💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › eric-laursen-only-change-is-permanent.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 09:37:35. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Only Change is Permanent
Author: Eric Laursen
Date: 2021, Summer
Language: en
Topics: the State, marxism, critical theory, anarchist analysis
Source: Fifth Estate #409, Summer, 2021. Accessed Juy 27, 2022 at https://www.fifthestate.org/archive/409-summer-2021/only-change-is-permanent/

Eric Laursen

Only Change is Permanent

Critical theory is a bit like pornography, as a Supreme Court justice

once said when asked to define the latter: “I know it when I see it.”

Critical theory can be defined pretty loosely as well. It’s the

multitude of intellectual spin-offs from Marx that began to take flight

roughly a hundred years ago, at about the time that Lenin and his

acolytes thought they have codified what Orthodox Marxism was, forever.

Starting with Rosa Luxemburg, Antonio Gramsci, and the thinkers who made

up the Frankfurt School in pre-Nazi Germany, the loosely-described

tradition of critical theorists have tried to figure out what comes next

when history stops behaving the way it was supposed to in the 19th

century.

New categories of struggle vie for attention, the State becomes ever

more violent and dominating, and capitalism keeps on adapting. Along the

way, many critical theorists have strayed far from what Marx had in

mind, although they still insist on quarrying the master’s work for

indications that he was moving in the same direction.

Stubbornly, they also resist admitting that the road they’ve taken was

already paved for them and already has a name: anarchism. You can find

any number of thinkers in the Marxist tradition citing texts by Hakim

Bey, the Invisible Committee, Todd May, and others, and invoking

concepts like autonomy and leaderlessness, without acknowledging that

they belong to a distinct anarchist tradition and instead using them as

a grab-bag from which they can pick and choose to bolster their own

theoretical case.

That doesn’t mean anarchists should ignore critical theory. These

writers are grappling with many of the same social and political

problems, and they’ve informed anarchist thinking as much as anarchists

have affected theirs. Theorists like Benjamin, Marcuse, Deleuze,

Foucault, Hardt and Negri, and Said have influenced anarchist thinking

on power, counterrevolution, and cultural domination, just as anarchists

have pushed them more in the direction of decentralization, autonomy,

and leaderlessness.

Anarchists have also made a somewhat parallel journey from their points

of origin. Like Marx, classical 19th century anarchists were imbued with

faith in science and convinced that society was moving toward an ideal

condition of freedom that it would certainly reach if only the world

read or heard its most cogent spokespeople, and acted accordingly.

Now, we’re not so sure. Is any ideal condition conceivable? Isn’t human

history a continuing process of struggle and change, and shouldn’t our

political thinking evolve with it? Don’t the earth and its non-human

inhabitants have their own history that follows its own path?

Critical theory began with a desire to answer some of these questions,

which Marx didn’t do in any easily discernible way. These theorists

wanted not just to understand and explain society, but to figure out how

to change it. What keeps people from doing the logical thing and

overthrowing capitalism and the State? How can we push back against the

power of cultural straitjackets like religion, ideology, racism and

gender oppression?

“The political condition is an endless struggle that does not terminate

in a perfect situation or a utopian state,” writes Bernard E. Harcourt

in a recent book updating critical theory, Critique & Praxis: A Critical

Philosophy of Illusions, Values, and Action, “but goes on forever so

that in the end, the political struggle has to be itself part of the

utopian vision and of what critical theory embraces.”

Recognizing this is just as essential to keeping anarchism practical and

relevant because it keeps us focused on understanding and addressing the

current condition of society, instead of reaching some utopian endpoint

that may no longer make sense by the time we get there. Context, in

other words, is everything. It’s important to remember that anarchism is

supposed to facilitate a larger struggle that keeps shifting as

political and economic conditions change. And we have to make sure we

don’t adopt strategies that replicate the patterns of power we’re trying

to overcome.

Critical theorists today address the same concerns. It is necessary to

move away from the old categories of revolution and instead focus our

energies on insurrectional practices: uprisings, revolts, insurgencies,

resistances, insubordinations, desertions. The difference is that

revolutions—even the most successful, like those that liberated the

colonized world after World War II—generally seek to replace one regime

or one version of the State with another.

We don’t take down capitalism and the State by storming the Capitol and

installing ourselves there the right is perfectly good at that, too—but

by attacking them in a thousand places and in a thousand different ways.

In other words, by creating a social revolution through our activism, as

the Zapatistas, the farmers in India’s Punjab, and the Movement for

Black Lives are all doing. Once we do this, it won’t be so hard to

topple what’s left of the State.

Critical theorists have always emphasized another valuable principle: to

avoid the pitfall of truth-seeking. Claims of truth are always

contingent, in part because the quest for truth is always soaked in the

relationships of power that course through a society defined by

capitalism and the State. Asserting or imposing a truth is a way of

canceling out politics, of masking relations of power in order to

declare victory in the fight for liberation that is never-ending. In

reality, there is no truth, only the struggle for it. Every time a power

regime—like capitalism or colonialism—is overthrown, there is a risk of

establishing a new truth in its place, which in turn has to be

criticized, resisted, and overturned.

In his book, Harcourt argues that critical theory got off track roughly

40 years ago when it became too tied to academic settings, stopped

focusing on how to change society rather than just understand it and

started to produce its own set of supposedly universal truths. But

nothing about anarchism makes it immune to such traps either.

What kinds of truths do we need to avoid? One is the ideal of

liberalism, which a lot of critical theory is devoted to dissecting and

tearing down. Liberalism is built on the myth that a society of laws and

constitutions can leave everyone free to pursue their own ideals without

getting in anyone else’s way. The contention is that there’s no reason,

for example, that NRA members can’t indulge their gun fetish while

African Americans attend church in safety, because the law regulates

their interactions. Do we really believe this?

At the same time, liberals deplore violence—but define the term so

narrowly that it becomes an excuse to avoid acting. Thinkers from

Benjamin to Marcuse have argued that violence is everywhere, from the

violent taking of Indigenous people’s lands to urban policing to slum

clearance to the poisoning of Flint, Michigan’s water supply. We’re just

not allowed to call it that. But actually, political change always

inflicts violence on someone in some form, whether it comes from the

right or the left. Once people understand the nature and impact of

particular forms of violence, it’s a lot harder to convince them that

burning a patrol car, for example, is as heinous as evicting a

low-income family from their home.

Critical theory also raises some thorny issues that anarchists need to

confront. Much of anarchist organizing revolves around a pursuit of

consensus as a basis for action. But consensus relies on people’s

reasonableness or rationality, as Harcourt points out, on the existence

of some kind of rational truth that we can all subscribe to. Consensus,

on the surface, appears to be the least oppressive form of

decision-making. But what if it can produce its own form of oppression:

another way to cancel or deny the fact that politics has always been

about struggle and conflict, and always will be?

Power is another sticky problem. Anarchism is about minimizing or

eliminating the exercise of power by one individual or group over

another, and maximizing cooperation. Critical theorists like Foucault

looked at power in a completely different way; it’s everywhere, in the

air we breathe, circulating all through our social relationships. We

can’t eliminate it, only work with it. The theorists may be wrong, but

it’s up to us to address their point.

Anarchists and critical theorists probably never will find themselves in

complete harmony—particularly on the pivotal matter of the relationship

between the State and capitalism. But we can keep learning from each

other, and sharpening our thinking in the areas where we disagree. What

we share is a desire to make theory something practical, a tool for

sustaining a real and effective opposition to the ever-more enveloping

system of the State and capitalism, not a self-reflexive exercise.

Before we can be effective either as revolutionaries, or

insurrectionists, or autonomists, we need to learn how to be in a world

that makes struggle and emancipation essentially synonymous.

Eric Laursen is a writer and activist and the author of The Operating

System: An Anarchist Theory of the State (AK Press, 2021).