đž Archived View for library.inu.red âş file âş iain-mckay-anarcho-anarchist-organisation.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 10:54:59. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄď¸ Next capture (2024-06-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Anarchist Organisation Author: Anarcho Date: 05/05/2016 Language: en Topics: anarchist organization, theory, praxis, organizing, organization Source: http://anarchism.pageabode.com/anarcho/anarchist-organisation-practice-theory-actualised
âorganisation, that is to say, association for a specific purpose and
with the structure and means required to attain it, is a necessary
aspect of social life. A man in isolation cannot even live the life of a
beast... Having therefore to join with other humans... he must submit to
the will of others (be enslaved) or subject others to his will (be in
authority) or live with others in fraternal agreement in the interests
of the greatest good of all (be an associate). Nobody can escape from
this necessity.â â Errico Malatesta[1]
Rather than being a peripheral concept, organisation is fundamentally a
core aspect of any ideology as it is âthe point where concepts lose
their abstractionâ and âare interwoven with the concrete practices
sanctioned or condemned by an ideologyâ.[2] What organisational forms an
ideology advocates say far more about its actual core values than the
words it uses.
George Woodcock proclaimed that âit seems evident that logically pure
anarchism goes against its own nature when it attempts to create
elaborate international or even national organisations, which need a
measure of rigidity and centralisation to survive.â A syndicalist union,
in contrast, needs ârelatively stable organisations and succeeds in
creating them precisely because it moves in a world that is only partly
governed by anarchist idealsâ. He reflected the opinions a large band of
more hostile commentators on anarchism who inflict a fundamental
irrationality on anarchists. If âpureâ anarchism is against any form of
organisation beyond its ânatural unitâ of the âloose and flexible
affinity groupâ then few sensible people would embrace it for neither a
rail network nor a hospital could be reliably run by such a unit.[3]
However, if we accept that anarchists are no different from other social
activists and so fundamentally rational and realistic people as Davide
Turcato correctly argues[4] then we need to admit that anarchist
theoreticians and activists would not be advocating an ideal that by
âits own natureâ precludes practical alternatives to the social ills
they are protesting against. Theory needs to be reflected in practice
and, as will be shown, anarchists have always addressed the need for
social organisation.
Anarchist thinkers and activists are not isolated individuals but rather
very much part of their society and its popular movements, seeking to
gain influence for the ideas they have produced to solve the problems of
their society. They are embedded in the world they were seeking to
transform, aware of the intellectual and social context in which they
live and critically engaged with both.
At the birth of anarchism the ideological context was liberalism (as
personified by John Locke) and democracy (as personified by Jean-Jacques
Rousseau). The social context was the failure of the French Revolution
and the rise of industrial capitalism as well as the oppositional
movements each produced: radical republicanism and the labour and
socialist movements, respectively.
Liberalism is usually associated with John Locke yet we cannot
understand him if he has âmodern liberal-democratic assumptions read
into his political thought.â[5] His theory is not primarily concerned
with defending liberty but rather property and the power that comes with
it.
Locke takes wage-labour (âMaster and Servantâ) as existing in his âstate
of natureâ. Thus âa Master of a Familyâ rules over others expressed by
âall these subordinate relations of Wife, Children, Servants, and
Slavesâ and with âa very distinct and differently limited Powerâ. The
power from wealth, of âa Master over his Servant, a Husband over his
Wife, and a Lord over his Slaveâ, was fine as long as it did not take
the form of a political power, namely âa Right of making Laws with
Penalties of Death, and consequently all less Penaltiesâ. However, as
the state had the right âfor the Regulating and Preserving of Property,
and of employing the force of the Community, in the Execution of such
Lawsâ[6], the property owner could expect the full backing of the state
in ensuring his authority was obeyed.
For Locke allegedly free and equal individuals create organisations in
which the few rule the many. Yet the objection remains: âit is hard to
see why a free and equal individual should have sufficient good reason
to subordinate herself to another.â[7] He rose to this challenge with
the liberal use of the word consent and a âjust-soâ story to justify
property inequality. Land is given to everyone in common by God while
labour âis the unquestionable property of the labourerâ. He argues
people who have taken the produce of the commons can appropriate the
commons themselves âwhere there is enough, and as good, left in common
for others.â[8] Yet this limitation is quickly overcome[9] and so âby a
tacit and voluntary consentâ there is âa disproportionate and unequal
Possession of the Earthâ[10].
Any agreement between the rich and proletariat would favour the former
and once the worker has consented to being under the authority of the
wealthy then his labour and its product is no longer his: âThus the
grass my horse has bit; the Turfs my Servant has cut; and the Ore I have
diggâd⌠become my Property.â The workersâ labour âhath fixed [his
employerâs] propertyâ in both the product and common resources worked
upon.[11] Lockeâs defence of property as resting on labour becomes the
means to derive the worker of the full product of her labour.[12]
Once the land is appropriated and wealth accumulated in a few hands then
this few combine to form a political state because the previous
government â a monarchy â no longer acts as an impartial umpire and
takes a self-interested part in the numerous conflicts between property
owners which turn âthe state of natureâ into âthe state of warâ. The
Monarch exercises absolute power over the property owners which
necessitates creating a political power which defends property and this
âturns out to be the majority of the representatives, and the latter are
chosen by the propertiedâ, that is âmales who own substantial amounts of
material propertyâ and so âpolitically relevant members of society.â The
liberal state âstands over and above, and external to, the world of
everyday life.â[13]
While the âlabouring class is a necessary part of the nation its members
are not in fact full members of the body politic and have no claim to be
soâ. Locke considered âall men as members [of civil society] for the
purposes of being ruled and only the men of estate as members for the
purpose of rulingâ (or, âmore accurately, the right to control any
governmentâ). The working class, the actual majority, âwere in but of
civil societyâ and so he âwould have no difficulty, therefore, in
thinking of the state as a joint-stock company of owners whose majority
of decision binds not only themselves but also their employees.â[14]
Locke âwas not a democrat at all.â[15] This is shown by his The
Fundamental Constitutions of Carolina that postulates rule by wealthy
landlords with hereditary serfs (âleet-menâ). It aimed to âavoid
erecting a numerous democracyâ and so âwe, the lords and proprietors of
the province⌠have agreed to this following form of governmentâ. Eight
âproprietorsâ received one-fifth of the land in perpetually while âthe
hereditary nobilityâ received another fifth. The parliament would be
made up âof the proprietors or their deputiesâ and âone freeholder out
of every precinct.â The freeholder members of parliament had to have
more than âfive hundred acres of freehold within the precinct for which
he is chosenâ while the electorate would be made up of those who have
more than âfifty acres of freehold within the said precinct.â[16]
Locke attacked both absolutist monarchy and radical democracy and his
theory gives âjustification to, and is expressly designed to preserve,
the social inequalities of the capitalist market economyâ[17].
Authoritarian (master-servant) social relationships were precisely what
his theory of property in the person sought to justify. The nature of
his theory can be seen from the organisation within which he sought to
apply it: the class state based on wealthy landlords assembling together
in a Parliament to rule themselves and their servants is exposed in his
organisation for Carolina.
Which brings us to Jean-Jacques Rousseau who âdenounces the liberal
social contract as an illegitimate fraudâ.[18] If Locke proclaimed âwe
are born Freeâ[19] then Rousseau replied that we are âeverywhere in
chainsâ[20] and sought to explain why Liberalism produced and justified
this.
Critiquing Liberalismâs âjust-soâ story of state formation, Rousseau
noted how â[a]ll ran headlong to their chains, in the hopes of securing
their libertyâ when, in fact, it âbound new fetters on the poor, and
gave new powers to the rich; which irretrievably destroyed natural
liberty, eternally fixed the law of property and inequality, converted
clever usurpation into unalterable right, and, for the advantage of a
few ambitious individuals, subjected all mankind to perpetual labour,
slavery, and wretchedness.â[21] The liberal social contract was based on
property and not liberty:
âThe first man who, having enclosed a piece of ground, bethought himself
of saying This is mine, and found people simple enough to believe him,
was the real founder of civil society. From how many crimes, wars and
murders, from how many horrors and misfortunes might not any one have
saved mankind, by pulling up the stakes, or filling up the ditch, and
crying to his fellows, âBeware of listening to this impostor; you are
undone if you once forget that the fruits of the earth belong to us all,
and the earth itself to nobody.ââ[22]
In contrast to liberalism, Rousseau recognised that the âgreatest good
of allâ reduces down to âtwo main subjects, liberty and equalityâ for
the former âcannot exist withoutâ the latter.[23] He rightly argued that
contracts between the wealthy few and the many poor will always benefit
the former and, for the latter, become little more than the freedom to
pick a master:
âThe terms of social compact between these two estates of men may be
summed up in a few words: âYou have need of me, because I am rich and
you are poor. We will therefore come to an agreement. I will permit you
to have the honour of serving me, on condition that you bestow on me
that little you have left, in return for the pains I shall take to
command you.ââ[24]
Thus âlaws are always useful to those with possessions and harmful to
those who have nothing: from which it follows that the social state is
advantageous to men only when all posses something and none has too
much.â The ideal society was one where âno citizen shall be rich enough
to buy another and none so poor as to be forced to sell himself.â[25]
Rousseau goes to the core problem with liberalism:
âThat a rich and powerful man, having acquired immense possessions in
land, should impose laws on those who want to establish themselves
there, and that he should only allow them to do so on condition that
they accept his supreme authority and obey all his wishes; that, I can
still conceive... Would not this tyrannical act contain a double
usurpation: that on the ownership of the land and that on the liberty of
the inhabitants?â[26]
We cannot really âdivest ourselves of our libertyâ like âwe transfer our
property from one to another by contractsâ for âthe property I alienate
becomes quite foreign to me, nor can I suffer from abuse of itâ but it
âconcerns me that my liberty should not be abusedâ. A contract âbinding
the one to command and the other to obeyâ would be âan odd kind of
contract to enter intoâ and so âto bind itself to obey a masterâ would
be âillegitimate.â This was the âvoluntary establishment of tyrannyâ and
if âthe people promises simply to obey, by that very act dissolves
itselfâ. The âmoment a master exists, there is no longer a Sovereignâ
and to ârenounce liberty is to renounce being a man, to surrender the
rights of humanity and even its duties.â[27]
Political association had to be participatory. The âpeople of England
regards itself as free; but it is grossly mistaken; it is free only
during the election of members of parliament. As soon as they are
elected, slavery overtakes it, and it is nothing.â Sovereignty, âfor the
same reason as makes it inalienable, is indivisibleâ and so it was
âessential, if the general will is to be able to express itself, that
there should be no partial society within the Stateâ. Any government âis
simply and solely a commission, an employmentâ and âmere officials of
the Sovereignâ. The âpeople, being subject to the laws, ought to be
their authorâ and so the âproblem is to find a form of association which
will defend and protect with the whole common force the person and goods
of each associate, and in which each, while uniting himself with all,
may still obey himself alone, and remain as free as before.â[28]
The democratic critique of liberalism produced both the idea of popular
sovereignty and the importance of equality. Rousseauâs ideas were never
implemented during his lifetime and so it is his followers during the
French Revolution we need to turn. This revolution was a conflict
between both the people and the monarchy but also between the rising
bourgeoisie and the toiling masses.[29] Power under the Jacobins was
centralised into fewer and fewer hands â from the electorate into
representatives, from representatives into the government, from the
government, finally, into the hands of Robespierre. The sections of
Paris, unions and strikes were repressed as being âstates within the
stateâ for the Republic âcalled itself one and indivisibleâ for a reason
while the centralisation of more and more decisions produced a
bureaucracy of âthousands of officials⌠to read, classify, and form an
opinionâ on them all.[30]
Rousseau presented a critique of inequality but did not fundamentally
criticise property. As he lived before the rise of industrial
capitalism, with peasant farming and artisan workshops predominating,
wage-labour was not widespread nor of prime importance in continental
Europe. The solution for inequality was clear and did not need question
property (land reform) while the small-scale of technology meant that
most could become artisans working with their own tools in their own
workshop.
The French Revolution, however, raised the issue of guilds and
journeymen societies while one building employer reported that the
âworkers, by an absurd parody of the government, regard their work as
their property, the building site as a Republic of which they are
jointly citizens, and believe in consequence that it belongs to them to
name their own bosses, their inspectors and arbitrarily to share out the
work amongst themselves.â[31] These perspectives only increased when the
industrial revolution transformed France. Faced with the obvious
authoritarianism within the factory, ex-artisans sought a solution
appropriate to the changed circumstances they faced.
The workplace could not be broken up without destroying machines and the
advantages they produced alongside master-servant relations. This
created a new perspective in the new working class. âAssociationism was
born during the waves of strikes and organised protests provoked by the
Revolution of 1830â when âthere appeared a workersâ newspaperâ which
âsuggested cooperative associations as the only way to end capitalist
exploitation.â This paper, lâArtisan, journal de la class ouvrière, was
produced by printers and âlaid the basis for trade socialism.â[32] While
some intellectuals â the utopian socialists like Saint-Simon and Fourier
â had raised various schemes for improving society, this was the first
example of workers themselves making practical suggestions for their own
liberation.
Across France, workers started to combine their existing organisations
for mutual support with trade union activity as well as visions of a
world without masters. This process intertwined with existing political
Republican ideas. Radical neo-Jacobins recruited amongst workers which
resulted in a âtwo-way interchange of ideasâ with them taking up âthe
ideology of producer associationism which was becoming centralâ to
artisanal socialism. Louis Blanc was the most public expression of this
process and his âdistinctive contribution was to fuse the associationist
idea with the Jacobin-Republican political traditionâ[33] but there were
many others who expressed the associational idea in different forms.[34]
By 1840 there was not only a wide appreciation for the need of some kind
of association to replace capitalism but also extensive workers
organisations across France which aimed to do so. It was in this
context[35] that a working man, a printer by trade, would transform
socialist politics forever by proclaiming himself an anarchist.
While Proudhon will forever be linked with âproperty is theftâ, this was
just one part of his answer to What is Property?. The other was
âproperty is despotismâ for property âviolates equality by the rights of
exclusion and increase, and freedom by despotism.â Anarchy was âthe
absence of a master, of a sovereign,â while proprietor was âsynonymousâ
with âsovereign,â for he âimposes his will as law, and suffers neither
contradiction nor controlâ and âeach proprietor is sovereign lord within
the sphere of his propertyâ.[36] He echoed Rousseau:
âLiberty is inviolable. I can neither sell nor alienate my liberty;
every contract, every condition of a contract, which has in view the
alienation or suspension of liberty, is null... Liberty is the original
condition of man; to renounce liberty is to renounce the nature of
manâ[37]
This brings him into conflict with Locke. Rejecting the notion that
master-servant contracts were valid, he dismisses its basis of property
in the person: âTo tell a poor man that he has property because he has
arms and legs, â that the hunger from which he suffers, and his power to
sleep in the open air are his property, â is to play with words, and add
insult to injury.â Property, then, is solely material things â land,
workplaces, etc. â and their monopolisation results in authoritarian
relationships. To ârecognise the right of territorial property is to
give up labour, since it is to relinquish the means of labourâ. Property
results in the worker having âsold and surrendered his libertyâ to the
proprietor so ensuring exploitation. Whoever âlabours becomes a
proprietorâ of his product but by that he did ânot mean simply (as do
our hypocritical economists)â â and Locke â the âproprietor of his
allowance, his salary, his wagesâ but âproprietor of the value which he
creates, and by which the master alone profits.â Locke is also the
target for Proudhonâs comment that âthe horse... and ox... produce with
us, but are not associated with us; we take their product, but do not
share it with them. The animals and workers whom we employ hold the same
relation to us.â[38]
Yet if Locke was rejected, Rousseau did not provide a genuine
solution.[39] While Proudhon favourably quotes Rousseau on âthe
conditions of the social pactâ[40] he also shows how democracy failed to
achieve its goals.
First, Rousseauâs âprogramme speaks of political rights only; it does
not mention economic rights.â By ignoring the economic sphere he ends up
creating a class state in which the Republic âis nothing but the
offensive and defensive alliance of those who possess, against those who
do not possessâ, a âcoalition of the barons of property, commerce and
industry against the disinherited lower classâ.[41]
Second, Rousseauâs political solution â a centralised, unitarian,
indivisible republic â recreates the division between rulers and ruled
which it claims to end. Thus, âhaving laid down as a principle that the
people are the only sovereignâ, Rousseau âquietly abandons and discards
this principleâ and so âthe citizen has nothing left but the power of
choosing his rulers by a plurality voteâ. Echoing Rousseauâs own words
about England, Proudhon proclaimed that France was âa quasi-democratic
Republicâ in which citizens âare permitted, every third or fourth year,
to elect, first, the Legislative Power, second, the Executive Power. The
duration of this participation in the Government for the popular
collectivity is brief... The President and the Representatives, once
elected, are the masters; all the rest obey. They are subjects, to be
governed and to be taxed, without surcease.â[42]
Democracy was simply not democratic enough. It âis the negation of the
Peopleâs sovereigntyâ as it âsays that the People reigns and does not
govern, which is to deny the Revolutionâ and concludes âthe People
cannot govern itself and is forced to hand itself over to
representativesâ. Instead of a democracy understood in the manner of the
Jacobin left, Proudhon suggested in anarchy âall citizens... reign and
governâ for they âdirectly participate in the legislation and the
government as they participate in the production and circulation of
wealthâ. While the state âis the external constitution of the social
powerâ in which others âare charged with governing [the People], with
managing its affairsâ, anarchists affirm that âthe people, that societyâŚ
can and ought to govern itself by itself⌠without masters and servantsâ.
When anarchists âdeny the Stateâ they âaffirm in the same breath the
autonomy of the peopleâ for âthe only way to organise democratic
government is to abolish government.â[43]
This meant a real democracy requires decentralisation and federation
otherwise âdemocracy is a fraud, and the sovereignty of the People a
jokeâ. The communes that âcomprise the confederationâ would be
âself-governing, self-judging and self-administering in complete
sovereigntyâ, âuniversal suffrage form [their] basisâ and each âenjoys a
right of secessionâ. Delegates would replace representatives for we âcan
followâ those we elect âstep-by-step in their legislative acts and their
votesâ and âmake them transmit our argumentsâ and when âwe are
discontented, we will recall and dismiss them.â The electoral principle
needed âthe imperative mandate, and permanent revocabilityâ as its âmost
immediate and incontestable consequencesâ. In âa mutualist
confederation, the citizen gives up none of his freedom, as Rousseau
requires him to do for the governance of his republic!â[44]
These democratic principles must also be extended to the economy.
Property âdegrades us, by making us servants and tyrants to one anotherâ
for the wage-workersâ lot was to âwork under a masterâ to whom they had
âsold their arms and parted with their libertyâ. Freedom and property
were incompatible and to secure the former for all we must seek the
âentire abolitionâ of the latter for âall accumulated capital being
social property, no one can be its exclusive proprietorâ and âthe land
[is] common propertyâ. While the use of property âmay be dividedâ its
ownership is âcollective and undividedâ for while âthe right to product
is exclusiveâ, the âright to means is common.â Anarchy required
âindustrial democracyâ as âleaders, instructors, superintendentsâ must
be âchosen from the workers by the workers themselvesâ and so everyone
âparticipates... as an active factorâ with âa deliberative voice in the
council⌠in accordance with equality.â Workplaces must become âworker
republicsâ within an âagricultural-industrial federationâ.[45]
Proudhon, then, stressed the âabolition of manâs exploitation of his
fellow-man and abolition of manâs government of his fellow-manâ were
âone and the same propositionâ for âwhat, in politics, goes under the
name of Authority is analogous to and synonymous with what is termed, in
political economy, Propertyâ. The âprinciple of AUTHORITYâ was
âarticulated throughâ both and an âattack upon one is an attack upon the
other.â[46]
Yet while denouncing both the state and the capitalist workplace as
authoritarian and seeking to replace both by associations, Proudhon
refused to apply his ideas within the family and advocated patriarchy.
This contradiction saw Joseph DĂŠjacque in 1857 applying Proudhonâs own
ideas to the family for it was a case of placing the âissue of the
emancipation of woman in line with the emancipation of the serfâ in the
workshop so that both enter âthe community of anarchyâ. Proudhon did
âcry against the great barons of capitalâ but would ârebuild a proud
barony of man on vassal-womanâ and so was âliberal, but not
libertarian.â[47]
Patriarchy was another archy and subsequent anarchists recognised the
need for consistency. The fundamental commonality between organisations
anarchists oppose â the state, capitalist firms, marriage, etc. â is
that they are authoritarian and âpower and authority corrupt those who
exercise them as much as those who are compelled to submit to them.â[48]
Anarchists, then, âdeny every form of hierarchical organisationâ [49]
So anarchists since the first self-proclaimed anarchist text had already
answered Engelsâ question of âhow do these people propose to operate a
factory, run a railway, or steer a ship without one will that decides in
the last resort, without unified directionâ?[50]Indeed, anarchism was
born precisely to do so and did so with a single word: association.
Anarchists recognise that freedom is a product of interaction between
people and it is how we associate which determines whether we are free
or not. While anarchismâs perspective is social, Engelsâ is
fundamentally liberal as it sees isolation as true freedom and so
confuses agreement with authority, co-operation with coercion.
The real question is simple: is an association based on self-government
of its members or do a few decide for all? So to qualify as libertarian
an organisation must be based on certain core principles that ensure
that liberty is not reduced to simply picking masters.
An organisation that is not voluntary would hardly be free. So free
association requires that individuals decide for themselves which groups
to join. Yet it is more than that for âto promise to obey is to deny or
to limit, to a greater or lesser degree, individualsâ freedom and
equality⌠To promise to obey is to state, that in certain areas, the
person making the promise is no longer free to exercise her capacities
and decide upon her own actions, and is no longer equal, but
subordinate.â[51] Being free to join a group that is internally
hierarchical is simply voluntary archy and so groups have to be
democratic so that those subject to decisions make them.
Thus how we organise was what mattered for âman in isolation can have no
awareness of his liberty. Being free for man means being acknowledged,
considered and treated as such by another man. Liberty is therefore a
feature not of isolation but of interaction, not of exclusion but rather
of connectionâ.[52] This means freedom does not end at the workplace
door or with a marriage ceremony. The capitalist workplace is not
consistent with anarchism for, lest we forget, âa corporation, factory
or business is the economic equivalent of fascism: decisions and control
are strictly top-down.â[53] This means that âstaying free is, for the
working man who has to sell his labour, an impossibilityâ and so a free
economy existed only when âassociations of men and women who would work
on the land, in the factories, in the mines, and so on, became
themselves the managers of production.â[54]
Collective decision making (democracy) must be contrasted to âthe
principle of authority, that is, the eminently theological,
metaphysical, and political idea that the masses, always incapable of
governing themselves, must at all times submit to the benevolent yoke of
a wisdom and a justice imposed upon them, in some way or other, from
above.â Long before Rosa Luxemburg made the same distinction, Bakunin
contrasted two kinds of discipline: an âauthoritarian conceptionâ which
âsignifies despotism on the one hand and blind automatic submission to
authority on the otherâ and another ânot automatic but voluntary and
intelligently understoodâ which is ânecessary whenever a greater number
of individuals undertake any kind of collective work or action.â The
latter was âsimply the voluntary and considered co-ordination of all
individual efforts for a common purposeâ and did not preclude âa natural
division of functions according to the aptitude of each, assessed and
judged by the collective wholeâ. However, âno function remains fixed and
it will not remain permanently and irrevocably attached to any one
person. Hierarchical order and promotion do not exist, so that the
executive of yesterday can become the subordinate of tomorrow.â In this
way âpower, properly speaking, no longer exists. Power is diffused to
the collectivity and becomes the true expression of the liberty of
everyone, the faithful and sincere realisation of the will of allâ. [55]
Yet while democratic, anarchist organisations have to be egalitarian for
simply electing a few who govern the rest reintroduces hierarchies,
albeit elected ones, and least we forget government is the âdelegation
of power, that is, the abdication of the initiative and sovereignty of
every one into the hands of the few.â[56] As the âpeople does not govern
itselfâ it meant that âfree and equal citizens, not about to abdicate
their rights to the care of the few, will seek some new form of
organisation that allows them to manage their affairs for themselvesâ.
Kropotkin pointed to the sections of the French Revolution as popular
institutions ânot separated from the peopleâ and âremained of the
people, and this is what made the revolutionary power of these
organisations.â Rather than nominating representatives and disbanding,
the sections âremained and organised themselves, on their own
initiative, as permanent organs of the municipal administrationâ and
âwere practising what was described later on as Direct Self-Governmentâ.
These were âthe principles of anarchismâ and they âhad their origin, not
in theoretic speculations, but in the deeds of the Great French
Revolutionâ and âby acting in this way â and the libertarians would no
doubt do the same today â the districts of Paris laid the foundations of
a new, free, social organisationâ for âthe Commune of Paris was not to
be a governed State, but a people governing itself directly â when
possible â without intermediaries, without masters.â[57]
Anarchists tend to call this self-management because democracy has, in
practice, meant electing a government rather than a group of people
governing themselves. Yet self-management does not preclude the need to
âallocate a given task to othersâ in the shape of committees but it is a
case of group members ânot abdicating their own sovereigntyâ by âturning
some into directors and chiefsâ.[58] Committees would be agents of the
group rather than their masters for they would be âalways under the
direct control of the populationâ and express the âdecisions taken at
popular assemblies.â[59] How much an individual participates is up to
each person but the option to take part is always there for anarchist
organisation is rooted in âthe possibility of calling the general
assembly whenever it was wanted by the members of the section and of
discussing everything in the general assemblyâ.[60]
Just as individuals associate within groups, so groups will need to
co-ordinate their activities by the same kind of horizontal links that
exist within an association. In this federalist structure decisions are
co-ordinated by elected, mandated and recallable delegates rather than
representatives.[61] This would, by definition, be a decentralised
organisation for power remains at the base in the individuals who
associate together into groups rather than at the top in the hands of a
few representatives and the bureaucracies needed to support them. This
would be in all areas of life: economic (âfederations of Trade Unionsâ),
social (âindependent Communesâ) and personal (âfree combines and
societiesâ).[62] Federation is extensive:
âsociety will be composed of a multitude of associations, federated for
all the purposes which require federation: trade federations for
production of all sorts... federations of communes among themselves, and
federations of communes with trade organisations; and finally, wider
groups covering all the country, or several countries, composed of men
who collaborate for the satisfaction of such economic, intellectual,
artistic, and moral needs as are not limited to a given territory. All
these will combine directly, by means of free agreements between themâŚ
for all sorts of work in common, for intellectual pursuits, or simply
for pleasure.â[63]
The permanence of specific groups or agreements is very much dependent
on the functional needs of the situation or the wishes of the
participants and so cannot be formalised by a hard or fast rule. Some
agreements will be fleeting (to provide specific goods or services) and
others more-or-less permanent (to provide healthcare or railway
networks). The key is that the federation lasts as long as is required,
that association is produced by objective needs and does not exist for
its own sake.
The question is âto organise universal suffrage in its plenitudeâ for
each âfunction, industrial or otherwiseâ. Each functional group would
elect its own delegates in its own separate bodies meaning âthe country
governs itself solely by means of its electoral initiativeâ and âit is
no longer governed.â Such popular assemblies are âa matter of the
organisation of universal suffrage in all its forms, of the very
structure of Democracy itself.â Instead of centralising all issues into
the hands of one assembly, there would be a multitude of assemblies each
covering a specific social function for âa society of free menâ is based
on the âassociating with different groups according to the nature of
their industries or their interests and by whom neither collective nor
individual sovereignty is ever abdicated or delegatedâ and so âthe
Government has ceased to exist as a result of universal suffrageâ. This
âtruly democratic regime, with its unity at the bottom and its
separation at the top, [is] the reverse of what now existsâ and
âcentralisation [would] be effected from the bottom to the top, from the
circumference to the centre, and that all functions be independent and
govern themselves independentlyâ.[64]
While some suggest that anarchism inherently supports small-scale groups
or industry this is not the case. It recognises that size is driven by
the objective needs of a functional task. A workplace is as big as its
output requires (âoceanic steamers cannot be built in village
factoriesâ[65]) while a commune can be a village, town or a city. While
large organisations would â as is the case now â be sub-divided
internally into functional groups, this does not change the fact that
anarchists have always incorporated the fact of, and need for,
large-scale organisation and industry. Indeed, federalism is advocated
precisely to co-ordinate, plan and provide services judged by those who
need them to be better done together.
What level a specific industry or service should be co-ordinated at will
vary depending on what it is so no hard and fast rule can be formulated
but the basic principle is that groups âunite with each other in a
mutual and equal way, for one or more specific tasks, whose
responsibility specially and exclusively falls to the delegates of the
federationâ. For example, it is a case of âthe initiative of communes
and departments as to works that operate within their jurisdictionâ plus
âthe initiative of the workers companies as to carrying the works outâ
for the âdirect, sovereign initiative of localities, in arranging for
public works that belong to them, is a consequence of the democratic
principle and the free contractâ. [66]
In short, self-governing individuals join self-governing groups that, in
turn, join self-governing federations.
Individuals are free in-so-far as the associations they join are
participatory and without hierarchy. Yet anarchists do not think that
there will be unanimity within each group for âvariety, conflict even,
is lifeâ while âuniformity is deathâ.[67] In disagreements, the minority
has a choice â agree to work with the majority, leave the association or
practice civil disobedience to convince the majority of the errors of
their way. Which option is best depends on the nature of the decision
and the group. Similarly, the majority has the right to expel a minority
(free association means the freedom not to associate).
Rather than constantly governed by the few â whether that few is the
elected of the majority matters little â individuals within an
association will participate in decisions and will sometimes be in the
majority, sometimes not, in numerous groups and federations. The
ânecessity of division and association of labourâ means âI take and I
give â such is human life. Each is an authoritative leader and in turn
is led by others. Accordingly there is no fixed and constant authority,
but continual exchange of mutual, temporary, and, above all, voluntary
authority and subordination.â[68] No oneâs permanent position would be
one of subjection as under statism, capitalism, patriarchy or racism.
This self-managed society was termed by Proudhon a âLabour
Democracyâ[69] to clearly differentiate it from existing â bourgeois â
forms of democracy:
âno longer do we have the abstraction of peopleâs sovereignty as in the
â93 Constitution and the others that followed it, and in Rousseauâs
Social Contract. Instead it becomes an effective sovereignty of the
labouring masses which rule and govern... the labouring masses are
actually, positively and effectively sovereign: how could they not be
when the economic organism â labour, capital, property and assets â
belongs to them entirelyâ[70]
None of this assumes that the majority has the right to rule the
minority just that, in general, members who join a group do so
understanding the decision making process within the association and can
leave if they no longer agree with specific decisions of the
majority.[71] Thus we have majority decision making but not majority
government for anarchists âhave the special mission of being vigilant
custodians of freedom, against all aspirants to power and against the
possible tyranny of the majorityâ.[72] The case for anarchy â
self-management â is not that the majority is always right but that no
minority can be trusted not to prefer its own advantage if given power.
Many anarchists are sympathetic to the saying â popularised if not
invented by the Situationists â that the difference between theory and
ideology is that the former is when you have ideas and the latter is
when ideas have you. As such, anarchists tend to suggest that theirs is
not an ideology but rather a theory. The dangers of ideology can best be
seen by comparing libertarian theory with the ideology that is called
âlibertarianismâ by its proponents.
Yet how can anarchists â who have called themselves libertarians since
1857 â be against âlibertarianismâ?
First, because the advocates of âlibertarianismâ did not let their
ideological support for absolute property rights stop them knowingly
stealing the name from those who invented and used it. As Murray
Rothbard recalled:
âOne gratifying aspect of our rise to some prominence [in 1950s America]
is that, for the first time in my memory, we, âour side,â had captured a
crucial word from the enemy... âLibertariansâ... had long been simply a
polite word for left-wing [sic!] anarchists, that is for anti-private
property anarchists, either of the communist or syndicalist variety. But
now we had taken it overâ[73]
Second, and more importantly, âlibertarianismâ ignores what drove the
creation of anarchism and returns to the authoritarianism of classical
liberalism.
This is shown when Rothbard proclaims that the state âarrogates to
itself a monopoly of force, of ultimate decision-making power, over a
given territorial areaâ then, buried in the chapterâs end notes, quietly
admits that â[o]bviously, in a free society, Smith has the ultimate
decision-making power over his own just property, Jones over his,
etc.â[74] He does not mention the obvious â they also have âultimate
decision-making powerâ over those who use that property. Robert Nozick
was more open: âif one starts a private town⌠persons who chose to move
there or later remain there would have no right to a say in how the town
was runâ.[75]
While some argue that it âwould be logically inconsistent for an
ideology to defend individual choice and to deny people the voteâ[76],
for âlibertarianismâ the opposite is the case. Yet the contradictions â
âlibertariansâ advocating dictatorship, a definition of the state (evil)
identical to property (good) â are all too clear as anarchists had
denounced since 1840. Ironically, Rothbard himself shows the validity of
the anarchist critique:
âIf the State may be said to properly own its territory, then it is
proper for it to make rules for everyone who presumes to live in that
area⌠So long as the State permits its subjects to leave its territory,
then, it can be said to act as does any other owner who sets down rules
for people living on his property.â[77]
The question now becomes one not of liberty within an association but
whether those who hold power (âsets down rulesâ) do so legitimately or
not and this relates to property. Rothbard argues that the state does
not âjustlyâ own its territory and asserts that his âhomesteading
theoryâ of the creation of private property âsuffices to demolish any
such pretensions by the State apparatusâ and so the problem with the
state is that it âclaims and exercises a compulsory monopoly of defence
and ultimate decision-making over an area larger than an individualâs
justly-acquired property.â[78] Yet private property has never been
acquired in the form Rothbard (echoing Locke) suggested but has been
bound-up with state and private coercion â assuming his theory was
robust, which it is not. His attempt to eliminate the obvious
difficulties he faces involves âadding mythical and imaginary happenings
to make up for the âreality gapsââ[79] along with hopes that he found
people âsimple enough to believe himâ.
Ignoring Rothbardâs immaculate conception of property as being as
unrelated to reality as Lockeâs social contract theory of the state, the
question arises why current and future generations should be
dispossessed from liberty by the private hierarchies associated with
property. Rothbard helps us answer that question by a hypothetical
example of a country whose King, threatened by a rising âlibertarianâ
movement, responses by âemploy[ing] a cunning stratagem,â namely he
âproclaims his government to be dissolved, but just before doing so he
arbitrarily parcels out the entire land area of his kingdom to the
âownershipâ of himself and his relatives.â Rather than taxes, his
subjects now pay rent and he can âregulate the lives of all the people
who presume to live onâ his property as he sees fit. Rothbard then
admits people would be âliving under a regime no less despotic than the
one they had been battling for so long. Perhaps, indeed, more despotic,
for now the king and his relatives can claim for themselves the
libertariansâ very principle of the absolute right of private property,
an absoluteness which they might not have dared to claim before.â[80]
While Rothbard rejects this âcunning stratagemâ he failed to note how
this argument undermines his own claims. As he himself argues, not only
does the property owner have the same monopoly of power over a given
area as the state, this is more despotic. He fails to notice that if the
state owning its territory makes it (âas well as the King in the Middle
Agesâ) âa feudal overlordâ[81]then this makes the capitalist or landlord
a feudal overlord within âlibertarianism.â It is a strange ideology that
proclaims itself liberty-loving yet embraces factory feudalism and
office oligarchy.
The one remaining defence of âlibertarianismâ is that these absolutist
social relationships are fine because they are voluntary in nature for
there is no such a thing as economic power under capitalism.[82] It is
easy to refute such claims with Rothbardâs words on the abolition of
slavery and serfdom in the 19^(th) century:
âThe bodies of the oppressed were freed, but the property which they had
worked and eminently deserved to own, remained in the hands of their
former oppressors. With economic power thus remaining in their hands,
the former lords soon found themselves virtual masters once more of what
were now free tenants or farm labourers. The serfs and slaves had tasted
freedom, but had been cruelly derived of its fruits.â[83]
So if âmarket forcesâ (âvoluntary exchangesâ) result in the few owning
most of the property then this is unproblematic and raises no questions
about the (lack of) liberty of the working class but if people are
placed in exactly the same situation as a result of coercion then it is
a case of âeconomic powerâ and âmastersâ.
Such is the danger of ideology that it allows someone to write a book
that actually refutes his own arguments.
This shows the importance of organisation to a political theory.
Anarchism by placing liberty as a priority principle took it seriously
and recognised the obvious contradictions in defining (limiting!) it to
just consent. They opposed the liberal attempt to decontest the notion
by pointing to its practice. That Nozick â repeating Locke[84] â can ask
whether âa free system would allowâ someone âto sell himself into
slaveryâ and answer âI believe that it wouldâ[85] shows the correctness
of anarchism.
The apparent paradox of why an ideology self-proclaimed as âlibertarianâ
is not particularly interested in liberty and justifies numerous
obviously authoritarian social relations (up to and including voluntary
slavery and dictatorship) is not a paradox at all. Contract in the
liberal sense âalways generates political right in the form of relations
of domination and subordinationâ and so rather than âundermining
subordination, contract theorists justified modern civil
subjection.â[86]
The farcical self-contradictions that Rothbard repeatedly gets himself
into shows why âevery society declines the moment it falls into the
hands of the ideologistsâ[87]. At its worse, ideology allows its
believers to not only ignore â even justify â social injustice but also
to contradict their stated aspirations and abuse logic. While it may be
argued that it is only by using ideology that we can expose this kind of
contradiction, the fundamental problem is that it is ideology which
blinds Rothbard and Nozick to the obvious: âif you have unbridled
capitalism, you will have all kinds of authority: you will have extreme
authority.â[87]
The contradictions of âlibertarianismâ also shows that historical
understanding and context is important. It does not afford âa typical
example of a gravitational shift within conventional ideologies that
obscures an ideologyâs foundational principles by reorganising the core
units of furniture.â Locke shows this is not the case for rather than
âcrowding out or demoting other liberal core conceptsâ, this ideology
sees itself as clearing the room of furniture which has no place in it.
It is not the case that its advocates âoveremphasize individual liberty
at the expense of other liberal valuesâ[88] for they do not âexpand the
liberty themeâ but rather aim to restrict it â for the many.
Once it is realised that core principle of âlibertarianismâ is property
rather than liberty then it is must be renamed to propertarianism.
Organisation is a fundamental aspect of any theory simply because it
shows how it is applied. If an ideology places organisation to the
periphery then its adherents are not particularly bothered by their
stated core principles for it expresses an indifference to whether they
are achieved in practice.
Anarchism is part of the reaction to liberalism and its production of
both âindustrial servitudeâ and âobedient subjects to a central
authority.â[89] Liberalism is a âtheoretical strategy that justifies
subjection by presenting it as freedomâ. It has âturned a subversive
propositionâ that we are born free and equal âinto a defence of civil
subjectionâ for âthe employment contract (like the marriage contract) is
not an exchange; both contracts create social relations that endure over
time â social relations of subordination.â[90]
Like democracy, anarchism saw its task as seeking a form of organisation
within which freedom was protected. In contrast to the stereotype of
anarchism as an impractical dream without an understanding of the
complexities of the modern world, anarchists have spent considerable
time discussing how to organise to meet social needs in a world marked
by large-scale industry and ever wider personal and social interactions
while ensuring individual and social freedom. Anarchist critiques of
Rousseau are driven not by a rejection of democracy but rather a desire
to see a genuine one created. Woodcock was wrong both logically and
historically to proclaim that âthe ideal of anarchism, far from being
democracy carried to its logical end, is much nearer to aristocracy
universalised and purified.â[91]
To âcontract a relationship of voluntary servitudeâ was inconsistent
with anarchist principles as âthe freedom of every individual is
inalienableâ and so associations could have no other footing âbut the
utmost equality and reciprocity.â[92] Anarchism values individual
liberty but sees it a product of social interaction and so embraces the
necessity of equality within groups to ensure it remains meaningful.
This, in turn, means embracing a critique of property to ensure that
those who join a workplace are associates rather than master and
servants. Finally, if self-management is applicable within the workplace
then it is also applicable for all social and private associations.
Anarchism recognises that there are many types of organisation â those
which are forced upon you and those you freely join as well as those
which are authoritarian (top-down) and those which are libertarian
(bottom-up). Genuine liberty necessitates groups that are free to join
and are free internally as voluntary archy is not an-archy. Anarchist
organisational principles are core because they intersect with other
core concepts by expressing them.
[87]Proudhon, Système des contradictions Êconomiques ou Philosophie de
la misère (Paris: Guillaumin, 1846) I: 75
[1] Errico Malatesta: His Life and Ideas (London: Freedom Press,
1993),Vernon Richards (ed.), 84â5
[2] Michael Freeden, Ideology: A Very Short Introduction (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2003), 62
[3] George Woodcock, Anarchism: A History of Libertarian Ideas and
Movements (England: Penguin Books, 1986), 226â7
[4] David Turcato, Making Sense of Anarchism: Errico Malatestaâs
Experiments with Revolution, 1889â1900 (Edinburgh/Oakland: AK Press,
2015)
[5]
C. B Macpherson, The Political Theory of Possessive Individualism:
Hobbes to Locke, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1964), 194
[6] John Locke, Two Treatises of Government (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2013), Peter Laslett (ed.), 322, 323, 268
[7] Carole Pateman, The Sexual Contract (Cambridge: Polity, 1988), 40
[8] Locke, 288
[9] Macpherson, 203â20
[10] Locke, 302
[11] Locke, 289
[12] Macpherson, 214â5
[13] Carole Pateman, The Problem of Political Obligation: A Critique of
Liberal Theory (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1985), 67â72
[14] Macpherson, 221â2, 248â9, 227, 251
[15] Macpherson, 196
[16] John Locke, Political Essays (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1997), Mark Goldie (ed.), 161â175
[17] Pateman, Problem, 68
[18] Pateman, Problem, 142
[19] Locke, Treatises, 308
[20] Jean-Jacques Rousseau, The Social Contract and Discourses (London:
Everyman, 1996), 181
[21] Rousseau, 99
[22] Rousseau, 84
[23] Rousseau, 225
[24] Rousseau, 162
[25] Rousseau, 199, 225
[26] Rousseau, 316
[27] Rousseau, 105, 269, 104, 200, 186
[28] Rousseau, 266, 201, 203â4, 230, 212, 191
[29] Peter Kropotkin, The Great French Revolution, 1789â1793 (London:
Orbach and Chambers Ltd, 1971)
[30] Peter Kropotkin, The State: Its Historic Role (London: Freedom
Press, 1987), 51â4
[31] quoted by Roger Magraw, A History of the French Working Class
(Oxford/Cambridge: Blackwell, 1992) I: 24â25
[32] Bernard H. Moss, The Origins of the French Labour Movement
1830â1914: The Socialism of Skilled Workers (Berkeley/Los
Angeles/London: University of California Press, 1980), 32â3
[33] Magraw, 55, 72
[34]
K. Steven Vincent, Pierre-Joseph Proudhon and the Rise of French
Republican Socialism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984) 127â140
[35] See Vincent for an excellent discussion of this.
[36] Property is Theft! A Pierre-Joseph Proudhon Anthology
(Edinburgh/Oakland/Baltimore: AK Press, 2011), Iain McKay (ed.), 132â5
[37] Property, 92
[38] Property, 95, 106, 117, 114, 129
[39] Aaron Noland, âProudhon and Rousseauâ, Journal of the History of
Ideas 28:1 (Jan-Mar 1967)
[40] Property, 565
[41] Property, 566
[42] Property, 566, 573
[43] Property, 261, 267, 280, 482â5
[44] Property, 595, 716, 763, 273, 762
[45] Property, 248, 212, 91, 118, 153, 137, 112, 610, 119, 215, 780,
711; also see Property, 583â6
[46] Property, 503â6
[47] âThe Human Beingâ, available at:
[48] Michael Bakunin, The Political Philosophy of Bakunin (New York: The
Free Press, 1953), G.P. Maximov (ed.), 249
[49] Peter Kropotkin, Direct Struggle Against Capital: A Peter Kropotkin
Anthology (Edinburgh/Oakland/Baltimore: AK Press, 2014), Iain McKay
(ed.), 385
[50] Marx-Engels Collected Works 44: 307
[51] Pateman, Problem, 19
[52] Bakunin, Michael Bakunin: Selected Writings (London: Jonathan Cape,
1973), Arthur Lehning (ed.), 131, 135, 147
[53] Noam Chomsky, Letters from Lexington: Reflections on Propaganda
(Monroe/Edinburgh: Common Courage Press/AK Press, 1993), 127
[54] Kropotkin, Direct, 160, 187
[55] Bakunin on Anarchism, 408, 142, 414â5; Rosa Luxemburg Speaks (New
York: Pathfinder Press, 1970), Mary-Alice Waters (ed.), 119â20
[56] Malatesta, The Method of Freedom: An Errico Malatesta Reader
(Edinburgh/Oakland, AK Press, 2014), Davide Turcato (Ed.), 136
[57] Direct, 225, 228, 419â25
[58] Malatesta, Freedom, 214
[59] Malatesta, Life, 175, 129
[60] Direct, 426
[61] Proudhon, Property, 377; Bakunin, Selected, 170â2, Malatesta,
Freedom, 63
[62] Direct, 188
[63] Direct, 105
[64] Property, 439â41, 461, 446â7
[65] Direct, 665
[66] Property, 969, 594â5
[67] Kropotkin, Anarchism: A Collection of Revolutionary Writings (New
York: Dover Press, 2002), Roger N. Baldwin (ed.), 143
[68] Bakunin, Political, 353â4
[69] Property, 724
[70] Property, 760â1
[71] Malatesta, Freedom, 488â9
[72] Malatesta, Life, 161
[73] The Betrayal of the American Right (Auburn, Alabama: Ludwig von
Mises Institute, 207), 83
[74] The Ethics of Liberty (Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press,
1982), 170, 173
[75] Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State and Utopia (Oxford: B. Blackwell,
1974), 270
[76] Freeden, 55
[77] Rothbard, 170
[78] Rothbard, 171, 173
[79] Freeden, 106
[80] Rothbard, 54
[81] Rothbard, 171
[82] Rothbard, 221â2
[83] Rothbard, 74
[84] Locke, Treatises, 284â5
[85] Nozick, 371
[86] Pateman, Sexual, 8, 40
[87] Noam Chomsky, Understanding Power: The Indispensable Chomsky (New
York: The New Press, 2002), Peter R. Mitchell and John Schoeffel (eds.),
200
[88] Freeden, 95, 64
[89] Kropotkin, Anarchism, 137
[90] Pateman, Sexual, 39, 148
[91] Woodcock, Anarchism, 31
[92] Bakunin, Selected, 147, 68