💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › tom-wetzel-on-organization.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 14:25:54. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: On Organization
Author: Tom Wetzel
Language: en
Topics: anarchist organization, organization, direct democracy,
Source: Retrieved on April 20, 2017 from https://reallibertarianism.com/democracy-pages/on-organization/

Tom Wetzel

On Organization

“Consensus” has had a certain popularity as a decision-making method

among social change groups since the ’60s, especially within the

anti-nuclear movement but also in anarchist and radical feminist

circles. I think we can understand why if we consider what sorts of

organizations exist in this country. Mass organizations in which the

membership directly shape the decisions are hard to find. How often have

members been ruled “out of order” at union meetings by an entrenched

official? Most leftist political groups also have a top-down concept of

organization, as befits their preoccupation with “leadership.”

On the other hand, this sort of alienation and lack of control appears

absent in activities organized through small circles of acquaintances.

Those who engage in an action together typically reached a common

agreement after talking it over informally. This leads to the model of

the small, informal group — no written constitution, no chair of

meetings, no elections for delegated tasks, no careful definition of

jobs, no written minutes of meetings. Decisions are made by having an

unstructured discussion until consensus is reached.

But informality does not eliminate hierarchy in organizations; it merely

masks it. To the insiders, everything appears friendly and egalitarian.

But newcomers do not have the same longstanding ties to the group. And

having no clear definition of responsibilities, and no elections of

individuals who carry out important tasks, makes it more difficult for

the membership to control what goes on.

Fortunately, the “small, informal group” is not the only alternative to

the dominant hierarchical model of organization. It is possible to build

a formal organization that is directly controlled by its membership.

Being “formal” merely means that the organization has a written set of

rules about how decisions are made, and duties of officers and

conditions of membership are clearly defined. An organization does not

have to be top-down in order to be “formal” in this sense. A libertarian

organization would have a constitution that explicitly lays out a

non-hierarchical way of making decisions.

Delegating Responsibilities

Sometimes people have the idea that setting up elected positions with

defined responsibilities is a “hierarchy,” as if any delegation of

responsibility creates a boss. Yet, informality does not avoid

delegation since some people will inevitably do tasks on behalf of the

group, such as answering correspondence or handling a bank account.

It is possible to elect people to perform delegated tasks without

creating a top-down organization. Here are a few guidelines:

secretary or treasurer, should be explicitly defined and delimited, so

that everyone knows what this person should be doing, and with the

requirement of regular reports to keep the membership informed.

should be subject to recall at any time by majority vote of the

membership (but with a requirement of adequate notice to ensure that

this is not “sprung” all of a sudden by those members least favorable to

the person currently doing the job).

rotation from office. This is especially important for any position of

acting as spokesperson or representative of an organization or body of

people. If an organization is very small, however, it is sometimes

difficult to rotate responsibilities. Even so, the person carrying out

responsibilities can report regularly to membership meetings and can be

thus directed by decisions of the membership.

to carry out those responsibilties that have been assigned by the

membership. The general membership meeting of the organization must

remain the supreme decision-making body and can over-rule any decisions

of elected officers.

The idea is that the main decision-making responsibility of the

organization is not to be delegated to some “steering committee” or

executive but is conducted directly by the membership through their own

discussions and votes; this is the heart of the libertarian concept of

organization.

Since many leftists define social change in terms of putting a

particular leadership into power — such as the Leninist concept of “the

revolutionary party taking state power” — it is no surprise that even

organizations formed, or influenced, by leftists may have a hierarchical

set-up where the power to make decisions is concentrated in some

executive board or steering committee. While libertarians oppose this

practice, and pose the alternative of direct decision-making by the

members or rank-and-file participants, it is, nonetheless, not necessary

to oppose all delegation of tasks or responsibilities.

The real question should be, “What is the relationship between those

vested with responsibilities and the rest of the membership?” If the

center of decision-making lies in the general meetings, and those with

responsibilities must report to these meetings, and are instructed by

them, and (where possible) jobs are rotated, then we do not have a

top-down structure, but an organization where decision-making is from

the bottom up.

A Chair is Not a Boss

Often people who favor the “small, informal group” model of organization

also oppose the practice of electing someone to chair a meeting, even if

the meeting is a larger gathering. It is easy to understand what they

are afraid of. Consider union meetings where the chair is a paid

official. He has certain entrenched interests to defend. To serve his

ends, he may rule “out of order” motions from the floor on matters of

concern to the rank and file, or manipulate the meeting in other ways.

But here the problem is that there is an entrenched bureaucracy;

chairing meetings is only one of the ways they control the organization.

The situation is different if the chair is elected at the beginning of

the meeting by those present, and if the chair can be removed by

majority vote at any time. Being chair of a meeting does not convert

someone into a bureaucrat.

I’ve sat through chairless meetings where people interrupt each other,

voices get louder as people try to express themselves, discussions get

side-tracked into numerous tangents, and important decisions are put off

or hurriedly decided at the last minute. This experience has made me

rather frustrated with the prejudice against having a chair of meetings.

If a meeting only consists of a few people, then obviously it does not

need to have a chair. But once meetings achieve a certain size, a chair

becomes necessary in order to ensure that the meeting stays on track and

moves through the agenda in a reasonable amount of time, while making

sure that people have an opportunity to speak.

I’ve heard opponents of chairmanship argue, “It’s the responsibility of

each individual to make sure that the meeting stays on track and

individuals don’t get out of hand.” But even with the best of

intentions, this is difficult to achieve in practice. When you’re

thinking about what you want to say next, it’s hard to also be keeping

track of whose turn it is to speak and of what the agenda is.

The rationale behind having a chair is that we delegate to one person

the responsibility to concentrate on such things as the agenda and the

order of speakers while the rest of us are free to concentrate on what

is being said. Of course, it can happen that a chair is manipulative,

favoring one particular “side” in a matter under dispute. But in such a

situation, a motion to replace the chair would be in order.

The Right to Dissociate

In working out a libertarian concept of organization, we need to

remember that the individual members not only have rights that must be

respected by the organization, they also have obligations to the rest of

the membership. Since the majority have the right to control their own

organization, individuals must conduct themselves so as to respect this

right of the majority.

For example, if an individual makes public statements that claim to

speak for the organization, but state only the viewpoint of the

individual, not a viewpoint actually discussed and agreed to by the

majority, then that individual is acting irresponsibly and

anti-democratically.

There is, however, no reason why an individual should be required to

stay mum publically about disagreements within the organization. As long

as the individual makes clear that the stated viewpoint is his or her

own, public disagreement with the position of the organization is not

irresponsible.

A libertarian concept of organization must allow for diversity of

opinions. This means that members must try to maintain a climate of

respecting the opinions of others in the organization. But what happens

when members do not respect the rights of others? What happens when

members are threatening to others, or conduct themselves in ways that

are very disruptive to the life of an organization? In such a case the

majority may have to consider disassociating themselves from that

individual. In other words, the rights of the majority include the right

to expel individual members.

To some anarchists, expulsions are always a “purge.” The authoritarian

connotation of the latter term are meant to suggest that any expulsion

is a violation of freedom, an illegitimate act. But the position of

these anarchists is actually self-contradictory. For, it is a very basic

libertarian principle that the membership of an organization have the

right to directly control it. And this means that no individual has the

“right” to act in ways that prevent the majority from accomplishing the

purposes for which they got together. If the majority in an organization

did not have the right to expel disruptive indivdiduals, this would mean

that they couldn’t control the conditions of membership and direction of

that organization. Freedom of association implies the freedom to

disassociate.

On the other hand, the power to expel members should never be delegated

to officials. For, if elected officers can expel members ontheir own,

they can expel critics of how they are conducting their

responsibilities. Expulsion certainly is used by officials in

hierarchical organizations as a means of maintaining their top-down

control. What is illegitimate in such cases is not the act of expulsion

in itself, but the top-down way it is carried out.

The point here is that individuals have obligations to the other members

of an organization. And the majority have the right to ensure that the

responsibilities of membership are observed. But expulsion is a last

resort, and should not be used lightly. Expulsion is something that the

membership should decide on directly, in a general membership meeting or

convention. And it should always be required that accused individuals be

given advance notice and have the right to defend themselves before the

general membership prior to a vote to expel.

Talking Until Agreement is Reached

The partisans of informality also tend to be averse to voting as a way

of making decisions. They prefer the process of talking until agreement

is reached (or not reached). In my experience, this process tends to

encourage informal hierarchy. That’s because this process tends to

heighten the influence of the more articulate and self-confident

individuals, and tends to disenfranchise the shy newcomer, and the less

articulate. Voting has the advantage that it is an equalizer. The shy

and the aggressive, the articulate and the not-so-articulate, all can

raise their hands, and each has only one vote.

Advocates of consensus sometimes say that hierarchical organization is

the only alternative to consensus. But there is also the alternative of

direct democracy where decisions are made by majority vote. Direct

voting by the members puts the majority of members in control, and

control by the majority of members is the opposite of hierarchy. In a

hierarchical organization, it is not the majority of members who are in

charge but a few leaders at the top — that is what “hiearchy” means.

The libertarian idea of direct, democratic voting is quite different

than the official concept of “democracy” in this society. “Democratic

voting” typically means electing officials who then have all the power

of making decisions. But that is really elective autocracy, not genuine

democracy, which requires direct decision-making by the rank and file.

Formal Consensus

Though “talking until agreement is reached” is the natural method of

decision-making for “small, informal groups,” not all advocates of

consensus decision-making are averse to formal organization. However,

making the organization formal — a written constitution, definition of

membership and so on — does not eliminate the basic problems of the

consensus process.

The requirement of unanimity means that disagreements have to be talked

out until verbal consensus emerges. This means that even a formal

consensus system tends to heighten the influence of the more talkative,

self-confident participants. Also, the requirement of consensus often

leads to prolonged, marathon sessions, or meetings where nothing is

decided.

This aspect of consensus tends to make the movement less conducive to

participation by working people, and tends to reduce participation to

the hard-core activists. When people have other demands on their time

(job, children, spouse), they will tend to be frustrated by meetings

that are unnecessarily long, indecisive, or chaotic. Most people will

want to have some sense that something will be accomplished, a clear

decision made, and in a reasonable amount of time.

In his pamphlet Blocking Progress, Howard Ryan describes a nightmarish

example of what can happen with consensus.[1] Many people in the

Livermore Action Group — an anti-nuclear action group here in the Bay

Area — were uncomfortable with the first point of LAG’s action

guidelines which stated: “Our attitude will be one of openness,

friendliness and respect toward all people we encounter.” “A common

sentiment”, Ryan points out, “was that oppressed people often do not

feel these things towards police or authorities and should not be

required to feel them in order to join the [Lawrence-Livermore

Laboratory] blockade.” In 1982 there was a month-long discussion of this

issue, followed by two full days of informal open debate. At the second

of these assemblies it was proposed to replace the “friendly and

respectful” language with “non-violent.”

Coming towards the end of this long process of discussion, there was a

suggestion by one of the participants in the second meeting that a straw

poll be taken to determine the general opinion in the room. This was

itself considered so controversial that two hours were consumed in

debating whether it was even okay to take a straw poll. Finally a poll

was taken and the vote was 74 to 2 in favor of changing the non-violence

code to remove the “respectful and friendly” language. One of the

participants has described what then took place:

One of the two people [a doctrinaire pacifist] blocked it. He was asked

repeatedly to stand aside, to leave, to die. People were just so upset.

He wouldn’t budge and it was blocked.

This is a good example of the elitist coercion that consensus permits.

Consensus is Anti-democratic

The requirement of unanimity is anti-democratic. A small minority does

not have the right to prevent the majority of members from doing what

they want to do. Organizations are not of value in themselves but only

as a vehicle for cooperation and collective activity. Insofar as

consensus thwarts the majority from doing what it wants, it makes the

organization an ineffective vehicle for them. This can lead to splits

and fragmentation — exactly the result that the advocates of consensus

say they want to avoid.

The rules of an organization can — and must — protect the rights of

individuals and minorities. If one studies the situation in the

AFL-CIO-type unions, and major political organizations, it is true that

the rights of individuals and political minorities are often in a sorry

state. But these are hierarchical organizations. It is the hierarchy,

not “majority voting,” that is the problem.

Anarchists of the more individualistic persuasion argue that consensus

is necessary to avoid “tyranny of the majority.” But where in the real

world does the majority have real power? The real tyrannies that people

are fighting around the world are tyrannies of entrenched minorities, of

governments and bosses. I don’t want to claim that “majorities are

always right” but I do believe that people have the right to make their

own mistakes. The issue here is whether people have the right to control

their own movements and organizations. To give a single individual or

small minority the right of veto on decisions is to have a system of

minority rule.

Even when individuals or minorities do not actually threaten or use a

block to keep the majority from doing what it wants, everyone is aware

that they could, if the organization is run by consensus. The structural

requirement of unanimity puts pressure on the majority to placate small

minorities in order to accomplish something. Often this leads to

decisions that paper over disagreements and leave everyone dissatisfied.

Rudy Perkins has described this problem, based on his experience in the

Clamshell Alliance in New England in the late ’70s:

Majority rule is disliked because amongst the two, three or many courses

of action proposed, only one is chosen; the rest are “defeated.”

Consensus theoretically accommodates everyone’s ideas. In pactice this

often led to:

of one side or another was actually implemented through committees or

office staff.

In other words, within the anti-nuclear movement ideas are in

competition and some do win, but under consensus the act of choosing

between alternatives is usually disguised. Because the process is often

one of mystification and subterfuge, it takes power of conscious

decision away from the organization’s membership.[2]

Consensus puts pressure on minorities not to express misgivings or

disagreements because their dissent would prevent the organization from

making a decision. Thus it actually becomes harder for minorities to

state dissenting opinions because dissent is always a disruptive act.

When decisions are made by majority vote, on the other hand, there is

not this heavy “cost” to dissent and minorities can freely state their

disagreement without thereby disrupting or blocking the organization

from reaching a decision.

Consensus also means that it becomes very difficult, if not impossible,

to change an organization’s orientation even when it is clear to most

members that the current direction is failing. That’s because there will

almost always be a minority who will be against change, because the

current direction of the organization may have been what attracted them

to it, or because they may simply prefer what they are used to.

Simple Majority

“Simple majority” is the requirement of one vote more than half the

votes cast in order to make a decision. A simple majority is the

smallest number of votes needed to guarantee that a decision is made.[3]

Advocates of simple majority sometimes hear the retort: “But do we want

to have a major decision made with 51% for 49% against?” Decisions that

organizations make in the course of conducting their affairs vary a lot

in their relative importance to the participants. For some decisions, a

narrow majority won’t matter because those who voted “no” may not have

really strong feelings one way or the other. If it is an important

issue, though, it is clearly a problem if an organization is closely

split.

Sometimes, in organizations that are based on membership participation

and democratic voting, close votes will lead the group to stop and

reconsider the issue in order to find a proposal that accommodates

objections.

More often, this process happens before it reaches a vote. When it

becomes clear in the course of the discussion on a proposal that the

membership are closely divided and have strong feelings on the issue,

there is likely to be an effort to find a proposal that mitigates

objections. For one thing, it is to the advantage of the proposal’s

partisans to have as much support as possible within the organization.

The work of the organization is bound to suffer if it is badly split —

dissatisfied members may drag their feet or drop out.

When a union conducts a strike vote, for example, the partisans of a

strike will want to get the largest possible majority for a strike. If

the vote for a strike isn’t overwhelming, if there is only a narrow

majority for striking, the union will be less likely to actually go out

because the division among the workforce undermines the chances of

winning a strike.

Such considerations have at times led people to propose decision-making

based on larger majorities, such as two-thirds or three-fourths. But the

problem with this is that most of the decisions that organizations make

are not so crucial that large majorities are needed.

Moreover, stipulating a majority larger than 50% plus one means that

decisions can be blocked by minorities. Though the minorities required

to “block” a majority are larger than under consensus, this still

permits minority control. A cohesive minority could exercize undue

influence on a group due to its potential for blocking what the majority

wants. Thus the arguments against consensus also apply to some extent

against a formal requirement of two-thirds or three-fourths majority.

The advantage to “simple majority” as a decision-making method is that

it is the only way to formally preclude minority rule.

There may be circumstances when it would be desireable to have a larger

majority than 50% plus one — as in those cases where the organization is

closely split on important issues. But instead of trying to make a

formal rule for this, I think this should be dealt with by the

membership using good sense in such situations. Not everything that is

desireable for an organization can be created by formal rules.

The conditions required for the healthy and democratic functioning of an

organization go beyond the formal rules. Whether the rights of members

are respected also depends on the climate in the organization. How

people treat each other is an informal factor but it is just as

important as clauses in constitutions.

There is usually some sort of underlying, informal consensus in almost

any organization. To take an obvious example, there needs to be a

consensus that disagreements are not settled by punching someone out.

So, there does need to be a consensus on some things, on certain basic

assumptions that underlie the unity of the organization. The advocates

of “consensus decision-making” are correct in perceiving this, but where

they go wrong is in trying to elevate this into a general principle of

decision-making so that everything requires a consensus. The consensus

system puts day-to-day decisions, on the one hand, and the most

important decisions, fundamental purposes and ways of treating each

other, on the other hand, all on the same level.

Small Groups, No Power

However, consensus does often work reasonably well in small groups,

especially where the participants have a common background and shared

assumptions. Some people might maintain that small, independent groups

are all that is needed.

Indeed, some partisans of the small group have argued that “bigness”

inevitably brings bureaucracy in movements and that only small,

independent groups can be genuinely controlled by their members. This

ignores the methods that libertarians have developed for avoiding

top-down control in mass organizations (such as the guidelines I

mentioned earlier), and the examples of libertarian mass unions that

functioned through assemblies, without an entrenched bureaucracy;

organizations like the Industrial Workers of the World back in the ’10s

or the Spanish National Confederation of Labor (CNT) in the ’30s.

If the “bigness means bureaucracy” dogma were true, a libertarian

society would be impossible. To have a society organized along anarchist

lines means that there must be a means by which the whole populace can

participate in making crucial decisions affecting society as a whole.

For this to happen it must be possible to have large organizations,

organizations spanning vast areas, such as the North American continent,

that are able to function in a non-hierarchical way, directly controlled

by their rank and file participants.

If the whole society could be organized to make decisions through direct

democracy and mass participation, as anarchists advocate, then surely it

must be possible for people to build mass organizations that are run

this way today. If not, then how could a libertarian society be brought

into existence? Only a mass movement that is itself organized

non-hierarchically could create a society free of top-down,

bureaucratic, exploitative social relations.

This brings us to the clearest problem with the “small groups” doctrine:

Small groups have no power. The power to change society requires a mass

movement, and the development of solidarity among working people on a

large scale. To unite people from a variety of backgrounds and cultures,

to coalesce the various groups into a real movement, to pool resources,

mass organizations are needed. In the absence of a larger movement,

small groups can be discouraged by their own lack of resources and sense

of isolation.

Unless working people can organize their solidarity into mass

organizations, they will not be able to develop the power to challenge

our very powerful adversaries — the corporations and their government.

Without a mass movement, most people will not develop a sense that they

have the power to change society. Our ideal of social change in the

direction of democratic participation and workers control will appear to

most people as merely a “nice idea, but impractical.” Only the strength

of a mass movement can convince the majority that our vision of a

society run by working people is feasible.

[1] Howard Ryan, Blocking Progress: Consensus Decision Making in the

Anti-Nuclear Movement, 1983, published by the Overthrow Cluster of the

Livermore Action Group. Ryan’s pamphlet makes a number of the same

arguments against consensus that I am making here.

[2] Rudy Perkins, “Breaking with Libertarian Dogma: Lessons from the

Anti-Nuclear Struggle,” Black Rose, Fall 1979, p. 15.

[3] If we were to allow a decision to be made when half vote for a

proposal, then it might happen that half vote for proposal A and half

vote for proposal B. And what if A and B are conflicting proposals?

Requiring one vote more than half guarantees that a single solution is

decided upon.