💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › anarcho-on-anarchist-organisation.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 07:24:14. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: On Anarchist Organisation
Author: Anarcho
Date: November 16, 2019
Language: en
Topics: anarchist organization
Source: Retrieved on 24th April 2021 from https://anarchism.pageabode.com/?p=1120

Anarcho

On Anarchist Organisation

“organisation, that is to say, association for a specific purpose and

with the structure and means required to attain it, is a necessary

aspect of social life. A man in isolation cannot even live the life of a

beast […] Having therefore to join with other humans […] he must submit

to the will of others (be enslaved) or subject others to his will (be in

authority) or live with others in fraternal agreement in the interests

of the greatest good of all (be an associate). Nobody can escape from

this necessity.”

– Errico Malatesta[1]

Introduction

The notion that anarchism is inherently against organisation is one much

asserted.

George Woodcock, the ex-anarchist turned anarchism’s self-appointed

historian, proclaimed that “it seems evident that logically pure

anarchism goes against its own nature when it attempts to create

elaborate international or even national organisations, which need a

measure of rigidity and centralisation to survive.” A syndicalist union,

however, needs “relatively stable organisations and succeeds in creating

them precisely because it moves in a world that is only partly governed

by anarchist ideals”. He reflected the opinion of a large band of more

hostile commentators on anarchism who inflict a fundamental

irrationality on anarchists. If “pure” anarchism is against any form of

organisation beyond its “natural unit” of the “loose and flexible

affinity group” then few sensible people would embrace it for neither a

rail network nor a hospital could be reliably run by such a unit.[2]

However, if we accept that anarchists are no different from other social

activists and so fundamentally rational and realistic people as Davide

Turcato persuasively (and correctly!) argues[3] then we need to admit

that anarchist theoreticians and activists would not be advocating an

ideal that could not possibly work. Unsurprisingly, then, we discover

that anarchists – in general – spent some time thinking about

organisation and how they could apply their ideas to the world around

them. This is understandable as anarchists aim to change society for the

better – whether by reform or revolution – and as such sought practical

solutions to the social problems they saw around them. Theory needs to

be reflected in practice and a theory which – by “its own nature” –

precludes practical alternatives to the social ills it is protesting

against would be a waste of time. No anarchist considers their ideas in

such a light.

Anarchism rather than ignoring the need for organisation has always

addressed it. This is because rather than being a peripheral concept,

organisation is fundamentally a core aspect of any ideology as it is

“the point where concepts lose their abstraction” and “are interwoven

with the concrete practices sanctioned or condemned by an ideology.”[4]

What organisational forms an ideology advocates says far more about its

actual core values than the words it uses.

This can be seen from anarchism considered as both a theory and a

movement. It was born in the context of an intellectual inheritance of

liberalism and democracy and a social context of the rise of industrial

capitalism and opposition to it in the shape of the workers’ movement

and socialism. We will show how it built upon the critique of liberalism

pioneered by Jean-Jacque Rousseau and applied it against both

wage-labour (capitalism) and democracy itself. In the process it

developed clear organisational principles to ensure social life could

continue – indeed, flourish – without archy.[5]

The Ideological and Social Context

While there has been a tendency, started by Paul Eltzbacher and

popularised by Woodcock to view anarchist theorists as being isolated

thinkers, in reality all the major thinkers have been very much part of

their society and its popular movements, seeking to gain influence for

the ideas they have produced to solve its problems.[6]

This applies to the key thinkers associated with the birth and rise of

anarchism as both a named theory and as a movement in the mid- to

late-nineteenth century: Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, Michael Bakunin and

Peter Kropotkin.

All three, like other lesser known anarchist thinkers and activists,

were embedded in the world they were seeking to transform. They were

aware of the intellectual and social context in which they lived and

critically engaged with both. This can be seen most obviously with

Proudhon’s writings and its well referenced polemics against the

defenders of property, liberal economists and state socialist colleagues

within the French democratic and labour movements but it should also be

clear that Bakunin and Kropotkin, being Russian aristocrats, were

well-versed with the intellectual currents of their times even if their

writings were usually for the readers of anarchist journals.

The main immediate ideological influences on anarchism were liberalism

(as personified by John Locke) and democracy (as personified by

Rousseau). The social context was the failure of the French Revolution

and the rise of industrial capitalism as well as the oppositional

movements each produced: radical republicanism and the labour and

socialist movements, respectively.

Locke: Justifying Subordinate Relations

Liberalism is usually associated with John Locke who is often presented

as the foundational thinker for modern Western freedoms and democracy.

Yet we cannot understand Locke if he has “modern liberal-democratic

assumptions read into his political thought.”[7] His political theory is

not primarily concerned with defending liberty but rather property and

the power that comes with it.[8] Thus he takes wage-labour as existing

in his “state of nature” and as a self-evident natural order:

“Master and Servant are names as old as History […] a freeman makes

himself a servant to another, by selling him, for a certain time, the

service he undertakes to do, in exchange for wages he is to receive […]

it gives the master but a temporary power over him, and no greater than

what is contained in the Contract between ‘em.”[9]

This produces a situation where “a Master of a Family” rules over others

with “all these subordinate relations of Wife, Children, Servants, and

Slaves” and with “a very distinct and differently limited Power”. He was

at pains to differentiate the power of “a Master over his Servant, a

Husband over his Wife, and a Lord over his Slave” from political power.

Thus power from wealth was considered as not an issue beyond ensuring

that it did not take the form of a political power, namely “a Right of

making Laws with Penalties of Death, and consequently all less

Penalties”. However as the State existed “for the Regulating and

Preserving of Property, and of employing the force of the Community, in

the Execution of such Laws”[10], the property owner could expect the

full backing of the state in ensuring his authority was obeyed.

Locke, then, argues that alleged free and equal individuals create

organisations in which the few rule over the many. That is, within the

liberal organisation “subordinate relations” – hierarchy – is the

outcome yet the awkward question remains: “it is hard to see why a free

and equal individual should have sufficient good reason to subordinate

herself to another.”[11]

Locke rose to this challenge with the liberal use of the word consent

and a “just-so” story rooted in what appear reasonable assumptions. The

latter are of note for Locke is keen to base his defence of the

bourgeois order on both labour and common property. Thus land is given

to everyone in common by God while labour “is the unquestionable

property of the labourer”. He uses examples of people who have

“appropriated” the produce of the commons (“the Acorns he pickt up under

an Oak, or the Apples he gathered from the Trees in the Wood”) to the

appropriating the commons themselves. To the objection that

appropriating the commons ends the freedom of others to take its

produce, he suggests “no man but he can have a right to what [his

labour] that is once joined to, at least where there is enough, and as

good, left in common for others.”[12]

Yet this limitation is quickly overcome[13] by the increased

productivity of the appropriated land which meant “there was still

enough, and as good left; and more than the yet unprovided could use. ”

The “tacit Agreement” to use money “introduced (by Consent) larger

Possessions” which in turn meant “it is plain, that Men have agreed to a

disproportionate and unequal Possession of the Earth, they having, by a

tacit and voluntary consent, found out, a way how a man may fairly

possess more land than he himself can use the product of, by receiving

in exchange for the overplus, Gold and Silver, which may be hoarded up

without injury to any one”[14] Significantly, this inequality of

property exists in the state of nature and precedes the creation of the

state. Equally significantly, Locke justifies appropriation of the world

not in terms of increased liberty for all but rather by the trickle-down

effect of increased wealth produced by that appropriation.

With all the land appropriated and inequality in wealth the norm, any

free agreement between the rich and proletariat would favour the former

and create authoritarian social relationships which Locke took as both

natural and unproblematic for liberty:

“since the Authority of the Rich Proprietor, and the Subjection of the

Needy Beggar, began not from the Possession of the Lord, but the Consent

of the poor Man, who preferr’d being his Subject to starving. And the

Man he thus submits to, can pretend to no more Power over him, than he

has consented to, upon Compact.”[15]

This is part of Locke’s argument against absolute Monarchy and its

ideological justifications, namely that the sovereignty of a Monarchy –

the King’s power of life and death – rested on ownership of the land

(“Private Dominion”). Thus while the property owner had authority over

his wage-worker and tenant as specified in a contract, ownership “could

give him no Sovereignty” understood as being “an Absolute, Arbitrary,

Unlimited, and Unlimitable power over the Lives, Liberties, and Estates

of his Children and Subjects”.[16]

Once the worker has consented to being under the authority of the

wealthy then his labour and its product is no longer his own property:

“Thus the Grass my Horse has bit; the Turfs my Servant has cut; and the

Ore I have digg’d in any place, where I have a right to them in common

with others, become my Property.” The workers’ labour is now his

employer’s and “hath fixed my property” in both the product and common

resources worked upon.[17] Thus Locke’s defence of property as resting

on labour becomes the means to derive the worker of the full product of

that labour. This is unsurprising for “the more emphatically labour is

asserted to be a property, the more it is to be understood to be

alienable. For property in the bourgeois sense is not only a right to

enjoy or use; it is a right to dispose of, to exchange, to

alienate.”[18]

Thus liberalism rationalises organisations based on “authority” and

“subjection”, which turns one into the “subject” of another thanks to

property which, lest we forget, “the Preservation” of was the “great and

chief end” for men “uniting into commonwealths, and putting themselves

under Government”. Therefore, “Subjects or Foreigners, attempting by

force on the Properties of any People, may be resisted with force”[19]

Government is based on an alienation of the natural liberty of the

property owners into “the Legislature” who could not “think themselves

in a Civil Society” until the government “was placed in collective

Bodies of Men, call them Senate, Parliament, or what you please”[20] and

so Locke’s “liberal state, or the political sphere, stands over and

above, and external to, the world of everyday life.”[21] This collective

body of landlords would rule supreme over the individuals who make it up

“for it would be a direct Contradiction, for any one, to enter into

society with others for the securing and regulating of property […] to

suppose his Land, whose Property is to be regulated by the Laws of the

Society, should be exempt from the Jurisdiction of that Government, to

which he himself, the Proprietor of the Land, is a Subject” After this,

a man “is at liberty to go and incorporate himself into any other

Commonwealth”.[22]

Once the land is appropriated and wealth accumulated in a few hands,

then this few combine to form a political state because the previous

government – a monarchy – no longer acts as an impartial umpire and

takes a self-interested part in the numerous conflicts between property

owners. This turns “the state of nature” into “the state of war” as the

King starts to exercise absolute power over the property owners and

their property. This produces the need to overthrow the monarchy and

create a political power which “turns out to be the majority of the

representatives, and the latter are chosen by the propertied.”[23]

This meant that while the “labouring class is a necessary part of the

nation its members are not in fact full members of the body politic and

have no claim to be so”. Locke considered “all men as members [of civil

society] for the purposes of being ruled and only the men of estate as

members for the purpose of ruling” (or “more accurately, the right to

control any government”). Workers, the actual majority, “were in but of

civil society” and so Locke “would have no difficulty, therefore, in

thinking of the state as a joint-stock company of owners whose majority

of decision binds not only themselves but also their employees.”[24]

In short, Locke “was not a democrat at all.”[25] Needless to say, many

liberal writers have objected to these kinds of arguments and

conclusions and given these conflicting interpretations of Locke and his

democratic credentials (or lack of them), some may consider it

impossible to determine the facts of the matter. Here, however, Locke

himself provides an answer with his The Fundamental Constitutions of

Carolina that postulates rule by wealthy landlords as well as the

introduction of serfdom. Significantly, its preamble is very clear on

who is forming this state and why:

“that we may avoid erecting a numerous democracy, we, the lords and

proprietors of the province aforesaid, have agreed to this following

form of government”[26]

Ignoring his “just-so” story of land appropriation, Locke simply

allocated the land to “eight proprietors” who each received “one-fifth

of the whole” in perpetually while “the hereditary nobility” received

another fifth. The parliament would be made up “of the proprietors or

their deputies” and “one freeholder out of every precinct.” The

freeholder members of parliament had to have more than “five hundred

acres of freehold within the precinct for which he is chosen” while the

electorate would be made up of those who have more than “fifty acres of

freehold within the said precinct.”[27]

Compare this to a Commonwealth described in the Second Treatise which

had a “single hereditary Person having the constant, supream, executive

Power”, an “Assembly of Hereditary Nobility” and an “Assembly of

Representatives chosen, pro tempore, by the People”.[28] Where “the

People” being those who matter, the wealthy, for “Locke’s argument says

nothing” about what the character of this majority in the two Treatises

is because he “took for granted” that the “members of the political

community” were “males who own substantial amounts of material property”

and so “politically relevant members of society.”[29]

Given that Locke, in spite of his apparent denunciations of slavery, was

a shareholder in slaving companies, it comes as no surprise that a

freeman “shall have absolute power and authority over his negro slaves”

while this civil dominion of a master over his slaves was likewise

extended to workers or, more correctly, hereditary serfs (called

leet-men) who were “under the jurisdiction of the respective lord” and

could not leave the land “without licences from his said lord”. Rest

assured, this serfdom is based on consent for an additional article

included in 1670 allowed anyone to voluntarily register himself as a

leet-man.[30]

This serfdom is not inconsistent with Locke’s Treatises on government.

There he noted that by commonwealth he wished “to be understood all

along to mean not a democracy, or any form of government, but any

independent community” while he acknowledged that “men did sell

themselves” into slavery, although he favoured the term “drudgery”.

Slavery, Locke argued, meant a relationship “between a lawful

Conquerour, and a Captive” where the former has the power of life and

death over the latter. Once a “Compact” is agreed between them, “an

agreement for a limited power on the one side, and obedience on the

other” meant “Slavery ceases.” As long as the master cannot kill or main

the slave, then it is “plain” that this was “only Drudgery” as “it is

evident” that “the person sold was not under an Absolute, Arbitrary,

Despotical power.”[31]

It should also be noted that Locke invented another story to justify

actual slavery, namely the notion of a “just war.” Like the one to

justify appropriation of land and rationalise master-servant relations,

in this story slavery could be justified when the victors in a war

started by those they have defeated offered the prisoners a choice,

slavery or death: “Slaves who being captives taken in a just War, are by

the Right of Nature subjected to the Absolute Dominion and Arbitrary

Power of their Masters.” This meant that the conqueror “has an Absolute

Power over the Lives of those, who by an Unjust War have forfeited

them,” a power Locke calls “purely Despotical” for “he has an absolute

power over the Lives of those, who putting themselves in a State of War,

have forfeited them.” The slave-owner can murder his slave and this,

too, is ultimately based on consent: “For, whenever he finds the

hardship of his Slavery out-weigh the value of his Life, ’tis in his

Power, be resisting the Will of his Master, to draw on himself the Death

he desires.”[32]

Just as his just-so story protected his property in land and capital

(and the status and power that went with it), so this just-so story

protected his substantial investments in the slave trade. That no

wealthy man had acquired his property in the manner described was as

irrelevant as the slaves he profited from were not aggressors against

the slavers (quite the reverse). So even absolute chattel slavery, with

the power of life and death, is based on consent – and his investments

safe and ethical.

All this indicates that Locke’s Constitutions of Serfdom was not in

contradiction with the alleged egalitarian and democratic ideas in the

Treatises any more than his spurious hair-splitting over “slavery” and

“drudgery” is no accident. Rather it exposes the core of his ideology as

his works were written to justify and rationalise rule by the wealthy

and provide a veneer of voluntarism for oppressive, authoritarian and

exploitative social relationships.

That Locke himself was a wealthy man hangs heavy over his work as it is

fundamentally a defence for his social position. He attacked both

absolutist monarchy and radical democracy. He justifies a class state

for he takes a class society – his own – for his starting point and,

indeed, eternalises it in “the state of nature”. The Lockean (liberal)

social contract gives “justification to, and is expressly designed to

preserve, the social inequalities of the capitalist market economy”[33]

and the authoritarian social relationships within production these

create, relations which Locke was well aware of. The master-servant

relationship was precisely what his theory of property in the person

sought to justify for a servant’s labour (and liberty) being their

property it could be alienated (sold). Yet, for Locke, both the owning

class and working class benefited from the social contract. The former

saw their property and power protected by a government of their own

class from the whims of Monarchs proclaiming their divine right to rule.

The latter saw the power of their masters reduced to a limited authority

and so could not be killed or maimed on a whim by those who they had

consented to obey. After all, “no rational Creature can be supposed to

change his condition with an intention to be worse”.[34]

In both cases, consent is the means used. This is the hardest worked

concept in Locke’s ideology and is used to justify a multitude of

liberty destroying social relationships: actual slavery, voluntary

slavery, wage-labour, patriarchal marriage. Yet any ambiguities in

Locke’s theoretical work – and any read into the work by later readers

whose liberalism has been modified by other influences – are clarified

when we look at the organisation within which he sought to apply it. A

class state based on wealthy landlords assembling together in a

Parliament to rule themselves and their servants is exposed in his

organisation for Carolina.[35]

Rousseau: Liberty cannot exist without Equality

Locke’s theory was “no less influential in France than in its native

England”[36] and was likewise utilised to combat absolutist Monarchy.

However, the person who is most associated with French democracy,

Jean-Jacque Rousseau, “denounces the liberal social contract as an

illegitimate fraud”.[37] If Locke proclaimed “we are born Free”[38] then

Rousseau replied that we are “everywhere in chains”[39] and sought to

explain why liberalism produced and justified this.

Critiquing Liberalism’s “just-so” story of state formation, Rousseau

noted how “[a]ll ran headlong to their chains, in the hopes of securing

their liberty” when, in fact, it “bound new fetters on the poor, and

gave new powers to the rich; which irretrievably destroyed natural

liberty, eternally fixed the law of property and inequality, converted

clever usurpation into unalterable right, and, for the advantage of a

few ambitious individuals, subjected all mankind to perpetual labour,

slavery, and wretchedness.”[40] The liberal social contract was based on

defending property rather than liberty:

“The first man who, having enclosed a piece of ground, bethought himself

of saying This is mine, and found people simple enough to believe him,

was the real founder of civil society. From how many crimes, wars and

murders, from how many horrors and misfortunes might not any one have

saved mankind, by pulling up the stakes, or filling up the ditch, and

crying to his fellows, ‘Beware of listening to this impostor; you are

undone if you once forget that the fruits of the earth belong to us all,

and the earth itself to nobody.’”[41]

In contrast to liberalism, Rousseau recognised that the “greatest good

of all” reduces down to “two main subjects, liberty and equality” for

the former “cannot exist without” the latter.[42] He rightly argued that

contracts between the wealthy few and the many poor will always benefit

the former and, for the latter, become little more than the freedom to

pick a master:

“The terms of social compact between these two estates of men may be

summed up in a few words: ‘You have need of me, because I am rich and

you are poor. We will therefore come to an agreement. I will permit you

to have the honour of serving me, on condition that you bestow on me

that little you have left, in return for the pains I shall take to

command you.’”[43]

Thus “laws are always useful to those with possessions and harmful to

those who have nothing: from which it follows that the social state is

advantageous to men only when all posses something and none has too

much.” The ideal society was one where “no citizen shall be rich enough

to buy another and none so poor as to be forced to sell himself.”[44] In

a passage sadly not included in the final version of the Social

Contract, Rousseau goes to the core problem with liberalism:

“That a rich and powerful man, having acquired immense possessions in

land, should impose laws on those who want to establish themselves

there, and that he should only allow them to do so on condition that

they accept his supreme authority and obey all his wishes; that, I can

still conceive […] Would not this tyrannical act contain a double

usurpation: that on the ownership of the land and that on the liberty of

the inhabitants?”[45]

We cannot really “divest ourselves of our liberty […] just as we

transfer our property from one to another by contracts” for “the

property I alienate becomes quite foreign to me, nor can I suffer from

abuse of it” but it “concerns me that my liberty should not be abused”.

This meant that a contract “binding the one to command and the other to

obey” would be “an odd kind of contract to enter into” and so “to bind

itself to obey a master” would be “illegitimate.” It would be the

“voluntary establishment of tyranny” and so if “the people promises

simply to obey, by that very act dissolves itself and loses what makes

it a people; the moment a master exists, there is no longer a

Sovereign.” In short: “To renounce liberty is to renounce being a man,

to surrender the rights of humanity and even its duties.”[46]

Political association had to be participatory and so the “people of

England regards itself as free; but it is grossly mistaken; it is free

only during the election of members of parliament. As soon as they are

elected, slavery overtakes it, and it is nothing.” The “people, being

subject to the laws, ought to be their author” and so the “problem is to

find a form of association which will defend and protect with the whole

common force the person and goods of each associate, and in which each,

while uniting himself with all, may still obey himself alone, and remain

as free as before.” Sovereignty, “for the same reason as makes it

inalienable, is indivisible; for will either is, or is not, general; it

is the will either of the body of the people, or only of a part of it.”

Any government “is simply and solely a commission, an employment” and

“mere officials of the Sovereign”.[47]

The proclaimed indivisible nature of sovereignty produced a tendency in

Rousseau’s ideas that subsequently influenced the Jacobin tradition: the

vision of a centralised republic. Local associations were viewed

negatively because “when factions arise […] partial associations are

formed at the expense of the great association” and it was “therefore

essential, if the general will is to be able to express itself, that

there should be no partial society within the State”. While Rousseau

also suggested that “if there are partial societies, it is best to have

as many as possible and to prevent them from being unequal”, his

preference (and how he was interpreted) was that the citizens should

have “no communication one with another” so that “the grand total of the

small differences would always give the general will, and the decision

would always be good.”[48] Thus democracy favoured a centralised,

unitarian regime.

The democratic critique of liberalism produced both the idea of popular

sovereignty and the importance of equality within society. Rousseau’s

ideas were never implemented during his lifetime and so, unlike Locke

and his Fundamental Constitutions, it is the example of his followers

during the French Revolution we need to turn. This revolution was a

conflict between both the people and the monarchy but also between the

rising bourgeoisie and the toiling masses.[49] It expressed itself in

both popular and representative organisational forms, both of which

could be found in Rousseau. Yet while “the Sections under sans-culotte

control” produced “a vision of a city taken over by workshop

Rousseaus,”[50] power under the Jacobins was increasingly centralised

into fewer and fewer hands – from the electorate into representatives,

from representatives into the government, from the government, finally,

into the hands of Robespierre. Eventually groups such as the sections of

Paris, workers associations or strikes were destroyed as they were

considered “states within the state” for the Republic was called “one

and indivisible” for a reason.[51]

Associationism: Fraternity does not stop at the workplace door

Rousseau presented a critique of inequality but did not fundamentally

criticise property. This is to be expected as he lived before the rise

of industrial capitalism. The economy was based predominantly on peasant

farming and artisan workshops, the authoritarian social relationships

within production associated with wage-labour were not widespread nor of

prime importance in continental Europe. The solution for the domination

of landlords over peasants was clear and, moreover, did not need

question property as such – land reform by breaking up large estates and

parcelling out the land to those who actually work it. The small-scale

of technology meant that most could eventually become artisans working

with their own tools in their own workshop.

The French Revolution raised the issue of artisan organisation in the

shape of guilds and journeymen societies with one building employer

reporting in alarm that the “workers, by an absurd parody of the

government, regard their work as their property, the building site as a

Republic of which they are jointly citizens, and believe in consequence

that it belongs to them to name their own bosses, their inspectors and

arbitrarily to share out the work amongst themselves.”[52] These

perspectives only increased when the industrial revolution transformed

France and artisans became wage-workers. Faced with the obvious

authoritarianism within the factory, these workers sought a solution

appropriate to the changed circumstances they faced.

Unlike peasant farmers, the workplace could not be broken up without

destroying machinery and the advantages it produced alongside

master-servant relations. This reality produced a new perspective in the

new working class and so “Associationism was born during the waves of

strikes and organised protests provoked by the Revolution of 1830” when

“there appeared a workers’ newspaper” which “suggested cooperative

associations as the only way to end capitalist exploitation.” This paper

was produced by printers and entitled l’Artisan, journal de la class

ouvrière and “laid the basis for trade socialism.”[53] It argued as

early as October 1830 that by “utilising the principle of association,

workers could overcome the tyranny of private property and themselves

become associated owners of industrial enterprises.”[54]

While many intellectuals – the so-called utopian socialists like

Saint-Simon and Fourier and their followers – had raised various schemes

for improving society, this was the first example of workers themselves

making practical suggestions for their own liberation. Across France,

many workers started to combine their existing organisations for mutual

support with trade union activity as well as visions of a world without

masters. This process intertwined with existing political Republican

ideas. The radical neo-Jacobin Sociéte des Droits de l’Homme recruited

amongst workers which resulted in a “two-way interchange of ideas” with

that organisation taking up “the ideology of producer associationism

which was becoming central” to artisanal socialism. Louis Blanc was the

most public expression of this process and his “distinctive contribution

was to fuse the associationist idea with the Jacobin-Republican

political tradition”[55] but there were many others who expressed the

associational idea in different forms.[56]

Organisation: the application of theory

By 1840 there was not only a wide appreciation for the need of some kind

of association to replace capitalism but also extensive workers

organisations across France which aimed to do so. It was in this context

that a working man, a printer by trade, would transform socialist

politics forever by proclaiming himself an anarchist.

Proudhon did not develop his ideas in isolation. Indeed, he did not

invent his preferred term for them – mutualism – as the workers

organisations in Lyon, where he stayed in 1843, had been using it since

the early 1830s. So there is “close similarity between the associational

ideal of Proudhon” and “the program of the Lyon Mutualists” and it is

“likely that Proudhon was able to articulate his positive program more

coherently because of the example of the silk workers of Lyon. The

socialist ideal that he championed was already being realised, to a

certain extent, by such workers.”[57]

This shows the importance of sketching the ideological and social

context within which Proudhon was living when he wrote his seminal What

is Property? in 1840. Indeed, the title of the first work in which a

person self-proclaimed themselves an anarchist is significant. While

there is a tendency (particularly by Marxists and right-wing

“libertarians”) to reduce anarchism to just being anti-state, the

reality is that from the start anarchism has always been critical of

property and capitalism. As Proudhon repeatedly stressed, the critiques

of property and of the state share common features and are interwoven.

They cannot be considered in isolation without destroying the very

notion of anarchism for the fundamental commonality between

organisations anarchists oppose – the state, capitalist firms, marriage,

etc. – is that they are authoritarian and “power and authority corrupt

those who exercise them as much as those who are compelled to submit to

them.”[58]

Moreover, these critiques are relevant with regards to what anarchists

aim for and what they do now to bring that desired future closer. The

logic is simple enough – if you oppose something for specific reasons

then you will not seek to reproduce them in your visions of a better

world nor in the organisations you create to bring that better world

about. So, for example, based on his analysis of how exploitation

occurred under capitalism – how wage-labour allowed the employer to

appropriate the “collective force” produced by his workforce – Proudhon

argued for the necessity of association (“By virtue of the principle of

collective force, workers are the equals and associates of their

leaders”[59]) and socialisation (“All human labour being the result of

collective force, all property becomes, by the same reason, collective

and undivided”[60]) Equally, we would expect thinkers who sought to

transform their world to have a politics that was practical, namely a

theory of organisation that could result in their principles being

applied – “All theory is practical at the same time. What is said in

theory today will be done tomorrow”[61] – and this is what we do find in

the works of Proudhon and those he influenced, not least Bakunin and

Kropotkin.

So analysis, advocacy and activity are interwoven, with the critique of

what exists informing what could be and what could be informing our

struggles of today. Anarchist organisation, in short, reflects anarchist

theory: it is its application.

Proudhon: Laying the Foundations

Like most aspects of anarchism, anarchist organisational theory did not

appear ready made in 1840. While a basic principle was postulated then,

it took over a decade for all its elements to be raised and incorporated

into it. This was for the very good reason that Proudhon had to respond

to current events and so expand his ideas to take them into account.

Initially, Proudhon’s ideas on organisation were made in the context of

economics and his critique of property. While he will forever be linked

with “property is theft” this was just one part of his answer to the

question What is Property?, the other being that “property is

despotism.” Property “violates equality by the rights of exclusion and

increase, and freedom by despotism.” Anarchy was “the absence of a

master, of a sovereign,” while the proprietor was “synonymous” with

“sovereign,” for he “imposes his will as law, and suffers neither

contradiction nor control” and “each proprietor is sovereign lord within

the sphere of his property”.[62] Echoing Rousseau, Proudhon laid down

his position clearly:

“Liberty is inviolable. I can neither sell nor alienate my liberty;

every contract, every condition of a contract, which has in view the

alienation or suspension of liberty, is null: the slave, when he plants

his foot upon the soil of liberty, at that moment becomes a free man.

[…] Liberty is the original condition of man; to renounce liberty is to

renounce the nature of man: after that, how could we perform the acts of

man?”[62]

This brings him into conflict with Locke and the liberal tradition.

Rejecting the notion that master-servant contracts were valid, he

dismisses its basis of property in the person in a few telling words:

“To tell a poor man that he has property because he has arms and legs, –

that the hunger from which he suffers, and his power to sleep in the

open air are his property, – is to play with words, and add insult to

injury.” Property, then, is solely material things – land, workplaces,

etc. – and their monopolisation results in authoritarian relationships.

To “recognise the right of territorial property is to give up labour,

since it is to relinquish the means of labour”, which results in the

worker having “sold and surrendered his liberty” to the proprietor. This

alienation of liberty is the means by which exploitation occurs. Whoever

“labours becomes a proprietor” of his product but by that he did “not

mean simply (as do our hypocritical economists)” – and Locke – the

“proprietor of his allowance, his salary, his wages” but “proprietor of

the value which he creates, and by which the master alone profits.”

Locke is also clearly the target for Proudhon’s comment that “the horse

[…] and ox […] produce with us, but are not associated with us; we take

their product, but do not share it with them. The animals and workers

whom we employ hold the same relation to us.” So for “[w]e who belong to

the proletarian class: property excommunicates us!”[63]

Freedom and property were incompatible and to secure the former for all

we have to seek the “entire abolition” of the latter for “all

accumulated capital being social property, no one can be its exclusive

proprietor” and land is “a common thing”. In short, the means of life

become “a collective property” for while “the right to product is

exclusive”, the “right to means is common.” This meant “equality of

conditions and universal association” was needed for “[f]ree

association, liberty – whose sole function is to maintain equality in

the means of production and equivalence in exchanges – is the only

possible, the only just, the only true form of society.” This meant

industrial democracy as “leaders, instructors, superintendents” must be

“chosen from the workers by the workers themselves.”[64]

Thus use rights replace property rights and so a piece of land or

workplace is “a place possessed, not a place appropriated.” Anarchism is

“association, which is the annihilation of property” for while “the use”

of wealth “may be divided” as “property [it] remains undivided” and so

“the land [is] common property” and capital is “common or collective.”

So “to destroy despotism and the inequality of conditions”, master and

worker must “become associates”.[65]

This position is reflected in his next significant work, 1846’s System

of Economic Contradictions.[66] As before, property “degrades us, by

making us servants and tyrants to one another” for the wage-workers’ lot

was to “work under a master” to whom they had “sold their arms and

parted with their liberty” and so monopoly “must republicanise

itself”.[67] A new economy would be organised on a new basis:

“a commercial society […] should lay down as a principle the right of

any stranger to become a member upon his simple request, and to

straightway enjoy the rights and prerogatives of associates and even

managers […] it is evident that all the tendencies of humanity, both in

its politics and in its civil laws, are towards universalisation […]

towards a complete transformation of the idea of the company as

determined by our statutes […] articles of association […] should

regulate, no longer the contribution of the associates – since each

associate, according to the economic theory, is supposed to possess

absolutely nothing upon his entrance into the company – but the

conditions of labour and exchange, and which should allow access to all

who might present themselves […] In order that association may be real,

he who participates in it must do so […] as an active factor; he must

have a deliberative voice in the council […] everything regarding him,

in short, should be regulated in accordance with equality. But these

conditions are precisely those of the organisation of labour”[68]

Rejecting capitalism and state socialism, this would be “a solution

based upon equality – in other words, the organisation of labour, which

involves the negation of political economy and the end of property.”[69]

This was because, under capitalism, work may be “free. But what freedom,

for heaven’s sake! Freedom for the proletarian is the ability to work,

that is, of being robbed again; or not to work, that is to say to die to

hunger! Freedom only benefits strength: by competition, capital crushes

labour everywhere and converts industry into a vast coalition of

monopolies.”[70]

Politically, Proudhon argued that the state was created to “conduct [an]

offensive and defensive war against the proletariat” and – again against

Locke – wondered “what advantage is it to [the proletarian] that society

has left the state of war to enter the regime of police?” This meant

that “from the moment that the essential conditions of power – that is,

authority, property, hierarchy – are preserved, the suffrage of the

people is nothing but the consent of the people to their oppression” and

so the task of the proletariat was to create “an agricultural and

industrial combination […] by means of which power, today the ruler of

society, shall become its slave” and so “envelop capital and the State

and subjugate them.”[71] Interestingly, he notes in passing the state

“contributes to the general welfare” by “establishing in society an

artificial centralisation, the image and prelude of the future

solidarity of industries”.[72]

Thus by 1847 Proudhon had produced both a critique of capitalism and an

alternative rooted in democratic values: “to unfold the system of

economic contradictions is to lay the foundations of universal

association.”[73] The current State could not be captured nor reformed

as it was an instrument of capital. This meant labour had to organise

itself, and so “we want the organisation of labour by the workers,

without capitalists or masters” along with “government of the people by

the people, without that supernatural person called the prince or the

state” and “guarding of the people by the people, without any other army

than a citizen militia.”[74]

The 1848 revolution thrust the issue of political – social –

organisation to the fore. This lead Proudhon into a direct and sustained

polemic with the Jacobin tradition with its vision of a centralised,

unitary and indivisible democracy and so Rousseau. While previously he

had proclaimed Rousseau “the apostle of liberty and equality,”[75]

Proudhon now appeared not only to attack him but also democracy as such.

However, a close reading shows that Proudhon’s critique of democracy was

that it was not democratic enough and so his negative words should not

make us forget Rousseau’s influence on him.[76]

The earliest weeks of the revolution saw Proudhon produce a pamphlet

entitled Democracy which proclaimed that “problem of the People’s

sovereignty is the fundamental problem of liberty, equality and

fraternity, the first principle of social organisation” but concluded

that democracy “does not answer any of the questions raised by that

idea” and “is the negation of the People’s sovereignty”. This was

because “democracy says that the People reigns and does not govern,

which is to deny the Revolution”, and concludes “the People cannot

govern itself and is forced to hand itself over to representatives”. His

solution to this problem has become a core idea of anarchist

organisation for “we can follow” those we elect “step-by-step in their

legislative acts and their votes” and “make them transmit our arguments”

and when “we are discontented, we will recall and dismiss them.” Thus

the electoral principle needed “the imperative mandate, and permanent

revocability” as its “most immediate and incontestable consequences”.

This should be “the inevitable program of all democracy” but one which

democracy rejects and so it “exists fully only at the moment of

elections” and then it “retreats; it withdraws into itself again and

begins its anti-democratic work. It becomes AUTHORITY.” This meant that

for democracy “the People cannot govern themselves” and so “after

declaring the principle of the People’s sovereignty” it “ends up

declaring the incapacity of the People!” Instead of a democracy

understood in the manner of the Jacobin left, Proudhon suggested in an

anarchy “all citizens […] reign and govern” for they “directly

participate in the legislation and the government as they participate in

the production and circulation of wealth”.[77]

Thus a genuine democracy had to be both participatory and include the

economic realm. Unsurprisingly, then, Proudhon considered his key

economic reform, the Bank of Exchange, as “an essentially republican

institution; it is a paradigmatic example of government of the People by

the People” for “association is universal” with workplaces becoming

“democratically organised workers’ associations” within a “vast

federation of companies and societies woven into the common cloth of the

democratic and social Republic” for “under universal association,

ownership of the land and of the instruments of labour is social

ownership.” The Bank of Exchange was seen as a means of a wider economic

transformation, as the means of abolishing wage-labour: “all the

workshops are owned by the nation, even though they remain and must

always remain free” for “[b]y virtue of its over-arching mandate, the

Exchange Bank is the organisation of labour’s greatest asset” and so

allow “the new form of society to be defined and created among the

workers.”[78]

Government, in the shape of an executive power with its Presidents and

Ministries would be replaced by the National Assembly “through

organisation of its committees […] exercise[ing] executive power, just

the way it exercises legislative power through its joint deliberations

and votes” while “as a consequence of universal suffrage” there would be

the “implementation of the imperative mandate” otherwise “the people, in

electing representatives, does not appoint mandatories but rather abjure

their sovereignty” which is “assuredly not socialism: it is not even

democracy.” The Assembly would be controlled by the “organisation of

popular societies” as these were “the pivot of democracy, the

cornerstone of republican order” and would “rip the nails and teeth off

state power and hand over the government’s public force to the

citizens.”[79]

With more experience of the workings of the Assembly – he was elected as

a representative in 1848 and remained one until imprisoned for insulting

the President in 1849 – Proudhon came to see the limitations of this

position. Rather than all questions flowing to a single body, the

decentralisation of power also required its decentring. So the question

was “to organise universal suffrage in its plenitude” for each

“function, industrial or otherwise”. Each functional group would elect

its own delegates in its own separate bodies (Proudhon uses the examples

of the church and the army). In this way “the country governs itself

solely by means of its electoral initiative” and “it is no longer

governed” for it “is a matter of the organisation of universal suffrage

in all its forms, of the very structure of Democracy itself.” Instead of

centralising all issues into the hands of one assembly, there would be a

multitude of assemblies each covering a specific social function. For “a

society of free men” is based on the “associating with different groups

according to the nature of their industries or their interests and by

whom neither collective nor individual sovereignty is ever abdicated or

delegated” and so “the Government has ceased to exist as a result of

universal suffrage”. This “truly democratic regime, with its unity at

the bottom and its separation at the top, [is] the reverse of what now

exists” and meant that “centralisation [would] be effected from the

bottom to the top, from the circumference to the centre, and that all

functions be independent and govern themselves independently.” He added

to anarchist theory by calling this vision a “revolution from below” for

“from below signifies the people” and “the initiative of the masses”

while “from above” meant “the actions of government”.[80]

Thus anarchist organisation was decentralised, decentred, from the

bottom-up, based on collective decision making with delegates elected,

mandated and subject to recall. He attacked his colleagues on the left

for advocating a democracy in which the sovereign people were ruled by

an elected few. Against Louis Blanc – whose economic ideas he has

previously attacked in 1846 – he argued that the state “is the external

constitution of the social power” and by this “external constitution of

its power and sovereignty, the people does not govern itself; now one

individual, now several, by a title either elective or hereditary, are

charged with governing it, with managing its affairs”. Anarchists,

however, affirm that “the people, that society, that the mass, can and

ought to govern itself by itself” and so “deny government and the State,

because we affirm that which the founders of States have never believed

in, the personality and autonomy of the masses.” Anarchy “maintains

itself without masters and servants” and so when we “deny the State and

the government” we “affirm in the same breath the autonomy of the people

and its majority” for “the only way to organise democratic government is

to abolish government.”[81]

This was needed because the State is “the constitutional silencing of

the people, the legal alienation of its thought and its initiative into

the hands of” the few in which “the people no longer have anything to do

but keep silent and obey”. It is a body “distinct from the people, apart

from and above the people” based on the “alienation of public power for

the profit of a few ambitious men” which “no sooner exists than it

creates an interest of its own, apart from and often contrary to the

interests of the people; because, acting then in that interest, it makes

civil servants its own creatures, from which results nepotism,

corruption, and little by little to the formation of an official tribe,

enemies of labour as well as of liberty”. Anarchy, however, “is the

living society, the people having consciousness of their ideas,

governing themselves as they work, through division of industries and

special delegation of jobs, in short by the egalitarian distribution of

forces.” Universal suffrage “implies the nomination by the people of all

the functionaries without exception, their permanent revocability, and

consequently the government of the people by the people.”[82]

Proudhon turned his polemical skills towards the intellectual father of

the French Left, Rousseau, in 1851’s General Idea of the Revolution. A

superficial reading of that work may cause some to consider the idea

that Proudhon was working in his tradition as paradoxical. Yet Proudhon

favourably quotes Rousseau on “the conditions of the social pact”[83]

before starting his polemic which showed how Rousseau failed to achieve

the task he set himself due to two key issues.

First, Rousseau “speaks of political rights only; it does not mention

economic rights.” By ignoring the economic sphere he ends up creating a

class state in which the Republic “is nothing but the offensive and

defensive alliance of those who possess, against those who do not

possess”, a “coalition of the barons of property, commerce and industry

against the disinherited lower class”.[84]

Second, Rousseau’s political solution – a centralised, unitarian,

indivisible republic – recreates the division between rulers and ruled

which it claims to end. Thus, “having laid down as a principle that the

people are the only sovereign”, Rousseau “quietly abandons and discards

this principle” and so “the citizen has nothing left but the power of

choosing his rulers by a plurality vote”. Echoing Rousseau’s own words

about England, Proudhon proclaimed that France was “a quasi-democratic

Republic” in which citizens “are permitted, every third or fourth year,

to elect, first, the Legislative Power, second, the Executive Power. The

duration of this participation in the Government for the popular

collectivity is brief […] The President and the Representatives, once

elected, are the masters; all the rest obey. They are subjects, to be

governed and to be taxed, without surcease.”[85]

Thus the democratic principle is nullified and the people exercise a

mythical sovereignty rather than a real one.

Against the idea of representative democracy in a one and indivisible

republic, Proudhon advocated a decentralised, federal, participatory

democracy. The “idea of contract excludes that of government” for it is

in “this agreement that liberty and well being increase” as there would

be “[n]o more laws voted by a majority [in a nation], nor even

unanimously; each citizen, each commune or corporation [i.e.,

co-operative], makes its own.”[86] There would be a radical

decentralisation of decision-making into the hands of the people and

their associations:

“Unless democracy is a fraud, and the sovereignty of the People a joke,

it must be admitted that each citizen in the sphere of his industry,

each municipal, district or provincial council within its own territory,

is the only natural and legitimate representative of the Sovereign, and

that therefore each locality should act directly and by itself in

administering the interests which it includes, and should exercise full

sovereignty in relation to them. The People is nothing but the organic

union of wills that are individually free, that can and should

voluntarily work together, but abdicate never […] it becomes necessary

for the workers to form themselves into democratic societies, with equal

conditions for all members, on pain of a relapse into feudalism […] they

will themselves be the State; that is to say, in all that concerns their

industrial speciality, they will be the direct, active representative of

the Sovereign.”[87]

Democratic principles must be extended to the economy – including the

workplace – and this, in turn, would eliminate class differences and so

the need for a state. The capitalist workplace involved the worker being

“simply the employee of the proprietor-capitalist-entrepreneur” and so

“subordinated, exploited” in a “permanent condition” of “obedience and

poverty”. So “due to the immorality, tyranny and theft suffered” under

wage-labour, association was needed. The worker must “become an

associate” and “participate in the chances of loss or gain of the

establishment, he will have a voice in the council” and so “resumes his

dignity as a man and citizen” by becoming “a part of the producing

organisation, of which he was before but the slave” just “as, in the

town, he forms a part of the sovereign power”. A workplace with

“subordinates and superiors” and “two industrial castes of masters and

wage-workers” is “repugnant to a free and democratic society” and must

be replaced with one in which “all positions are elective, and the

by-laws subject to the approval of the members.”[88]

This meant that there “will no longer be nationality, no longer

fatherland, in the political sense of the words: they will mean only

places of birth. Whatever a man’s race or colour, he is really a native

of the universe; he has citizen’s rights everywhere.”[89] So freedom and

democracy did not end at the workplace door for the political and

economic regimes were linked. As well as meaning association within the

political and economic spheres in a free society, this also showed why

the centralised political structure did not come about by accident. It

was required to ensure bourgeois rule:

“And who benefits from this regime of unity? The people? No, the upper

classes […] Unity […] is quite simply a form of bourgeois exploitation

under the protection of bayonets. Yes, political unity, in the great

States, is bourgeois: the positions which it creates, the intrigues

which it causes, the influences which it cherishes, all that is

bourgeois and goes to the bourgeois.”[90]

The centralised, hierarchical, state is “the cornerstone of bourgeois

despotism and exploitation”[91] for how else can a minority class rule?

So it was no coincidence that “nothing resembles a monarchy more than a

unitarian republic” and “[l]et us not forget that the constitutional,

bourgeois and unitary monarchy, tends, with regard to international

politics, to guarantee from State to State the exploiting classes

against the exploited classes, consequently to form the coalition of

capital against the wage-workers, of whatever language and nationality

they all are.”[92] Thus monarchies and republics were class states, run

by and for dominant minorities regardless of whether elections take

place. This was the function of centralism, hence the need for

federalism:

“In short, whoever says freedom says federation, or says nothing;

“Whoever says republic, says federation, or says nothing;

“Whoever says socialism, says federation, or yet again says

nothing.”[93]

If, in 1847 he suggested the goal of “industrial centralisation,

administrative, without hierarchy,”[94] by the early 1850s he had

embraced the more precise and clearer term federalism as better

expressing his vision. In 1863 he stressed “the idea of an industrial

federation serving as a complement to and ratification of the political

federation” and that his “economic ideas, elaborated for twenty-five

years, can be summarised” as “Agricultural-Industrial Federation” and

his “political views are reduced to a similar formula: Political

Federation or Decentralisation.”[95]

Anarchy, then, was an economic as well as political participatory

democracy – a self-governing society – for “any one-sided conditions” in

which “one part of the citizens should find themselves, by the contract,

subordinated and exploited by the others, it would no longer be a

contract; it would be a fraud”. Politically, “the object of the

Revolution” is “to put paid to all authority and do away with the entire

machinery of government” by “the organisation of universal suffrage” for

“freedom and authority must be equal in every citizen: otherwise, there

would be no equality […] and the sovereignty of the people, vested in a

small number of representatives, would be a fiction.” Economically, just

as citizens could not alienate their liberty to a government, so the

revolution meant that workers would not sell their liberty to a boss so

“[c]apitalist and landlord exploitation [is] stopped everywhere,

wage-labour abolished” by association for “industrial associations” were

“worker republics”.[96]

Individuals would join self-government groups within a “universal

federalism” based on making “the citizens vote by categories of

functions, in accordance with the principle of the collective force” for

“the federative system is the opposite of administrative and

governmental hierarchy or centralisation”. Thus the “groups that

comprise the confederation” would be “self-governing, self-judging and

self-administering in complete sovereignty” and “universal suffrage form

[their] basis” and each “enjoys a right of secession”. This means that

in “a mutualist confederation, the citizen gives up none of his freedom,

as Rousseau requires him to do for the governance of his republic!”[97]

In summary:

“no longer do we have the abstraction of people’s sovereignty as in the

’93 Constitution and the others that followed it, and in Rousseau’s

Social Contract. Instead it becomes an effective sovereignty of the

labouring masses which rule and govern […] the labouring masses are

actually, positively and effectively sovereign: how could they not be

when the economic organism – labour, capital, property and assets –

belongs to them entirely”[98]

Thus the “abolition of man’s exploitation of his fellow-man and

abolition of man’s government of his fellow-man” were “one and the same

proposition” for “what, in politics, goes under the name of Authority is

analogous to and synonymous with what is termed, in political economy,

Property; that these two notions overlap one with the other and are

identical”. The “principle of AUTHORITY [was] articulated through

property and through the State.” and so “an attack upon one is an attack

upon the other.”[99] Association had to replace both.

Before leaving Proudhon to see how his ideas were later developed, it

must be noted that many commentators view him as an opponent to

association, large-scale industry and social ownership. To do so is to

misunderstand his ideas and the context in which he expressed them.

Against those other socialists vying for influence in the French labour

movement, Proudhon was keen to stress that these utopian schemes turned

the “community” into proprietor and so resulted in the oppression and

exploitation of labour just as much as capitalism did.[100] Similarly

with Louis Blanc, who came “under attack by Proudhon for eliminating all

competition, and for fostering state centralisation of initiative and

direction at the expense of local and corporative powers and

intermediate associations. But the term association could also refer to

the mutualist associations that Proudhon favoured, that is, those

initiated and controlled from below.”[101] If Blanc advocated

Association, Proudhon supported associations:

“But there is not one single public function, one single industry in

society; and the question is precisely to know if the public thought or

action can and should be exerted ex æquo, in equal measure and by equal

title, by all the citizens individually and independently of one

another: that is the democratic or anarchic system – or whether that

collective thought and collective action should become the exclusive

attribute of an elite of functionaries, appointed for that purpose by

the people and with respect to whom the people are then no longer

COLLEAGUES, but obedient, passive subjects or instruments.”[102]

Proudhon, then, had an opposition to one centralised Association or

association for its own sake (what Proudhon termed “the principle of

Association”) but he was in favour of workplace associations to replace

wage-labour as well as an “agricultural–industrial federation” in which

associations would “not to absorb one another and merge, but to mutually

guarantee the conditions of prosperity that are common to them”.[103]

Nor was he opposed to large-scale industry for these associations were

advocated precisely to ensure its benefits for workers rather than a few

capitalists.[104] Similarly, the free access to workplaces and land to

abolish wage-labour required Proudhon to advocate their social ownership

precisely to ensure that those who used them controlled them. Thus

possession (or use-rights) were postulated within the context of

collective or undivided ownership by all.[105]

Déjacque, Léo and Varlin: Being consistently libertarian

It was in reaction to a specific aspect of Proudhon’s ideas that the

term libertarian (libertaire) was first used in the modern sense. While

denouncing both the state and the capitalist workplace as authoritarian

and seeking to replace both with a federation of self-governing

associations, Proudhon refused to apply his ideas within the family:

there he advocated (and rigorously defended) patriarchy.

Yet, as Carole Pateman reminds us, until “the late nineteenth century

the legal and civil position of a wife resembled that of a slave”. A

slave “had no independent legal existence apart from his master, and

husband and wife became ‘one person,’ the person of the husband.”

Indeed, the law “was based on the assumption that a wife was (like)

property” and only the marriage contract “includes the explicit

commitment to obey.”[106] Other anarchists saw the obvious contradiction

in Proudhon’s position.

Joseph Déjacque in 1857 extended Proudhon’s ideas to communist-anarchist

conclusions as well as applying them to the family and in the process

coined the word libertarian. It was a case of “plac[ing] the question of

the emancipation of woman in line with the question of the emancipation

of the proletarian” so that both enter “the anarchic-community” in which

“all despotism [is] annihilated, all social inequalities levelled.”

Proudhon did “cry out against the high barons of capital” but “wish[ed]

to rebuild the high barony of the male upon the female vassal” and so

was “a liberal and not a LIBERTARIAN.” The need was to create a “true

anarchy, of absolute freedom, [in which] there would undoubtedly be as

much diversity between beings as there would be people in society,

diversity of age, sex, aptitudes: equality is not uniformity.”[107] The

following year Déjacque used this new synonym for anarchist as the title

for his paper La Libertaire, Journal du Mouvement Social.[108]

Eleven years after Déjacque issued his challenge to Proudhon, André Léo,

a feminist mutualist and future Communard, also pointed out the obvious

contradiction to his French followers and others on the left in her work

La Femme et les mœurs:

“These so-called lovers of liberty, if they are unable to take part in

the direction of the state, at least they will be able to have a little

monarchy for their personal use, each in his own home. When divine right

was shattered, it was so that each male (Proudhonian-type) could have a

piece of it. Order in the family without hierarchy seems impossible to

them – well then, what about in the state?”[109]

Both Déjacque and Léo argued that Proudhon’s Rousseau-derived critique

of wage-labour and the state (including Rousseau’s democracy) was

equally applicable to family relations. Anarchists, to be consistent,

cannot be blind to social (“private”) hierarchies while denouncing

economic and political ones. Given that the rationale for all these

forms of subjection were justified in liberal theory in the same manner

– voluntary or contractual – there was no logical reason to defend

patriarchy any more than any other archy. Unsurprisingly, almost all

subsequent anarchists (including Bakunin and Kropotkin) recognised the

need for consistency and so followed the likes of Déjacque and Léo in

applying Proudhon’s principles against his own contradictory application

just as Proudhon had done to Rousseau.

They also sought to apply their ideas within another area Proudhon

opposed, namely in the union movement. Thus we find Eugène Varlin as

well as “advocat[ing] equal rights for women in opposition” to Proudhon

also arguing that unions and strikes were “necessary to abolish

capitalism.”[110] As well as mitigating capitalist exploitation and

oppression in the here and now, unions had a wider role in “organis[ing]

the production and distribution of products” in the future:

“Unless you want to reduce everything to a centralising and

authoritarian state, which would appoint the directors of mills,

factories, distribution outlets, whose directors would in turn appoint

deputy directors, supervisors, foremen, etc. and thus arrive at a

top-down hierarchical organisation of labour, in which the worker would

be nothing but an unconscious cog, without freedom or initiative; unless

we do, we are forced to admit that the workers themselves must have the

free disposal of their instruments of labour […] Workers societies, in

whatever form they exist at present, already have this immense advantage

of accustoming men to social life, and so preparing them for a wider

social organisation. They accustom them not only to reach an agreement

and understanding, but also to take care of their affairs, to organise,

to discuss, to think about their material and moral interests, and

always from the collective point of view […] trade societies

(resistance, solidarity, union) deserve our encouragement and sympathy,

for they are the natural elements of the social construction of the

future; it is they who can easily become producer associations; it is

they who will be able to operate social tools and organise production

[…] all workers should group themselves into resistance societies by

trade in order to secure the present and prepare for the future.”[111]

This position was held in the libertarian sections of the International

Workers’ Association, which had been founded in 1864 by British trade

unionists and French mutualists. The idea of unions becoming the

economic framework of socialism in chambres de travail (workers

councils) was first raised by mutualist delegates from the Belgium

section at its Brussels conference in 1868 before becoming policy at the

Basle Congress.[112]

Bakunin: Building and Applying

When Bakunin joined the International in 1868 he took up and championed

these syndicalist ideas, arguing that it had to “expand and organise

itself […] so that when the Revolution […] breaks out, there will be […]

a serious international organisation of workers’ associations […]

capable of replacing this departing world of States.”[113] Anarchists

would only achieve their goal “by the development and organisation” of

the “social (and, by consequence, anti-political) power of the working

masses.”[115] The “organisation of the trade sections and their

representation in the Chambers of Labour […] bear in themselves the

living seeds of new society which is to replace the old world. They are

creating not only the ideas, but also the facts of the future

itself.”[114] Thus libertarian socialism was based on federations of

workers’ councils organised at the point of production in the fight

against exploitation and oppression:

“Workers, no longer count on anyone but yourselves […] You bear within

you today all the elements of the power that must renew the world […]

Abstain from all participation in bourgeois radicalism and organise

outside of it the forces of the proletariat. The basis of that

organisation is […] the workshops and the federation of the workshops

[…] and their federation not just nationally, but internationally. The

creation of chambres de travail […] the liquidation of the State and of

bourgeois society […] Anarchy, that it to say the true, the open popular

revolution […] organisation, from top to bottom and from the

circumference to the centre”[115]

An anarchist organisation “must be a people’s movement, organised from

the bottom up by the free, spontaneous action of the masses. There must

be no secret governmentalism, the masses must be informed of everything

[…] All the affairs of the International must be thoroughly and openly

discussed without evasions and circumlocutions.” This is in contrast to

“the principle of authority, that is, the eminently theological,

metaphysical, and political idea that the masses, always incapable of

governing themselves, must at all times submit to the benevolent yoke of

a wisdom and a justice imposed upon them, in some way or other, from

above.”[116]

Like Proudhon, Bakunin contrasted authority with collective

self-government. He argued for “no external legislation and no

authority” and rejected “all legislation, all authority, and all

privileged, licensed, official, and legal influence, even though arising

from universal suffrage” because “it can turn only to the advantage of a

dominant minority of exploiters against the interests of the immense

majority in subjection to them.” However, he was well aware of the need

for individuals to associate together into groups and make decisions.

This meant how we organised was what mattered for “man in isolation can

have no awareness of his liberty. Being free for man means being

acknowledged, considered and treated as such by another man. Liberty is

therefore a feature not of isolation but of interaction, not of

exclusion but rather of connection”.[117]

Long before Rosa Luxemburg made the same distinction,[118] Bakunin

contrasted two kinds of discipline, an “authoritarian conception of

discipline” which “signifies despotism on the one hand and blind

automatic submission to authority on the other” and another “not

automatic but voluntary and intelligently understood [which] is, and

will ever be, necessary whenever a greater number of individuals

undertake any kind of collective work or action.” The latter was “simply

the voluntary and considered co-ordination of all individual efforts for

a common purpose” and did not preclude “a natural division of functions

according to the aptitude of each, assessed and judged by the collective

whole” but “no function remains fixed and it will not remain permanently

and irrevocably attached to any one person. Hierarchical order and

promotion do not exist, so that the executive of yesterday can become

the subordinate of tomorrow.” In this way “power, properly speaking, no

longer exists. Power is diffused to the collectivity and becomes the

true expression of the liberty of everyone, the faithful and sincere

realisation of the will of all”.[119]

An anarchist organisation made decisions without giving power to the

few. Anarchists “recognise all natural authority, and all influence of

fact upon us, but none of right; for all authority and all influence of

right, officially imposed upon us, immediately becomes a falsehood and

an oppression.” The “only great and omnipotent authority, at once

natural and rational, the only one we respect, will be that of the

collective and public spirit of a society founded on equality and

solidarity and the mutual respect of all its members.” Freedom “is

something very positive, very complex, and above all eminently social,

since it can be realised only by society and only under conditions of

strict equality and solidarity.”[120]

He contrasted this with Marxists who, he argued, were “champions of

order established from the top downwards, always in the name of

universal suffrage and the sovereignty of the masses, for whom they save

the honour and privilege of obeying leaders, elected masters.” The

state, then, was “the minority government, from the top downward, of a

vast quantity of men”[121] while in an anarchy the “whole people govern”

and so “there will be no one to be governed. It means that there will be

no government, no State.”[122] Therefore anarchists do “not accept, even

in the process of revolutionary transition, either constituent

assemblies, provisional governments or so-called revolutionary

dictatorships; because we are convinced that revolution is only sincere,

honest and real in the hands of the masses, and that when it is

concentrated in those of a few ruling individuals it inevitably and

immediately becomes reaction.”[123]

Thus, like Proudhon, Bakunin contrasted collective decision making with

representative government. The latter – whether within the groups at the

base of a society or at the top – empowered the few at the expense of

the many.

This is reflected on Bakunin’s discussion of union bureaucracy and how

to combat it. In the Geneva section of the International, the

construction workers’ section “simply left all decision-making to their

committees […] In this manner power gravitated to the committees, and by

a species of fiction characteristic of all governments the committees

substituted their own will and their own ideas for that of the

membership.” The union “sections could only defend their rights and

their autonomy in only one way: the workers called general membership

meetings. Nothing arouses the antipathy of the committees more than

these popular assemblies […] In these great meetings of the sections,

the items on the agenda was amply discussed and the most progressive

opinion prevailed.” In addition, delegates elected by the membership had

to fulfil “their obligations to their respective sections” by “reporting

regularly to the membership the proposals made and how they voted” and

“asking for further instructions (plus instant recall of unsatisfactory

delegates).”[124]

In short, to “contract a relationship of voluntary servitude” was

inconsistent with anarchist principles as “the freedom of every

individual is inalienable” and so associations could have no other

footing “but the utmost equality and reciprocity.”[125] Like Proudhon,

Bakunin saw the need for directly democratic – self-managed –

associations for the capitalist workplace created “master and slave”

relationships for “the worker sells his person and his liberty for a

given time.”[126] The workplace had to be a free association of

individuals who organise their joint work as equals and so he was

“convinced that the co-operative will be the preponderant form of social

organisation in the future, in every branch of labour and science.”[127]

This implied socialisation of property so that the “land belongs to only

those who cultivate it with their own hands; to the agricultural

communes. The capital and all the tools of production belong to the

workers; to the workers’ associations.” By being “converted into

collective property of the whole of society” it would be “utilised only

by the workers, i.e., by their agricultural and industrial

associations.”[128] He extended this into a vision of social revolution

in the traditional rather than reformist sense that Proudhon had used:

“the revolution must set out from the first radically and totally to

destroy the State and all State institutions […] confiscation of all

productive capital and means of production on behalf of workers’

associations, who are to put them to collective use […] the federative

Alliance of all working men’s associations […] will constitute the

Commune. […] The Commune will be organised by the standing federation of

the Barricades and by the creation of a Revolutionary Communal Council

composed of one or two delegates from each barricade, one to each street

or district, vested with plenary but accountable and removable mandates

[…] all provinces, communes and associations […] first reorganising on

revolutionary lines and then sending their representatives to an agreed

meeting-place, these too vested with similar mandates to constitute the

federation of insurgent associations, communes and provinces in the name

of the same principles and to organise a revolutionary force capable of

defeating reaction. […] There can no longer be any successful political

or national revolution unless the political revolution is transformed

into social revolution, and unless national revolution, precisely

because of its radically socialist, anti-State character, becomes

universal revolution […] created by the people, and supreme control must

always belong to the people organised into a free federation of

agricultural and industrial associations […] organised from the bottom

upwards by means of revolutionary delegation”[129]

A free society would be based on federations of community and workplace

assemblies, initially locally in the Commune and then ever wider in

regions, nationally and, ultimately, internationally – all based on

decision making from the bottom-up with all delegates elected, mandated

and recallable. This would ensure that society would be “reconstituted

on the basis of liberty, henceforward to be the sole determinant of its

organisation, both political and economic. Order in society must be the

outcome of the greatest possible development of all local, collective

and individual liberties” to ensure that the “political and economic

organisation of society must therefore not flow downwards, from high to

low, and outwards, from centre to circumference, as it does today on the

principle of unity and enforced centralisation, but upwards and inwards,

on the principle of free association and free federation.”[130]

It is useful to note that, in stark contrast to those who (like Marx and

Lenin) assert that Bakunin, like all anarchists, thought an ideal

socialist society would spring-up overnight, Bakunin himself explicitly

stated that he did “not say” that the peasants and workers, “freely

organised from the bottom up, will miraculously create an ideal

organisation, conforming in all respects to our dreams. But […] that

what they construct will be living and vibrant, a thousand times better

and more just than any existing organisation,” be “open to revolutionary

propaganda” and so “will develop and perfect itself through free

experimentation” with the “development of each commune” taking as “its

point of departure the actual condition of its civilisation.”[131]

Bakunin, then, urged a socialism from below by means of a “popular

revolution” which would “create its own organisation from the bottom

upwards and from the circumference inwards, in accordance with the

principle of liberty, and not from the top downwards and from the centre

outwards, as in the way of all authority.”[132]

Kropotkin: Expanding and Consolidating

As with Bakunin, Kropotkin aimed for a society “wherein nobody should be

compelled to sell his labour (and consequently, to a certain degree, his

personality) to those who intend to exploit him” and sought “to create

among the working classes the union structures that might some day

replace the bosses and take into their own hands the production and

management of every industry.”[133] He dismissed the “Economists [who]

represented as a state of freedom the forced contract agreed by the

worker under the threat of hunger with the boss”[134] for capitalism

produced hierarchical relationships:

“In today’s society, where no one is allowed to use the field, the

factory, the instruments of labour, unless he acknowledges himself the

inferior, the subject of some Sir – servitude, submission, lack of

freedom, the practice of the whip are imposed by the very form of

society.”[135]

Returning repeatedly to the French Revolution, Kropotkin noted that

while it had “proclaimed the sovereignty of the people” it “by an

inconsistency” also “proclaimed, not a permanent sovereignty, but an

intermittent one, to be exercised at certain intervals only, for the

nomination of deputies supposed to represent the people”. It was “absurd

to take a certain number of men from out the mass, and to entrust them

with the management of all public affairs”. The state “is the power of

the bureaucracy”[136] for the “pyramidal ladder that makes the essence

of the State” means “the existence of a power placed above society” but

also the “concentration of many functions in the life of societies in

the hands of a few” and this resulted in “thousands of functionaries”

(“most of them corruptible”) to “read, classify, evaluate” on numerous

issues, great and small.[137] Worse, if “an all-powerful centralised

Government” – as in state socialism – tries to manage production as well

its other tasks then it “develops such a formidable bureaucracy” which

proves “absolutely incapable of doing that through its functionaries, no

matter how countless they may be”.[138]

The State, then, was “developed during the history of human societies”

to “subjugate the masses to minorities” and dismissed the arguments of

the politicians who “described as a state of freedom the present

situation in which the citizen becomes a serf and a taxpayer of the

State.” Referencing Proudhon’s debate with Louis Blanc, he argued that

the state “is necessarily hierarchical, authoritarian – or it ceases to

be the State.”[139] This meant that both the Liberal and Democratic

States were class regimes, and as regards the latter “the Jacobin club

was the bulwark of the bourgeoisie coming to power against the

egalitarian tendencies of the people. […] the ideal of the Jacobin State

[…] had been designed from the viewpoint of the bourgeois, in direct

opposition to the egalitarian and communist tendencies of the people

which had arisen during the Revolution.”[140] A State was needed because

of the class interests of the few who owned and ruled society:

“To attack the central power, to strip it of its prerogatives, to

decentralise, to dissolve authority, would have been to abandon to the

people the control of its affairs, to run the risk of a truly popular

revolution. That is why the bourgeoisie sought to reinforce the central

government even more, to invest it with powers of which the king himself

would never have dreamt, to concentrate everything in its hands, to

subordinate to it the whole of France from one end to another – and then

to make sure of it all through the National Assembly.”[141]

The “people does not govern itself” and so Kropotkin’s aim was “economic

equality” in which “free and equal citizens, not about to abdicate their

rights to the care of the few, will seek some new form of organisation

that allows them to manage their affairs for themselves”. He pointed to

the sections of the French Revolution as popular institutions “not

separated from the people” and “remained of the people, and this is what

made the revolutionary power of these organisations.” Rather than

nominating representatives and disbanding, the sections “remained and

organised themselves, on their own initiative, as permanent organs of

the municipal administration” and “were practising what was described

later on as Direct Self-Government”. These were “the principles of

anarchism” and they “had their origin, not in theoretic speculations,

but in the deeds of the Great French Revolution” for the Commune “was

not to be a governed State, but a people governing itself directly ―

when possible ― without intermediaries, without masters.”[142]

A similar organisation would exist on the economic field, based on the

“expropriation pure and simple of the present holders of the large

landed estates, of the instruments of labour, and of capital of every

kind, and by the seizure of all such capital by the cultivators, the

workers’ organisations, and the agricultural and municipal communes. The

task of expropriation must be carried out by the workers themselves in

the towns and the countryside.” The workers “ought to be the real

managers of industries” and “the importance of th[e] labour movement for

the coming revolution” is that these “agglomerations of wealth

producers” will “reorganise production on new social bases. They will

[…] organise the life of the nation and the use which it will make of

the hitherto accumulated riches and means of production. They – the

labourers, grouped together – not the politicians.”[143]

These social and economic self-managed assemblies would then federate

with others, locally, regionally, nationally and internationally:

“Our needs are in fact so various, and they emerge with such rapidity,

that soon a single federation will not be sufficient to satisfy them

all. The Commune will then feel the need to contract other alliances, to

enter into other federations. Belonging to one group for the acquisition

of food supplies, it will have to join a second group to obtain other

goods, such as metals, and then a third and a fourth group for textiles

and works of art […] the federations of Communes, if they were to follow

their free development, would very soon start to mingle and intersect,

and in this way form a network […] the Commune […] no longer means a

territorial agglomeration; it is rather a generic name, a synonym for

the grouping of equals which knows neither frontiers nor walls. The

social Commune will soon cease to be a clearly defined entity. Each

group in the Commune will necessarily be drawn towards similar groups in

other communes; they will come together and the links that federate them

will be as solid as those that attach them to their fellow citizens, and

in this way there will emerge a Commune of interests whose members are

scattered in a thousand towns and villages.”[144]

This diversity of groupings, federations, links and contracts means that

a free society would by decentralised and decentred, with questions no

longer channelled into one body. This would allow genuine delegation to

develop:

“The question of true delegation versus representation can be better

understood if one imagines a hundred or two hundred men, who meet each

day in their work and share common concerns, who know each other

thoroughly, who have discussed every aspect of the question that

concerns them and have reached a decision. They then choose someone and

send him to reach an agreement with other delegates of the same kind on

this particular issue. On such an occasion the choice is made with full

knowledge of the question, and everyone knows what is expected of his

delegate. The delegate is not authorised to do more than explain to

other delegates the considerations that have led his colleagues to their

conclusion. Not being able to impose anything, he will seek an

understanding and will return with a simple proposition which his

mandatories can accept or refuse.”[145]

Groups raised “questions and discussed them first themselves” and “sent

delegates – not rulers” – to congresses who “returned with no laws in

their pockets, but with proposals of agreements.”[146] This “free

agreement, by exchange of letters and proposals, by congresses at which

delegates met to discuss certain special subjects […] is a new principle

that differs completely from all governmental principle, monarchical or

republican, absolute or parliamentarian.”[147]

This would produce “an interwoven network, composed of an infinite

variety of groups and federations of all sizes and degrees, local,

regional, national and international – temporary or more or less

permanent – for all possible purposes.”[148] The Commune “will know that

it cannot admit any higher authority; above it there can only be the

interests of the Federation, freely accepted by itself as well as the

other communes […] the Commune will be absolutely free to adopt all the

institutions it wishes and to make all the reforms and revolutions it

finds necessary […] The Commune will know that it must break the State

and replace it by the Federation.”[149] Anarchism now had its full

social organisation on all three levels – economic, social and personal:

“The idea of independent Communes for the territorial organisation, and

of federations of Trade Unions for the organisation of men in accordance

with their different functions, gave a concrete conception of society

regenerated by a social revolution. There remained only to add to these

two modes of organisation a third […] the thousands upon thousands of

free combines and societies growing up everywhere for the satisfaction

of all possible and imaginable needs, economic, sanitary, and

educational; for mutual protection, for the propaganda of ideas, for

art, for amusement, and so on.”[150]

Socialism “will therefore have to find its own form of political

relations” as it “cannot utilise the old political forms”. In “one way

or another it will have to become more popular, closer to the assembly

[forum], than representative government. It must be less dependent on

representation, and become more self-government, more government of each

by themselves.”[151] This was needed because the State was no neutral

structure:

“Developed in the course of history to establish and maintain the

monopoly of land ownership in favour of one class – which, for that

reason, became the ruling class par excellence – what means can the

State provide to abolish this monopoly that the working class could not

find in its own strength and groups? Then perfected during the course of

the nineteenth century to ensure the monopoly of industrial property,

trade, and banking to new enriched classes, to which the State was

supplying ‘arms’ cheaply by stripping the land from the village communes

and crushing the cultivators by tax – what advantages could the State

provide for abolishing these same privileges? Could its governmental

machine, developed for the creation and upholding of these privileges,

now be used to abolish them? Would not the new function require new

organs? And these new organs would they not have to be created by the

workers themselves, in their unions, their federations, completely

outside the State?”[152]

In short, the revolution would see “the commune, independent of the

State, abolishing in itself the representative system” while the

“workers’ organisations” seize “the instruments of labour” and land. So

instead of a society “based on the subjugation of the people to rulers,

be they usurpatory, hereditary or elected, anarchists work for the

realisation of a society based on the mutual agreement” for they “deny

every form of hierarchical organisation”.[153] Thus the aim was to

produce a society where people were genuinely free rather than simply

free to pick their masters:

“We finally realise now that without communism man will never be able to

reach that full development of individuality which is, perhaps, the most

powerful desire of every thinking being.”[154]

Anarchy, though, was not for the future. Anarchists “work so that the

masses of workers of the soil and of [the] factory endeavour to form

organisations” based “not in pyramidal hierarchy, not in the orders of

the central committee” but rather “in the free group, federative, from

the simple to the complex.”[155] The struggle against exploitation and

oppression was the means by which anarchism was created, for “to make

revolution, the mass of workers must organise themselves, and resistance

and the strike are excellent means by which workers can organise.” What

was needed was “to build resistance associations” and “fight against the

exploiters, to unify the workers’ organisations of each town and trade

and to put them in contact with those of other towns, to federate across

France, to federate across borders, internationally”.[156]

Let Bakunin, Kropotkin – myths aside – saw that a social revolution “is

not the work of one day. It means a whole period, mostly lasting for

several years, during which the country is in a state of effervescence;

when thousands of formerly indifferent spectators take a lively part in

public affairs”. For “this immense problem – the reorganisation of

production, redistribution of wealth and exchange, according to the new

principles – cannot be solved by parliamentary commissions nor by any

kind of government. It must be a natural growth resulting from the

combined efforts of all interested in it” and “must grow naturally,

proceeding from the simplest up to complex federations, and it cannot be

something schemed by a few men and ordered from above.”[157]

Anarchist Organisation: Principles and Practice

Our discussion of the origins of anarchist organisation has shown its

influences – ideological and practical – and its characteristics.

Anarchists since the first self-proclaimed anarchist text, What is

Property?, had already answered Engels’ question of “how do these people

propose to operate a factory, run a railway, or steer a ship without one

will that decides in the last resort, without unified direction”?[158]

Anarchism was born precisely to answer it and did so with a single word:

association.[159]

Anarchists have always recognised that freedom is a product of

interaction between people and it is how we associate which determines

whether we are free or not. While anarchism’s perspective is social,

Engels’ is fundamentally liberal as it sees isolation as true freedom

(“each gives up some of his autonomy”[160]) and so confuses agreement

with authority, co-operation with coercion.

The real question is simple: is an association based on the

self-government of its members or do a few decide for all? So to qualify

as libertarian an organisation must be based on certain core

principles[161] that ensure that liberty is not reduced to simply

picking masters:

Taking each in turn, we can sketch the principles of anarchist

organisation which “has sought to change relationships between people,

and that will one day transform them, both those that are established

between people living under a single roof and those that may be

established in international associations.”[162]

An organisation that is not voluntary would hardly be free. So free

association requires that individuals decide for themselves which groups

to join. Yet it is more than that for “to promise to obey is to deny or

to limit, to a greater or lesser degree, individuals’ freedom and

equality and their ability to exercise these capacities [of independent

judgement and rational deliberation]. To promise to obey is to state,

that in certain areas, the person making the promise is no longer free

to exercise her capacities and decide upon her own actions, and is no

longer equal, but subordinate.”[163] Being free to join a group that is

internally hierarchical is simply picking masters and this means that

groups have to be democratic so that those subject to decisions make

them. Thus anarchist organisation is rooted in “the possibility of

calling the general assembly whenever it was wanted by the members of

the section and of discussing everything in the general assembly”.[164]

This means freedom does not end at the workplace door or with a marriage

ceremony. As Proudhon noted, under capitalism workers may ostensibly

sell just their labour but in reality they sell their liberty as well

for the reasons Pateman summarises:

“Capacities or labour power cannot be used without the worker using his

will, his understanding and experience, to put them into effect. The use

of labour power requires the presence of its ‘owner’ […] the worker

labours as demanded. The employment contract must, therefore, create a

relationship of command and obedience between employer and worker […] In

short, the contract in which the worker allegedly sells his labour power

is a contract in which, since he cannot be separated from his

capacities, he sells command over the use of his body and himself. To

obtain the right to use another is to be a (civil) master. To sell

command over the use of oneself for a specified period [...] is to be an

unfree labourer. The characteristics of this condition are captured in

the term wage slave.”[165]

Wage-labour is not consistent with anarchism for, least we forget, “a

corporation, factory or business is the economic equivalent of fascism:

decisions and control are strictly top-down.”[166] This means that

“staying free is, for the working man who has to sell his labour, an

impossibility” and so a free economy existed only when “associations of

men and women who would work on the land, in the factories, in the

mines, and so on, became themselves the managers of production.”[167]

In short, “neither a commercial, nor an industrial, nor an agricultural

association can be conceived of in the absence of equality”.[168] The

anarchist critique of property rests on its core principles of liberty

and equality and is reflected in its organisational principles. Yet

while democratic, anarchist organisations have to be egalitarian as well

for simply electing a few who govern the rest reintroduces hierarchies,

albeit elected ones, and least we forget government is the “delegation

of power, that is, the abdication of the initiative and sovereignty of

every one into the hands of the few” and should not be confused with

administration, which “signifies delegation of work.”[169] This means

“organising society, not from above downwards, but on a basis of

equality, without authority, from the simple to the complex”.[170] If an

organisation is not centralised and top-down then it is not a state. So

anarchism’s anti-state position, like its anti-property one, is a

socialist critique driven by its egalitarian core principle:

“we are the most logical and most complete socialists, since we demand

for every person not just his entire measure of the wealth of society

but also his portion of social power, which is to say, the real ability

to make his influence felt, along with that of everybody else, in the

administration of public affairs.”[171]

Anarchists have tended to call this self-management rather than

democratic precisely because democracy has, in practice, meant electing

a government rather than a group of people governing themselves. This

does not preclude the need to “allocate a given task to others” in the

shape of committees but it is a case of group members “not abdicating

their own sovereignty” by “turning some into directors and chiefs”.[172]

These would be agents of the group rather than their masters for these

committees would be “always under the direct control of the population”

and express the “decisions taken at popular assemblies”[173] – subject

to election, mandating and recall, like all delegates. How much an

individual participates within an association is up to each person but

the option to take part is always there.

Just as individuals associate within groups, so groups will need to

co-ordinate their activities (“collective beings are as much realities

as individual ones are”[174]) by the same kind of horizontal links that

exist within an association. This federalist structure is made up of

delegates “elected by each section or federation”, “duty-bound to enact

the wishes of their mandatories” and “liable to be recalled at any

point.”[175] Decisions, then, are co-ordinated by means of elected,

mandated and recallable delegates rather than representatives. This

would, by definition, be a decentralised organisation for power remains

at the base in the individuals who associate together into groups rather

than at the top in the hands of a few representatives and the

bureaucracies needed to support them:

“True progress lies in the direction of decentralisation, both

territorial and functional, in the development of the spirit of local

and personal initiative, and of free federation from the simple to the

compound, in lieu of the present hierarchy from the centre to the

periphery […] through the organisation in every township or commune of

the local groups of producers and consumers, as also the regional, and

eventually the international, federations of these groups.”[176]

It would also be decentred, with decisions made by those affected rather

than every decision being channelled into the hands of a single

organisation, whether locally or nationally, which decides upon

everything – regardless of its (lack of) competency to discuss and

decide upon the issue. Federalism, then, is based on both decentralising

and decentring decision making back into the hands of all affected by

the decisions made.

Groups and federations exist for clear reasons and self-manage the

activities they exist to achieve and so the permanence or otherwise of

specific groups or agreements is very much dependent on the functional

needs of the situation or the participants and so cannot be formalised

by a hard or fast rule. Some agreements will be fleeting (to provide

specific goods or services) and other more-or-less permanent (to provide

healthcare or run a railway network). The key is that the federation

lasts as long as is required, that association is produced by objective

needs and does not exist for its own sake. This does not preclude

general gatherings at specific times or in response to specific events

or needs, just that there will be a multitude of groups and federations

alongside these.

This brings us to another issue, namely size. While some suggest that

anarchism inherently supports small-scale groups or industry this is not

the case. It recognises that size is driven by the objective needs of a

functional task. A workplace is as big as its output requires (“oceanic

steamers cannot be built in village factories”[177]) while a commune can

be a village, a town or a city. While large organisations would – as is

the case now – be sub-divided internally into functional groups, this

does not change the fact that anarchists have always incorporated the

fact of, and need for, large-scale organisation and industry. Indeed,

federalism is advocated precisely to co-ordinate, plan and provide

services judged by those who need them to be better done together.

What level a specific industry or service should be co-ordinated at will

vary depending on what it is so no hard and fast rule can be formulated

but the basic principle is that groups “unite with each other in a

mutual and equal way, for one or more specific tasks, whose

responsibility specially and exclusively falls to the delegates of the

federation” Thus it is a case of “the initiative of communes and

departments as to works that operate within their jurisdiction” plus

“the initiative of the workers companies as to carrying the works out”

for the “direct, sovereign initiative of localities, in arranging for

public works that belong to them, is a consequence of the democratic

principle and the free contract”.[178] In contrast to Marxists who have

traditionally fetishised large-scale industry, planning and organisation

at the expense of common-sense, anarchists advocate appropriate levels

of all these within a federal structure which is the only form flexible

enough to take into account all the differing objective requirements and

needs of a complex world.

In short, self-governing individuals join self-governing groups that, in

turn, join self-governing federations. Individuals are free in-so-far as

the associations they join are participatory and without hierarchy:

“The essential principle of anarchism is that mankind has reached a

stage of development at which it is possible to abolish the old

relationship of master-man (capitalist-proletarian) and substitute a

relationship of egalitarian co-operation. This principle is based, not

only on ethical ground, but also on economic grounds.”[179]

This self-managed society was termed by Proudhon a “Labour

Democracy”[180] to clearly differentiate it from existing – bourgeois –

forms of democracy.

Minorities and Majorities

Rather than constantly governed by the few – whether that few is the

elected of the majority matters little – individuals within an

association will participate in decisions and will sometimes be in the

majority, sometimes not, in numerous groups and federations. The

“necessity of division and association of labour” means “I take and I

give – such is human life. Each is an authoritative leader and in turn

is led by others. Accordingly there is no fixed and constant authority,

but continual exchange of mutual, temporary, and, above all, voluntary

authority and subordination.”[181] No one’s permanent position would be

one of subjection as under statism and capitalism.

Anarchists do not think that there will be unanimity within each group

for “variety, conflict even, is life” while “uniformity is death.”[182]

In disagreements, the minority has a choice – agree with the majority,

decide to leave the association or practice civil disobedience to

convince the majority of the errors of their way. Which option is best

depends on the nature of the decision and the group. Similarly, the

majority has the right to expel a minority (free association means the

freedom not to associate) which is acting in anti-social ways or not

keeping their word and so threatening a joint activity:

“Let us take a group of volunteers, combining for some particular

enterprise. Having its success at heart, they all work with a will, save

one of the associates, who is frequently absent from his post. Must they

on his account dissolve the group, elect a president to impose fines, or

maybe distribute markers for work done, as is customary in the Academy?

It is evident that neither the one nor the other will be done, but that

some day the comrade who imperils their enterprise will be told:

‘Friend, we should like to work with you; but as you are often absent

from your post, and you do your work negligently, we must part. Go and

find other comrades who will put up with your indifference!’ […] A

certain standard of public morals is maintained in the same way.”[183]

None of this assumes that the majority has the right to rule the

minority just that, in general, members who join a group do so

understanding the decision making process within the association and can

leave if they no longer agree with specific decisions of the

majority.[184] Thus we have majority decision making but not majority

government for the minority can leave and join or form other

associations. While anarchists “have the special mission of being

vigilant custodians of freedom, against all aspirants to power and

against the possible tyranny of the majority,”[185] the case for anarchy

– self-management – is not that the majority is always right but that no

minority (even an elected one) can be trusted not to prefer its own

advantage if given power:

“the present capitalist, authoritarian system is absolutely

inappropriate to a society of men so improvident, so rapacious, so

egotistic, and so slavish as they are now. Therefore, when we hear men

saying that the Anarchists imagine men much better than they really are,

we merely wonder how intelligent people can repeat that nonsense. Do we

not say continually that the only means of rendering men less rapacious

and egotistic, less ambitious and less slavish at the same time, is to

eliminate those conditions which favour the growth of egotism and

rapacity, of slavishness and ambition? The only difference between us

and those who make the above objection is this: We do not, like them,

exaggerate the inferior instincts of the masses, and do not complacently

shut our eyes to the same bad instincts in the upper classes. We

maintain that both rulers and ruled are spoiled by authority; both

exploiters and exploited are spoiled by exploitation; while our

opponents seem to admit that there is a kind of salt of the earth – the

rulers, the employers, the leaders ― who, happily enough, prevent those

bad men – the ruled, the exploited, the led – from becoming still worse

than they are.

“There is the difference, and a very important one. We admit the

imperfections of human nature, but we make no exception for the rulers.

They make it, although sometimes unconsciously, and because we make no

such exception, they say that we are dreamers, ‘unpractical men.’”[186]

The aim of anarchism is to eliminate permanent relations of

subordination, in other words hierarchy. This is achieved by collective

decision making (self-management) and socialisation (abolition of

private property). It does not postulate the notion of everyone always

seeing their ideas implemented within every freely joined association

they are part of. This would be near impossible, unless the person is

the dictator of the group and so violates the freedom of the others.

The key is that internally the associations are as free as they were to

join and so no one alienates or denies their liberty in order to become

part of them. Thus the newcomer to an anarchist workplace has the same

rights as existing members while the capitalist firm can only be joined

if the potential worker agrees to obey the property-owner: the

servant-master relationships inherent in the latter are abolished in the

former. It also shows how other, more obviously, core principles are

expressed – thus liberty is protected by means of equality which is

achieved by the abolition of property.

This raises the issue of minorities and majorities. Anarchists are well

aware that majorities can be unimaginative and oppressive, that social

progress is a product of energetic minorities – sometimes even

individuals – who push the accepted norms, challenge the status quo, and

so on. Emma Goldman put it well in her article “Minorities and

Majorities”:

“Not because I do not feel with the oppressed, the disinherited of the

earth; not because I do not know the shame, the horror, the indignity of

the lives the people lead, do I repudiate the majority as a creative

force for good. Oh, no, no! But because I know so well that as a compact

mass it has never stood for justice or equality. It has suppressed the

human voice, subdued the human spirit, chained the human body. As a mass

its aim has always been to make life uniform, grey, and monotonous as

the desert. As a mass it will always be the annihilator of

individuality, of free initiative, of originality.”[187]

This was why she, like most other anarchists, supported syndicalism and

other mass movements based on direct action, to encourage what Kropotkin

called the “spirit of revolt” and break the mental chains which secure

those of economic and political inequality.[188] However, the issue

remains – would a self-managed socialist society ensure freedom for all,

for minorities along with majorities? Would social pressure be

oppressive, would the associations become bureaucratic due to

administrative routine?

This is no idle point and many sympathetic to anarchism, including

George Orwell and Ursula le Guin, made this point.[189] Yet anarchist

thinkers have long recognised the issue. Kropotkin, for example, noted

in the conclusion of Mutual Aid the importance of minority action to

shatter social forms which have become set in their ways:

“It will probably be remarked that mutual aid, even though it may

represent one of the factors of evolution, covers nevertheless one

aspect only of human relations; that by the side of this current,

powerful though it may be, there is, and always has been, the other

current – the self-assertion of the individual, not only in its efforts

to attain personal or caste superiority, economical, political, and

spiritual, but also in its much more important although less evident

function of breaking through the bonds, always prone to become

crystallised, which the tribe, the village community, the city, and the

State impose upon the individual. In other words, there is the

self-assertion of the individual taken as a progressive element.”[190]

The importance of revolutionary minorities, then, does not end with the

creation of anarchy.[191] Thus the majority will be subject to the

influence of minorities within associations and the federal structure of

anarchy ensures experimentation due to the diversity it inherently

allows:

“The principle of political centralism is openly opposed to all laws of

social progress and of natural evolution. It lies in the nature of

things that every cultural advance is first achieved within a small

group and only gradually finds adoption by society as a whole.

Therefore, political decentralisation is the best guaranty for the

unrestricted possibilities of new experiments. For such an environment

each community is given the opportunity to carry through the things

which it is capable of accomplishing itself without imposing them on

others. Practical experimentation is the parent of every development in

society. So long as each district is capable of effecting the changes

within its own sphere which its citizens deem necessary, the example of

each becomes a fructifying influence on the other parts of the community

since they will have the chance to weigh the advantages accruing from

them without being forced to adopt them if they are not convinced of

their usefulness. The result is that progressive communities serve the

others as models, a result justified by the natural evolution of

things.”[192]

Diversity, disagreement, is reflected in anarchist organisational theory

for anarchists are well aware of the importance of individual and

minority freedom within the wider context of social self-management. The

idea that full, unanimous agreement (“consensus”) is needed is not part

of the anarchist tradition.[193] While anarchists recognise that

consensus may be suitable for some groups – most obviously, the family

and circles of friends – it would not be so for most others,

particularly those associated with waging the class struggle or the

post-revolutionary organising of industry on a large-scale. Yet, the

danger which consensus seeks to eliminate (while exaggerating it) – that

minorities are subject to the oppressive will of the majority – is

minimised within anarchist organisations. Participation within a

multitude of associations means that no one will be a minority all the

time whether in a specific group or in life as a whole.

In addition, with the means of life socialised, individuals and groups

have the real freedom to leave groupings and form new ones for they have

the resources available. Thus, if you are permanently in a minority then

you can leave an association far more easily than under capitalism – you

do not have to pay for or gain the permission of others to utilise

unused resources to do so. As Kropotkin argued:

“in a communist society which recognises the right of everyone, on an

egalitarian basis, to all the instruments of labour and to all the means

of existence that society possesses, the only men on their knees in

front of others are those who are by their nature voluntary serfs. Each

being equal to everyone else as far as the right to well-being is

concerned, he does not have to kneel before the will and arrogance of

others and so secures equality in all personal relationships with his

co-members. […] communism […] guarantees the most freedom for the

individual – provided that the guiding idea of the commune is

egalitarian Freedom, the absence of authority, Anarchy.”[194]

Thus there is substantial freedom for individuals and minorities to not

only live their own lives as they see fit but also to push society

forward, to ensure social progress. While under authoritarian systems

like capitalism “progress” is usually imposed by minorities for their

own advantage (such as higher profits or power) at the expense of the

many, with any wider gains purely coincidental, in an anarchist society

progress would be achieved by the possibility to experiment and the

knowledge that the benefits of change would be shared by all. Few would

object to changes which improve their life – particularly if they see

pioneers reaping the benefits of applying the new ways.

Any discussion of the dynamic between minorities and majorities must

note that this works both ways – groups can expel individuals who

systematically undermine decisions reached by the organisation. Just as

majorities can be oppressive, so can minorities. An anarchist society

would seek to defend itself against those seeking power, whether

economic, political or social – a point worth stressing as some seem to

believe, as Malatesta so elegantly put it, “that anarchists, in the name

of their principles, would wish to see that strange freedom respected

which violates and destroys the freedom and life of others. They seem

almost to believe that after having brought down government and private

property we would allow both to be quietly built up again, because of

respect for the freedom of those who might feel the need to be rulers

and property owners. A truly curious way of interpreting our

ideas.”[195] In other words:

“Our Revolution […] is […] a fact consisting of the aggregate of

individual victories over the resistance of every individual who has

stood in the way of Liberty. Under these circumstances it is obvious

that any visible reprisal [of authority] could and would be met by a

resumption of the same revolutionary action on the part of the

individuals or groups affected, and the maintenance of a state of

Anarchy in this manner would be far easier than the gaining of a state

of Anarchy by the same methods and in the face of hitherto unshaken

organised opposition. […] the gradual and temporarily imperceptible

regeneration of the old evils […] must eventually become perceptible to

those affected by them, who cannot fail to become aware that in such or

such a quarter they are excluded from the liberty they enjoy elsewhere,

that such or such a person is drawing from society all that he can, and

monopolising from others as much as possible. They have it in their

power to apply a prompt check by boycotting such a person and refusing

to help him with their labour or to willingly supply him with any

articles in their possession. They have it in their power to exert

pressure upon him […] to use force against him. They have these powers

individually as well as collectively. Being either past rebels who have

been inspired with the spirit of liberty, or else habituated to enjoy

freedom from their infancy, they are hardly likely to rest passive in

view of what they feel to be a wrong. […] And at the worst, it can

hardly be supposed that the abuse would grow to be a general system like

that which exists at present, without having already provoked a severe

struggle.”[196]

Anarchist organisational theory, in short, has always built into

libertarian systems safeguards against irremovable imperfections –

safeguards such as federalism, election, mandates, recall,

socialisation. In this way, both minorities and majorities have freedom

and so social progress is ensured based upon the natural give and take

of group life. Anarchism, then, does not deny the potential dangers of

majority decision-making and the possible bureaucratic degeneration of

even the best organisation but it seeks to minimise them by means of

bottom-up structures and the role of vigilant individuals and active

minorities in challenging social crystallisation.[197]

This discussion of majorities and minorities points to a paradox of

individualism. In order to always see your ideas implemented you either

have to abolish all groups (including the family) or be a dictator (or

owner, the terms being synonymous). The first option is impossible while

the second is hardly libertarian. Most individualists, however, opt for

the second option but obscure what is little more than voluntary

dictatorship under – like Locke – much talk of “consent” and “property

in the person”. It is to these we now turn in order to show the

contradictions of this position as well as the dangers of ideology.

Libertarians against “Libertarianism” (or the dangers of ideology)

Many anarchists are sympathetic to the saying – popularised if not

invented by the Situationists – that the difference between theory and

ideology is that the former is when you have ideas and the latter is

when ideas have you. As such, anarchists tend to suggest that anarchism

is not an ideology but rather a theory. The dangers of ideology can best

be seen by comparing libertarian theory with the ideology that is called

“libertarianism” by its proponents.

We need to clarify an obvious objection: how can anarchists – who have

been calling themselves libertarian since 1857 – be against

“libertarianism”? Simply because the advocates of “libertarianism” did

not let their ideological support for absolute property rights stop them

knowingly stealing the name from those who invented and used it. As

Murray Rothbard, one of the founders of “Libertarianism”, recalled:

“One gratifying aspect of our rise to some prominence [in 1950s America]

is that, for the first time in my memory, we, ‘our side,’ had captured a

crucial word from the enemy […] ‘Libertarians’ […] had long been simply

a polite word for left-wing [sic!] anarchists, that is for anti-private

property anarchists, either of the communist or syndicalist variety. But

now we had taken it over”[198]

Given this quite brazen – and ideology contradicting! – act of theft, it

is understandable that anarchists are somewhat less than sympathetic to

“libertarianism”. This is confirmed by the self-contradictory and

liberty-denying conclusions that its advocates reach. Ignoring what

drove the creation of anarchism, “libertarianism” seeks to return to the

authoritarianism of classical liberalism and, inevitably, to the

contradictions Rousseau had exposed. Thus we find Rothbard proclaiming

that the state “arrogates to itself a monopoly of force, of ultimate

decision-making power, over a given territorial area” before, buried in

the chapter’s end notes, quietly admitting that “[o]bviously, in a free

society, Smith has the ultimate decision-making power over his own just

property, Jones over his, etc.”[199] Needless to say, Rothbard does not

mention the obvious issue – they like the State have “ultimate

decision-making power” over those who use that property as well. Unlike

Robert Nozick who was more open:

“if one starts a private town, on land whose acquisition did not and

does not violate the Lockean proviso [of non-aggression], persons who

chose to move there or later remain there would have no right to a say

in how the town was run, unless it was granted to them by the decision

procedures for the town which the owner had established.”[200]

While some would argue that it “would be logically inconsistent for an

ideology to defend individual choice and to deny people the vote”[201],

for “libertarianism” the opposite is the case – individual choice is the

means by which people are subjected to authoritarian (indeed,

dictatorial) social relationships in the name of “liberty”. Yet the

glaring contradictions – “libertarians” advocating dictatorship, a

definition of the state (evil) identical to property (good) – are all

too clear and already denounced by anarchists in the critique of

liberalism they extended from Rousseau into property itself. Rothbard,

ironically, shows the validity of the anarchist position while haplessly

trying to defend his own:

“If the State may be said to properly own its territory, then it is

proper for it to make rules for everyone who presumes to live in that

area. It can legitimately seize or control private property because

there is no private property in its area, because it really owns the

entire land surface. So long as the State permits its subjects to leave

its territory, then, it can be said to act as does any other owner who

sets down rules for people living on his property.”[202]

The question now becomes one not of liberty within an association but

whether those who hold power (“sets down rules”) do so legitimately or

not and this relates to property rights. Rothbard argues that the state

does not “justly” own its territory and asserts that his “homesteading

theory” of the creation of private property “suffices to demolish any

such pretensions by the State apparatus” and so the problem with the

state is that it “claims and exercises a compulsory monopoly of defence

and ultimate decision-making over an area larger than an individual’s

justly-acquired property.”[203] Yet private property has never been

acquired in the form Rothbard (repeating Locke) suggested but has been

bound-up with state and private coercion – assuming his theory was

robust, which it is not. He attempts to eliminate the clear difficulties

he faces by liberal (pun intended) use of “adding mythical and imaginary

happenings to make up for the ‘reality gaps’”[204] combined with the

hope that he found people “simple enough to believe him” (to requote

Rousseau).

Ignoring Rothbard’s “immaculate conception of property” as being as

unrelated to reality as Locke’s social contract theory of the state, the

question arises why current and future generations should be

dispossessed from liberty because property is monopolised by the few.

While he denounced social contract theories of the state as invalid

because “no past generation can bind later generations”[205] he fails to

see he is doing exactly that with his support of private property:

current and future generations of humanity must be – to use Proudhon’s

word – excommunicated from liberty by proprietor hierarchy.

One of the many reasons why the state has intervened in society – and

why liberalism has evolved away from its classical form – is because

people recognised both the contradiction between proclaiming liberty in

the abstract while denying it in practice and the obvious injustices

that the private hierarchies associated with property can produce.[206]

Ironically, Rothbard himself shows that this is the case when he

utilised a hypothetical example of a country whose King, threatened by a

rising “libertarian” movement, responses by “employ[ing] a cunning

stratagem,” namely he “proclaims his government to be dissolved, but

just before doing so he arbitrarily parcels out the entire land area of

his kingdom to the ‘ownership’ of himself and his relatives.” Rather

than taxes, his subjects now pay rent and he can “regulate the lives of

all the people who presume to live on” his property as he sees fit.

Rothbard then admits people would be “living under a regime no less

despotic than the one they had been battling for so long. Perhaps,

indeed, more despotic, for now the king and his relatives can claim for

themselves the libertarians’ very principle of the absolute right of

private property, an absoluteness which they might not have dared to

claim before.”[209]

While Rothbard rejects this “cunning stratagem” he failed to note how

this argument undermines his own claims that capitalism is the only

system which is based upon and fosters liberty. As he himself argues,

not only does the property owner have the same monopoly of power over a

given area as the state, it is more despotic as it is based on the

“absolute right of private property”. Indeed, he states that the theory

that the state owns its territory “makes the State, as well as the King

in the Middle Ages, a feudal overlord, who at least theoretically owned

all the land in his domain”[207] without noticing that this makes the

capitalist or landlord a feudal overlord within “libertarianism.”

The one remaining defence of “libertarianism” is that these absolutist

social relationships are fine because they are voluntary in nature: no

one forces someone to work for a specific employer and everyone has the

possibility of becoming an employer or landlord. That some may become a

proprietor is true but that does not address the issue – are people to

be free or not. It is a strange ideology that proclaims itself

liberty-loving yet embraces factory feudalism and office oligarchy.

The context in which people make their decisions is important.

Anarchists have long argued that, as a class, workers have little choice

but to “consent” to capitalist hierarchy as the alternative is either

dire poverty or starvation. “Libertarianism” dismisses this by denying

that there is such a thing as economic power.[208] It is easy to refute

such claims by turning to Rothbard’s arguments about the abolition of

slavery and serfdom in the 19^(th) century:

“The bodies of the oppressed were freed, but the property which they had

worked and eminently deserved to own, remained in the hands of their

former oppressors. With economic power thus remaining in their hands,

the former lords soon found themselves virtual masters once more of what

were now free tenants or farm labourers. The serfs and slaves had tasted

freedom, but had been cruelly derived of its fruits.”[209]

So if “market forces” (“voluntary exchanges”) result in the few owning

most of the property then this is unproblematic and raises no questions

about the (lack of) liberty of the working class but if people are

placed in exactly the same situation as a result of coercion then it is

a case of “economic power” and “masters”.

Such is the danger of ideology that it allows someone to write a book

that actually refutes its own arguments.

It also shows the importance of organisation to a political theory.

Anarchism by placing liberty as a priority principle took it seriously

and organised the concepts it had inherited from previous ideologies in

such a manner that it also took organisation seriously. It recognised

the obvious contradiction in defining (or, more correctly, limiting)

liberty to just consent and, with Rousseau, opposed the liberal attempt

to decontest the notion by pointing to its practice. That Nozick can ask

whether “a free system would allow [the individual] to sell himself into

slavery” and answer “I believe that it would”[210] shows the correctness

of anarchism in this.

The apparent paradox of why an ideology self-proclaimed as “libertarian”

is not particularly interested in liberty and justifies numerous

obviously authoritarian social relations (up to and including voluntary

slavery and dictatorship) is not a paradox at all. Contract in the

liberal sense “always generates political right in the form of relations

of domination and subordination” and so rather than “undermining

subordination, contract theorists justified modern civil

subjection.”[211] Once it is realised that its core principle is

property rather than liberty then it is logical to rename it something

more accurate: propertarianism.

This may seem counter-intuitive or contradictory but it is not: it is

the aim of the whole ideological tradition. Locke was not seeking to

undermine traditional hierarchies (beyond absolute monarchy) but rather

to reinforce them. He did so by a “just-so” story whose desired

conclusions – his favoured socio-economic system, the one he benefited

from – are reached by what appear reasonable steps. And here we have the

crux of the matter for in Locke’s “just-so” story the state does

rightfully own its property for it is a joint-stock corporation formed

by landlords (servants are in civil society but not of civil society and

have no say, just as employees are part of a company but its owners run

it). Rothbard refuses to take this final step but gives no reason to

reject this final chapter of the same fictional story. For we must never

forget that this is what this ideology is based upon – a “just-so”

story. Locke, Nozick and Rothbard seek to defend the inequalities of

capitalism by convincing us to believe his story and ignore history –

not to mention the evidence of unfreedom before our eyes.

The farcical self-contradictions that Rothbard repeatedly gets himself

into shows why “every society declines the moment it falls into the

hands of the ideologists”[212]. At its worse, ideology allows its

believers to not only ignore – even justify – social injustice but also

to contradict their stated aspirations and abuse logic. While it may be

argued that it is only by using ideology as a concept that we can expose

this kind of contradiction, the fundamental problem is that it is

ideology which blinds Rothbard and Nozick to the obvious, namely that

the state and private property produce identical social relationships

and “if you have unbridled capitalism, you will have all kinds of

authority: you will have extreme authority.”[213]

The contradictions of propertarianism also shows that historical

understanding and context is important. It does not afford “a typical

example of a gravitational shift within conventional ideologies that

obscures an ideology’s foundational principles by reorganising the core

units.” As Locke shows, this is not the case and rather than “crowding

out or demoting other liberal core concepts,”[214] propertarianism sees

itself as clearing it of that which has no place in it.

While it may be true that “private property migrated within liberal

ideology from a core position to a more marginal one” this is due to the

rise of subsequent theories which critiqued it (most notably democracy).

This means that propertarianism is a reaction to liberal-democratic

ideology and the erosion of property rights and power it implies. It is

simply not the case that propertarians “overemphasize individual liberty

at the expense of other liberal values” because they do not “expand the

liberty theme” at all but rather aim to restrict it – for the many. This

can be seen by the awkward fact that while neo-liberalism may have “a

built in reluctance to contemplate state regulation as a possible cure

to social evils”[215] but this does not apply when it comes to, say,

organised labour when State power is regularly invoked.[216]

This means that propertarianism is not “a strange hybrid” which is “also

carved out of conservativism” with the aim of “the sanctioning of

existing economic inequalities”[217] for classical liberalism’s goal was

precisely to sanction the economic inequalities of the developing

capitalist economy and to firmly secure (conserve!) the market-driven

master-servant relationships which were replacing more traditional ones.

That other self-described liberals, are horrified by it is down to the

evolution of liberalism and its embrace of ideas from other traditions,

namely democracy and socialism.

Resistance is Fertile: From Here to There

Regardless of propertarian claims, it is as not a simple fact of nature

that the propertyless must serve those with property – it is a product

of specific, human created, social institutions which produce specific

hierarchical social relationships and these can and must be ended to

achieve freedom for all rather than a few. The struggle to end them is

the link between the present and the future, from here to there.

Thus anarchist organisation is not something for the future, it must be

applied now. It is only by applying libertarian ideas today, in our

daily lives and struggles, that we become capable of being free.

Anarchists “are convinced that one learns through struggle, and that

once one begins to enjoy a little freedom one ends by wanting it

all”[218] and so “by degrees, the revolutionary education of the people”

is “accomplished by the revolution itself.”[219] Struggle against social

hierarchies, whether public or private, political or economic, is the

means to transform both individuals and society:

“Between man and his social environment there is a reciprocal action.

Men make society what it is and society makes men what they are, and the

result is therefore a kind of vicious circle. To transform society men

must be changed, and to transform men, society must be changed.

“Poverty brutalises man, and to abolish poverty men must have a social

conscience and determination. Slavery teaches men to be slaves, and to

free oneself from slavery there is a need for men who aspire to liberty

[…] Governments accustom people to submit to the Law and to believe that

Law is essential to society; and to abolish government men must be

convinced of the uselessness and the harmfulness of government.

“How does one escape from this vicious circle?

“Fortunately existing society has not been created by the inspired will

of a dominating class, which has succeeded in reducing all its subjects

to passive and unconscious instruments of its interests. It is the

result of a thousand internecine struggles of a thousand human and

natural factors […] From this the possibility of progress […] We must

take advantage of all the means, all the possibilities and the

opportunities that the present environment allows us to act on our

fellow men and to develop their consciences and their demands […] to

claim and to impose those major social transformations which are

possible and which effectively serve to open the way to further advances

later […] We must seek to get all the people, or different sections of

the people, to make demands, and impose itself and take for itself all

the improvements and freedoms it desires as and when it reaches the

state of wanting them, and the power to demand them […] we must push the

people to want always more and to increase its pressures, until it has

achieved complete emancipation.”[220]

In short, as Bakunin stressed, there is “but a single path, that of

emancipation through practical action” which “has only one meaning. It

means workers’ solidarity in their struggle against the bosses. It means

trades-unions, organisation, and the federation of resistance

funds.”[224] The struggle against hierarchy is the means to achieve

anarchy, for by challenging hierarchy we both create the structures

which will replace it and get used to managing our own affairs without

masters. As George Barrett put it:

“The Anarchist’s argument is that government fulfils no useful purpose.

Most of what it does is mischievous, and the rest could be done better

without its interference. It is the headquarters of the profit-makers,

the rent-takers, and of all those who take from but who do not give to

society. When this class is abolished by the people so organising

themselves that they will run the factories and use the land for the

benefit of their free communities, i.e., for their own benefit, then the

Government must also be swept away, since its purpose will be gone. The

only thing then that will be put in the place of government will be the

free organisations of the workers. When Tyranny is abolished Liberty

remains, just as when disease is eradicated health remains.”[221]

So, “[t]o make a revolution it is not, however, enough that there should

be […] risings […] It is necessary that after the risings there should

be left something new in the institutions, which would permit new forms

of life to be elaborated and established.”[222] Struggle is the means by

which the new social organism is created.

It is easy to see how union and strike assemblies and committees can

become the structures by which workers run their workplaces. Indeed, how

else could it occur? Thus “the weapon of the future will be the general

strike” and “it must be the strike which will stay in the factory, not

go out,” which “will guard the machines and allow no scab to touch

them,” which “will organise, not to inflict deprivation on itself, but

on the enemy,” which “will take over industry and operate it for the

workers, not for franchise holder, stockholders, and

officeholders”.[223] So the need, as Kropotkin summarised, is to

“constitute a formidable workers’ force that might impose its will on

the managers of industry and extract from them, first, improved working

conditions – better pay, reductions in working hours, healthier

factories, less dangerous machinery, and so on – but also, – ultimately,

wrest the very organisation of industry from their hands. […] unions

[are] more than merely a tool for bettering wages. They must, of

necessity, become bodies that would, one day, take the entire

organisation of each branch of industry into their hands.”[224] In this

he was repeating the ideas raised in the first International and

championed by the likes of Bakunin and Varlin.

Thus strikes “trains the participants for a common management of affairs

and for distribution of responsibilities, distinguishes the people most

talented and devoted to a common cause, and finally, forces the others

to get to know these people and strengthens their influence.”[225] Trade

unions were “natural organs for the direct struggle with capital and for

the organisation of the future order,”[226] a position echoed by others

who “recognise[d] in the Trades Unions the embryonic group of the future

‘free society.’ Every Trades Union is […] an autonomous commune in the

process of incubation” which as well as fighting capitalism “will yet

take its place by superseding it under the system of universal free

co-operation.”[227]

These unions – the people in their workplaces assembled and federated –

would be the means to first challenge Capital and then destroy it.

Likewise with community organisations, with Kropotkin pointing to the

“sections” of the French Revolution as the means by which “Revolution

began by creating the Commune […] and through this institution it gained

[…] immense power.” The “masses, accustoming themselves to act without

receiving orders from the national representatives” and “[b]y acting in

this way – and the libertarians would no doubt do the same today – the

districts of Paris laid the foundations of a new, free, social

organisation.”[228]

These sections – the people in their communities assembled and federated

– would be the means to first challenge the State and then destroy it.

In this way workplaces and communities would govern themselves,

federating with others to manage their common interests. Thus,

“Anarchism is not […] a theory of the future to be realised by divine

inspiration. It is a living force in the affairs of our life, constantly

creating new conditions.” It “stands for the spirit of revolt” and this

– the class struggle, the struggle against political, economic and

social hierarchy – is based on and encourages “defiance and resistance”

and these “necessitates integrity, self-reliance, and courage.” It

breaks the mental chains hierarchy forges within us all and fuels the

spark of liberty which always remains even in the most tyrannical

system. This is why “[d]irect action against the authority in the

[work]shop, direct action against the authority of the law, of direct

action against the invasive, meddlesome authority of our moral code, is

the logical, consistent method of Anarchism.”[229] If, as Bakunin

rightly argued, trade unions created the living seeds of (libertarian)

socialism within capitalism, then the class struggle ensures they

blossom.

In this way we create the means by which anarchy becomes a possibility

for, as Proudhon argued during the 1848 Revolution, if “a body

representative of the proletariat be formed […] in opposition to the

bourgeoisie’s representation” then “a new society [is] founded in the

heart of the old society.”[230] The structure of the new society is not

only formed within the shell of the old, as the famous words from the

Industrial Workers of the World’s preamble puts it, we are transformed

as we fight it. In short: “Only freedom or the struggle for freedom can

be the school for freedom.”[231]

Conclusion

Organisation is a fundamental aspect of any theory simply because it is

how its core principles are applied. If an ideology places organisation

to the periphery then it suggests that its adherents are not

particularly bothered by their stated core principles for it implies an

indifference to whether they are achieved in practice.

This can be seen from propertarianism and its return to classical

liberalism in protest to the attempts by many liberal thinkers to grasp

the obvious contradictions between their stated aspiration to liberty

and the various authoritarian social relationships that can happily

coexist with consent. Yet this transformation of mainstream liberalism

due to the influence of democratic, socialist and labourist ideas and

movements should not blind us to the authoritarian social relationships

which liberalism was created to justify and defend.

Anarchism is part of the reaction to liberalism and its production of

both “industrial servitude” and “obedient subjects to a central

authority.”[232] Liberalism “is primarily about a way of creating social

relations constituted by subordination, not about exchange.” Indeed,

“contract doctrine has proclaimed that subjection to a master – a boss,

a husband – is freedom” and is a “theoretical strategy that justifies

subjection by presenting it as freedom” and has “turned a subversive

proposition” that we are born free and equal “into a defence of civil

subjection” for “the employment contract (like the marriage contract) is

not an exchange; both contracts create social relations that endure over

time – social relations of subordination.”[233] Democracy recognised the

problem but its solution failed – it created a new class state, albeit

with a different basis and rationalisation.

Like democratic theory, anarchism saw its task as seeking a form of

organisation within which freedom was protected and so critiqued both

democracy and property. In contrast to the stereotype of anarchism as an

impractical dream without an understanding of the complexities of the

modern world, anarchists have spent considerable time discussing how to

best organise to meet social needs in a world marked by large-scale

industry and ever wider personal and social interactions while ensuring

individual and social freedom. This was achieved by extending

democracy’s critique liberalism to democracy itself and extending it to

the economic and social realms.

This was why Proudhon quoted Rousseau approvingly on the nature of the

social contract while denouncing how far in reality he was from it and

showing what was needed to achieve it. So if, in an “embryonic” form,

“universal suffrage provides” us “with the complete system of future

society” anarchists recognise that “[i]f it is reduced to the people

nominating a few hundred deputies” (i.e., a government) then “social

sovereignty becomes a mere fiction and the Revolution is strangled at

birth.”[234] Anarchist opposition to Rousseau is driven not by a

rejection of democracy but rather a desire to see a genuine one

created.[235] Woodcock was wrong both logically and historically to

proclaim that “the ideal of anarchism, far from being democracy carried

to its logical end, is much nearer to aristocracy universalised and

purified.”[236]

Anarchism recognises that there are many types of organisation – there

are those which are forced upon you and those which you freely join as

well as those which are authoritarian (run from the top-down) and those

which are libertarian (run from the bottom-up). Genuine liberty

necessitates groups that are free to join and are libertarian internally

as voluntary archy is not compatible with an-archy. Anarchist

organisational principles are core ones because they intersect with

other core concepts – not least (the critiques of) property and state –

as they express them:

“All depends on the fundamental ideas by which we wish to association.

It is not […] association which brings about slavery; it is the ideas of

individual freedom which we bring into the association which determine

its more or less libertarian character. […] The cohabitation of two

individuals in the same house can lead to the enslavement of one to the

will of the other as it can bring freedom for both. […] Likewise for any

association, however large or small it may be. Likewise for any social

institution.”[237]

Anarchism values individual liberty but sees it a product of social

interaction and so embraces the necessity of equality (self-management)

within groups to ensure it remains meaningful. This, in turn, means

embracing a critique of property to ensure that those who join a

workplace are associates rather than master and servants. Finally, if

self-management is applicable within the workplace then it is also

applicable for all social and private associations. The anarchist

critique of hierarchy – whether the state, capital, patriarchy, racism

or homophobia – is rooted in an awareness that “far from creating

authority, organisation is the only cure for it and the only means

whereby each of us will get used to taking an active and conscious part

in collective work, and cease being passive instruments in the hands of

leaders.”[238]

[62] Property, 132–5.

[115] Michael Bakunin: Selected Writings (London: Jonathan Cape, 1973),

Arthur Lehning (ed.), 197–8.

[209] Rothbard, 54.

[224] Bakunin, The Basic Bakunin, 102–3.

[1] Errico Malatesta: His Life and Ideas (London: Freedom Press, 1993),

Vernon Richards (ed.), 84–5.

[2] George Woodock, Anarchism: A History of Libertarian Ideas and

Movements (England: Penguin Books, 1986), 226–7.

[3] David Turcato, Making Sense of Anarchism: Errico Malatesta’s

Experiments with Revolution, 1889–1900 (Edinburgh/Oakland: AK Press,

2015).

[4] Michael Freeden, Ideology: A Very Short Introduction (Oxford: Oxford

University Press, 2003), 62.

[5] For a similar analysis see Robert Graham’s “The Role of Contract in

anarchist theory” in For Anarchism: History, Theory and Practice

(London: Routledge, 1989), David Goodway (ed.). For a useful exploration

of the same issues from a non-anarchist perspective which draws similar

conclusions see David P. Ellerman , Property and Contract in Economics:

The Case for Economic Democracy, (Oxford: Blackwell, 1992).

[6] Iain McKay, “Sages and Movements: An Incomplete Peter Kropotkin

Bibliography”, Anarchist Studies 22:1.

[7]

C. B Macpherson, The Political Theory of Possessive Individualism:

Hobbes to Locke, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1964), 194.

[8] For a wider analysis of liberalism along the lines explored here see

Domenico Losurdo, Liberalism: A Counter-History (London/New York: Verso,

2011).

[9] John Locke, Two Treatises of Government (Cambridge: Cambridge

University Press, 2013), Peter Laslett (ed.), Second Treatise, section

85 (322).

[10] Second Treatise, sections 86, 2, 3 (323, 268).

[11] Carole Pateman, The Sexual Contract (Cambridge: Polity, 1988), 40.

[12] Second Treatise, sections 27, 28, 27 (288).

[13] Macpherson, 203–20; Carole Pateman, The Problem of Political

Obligation: A Critique of Liberal Theory (Cambridge: Polity Press,

1985), 66–7.

[14] Second Treatise, sections 33, 36, 50 (291, 293, 302).

[15] First Treatise, section 43 (170–1).

[16] First Treatise, sections 43, 9 (171, 148).

[17] Second Treatise, section 28 (289).

[18] Macpherson, 214–5.

[19] Second Treatise, sections 124, 231 (418, 550–1).

[20] Second Treatise, section 94 (329–30).

[21] Pateman, Problem, 71.

[22] Second Treatise, sections 120, 121 (348, 349).

[23] Pateman, Problem, 67, 72.

[24] Macpherson, 221–2, 248–9, 227, 251.

[25] Macpherson, 196.

[26] John Locke, Political Essays (Cambridge: Cambridge University

Press, 1997), Mark Goldie (ed.), 161–2.

[27] Locke, Political, 162, 174–5.

[28] Second Treatise, section 213 (408).

[29] Pateman, Problem, 71–2.

[30] Political Essays, 180, 166.

[31] Second Treatise, sections 133, 24 (355, 284–5).

[32] Second Treatise, sections 85, 178, 180, 23 (322–3, 387, 388, 284).

[33] Pateman, Problem, 68.

[34] Second Treatise, section 131 (353).

[35] Rudolf Rocker’s notion that anarchism is “socialism vitalised by

liberalism” and “the synthesis of liberalism and socialism” therefore

misreads liberalism. He is right to highlight the authoritarian

tendencies of Rousseau but completely ignores those of Locke. While he

notes that “deficiencies in [Locke’s] political program” were “enhanced

by the economic inequalities in society”, Rocker fails to mention that

Locke sought to protect these as his ideas assumed “victorious

capitalism” in the state of nature and that the liberal regime was rule

by the wealthy over the rest. (Nationalism and Culture [Minnesota:

Michael E. Coughlin, 1978], 142, 238).

[36] William H. Sewell, Work and Revolution in France: The language of

labor from the old regime to 1848 (Cambridge: Cambridge University

Press, 1980), 120.

[37] Pateman, Problem, 142.

[38] Second Treatise, section 61 (308).

[39] Jean-Jacques Rousseau, The Social Contract and Discourses (London:

Everyman, 1996), 181.

[40] Rousseau, 99.

[41] Rousseau, 84.

[42] Rousseau, 225.

[43] Rousseau, 162.

[44] Rousseau, 199, 225.

[45] Rousseau, 316.

[46] Rousseau, 105, 269, 104, 200, 186.

[47] Rousseau, 266, 212, 191, 201, 230.

[48] Rousseau, 203–4.

[49] Peter Kropotkin, The Great French Revolution, 1789–1793 (London:

Orbach and Chambers Ltd, 1971); Daniel Guérin, Class struggle in the

First French Republic: bourgeois and bras nus, 1793–1795 (London: Pluto

Press, 1977).

[50] Gwyn A. Williams, Artisans and Sans-Culottes: Popular Movements in

France and Britain during the French Revolution (London: Edward Arnold,

1981), 25.

[51] Peter Kropotkin, Modern Science and Anarchy (Edinburgh: AK Press,

2018), 270.

[52] quoted by Roger Magraw, A History of the French Working Class

(Oxford/Cambridge: Blackwell, 1992) I: 24–25.

[53] Bernard H. Moss, The Origins of the French Labour Movement

1830–1914: The Socialism of Skilled Workers (Berkeley/Los

Angeles/London: University of California Press, 1980), 32–3.

[54] Sewell, 202.

[55] Magraw, 55, 72.

[56]

K. Steven Vincent, Pierre-Joseph Proudhon and the Rise of French

Republican Socialism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984)

127–140.

[57] Vincent, 164.

[58] Michael Bakunin, The Political Philosophy of Bakunin (New York: The

Free Press, 1953), G.P. Maximov (ed.), 249.

[59] Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, Système des contradictions économiques ou

Philosophie de la misère (Paris: Guillaumin, 1846) I: 377.

[60] Property is Theft! A Pierre-Joseph Proudhon Anthology

(Edinburgh/Chico: AK Press, 2011), Iain McKay (ed.), 137.

[61] Peter Kropotkin, Le Révolté, 8 July 1882.

[62] Property, 92.

[63] Property, 95, 106, 117, 114, 129, 104. It should be noted that

Proudhon takes for granted Adam Smith’s assertion that the “produce of

labour constitutes the natural recompence or wages of labour.” (An

Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations [Chicago:

University of Chicago, 1976], Volume 1, 72). Needless to say, he had no

time for arguments by any economist on why this was not applicable under

capitalism.

[64] Property, 91. 118, 105, 137, 112, 109, 137, 119. Proudhon appears

to have first used the term “industrial democracy” in 1852 when he noted

“an unavoidable transition to industrial democracy”. (La Révolution

sociale démontrée par le coup d’État du 2 décembre [Antony:

Tops-Trinquier, 2013], 156). Later the same decade saw him argue that

“an industrial democracy must follow industrial feudalism” for “Workers’

Associations are the locus of a new principle and model of production”

(Property, 610, 616)

[65] Property, 93, 148, 153, 150.

[66] This work has been misrepresented by some, particularly by Marx in

his The Poverty of Philosophy. Most obviously, Proudhon did not advocate

“labour notes” regardless of Marx’s assertions – see my “Proudhon’s

Constituted Value and the Myth of Labour Notes,” Anarchist Studies 25: 1

(Summer 2017) and “The Poverty of (Marx’s) Philosophy,”

Anarcho-Syndicalist Review 70 (Summer 2017).

[67] Property, 248, 212, 255.

[68] Property, 213–5. See Vincent’s excellent discussion (154–6).

[69] Property, 202.

[70] Système II: 519.

[71] Property, 223, 222, 223, 225, 226.

[72] Système I: 288.

[73] Property, 179.

[74] Besancon municipal library, MS 2881 f. 30v.

[75] Property, 179, 147.

[76] Aaron Noland, “Proudhon and Rousseau,” Journal of the History of

Ideas 28:1 (Jan-Mar 1967).

[77] Property, 260, 261, 267, 273, 277–8, 280.

[78] Property, 287–9, 377–8, 296–7.

[79] Property, 378–9, 407.

[80] Property, 439–41, 461, 446–7, 398.

[81] Property, 482–5.

[82] “Regarding Louis Blanc – The Present Utility and Future Possibility

of the State”, Anarcho-Syndicalist Review 66 (Winter 2016).

[83] Property, 565.

[84] Property, 566.

[85] Property, 566, 573.

[86] Property, 562–3, 591. By corporation Proudhon, like many socialists

at the time in France, meant organisations of worker-run co-operatives.

This federation of co-operatives in a given industry should not be

confused with modern corporations (i.e., stock issuing companies) which

Proudhon opposed as being basically identical to state-communist

associations.

[87] Property, 595–6.

[88] Property, 583–6.

[89] Property, 597.

[90] La fédération et l’unité en Italie (Paris: E. Dentu, 1862), 27–8

[91] La fédération, 33.

[92] Du principe fédératif (Antony: Tops-Trinquier, 2013), 125, 163.

[93] Du principe fédératif, 122.

[94] Besancon municipal library, MS 2881 f. 30v.

[95] Property, 712, 714.

[96] Property, 563, 502, 596, 780.

[97] Property, 677, 698, 716, 763, 762.

[98] Property, 760–1.

[99] Property, 503–6.

[100] Property, 132.

[101] Vincent, 224–5.

[102] Proudhon, Regarding, 29.

[103] Proudhon, Property, 711–3.

[104] Vincent, 156.

[105] Iain McKay, “Proudhon, Property & Possession”, Anarcho-Syndicalist

Review 66 (Winter 2016).

[106] Pateman, Sexual, 119, 122, 181.

[107] Joseph Déjacque, “On the Male and Female Human-Being”,

Anarcho-Syndicalist Review 71–72 (Fall 2017).

[108] Max Nettlau, A Short History of Anarchism (London: Freedom Press,

1995), 75–6. Use of libertarian became more commonplace in the 1880s and

1895 saw leading anarchists Sébastien Faure and Louise Michel publish La

Libertaire in France. (Nettlau, 145, 162). Soon after libertarian was

used as an alternative for anarchist internationally, see my “160 Years

of Libertarian,” Anarcho-Syndicalist Review 71–72 (Fall 2017).

[109] quoted by Carolyn J. Eichner, Surmounting the Barricades: Women in

the Paris Commune (Bloomington, Indiana University Press, 2004), 40.

[110] Robert Graham, We do not Fear Anarchy, we invoke it: The First

International and the Origins of the Anarchist Movement

(Oakland/Edinburgh: AK Press, 2015), 77, 128.

[111] Eugène Varlin, “Workers Societies,” La Marseillaise, 11 March

1870, from “Precursors of Syndicalism I,” Anarcho-Syndicalist Review 75

(Winter 2019).

[112] Graham, 92, 109–111, 118–120.

[113] The Basic Bakunin (Buffalo, NY: Promethus Books, 1994), Robert M.

Cutler (ed.), 110.

[114] Bakunin on Anarchism (Montreal: Black Rose Books, 1980), Sam

Dolgoff (ed.), 255.

[115] “Letter to Albert Richard”, Anarcho-Syndicalist Review 62 (Summer

2014).

[116] Bakunin on Anarchism, 408, 142.

[117] Selected, 131, 135, 147.

[118] “Organisational Question of Social Democracy,” Rosa Luxemburg

Speaks (New York: Pathfinder Press, 1970), Mary-Alice Waters (ed.),

119–20.

[119] Bakunin, Anarchism, 414–5.

[120] Philosophy, 241, 255, 268.

[121] Selected, 237–8, 265.

[122] Philosophy, 287.

[123] Selected, 237

[124] Bakunin, Anarchism, 246–7

[125] Selected, 147, 68

[126] Philosophy, 187

[127] Basic, 153

[128] Bakunin, Anarchism, 247, 427

[129] Selected, 170–2.

[130] Selected, 65.

[131] Bakunin, Anarchism, 207.

[132] Selected, 170.

[133] Direct Struggle Against Capital: A Peter Kropotkin Anthology

(Edinburgh/Oakland/Baltimore: AK Press, 2014), Iain McKay (ed.), 203,

385

[134] Modern, 223.

[135] Modern, 226.

[136] Direct, 120–1, 464

[137] Modern, 275, 234, 269.

[138] Direct, 490.

[139] Modern, 273, 223, 227.

[140] Modern, 364–6.

[141] Words of a Rebel (Montreal: Black Rose Books, 1992), 143.

[142] Direct, 225, 228, 419–25.

[143] Direct, 500, 680, 344.

[144] Words, 87–9.

[145] Words, 133.

[146] Kropotkin, Anarchism: A Collection of Revolutionary Writings (New

York: Dover Press, 2002), Roger N. Baldwin (ed.), 68.

[147] Kropotkin, The Conquest of Bread and Other Writings (Cambridge:

Cambridge University Press, 1995), 117–21.

[148] Kropotkin, Anarchism, 284. Also see Direct, 229.

[149] Words, 83.

[150] Direct, 188; Also see Direct, 105, 598–9.

[151] Modern, 187.

[152] Modern, 164.

[153] Direct, 504, 500, 131, 475

[154] Modern, 227.

[155] Modern, 367.

[156] Direct, 309.

[157] Direct, 535.

[158] Marx-Engels Collected Works 44: 307.

[159] Interestingly, Errico Malatesta speculated in 1924 that

“associationist” could be used as an alternative to communist by

anarchists as that term was falling into “disrepute as a result of

Russian ‘communist’ despotism.” (The Anarchist Revolution [London:

Freedom Press, 1995], Vernon Richards [ed.], 20).

[160] Engels, 307.

[161] Colin Ward produces similar criteria in “Anarchism as a Theory of

Organisation”, Autonomy, Solidarity, Possibility: The Colin Ward Reader

(Edinburgh/Oakland: AK Press: 2011).

[162] Kropotkin, Direct, 199.

[163] Pateman, Problem, 19.

[164] Kropotkin, Direct, 426.

[165] Pateman, Sexual, 150–1.

[166] Noam Chomsky, Letters from Lexington: Reflections on Propaganda

(Monroe/Edinburgh: Common Courage Press/AK Press, 1993), 127.

[167] Kropotkin, Direct, 160, 187.

[168] Proudhon, Property, 129.

[169] Malatesta, The Method of Freedom: An Errico Malatesta Reader

(Edinburgh/Oakland, AK Press, 2014), Davide Turcato (ed.), 136.

[170] Kropotkin, Direct, 201.

[171] Malatesta and Hamon, No Gods, No Masters: An Anthology of

Anarchism (Oakland/Edinburgh: AK Press, 2005), Daniel Guérin (ed.) ,

370.

[172] Malatesta, Method, 214.

[173] Malatesta, Life, 175, 129.

[174] Proudhon, Property, 655.

[175] Malatesta, Method, 63.

[176] Kropotkin, Direct, 165.

[177] Kropotkin, Direct, 665. As Proudhon put it: “Large industry and

high culture come to us by big monopoly and big property: it is

necessary in the future to make them rise from the [workers]

association.” (quoted by Vincent, 156).

[178] Proudhon, Property, 969, 594–5.

[179] Herbert Read, Anarchy and Order: essays in politics (London: Faber

and Faber Ltd, 1954), 92.

[180] Property, 724.

[181] Bakunin, Political, 353–4.

[182] Kropotkin, Anarchism, 143.

[183] Kropotkin, Conquest, 137–8.

[184] Malatesta, Method, 488–9.

[185] Malatesta, Life and Ideas, 161.

[186] Kropotkin, Direct, 609.

[187] Emma Goldman, Red Emma Speaks: An Emma Goldman Reader (London:

Wildwood House, 1979), Alix Kates Shulman (ed.), 85.

[188] Goldman, 75–6, 87–100.

[189] Orwell in the essay “Politics vs. Literature – An examination of

Gulliver’s Travels” (1946) and le Guin in her classic Science-Fiction

novel The Dispossessed (1974).

[190] Kropotkin, Direct, 368. Also see Direct, 613–6.

[191] See Kropotkin’s discussion of “Revolutionary Minorities” in Words

of a Rebel.

[192] Rudolf Rocker, Pioneers of American Freedom: Origin of Liberal and

Radical Thought in America (Los Angeles: Rocker Publications Committee,

1949), 16–7.

[193] Neither Proudhon nor Bakunin mentioned consensus (in the sense of

unanimous decisions), while Malatesta explicitly and repeated defended

majority decision making. Kropotkin mentioned it a few times, usually in

relation to the peasant villages of his native Russia and once in

relation to the Medieval Commune but also noted that the minority “ended

up accepting with good grace, even if only on trial, the view that

gained support of the greater number.” (Words, 139) It only became

associated with anarchism during the 1960s and the influence of radical

pacifists (often coming from Quaker and other radical religious

traditions) within the peace and other movements.

[194] Modern, 226.

[195] Anarchy (London: Freedom Press, 2001), 42–3.

[196] Kropotkin, Direct, .614. This obviously applies to those who seek

to exclude others from socially used resources. So regarding those who

spuriously invoke “freedom” to justify hierarchies (for example,

discrimination against people of certain skin colours or sexuality from

restaurants), this would not be tolerated in a free society. While

bigots, like all possessors, would be able to control who they invite to

their homes (as it is personally used), socially used resources (such as

a restaurant) would be available to all and any individual or group

acting in such a manner would face the solidarity and direct action of

the wider society. With no State to call upon to enforce such claims,

freedom for all rather than a few would soon prevail.

[197] This is a theme of Ursula Le Guin’s classical Science Fiction

novel The Dispossessed (1974), which addresses the issue well and shows

the importance of individual and minority “self-assertion” against

“crystallised” social structures even in an Anarchy, see my “Ursula Le

Guin and Utopia,” Anarcho-Syndicalist Review 73 (Spring 2018).

[198] The Betrayal of the American Right (Auburn, Alabama: Ludwig von

Mises Institute, 207), 83.

[199] The Ethics of Liberty (Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press,

1982), 170, 173.

[200] Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State and Utopia (Oxford: B. Blackwell,

1974), 270.

[201] Freeden, 55.

[202] Rothbard, 170.

[203] Rothbard, 171, 173.

[204] Freeden, 106.

[205] Rothbard, 145.

[206] This tendency should not blind us to the reality that the State

has always interfered far more in the interests of the wealthy. That

intervention occasionally occurs with a wider remit is due to popular

pressure and because “government cannot want society to break up, for it

would mean that it and the dominant class would be deprived of sources

of exploitation; nor can it leave society to maintain itself without

official intervention, for then people would soon realise that

government serves only to defend property owners […] and they would

hasten to rid themselves of both.” (Malatesta, Anarchy, 25)

[207] Rothbard, 171.

[208] Rothbard, 221–2.

[209] Rothbard, 74.

[210] Nozick, 371.

[211] Pateman, Sexual, 8, 40.

[212] Proudhon, Système I: 75.

[213] Noam Chomsky, Understanding Power: The Indispensable Chomsky (New

York: The New Press, 2002), Peter R. Mitchell and John Schoeffel (eds.),

200.

[214] Freeden, 95.

[215] Freeden, 61, 64, 95.

[216] This applied to propertarianism as well, for many of its leading

lights embraced fascism as a temporary bulwark against the labour

movement and socialism (see my “Propertarianism and Fascism,”

Anarcho-Syndicalist Review 75 [Winter 2019]).

[217] Freeden, 95.

[218] Malatesta, Life and Ideas, 195.

[219] Kropotkin, Great French Revolution, 241.

[220] Malatesta, Life and Ideas, 188–9.

[221] “Objections to Anarchism,” Our Masters are Helpless: The Essays of

George Barrett (London: Freedom Press: 2019), Iain McKay (ed.), 71.

[222] Kropotkin, Great French Revolution, 180.

[223] Voltairine de Cleyre, “A Study of the General Strike in

Philadelphia”, Anarchy! An Anthology of Emma Goldman’s Mother Earth

(Washington D.C.: Counterpoint, 2001), Peter Glassgold (ed.), 311.

[224] Kropotkin, Direct Struggle, 384–5.

[225] Kropotkin, “Must We Occupy Ourselves with an Examination of the

Ideal of a Future System?,” Selected Writings on Anarchism and

Revolution (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1970), Martin A. Miller (ed.), 113.

[226] Kropotkin, Direct, 476.

[227] Albert Parsons, “The International,” The Alarm, 4 April 1885, from

“Precursors of Syndicalism II,” Anarcho-Syndicalist Review 76 (Summer

2019).

[228] Kropotkin, Direct Struggle, 419, 421, 423.

[229] Goldman, 74, 76–7.

[230] Proudhon, Property, 321.

[231] Malatesta, Life and Ideas, 59.

[232] Kropotkin, Anarchism, 137.

[233] Pateman, Sexual, 40, 146, 39, 148.

[234] Proudhon, Property, 29.

[235] Read, 130–2.

[236] Woodcock, Anarchism, 31.

[237] Kropotkin, Modern, 226.

[238] Malatesta, Life and Ideas, 86.