismâ. Faced with the events of the
Russian Revolution and the establishment of a capitalist state freed
from the fetters of Tsarism, Kropotkin should logically have seen the
new state as a form of collectivism. He should have recognised that its
character was determined by the wages system, as with other varieties of
collectivism that he had previously exposed. In fact, he limited himself
to criticising the Bolsheviksâ methods, without drawing attention to the
fact that the object towards which those methods were directed had
nothing to do with communism. A good example of this is the question
that he directed at Lenin in the autumn of 1920:
âAre you so blind, so much a prisoner of your authoritarian ideas, that
you do not realize that, being at the head of European Communism, you
have no right to soil the ideas which you defend by shameful
methods...?â
After Kropotkinâs death, the theory of anarchist-communism survived, but
was consigned to isolation by the unfolding counter-revolution from the
1920âs onwards. Unlike the Italian Left and the German-Dutch council
communists (the latter above all, with their criticism of the whole
workersâ movement and their analysis of the general tendency for a
unification of labour, capital and the state), the partisans of
anarchist-communism did not really try to discover the causes of this
counter-revolution; nor did they perceive its extent. As a result, their
contributions amounted to little more than a formal defence of
principles, without any critical depth. Moreover, these contributions
ceased rapidly. Sebastien Faureâs Mon Communisme appeared in 1921, Luigi
Galleaniâs The End of Anarchism? in 1925 and Alexander Berkmanâs What is
Communist Anarchism? (better known in its abridged form as the ABC of
Anarchism) in 1929.
From this date on, if we exclude the minority current in the General
Confederation of Labor, Revolutionary Syndicalist (CGTSR), whose
positions were made clear by Gaston Britel, the critical force that
anarchist-communism had represented left the anarchist movement to
reappear with the dissident Bordigist Raoul Brémond (see his La
Communauté, which was first published in 1938) and certain communist
currents that arose in the 1970âs. Representative of these latter was
the group that published in Paris in 1975 the pamphlet Un Monde sans
Argent: Le Communisme.
As a practical movement, anarchist-communism came to an end in Mexico
and Russia. In Mexico before the First World War, the Patrido Liberal
Mexicano (PLM) of the brothers Enrique and Ricardo Florés Magon,
supported by a movement of peasants and indigenous peoples, which aimed
to expropriate the land, tried to achieve anarchist-communism. The PLMâs
objective was to revive the community traditions of the ejidos â common
lands â and ultimately to extend the effects of this essentially
agrarian rebellion to the industrial areas. The PLM came to control the
greater part of Lower California and was joined by a number of IWW
âWobbliesâ and Italian anarchists. But it was unable to implement its
project of agricultural co-operatives organised on anarchist-communist
principles and was eventually defeated militarily.
The 1917 revolution in Russia gave impetus to a process that had begun
before, whereby anarchist-communism was absorbed or replaced by
anarcho-syndicalism. In addition to this, in certain cases
anarchist-communists allowed themselves to be integrated into the
Bolshevik State. It is true that a few groups refused all support, even
âcriticalâ, for the Bolsheviks and combated them with terrorism, but
they experienced increasing isolation. For the last time in the
twentieth century a social movement of some size â in particular in
Petrograd where the Federation of Anarchists (Communists) had
considerable influence before the summer of 1917, the date when the
exiled syndicalists returned â consciously proposed to remove
âgovernment and property, prisons and barracks, money and profitâ and
usher in âa stateless society with a natural economyâ. But their
programme of systematic expropriations (as opposed to workersâ control),
âembracing houses and food, factories and farms, mines and railroadsâ,
was limited in reality to several anarchist-communist groups after the
February Revolution expropriating âa number of private residences in
Petrograd, Moscow, and other citiesâ.
As for the Makhnovist insurrectionary movement, although it was in
favour of communism in the long run, and although it declared that âall
forms of the wages system must be irredeemably abolishedâ, it
nevertheless drew up a transitional program which preserved the
essential features of the commodity economy within a framework of
co-operatives. Wages, comparison of products in terms of value, taxes, a
âdecentralised system of genuine peopleâs banksâ and direct trade
between workers were all in evidence in this transitional programme.
As a conclusion, we will recall Kropotkinâs warning: âThe Revolution
must be communist or it will be drowned in blood.â