💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › geoffrey-ostergaard-indian-anarchism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 10:37:38. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Indian anarchism
Author: Geoffrey Ostergaard
Date: August 1964
Language: en
Topics: India, anarchist movement
Source: Retrieved on 4th March 2021 from https://libcom.org/library/indian-anarchism
Notes: Published in Anarchy #042: India

Geoffrey Ostergaard

Indian anarchism

TO A SUPERFICIAL OBSERVER OF THE INDIAN POLITICAL SCENE an article on

Indian anarchism might promise to be as brief as the celebrated chapter

on snakes in the natural history of Ireland: there are no anarchists in

India. Other Wes tern ideologies, such as liberalism. nationalism,

communism, democratic socialism and even fascism, have clearly taken

root in modem India but anarchism appears to be conspicuously absent.

The recent publication of Adi Doctor’s book. Anarchist Thought in India

(Asia Publishing House, Bombay, Rs. 8.50), however, shows the error of

this view and at the same time accounts for it. If there appear to be no

anarchists in India, it is because they are ranged behind another banner

imprinted with the word used by Gandhi to symbolise his social

philosophy: Sarvodaya, the Welfare of All [1]. The Indian anarchists

whose theories Doctor expounds and criticises are, in fact, the Mahatma

himself, his major contemporary disciple, Vinoba Bhave, and other

leading figures in the Sarvodava movement such as Jayaprakash Narayan,

Dada Dharmadhikari and Dhirenda Mazumdar.

To pin the anarchist label on these men may appear to be the provocative

act of a critic before leading them to the slaughterhouse reserved for

utopians. Few, if any, of them would use the label themselves and

Jayaprakash Narayan, the most Westernised and sophisticated social

theorist among them, would certainly prefer to be known as a

“communitarian socialist.” However, as Doctor is well aware, “a rose is

a rose is a rose”: when the Sarvodaya doctrine is analysed, it clearly

emerges as a species of the anarchist genus. And, if Western anarchists

wish to know why their Indian counterparts prefer another label, part of

the answer may lie in the persistent and not wholly unwarranted

association in the popular mind between anarchism and violence.

Sarvodaya anarchism is, of course, an anarchism of nonviolence and, like

Tolstoy, its exponents prefer a label which bears no traces of dynamite.

It is not the whole answer, however, because it is doubtful whether more

than a handful of Sarvodayites have found it necessary to define their

philosophy in relation to the ideology of Western anarchism. To most of

them the Sarvodaya doctrine appears to be very much an indigenous creed;

universalistic, no doubt, in its implications but as distinctively

Indian in its origins and colouring as the Mahatma himself. The

Sarvodaya worker dressed in his home-spun, hand-woven dhoti and shirt

and striving for the uplift of his country’s 550,000 villages, feels

himself to be working within the mainstream of the Indian tradition. If,

under Vinoba’s tutoring, he does not reject outright Western influences

but seeks rather a synthesis of (Western) Science and (Indian)

Spirituality, his object is to preserve and to revive what he sees as

the Indian heritage that has been dangerously impaired by two centuries

of Imperialist rule.

Of all the competing social ideologies in Indian today, there can be

little doubt that Sarvodaya is the most distinctively Indian. The

Marxism of the Communist Party and the free enterprise of the Swatantra

Party are clearly exotic creeds. The socialism of Congress claims to be

peculiarly Indian but is patently Fabian in character, except to the

extent that it has been influenced by the Gandhians. It is rather

surprising, therefore, to find Doctor devoting a chapter of his book to

prove that Sarvodaya anarchism has no basis in ancient Indian political

thought. Passing references to an ideal stateless society are to be

found in Vedic, Buddhist and Jaina literature but these represent no

more than allusions to a mythical “golden age” contrasted with man’s

present sinful lot. Hindu political theories, in fact, start from an

assumption of the inherently wicked nature of man and paint a Hobbesian

picture of the strong preying on the weak—“like the fishes in shallow

water”—until men see the wisdom of placing themselves under the

protection of the king. Kingship, tempered and moderated by (the law of

right conduct), was regarded as both natural and necessary if anarchy in

the sense of chaos was to be avoided. Doctor concludes: “If one can

single out any country in which the political philosophy of anarchism

was placed in a coffin, the coffin tightly packed and nailed, and then

buried full six feet deep, then that country was ancient India.”

Doctor is undoubtedly right in his main contention that a philosophy of

anarchism is absent in ancient Indian political thought but his argument

misses the central point about Sarvodaya: its emphasis on non-violence.

The anarchism of Sarvodaya is, in fact, arrived at largely, if not

wholly, by swelling out the social and political implications of the

principle of non-violence. Once this is appreciated, the indigenous

roots of the doctrine become manifest. Now, while nonviolence has been

preached and to some extent practised by many individuals in many

countries and at every stage of culture, it cannot be denied that it has

been a deep rooted and continuous element in the Indian cultural

tradition. Some, indeed, would argue that nonviolence or ahimsa is

“India’s greatest contribution to world-thought” [2]. The apparent

paradox of an emphasis on non-violence combined with an absence of a

philosophy of anarchism in ancient Indian thought is explained by the

fact that, until recent years, ahimsa was seen simply as an ethical

principle for the self-realisation of the individual. It was Gandhi’s

great contribution to make it a principle of social ethics and to insist

on its application to all social relations. Just as he transformed the

old principle of individual passive resistance into the new principle of

satyagraha by showing how it could be used as a form of social protest

and resistance against institutions defined as evil, so he transformed

the old principle of ahimsa into the new social philosophy of

non-violent revolution. Gandhi’s autobiography, My Experiments with

Truth, is essentially a record of the process of transformation of these

two closely related ideas.

Gandhi’s insistence that ahimsa is a principle of social as well as

individual ethics undoubtedly involved a rejection of the ancient Hindu

assumption of the inherent wickedness of mankind. This rejection,

however, was not based on a simple-minded assertion of the contrary

assumption that man is naturally good. “Every one of us,” he asserted,

“is a mixture of good and evil” [3]. But he did believe, most firmly,

that all men have a potentiality for goodness, that “no soul is beyond

redemption,” and that the nature of man is not static or could ever be

made perfect but he did believe that they were perfectible. Indeed, he

seems to have posited an inevitable evolutionary process by which men,

as they gained increasing insight into spiritual “Truth,” would become

progressively less violent. In the era of Belsen and Auschwitz—to cite

only the most glaring symbols of modern bestiality—it has become

fashionable to deride this kind of belief and, not unexpectedly,

Doctor’s criticisms of Sarvodaya doctrine begin by challenging its

assumptions about human nature. It is worth reminding ourselves,

therefore, that the balance of good and evil is not permanently

lop-sided and that the history of mankind does provide some evidence of

what most of us would regard as moral progress. Moreover, while it must

be admitted that presuppositions about the “goodness,” “badness” or

“perfectibility” of human nature are not susceptible to scientific

proof, the Gandhian ones do at least possess the virtue of not

inhibiting the quest for moral progress in the way that the contrary

ones do. What it is possible for men to become, we do not fully know but

the presupposition of perfectibility ensures that men will continue

striving to prize open the limits of the possible. Anarchism is grounded

on at least one indisputable fact. Some men (though not necessarily all

those who have styled themselves anarchists) have found it possible to

develop to a stage where they could live peacefully without the coercive

apparatus of the state. The question then is: If some, why not all? If

Gandhi or Vinoba (and many less saintly men), why not you or me?

Doctor’s failure to bring out the essential relation between the

principle of non-violence and the anarchism of Sarvodaya stems from his

desire to relate the doctrine to the body of Western anarchist thought.

No doubt, to an Indian political scientist the similarities between the

ideas of Sarvodaya and those of the great classical anarchist thinkers

is the most interesting question [4]. To the Western anarchist, however,

it is more interesting and i11uminating to consider the dissimilarities.

The extent of the common ground between Sarvodaya and Western anarchism

is quite considerable. Both aim, in Woodcock’s general definition of

anarchism, “at fundamental changes in the structure of society and

particularly … at the replacement of the authoritarian state by some

form of non-governmental co-operation between free individuals” [5].

Both see the modem state, with its claim to a monopoly of the legal

instruments of coercion, as the great obstacle to a free co-operative

order in which men will really practise self-government. Echoing the

familiar anarchist critique of what now passes as selfgovernment, Vinoba

asks: “If I am under some other person’s command, where is my

self-government? Self-government means ruling your own self. It is one

mark of swarai not to allow any outside power in the world to exercise

control over oneself. And the second mark of swaraj is not to exercise

power over any other. These two things together make swarai—no

submission and no exploitation” [6]. For both the anarchist and the

Sarvodayite, the duty of the individual to obey his own conscience is

the supreme norm, taking precedence over the state’s claim to political

obedience. Neither school, with the possible exception of the Stirnerite

egoists, envisages a society without some restraints on the individual

but both demand that the restraints necessary to maintain an ordered

society be sumitted to voluntarily. Both emphasise the factor of moral

authority in maintaining social control and cohesion and believe that,

given the appropriate social institutions, it could entirely replace

political and legal authority.

In their conceptions of the necessary conditions for the realisation and

maintenance of a society of free, self-governing individuals, again,

there is close agreement. First and foremost is the abolition of the

institution of private property in the means of production. As in the

family, so in society, property is to be held in common, each

contributing according to his capacity and each receiving according to

his needs. For the Sarvodayites in present India this implies the

pooling of the ownership of the village land through gramdan and, for

those outside the villages, a full acceptance of what Gandhi called the

principle of trusteeship-the idea that any private property one may

possess, including one’s talents, is held on behalf of, and is to be

used in the service of, society. With the abolition of private property

goes the abolition of the inequalities it engenders. Both Sarvodayites

and anarchists envisage a society in which individuals are at the same

time free and equal. Absolute equality is, of course, not a feasible

idea, but as Vinoba puts it, the inequality that may be permitted will

be no more than that which exists between the five fingers of one’s

hand. The important point stressed by both Sarvodayites and anarchists

is the need to recognise the equal value, moral, social and economic, of

the various types of work performed by different individuals. Echoing

Kropotkin’s plea for integrated work, Gandhi and Vinoba call for the

abolition of the distinction between intellectual and manual labour and

for the recognition of the dignity of work done with the hands. Part, at

least, of the Sarvodaya emphasis on the charka or spinning-wheel stems

from its symbolisation of the kind of productive work that all men and

women should rightly be expected to perform.

A further important condition of a free society stressed by Sarvodayites

and anarchists alike is decentralisation: social power must be widely

dispersed if tyranny is to be avoided. For the 19^(th) century

anarchist-communists this condition could be achieved if the local

commune were recognised as the basic unit of social organisation.

Enjoying complete autonomy with regard to its internal affairs, it would

be linked on a federal basis with other communes at the regional,

national and international levels for the administration of business

involving relations with other communes. For the Sarvodayites the

villages, in which 80 per cent of India’s population still live, would

be the basic units. Each village would constitute a miniature republic

and be linked with other villages not, as Gandhi put it, in a pyramidal

fashion “with the apex sustained by the bottom.” Rather, the structure

will be ·’ an oceanic circle whose centre will be the individual always

ready to perish for the village, the latter ready to perish for the

circle 0ÂŁ villages, till at last the whole becomes one life composed of

individuals.never aggressive in ther arrogance but ever humble, sharing

the majesty of the oceanic circle of which they are integral units.

Therefore, the outermost circumference will not yield power to crush the

inner circle but will give strength to all within and derive its own

strength from it.” [7] Such a decentralised polity implies a

decentralised economy. Large-scale industry and its concentration in

vast megapolitan centres is to be avoided or reduced to the absolute

minimum. Industries are to be brought to the villages so that it will be

possible for a village, or rather a group of villages, to constitute a

practically self-sufficient agro-industrial community. The present

generation of Sarvodayites do not see this scheme as an attempt to put

back the clock. Less ambiguously than Gandhi, Vinoba does not reject

modern technology. On the contrary, he welcomes it as a means of

avoiding drudgery and increasing production : he insists only that

technology be applied for the welfare of all instead of being used to

bolster a system of human exploitation.

In working for their goal the Sarvodayites join with the classical

anarchists in condemning political action. No good service can be

rendered by the state and those who seek political power, even for

beneficient ends, will inevitably be corrupted. The seat of power,

argues Vinabo, casts a magic spell over those who occupy it. “If instead

of those at present occupying it, we were to occupy it, we would do

things very similar to what they are doing now. The seat of power is

such. Whoever sits on it becomes narrow in outlook. He develops fear and

desires to safeguard himself by keeping a large army”[8]. Parliamentary

democracy stands condemned for several reasons. Despite “the sham device

of voting,” it does not really result in state policy being guided by

public opinion. It involves also the principle of majority rule which

can only mean the tyranny of the majority over the minority, not the

welfare of all. For the Sarvodayites, decisions consistent with the

latter can be reached only through strict adherence to the principle of

unanimity which compels the search for a consensus. Again, parliamentary

democracy involves political parties which are divisive forces and which

seek power by hook or by crook, by vilification of their opponents and

by bribes and threats. “Difference of views is a healthy sign,” says

Vinoba, “and I regard it as necessary and inevitable. But when parties

are formed on the basis of different views, they are less concerned with

ideology than with organisation, discipline and propaganda. The party is

an instrument for attaining political power. And power predominates

while ideas become mere convenient trade-marks used for power and

political rivalry”[9].

In place of political action the Sarvodayites, like the anarchists,

advocate direct action by the people themselves. The politics of the

people must be substituted for the politics of the power-state. People

must become aware of their own strength and learn to solve their own

problems. The revolution can be made only from below, not from above.

The Sarvodaya workers do not constitute a revolutionary party appealing

to the people for support and promising to usher in the millennium. They

exist only to give help and advice: the people themselves must take the

initiative and work out their own salvation.

These and other parallels between Sarvodaya and Western anarchist

thought are important aids to understanding what the movement initiated

by Gandhi and taken further by Vinoba is all about. For an anarchist

evaluation of the movement, however, the divergencies are more

illuminating.

Compared with the mainstream of the Wes tern anarchist tradition, the

most obvious difference is the Sarvodaya attitude towards religion. Of

the great anarchist thinkers discussed by Eltzbacher [10] and Woodcock,

only one, Leo Tolstoy, based his anarchism on religion. Many, perhaps

the majority, of Western anarchists have followed Bakunin in coupling

God and the State and rejecting both for the same reason: their denial

of the sovereignty of the individual. In the West, atheism and anarchism

appear as natural bed-fellows, the twin off-spring of Protestantism when

taken to its logical conclusion. Sarvodaya anarchism, however, is

fundamentally religious. “At the back of every word that I have uttered

since I have known what public life is, and of every act that I have

done,” declared Gandhi, “there has been a religious consciousness and a

downright religious motive” [11]. An unshakable faith in God and an

insistence on the primacy of spirit constitute the core of the

philosophy of most Sarvodayites. But, when this has been said, it is

important to note the catholicity of their religious views. Gandhi and

Vinoba are Hindus but they claim no special status for the Hindu

religion: all religions are merely different ways of finding God.

Moreover, according to the Gandhian conception of religion as that

“which changes one’s nature, which binds one to the truth within and

which ever purifies,” [12] even the sincere atheist qualifies as a

religious man. [13] If the atheist subscribes to a “belief in the

ordered moral government of the universe” [14], then, despite his

denials, he has the essence of religion in him. As if to make it easier

for those who boggle at metaphysics, Gandhi reversed the familiar

equation and asserted, “Truth is God”—adding that this was the most

perfect definition of God as far as human speech could go. [15]

Clearly, for the Gandhians the importance of religion lies in its.

buttressing of the belief in an objective moral order. Belief in God

rules out ethical relativism and moral injunctions, therefore, take on

the character of absolutes. This ethical absolutism provides a further

contrast with the main Western anarchist thinkers who, like Godwin and

Kropotkin, have attempted to provide rational and naturalistic

foundations for their ethical codes. The consequences of this different

approach to ethics are vividly apparent when one considers the contra!

moral principle of Sarvodaya, non-violence. For the Sarvodayites,

nonviolence is not something one argues for or again : it is something

one either accepts or rejects. It is most certainly not a subject for

utilitarian considerations. In this connection, it is necessary to

recall Gandhi’s distinction between passive resistance and satyagraha.

The former is a technique of non-violent resistance which may be, and

often has been, adopted by those who do not rule out the use of violence

in certain circumstances. The choice of this technique may be dictated

by the fact that the resisters have no other effective means of

resistance at their disposal. This kind of non-violence Gandhi regarded

as the non-violence of the weak. Satyagraha, in contrast, is the

non-violence of the strong, a method of resistance adopted because it is

felt to be the only morally right course of action and which would be

used even in those circumstances when the resisters had superior

physical force on their side. As a result of the sorry history of the

use of violence by anarchists in the past and under the impact of the

current campaign for nuclear disarmament, many Western anarchists would

now be prepared to admit the futility of violence but few would accept

non-violence as an absolute moral injunction. At the most, the new

pacifist anarchists would argue that they can foresee no circumstances

in which the use of violence would be justified. This is very different

in theory, if not in practice, from accepting non-violence as a

categorical imperative. The latter, though not the former, involves a

willingness to suspend the rational mode of thinking in terms of cause

and consequence, the mode which now dominates the Western mind.

To complicate the matter still further, the Sarvodayites combine an

absolute commitment to non-violence with a flexibility which, on

occasions, even to Western sympathisers, appears to be outrageously

inconsistent. In part, this flexibility stems from Gandhi’s insistence

that absolute truth cannot be known to the as yet unfulfilled human

mind. He claimed only to be a seeker after Truth, not to have found it.

[16] A human being, however good, can arrive only at relative truth.

Since non-violence is deemed to be the way to Truth, it follows that no

human being can ever achieve perfect non-violence: a person is always.

more or less non-violent; the ideal is achieved only in death. The

combination of this premise with the premise of an evolutionary tendency

towards non-violence which is unevenly distributed among mankind leads

to the conclusion that non-violence resistance, in the Gandhian sense,

is not always possible as a practical policy. It was not possible. for

example, in the Sino-Indian border war of 1962 because the Indian

people, for all Gandhi’s efforts, were not strong enough to adopt

ahimsa.

And since genuine ahimsa is a doctrine of the strong and violence is

preferable to non-violence adopted for cowardly reasons, armed

resistance was justifiable, although of course the Sarvodayites

themselves could not participate in it.

This kind of reasoning leads to a further difference between Sarvoday

and mainstream Western anarchism. The latter is predicated on the

assumption not only that it is possible for men to live an ordered

existence without the state but that it is possible for them to do so

now. ln its extreme form, this assumption finds expression in the

Bakuninite theory of spontaneous revolution according to which the

masses, inspired by the heroic endeavours of dedicated revolutionaries,

would shortly rise to throw off, once and for all, the artificial chains

of the state. Today, some Western anarchists are prepared to countenance

“gradualism” but only faute de mieux, in the absence of a revolutionary

situation. The Sarvodaya anarchists, however, are convinced

“gradualists” : they see the anarchist goal in much the same way as

Godwin did, as something to be reached only after men have become more

perfect than they now are. This position, known in the West as

“philosophical anarchism,” partly explains the apparent inconsistencies

of the Sarvodayites towards the institution of government. Until all

men, or at least a large proportion of them, are fit for

non-governmental society, government, as a matter of fact, will continue

to exist. It seems reasonable, therefore, to try to ensure that society

gets the best government it is presently capable of. For the

Sarvodayites this means at least a democratic government, with all its

faults. Vinoba’s gradualism is quite apparent in his statement

envisaging three distinct stages : first, a free central government;

second, the decentralised self-governing state; and third, pure anarchy

or freedom from all government. [17]

This kind of anarchism seems to come close to the anarchism of the

Marxists with their idea of a transitional stage of socialism between

capitalism and complete communism. Some of Vinoba’s statements in which

he compares his views with those of the Marxists but challenges their

notion that the dictatorship of the proletariat is a step towards the

stateless society, would seem to bear out this interpretation. This,

however, would be a mistake, as can be clearly seen when we consider the

celebrated Gandhian stance on the question of ends and means. Marxist

theorising, like most Western theorising, is in terms of the dichotomy

of ends and means: the end is pure anarchist communism, the means to it

is the dictatorship of the proletariat. Moreover, if the end is good

enough (as it is usually assumed to be), it seems reasonable to hold

that “the end justifies the means.” Gandhian thought, however, rejects

the dichotomy: means and end are part of a continuous process; the means

preceed the end temporally, but there is no question of one being

morally superior to the other. Put in another way, means for the

Gandhians are never merely instrumental; they are always end-creating.

It follows, therefore, that the choice of means determines the end and

that from immoral or even amoral means no moral end can result. It is

essential to grasp this point since it provides the key to Gandhi’s

philosophy of action and represents his most illuminating insight for

social theory. [18]

Applied to the point under discussion—the ultimate goal of a stateless

society—the fusion of means and end implies that there is no transition

period or, what amounts to the same thing, every period is one of

transition. With non-violence as both the means and the end, the

Sarvodayite acts now, according to the principle and as far as he is

able, and thereby achieves the goal he is striving for. For him, as for

Bernstein and Sorel, “The movement is everything; the goal is nothing.”

Commitment to this philosophy of action accounts for yet a further

difference between Sarvodaya and Western anarchism. It would be

incorrect to say that Western anarchists have shown no interest in

constructive activity. The anarcho-syndicalists certainly believed that,

in building up their trade unions, the workers were constructing the

social organisation of the new society. But, in the main, Western

anarchism has been satisfied to echo Bakunin’s famous dictum:

“Destruction is itself a form of creation!” In historical retrospect,

classical anarchism—even syndicalism, now that the unions have proved

broken reeds in their hands—appears essentially as a movement of

protest: a protest against the whole social and political structure of

modern industrial society. At the end of his highly critical eyaluative

chapter, Doctor comes to the same conclusion with regard to Sarvodaya.

But this, surely, is an extremely myopic judgment. Protest, there

certainly is but the Gandhians have never been satisfied with mere

protest. “Be ye also do-ers of the word!” has always been their text.

Bhoodan followed by gramdan and Santi Sena (Peace Army) are only the

latest additions to the Constructive Programme initiated by Gandhi. This

constructive programme includes such items as: communal unity, removal

of untouchability, prohibition, khadi and other village industries, the

emancipation of women, the promotion of provincial and national

languages, the uplift of the peasantry, the establishment of economic

equality, and service to the adivasis or tribal people. [19] Although

Gandhi is best known in the West for his satyagraha campaigns, he

himself attached more importance to constructive work. “If you make a

real success of the constructive programme,” he once told his followers,

“you will win Swaraj for India without civil disobedience.” [20] It is

not possible here to evaluate the constructive work of the Sarvodaya

movement but its importance cannot be denied. The public image of the

Gandhian disciple in India is, in fact, very much that of a social

worker. In reality he is more than that because the motive behind the

work is not merely to relieve suffering but to remove its causes, i.e.,

it is social service with a radical objective.

The item of prohibition in the constructive programme suggests: another

difference between Sarvodaya and Western anarchism: its severely ascetic

character. Western anarchism has had its puritans and “simple lifers”:

indeed, from one perspective, all anarchism may be seen as a plea for

the radical simplification of life—a plea symbolised.

in a bureaucratic world by the passionate slogan, “Incinerate the

documents !” But the asceticism of Indian anarchism extends far beyond

anything found in the West. The loin-clad figure, carrying all his

worldly possessions in a small bundle and without a penny in his purse,

is the Indian ideal. Among the ethical principles, besides ahimsa,

enunciated by Gandhi as necessary for self-realisation are: brahmacharya

which involves not merely sexual continence but complete control over

the senses; aparigraha or non-possession; aswad or tastelessness which

implies looking upon food and drink as a kind of medicine, to be taken

only in the limited quantities necessary to maintain the body; and

asteya or non-stealing which is related to non-possession since it

involves not only not taking that which does not belong to us but also

refraining from taking anything of which we have no real need. The free

and easy relations that characterise anarchist circles in the West and

especially, since Godwin and more particularly since Freud and Reich,

the emphasis on sexual freedom find no echoes in Indian anarchism. And

it is perhaps significant that the only satyagrapha campaign of any

importance sanctioned by Vinoba since Independence was directed against

the use of “obscene” cinema posters in Indore.

Finally, in their theories of revolution there are significant

differences between Sarvodaya and mainstream Western anarchism. The

Sarvodayites see the revolution as in essence a revaluation of values.

[21] The first step in the revolution is to convert individuals, if

possible on a mass scale, to the new point of view by appealing to both

their intellect and their emotions. The new values chosen for emphasis

are those which have a direct bearing on some major problem such as the

plight as the landless labourers, so that their acceptance is likely to

lead to radical social change. As with Tolstoy, the revolution takes

place as a result of individuals beginning here and now to live the

values of the future society. Since the new values are difficult to

practise, a phased programme is contrived so that ordinary men are able

to advance by easy steps towards the new society. Gradually, through

cooperative effort the people proceed to create new institutions and new

forms of social life. The theory is a theory of social change and not

merely a plea for individual regeneration (like Moral Rearmament for

which Gandhi’s grandson is now campaigning in India) because it does

mvolve changing the social structure. But the Sarvodayites place greater

emphasis on transforming individuals because they insist that it is

individuals who start the process of revolution and because they believe

that the desired social structure can be achieved and maintained .only

if individuals are adequately developed morally. In seeking individual

conversion, they direct their efforts to all men and women, without

discrimination by sex, caste, creed or class.

In comparison with classical anarchism (and, of course, with Marxism),

it is the absence of any appeal to class which most distinguishes the

Sarvodaya theory of revolution. In the West, anarchism as a social

movement developed in part as a critique of the Marxist theory of

revolution. From a narrow perspective, the anarchism of Bakunin,

Kropotkin and the syndicalists may be seen as a form of deviation from

Marxism. Not surprisingly, therefore, classical anarchism has much in

common with Marxism, especially in its analysis of capitalist society.

Anarchists, other than the syndicalists, have not assigned to the

industrial proletariat the central role assigned to it by Marxists but

they have always directed their revolutionary appeal primarily to the

oppressed and the dispossessed. They have not expected to enlist the

oppressors, the powerful and the privileged in the cause of revolution.

This is not the place to argue the merits and demerits of either the

Marxist or classical anarchist theory of revolution. But, to a Western

social scientist, it appears a weakness in Sarvodaya theory that it has

neglected the valuable insights into the mechanics of power structures

provided by both Marxists and anarchists. In their absence, the actions

of the Sarvodayites often seem to be somewhat remote from harsh

realities. In defence of the Sarvodayites it may be said that they have

enjoyed some spectacular successes in appealing to the wealthy and

powerful classes. Sneering critics in India are always emphasising the

large proportion of rocky, uncultivable and legally disputed land given

in bhoodan. But what is truly remarkable is that land-gifts including

much valuable land, should be given at all. It should also be remembered

that the Sarvodaya movement is operating in a social context still very

different from that of even 19^(th) century Europe: the Marxist and

anarchist models may not be all that relevant to rural India. (The

industrial urban sector is another matter but, to date, Sarvodaya theory

has failed to encompass this.)

After the defence of Sarvodaya has been made, however, this observer at

least would still sympathise with that minority in the Indian movement

which favours more militant action against the possessing classes. Such

militancy, based on realistic social analysis, would not involve a

rejection of the theory of non-violent revolution. It would mean,

rather, a reversion from what Vinoba calls the “gentle” satyagraha of

the gifts-movement to the “tough” satyagraha associated with Gandhi—but

applied this time against India’s newly emerging ruling class instead of

the Imperialist masters. In the country of Gandhi it is odd that the

first large scale satyagraha campaign since 1947 among the peasants—that

now taking place in Andhra Pradesh—should be promoted by the Communist

Party rather than by Gandhi’s own followers,

In cataloguing some of the major resemblances and differences between

Indian and Western anarchism, I have confined myself to the realm of

ideology. Comparison and contrast in sociological terms would be

essential for a deeper understanding of Sarvodaya. There is no space to

consider this aspect here but one point at least may be made. Indian

anarchism, unlike Western anarchism, is a movement bestowed with

legitimacy. Founded by Gandhi, “the Father of the Nation,” few political

leaders are willing or prepared to deny it that legitimacy. In this

connection, its firm commitment to non-violence and its present lack of

militancy referred to above help to preserve this status. As I see it,

its possession of legitimacy is both a strength and a weakness; but

whether it gains more than it loses by it, is difficult to judge. There

is no doubt, however, that its legitimate status involves it in postures

which the average Western anarchist, accustomed to thinking of himself

as “outside” the dominant social ethos, would find puzzling, to say the

least.

Sarvodaya is not yet a mass movement, despite the millions who have been

touched by it at some point or other, and its future remains

problematical. It is, however, the largest and most effective movement

now working for anarchist goals in any country in the world. Its

existence proves the continued vitality of anarchist ideas. Today, when

there is in the West a revival of interest in these ideas, those

anarchists who are alive to the need to find fresh inspiration for a

renewal of their great tradition from Godwin to Malatesta would be well

advised to study carefully the theory and practice of Sarvodaya. It may

be that we require to call in the East to redress the balance of the

West.

[1] The term “Sarvodaya” was first used by Gandhi as the title of his

translation into Gujerati of Ruskin’s Unto This Last—one of the

important Western influences on his thought.

[2]

G. Dhawan, The Political Philosophy of Mahatma Gandhi, (Navajivan:

Ahmedabad), 3^(rd) ed., 1957, p.8.

[3] Quoted in Dhawan, op. cit., p.104.

[4] Even so, Doctor’s first chapter on Western anarchism pays scant

attention to the one great classical anarchist figure whose thought is

closest to Gandhi’s: Leo Tolstoy.

[5] George Woodcock, Anarchism, (Penguin Books), 1962, p.11.

[6] Vinoba Bhave, Democratic Values, (Sarva Seva Sangh: Kashi), 1962,

pp.13–14.

[7]

M. K. Gandhi, Sarvodaya, (Navajivan: Ahmedabad), 1954, pp.70–1.

[8] Quoted in Doctor, op. cit., pp.57–8.

[9] Quoted in Suresh Ram, Vinoba and His Mission, (Sarva Seva Sangh:

Kashi), 3^(rd) ed., J 962, pp.385. This is the fullest and best history

of the movement for bhoodan and gramdan.

[10]

P. Eltzbacher. Anarchism, 1908.

[11] Quoted in Dhawan, op. cit., p.38.

[12] ibid.

[13] At least one prominent Gandhian is an avowed atheist—Gora (G.

Ramchandra Rao). For an account of his discussions with Gandhi on this

question, see his An Atheist with Gandhi, (Navajivan: Ahmedabad), 1951.

[14] Quoted in Dhawan, op. cit., p.38.

[15] ibid., p.42.

[16] See Joan Bondurant, Conquest of Violence, (O.U.P.), 1959, pp.16–7.

[17] Cited by Doctor, op. cit., p.65.

[18] Gandhi’s views on the means-end question and its importance for

social theory is admirably discussed in Bondurant, op. cit., Ch.VI.

[19]

M. K. Gandhi. Constructive Programme, (Navajivan : Ahmedabad), 2^(nd),

ed., 1945.

[20] Pyarelal, The Last Phase, (Navajivan: Ahemabad), 1956, I, p.44.

[21] For the substance of this paragraph, I am indebted to V. Tandon,

The Social and Political Philosophy of Sarvodaya after Gandhiji,

unpublished Ph.D. thesis. Agra University, 1963.