💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › bob-black-debunking-democracy.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 07:54:42. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Debunking Democracy
Author: Bob Black
Date: April 2011
Language: en
Topics: political theory, anarchist analysis,democracy
Source: Scanned from CAL Press Pamphlet Series #2, Printed April 2011.  Proofread online source http://www.revoltlib.com/?id=3860, retrieved on November 30, 2020.
Notes: Scanned from original

Bob Black

Debunking Democracy

For the first time in history, "nearly everyone today professes to be a

democrat." [1] Professors profess democracy profusely, although they

keep it off campus. Democracy—truly, "that word can mean anything." [2]

Even North Korea calls itself a Democratic People’s Republic. Democracy

goes with everything. For champions of capitalism, democracy is

inseparable from capitalism. For champions of socialism, democracy is

inseparable from socialism. Democracy is even said to be inseparable

from anarchism. [3] It is identified with the good, the true, and the

beautiful. [4] There’s a flavor of democracy for every taste:

constitutional democracy, liberal democracy, social democracy, Christian

democracy, even industrial democracy. Poets (admittedly not many) have

hymned its glory. And yet the suspicion lurks that, as it seemed to

another poet, Oscar Wilde, "democracy means simply the bludgeoning of

the people, by the people, and for the people. It has been found out."

[5] Found out, and found to be unfounded.

Until the 20th century, there were few democracies. Until the 19th

century, the wisdom of the ages was unanimous in condemnation of

democracy. All the sages of ancient Greece denounced it, especially the

sages of democratic Athens. [6] As Hegel wrote: "Those ancients who as

members of democracies since their youth, had accumulated long

experience and reflected profoundly about it, held different views on

popular opinion from those more a priori views prevalent today." ** [7]

The Framers of the U.S. Constitution rejected democracy. [8] So did

their opponents, the Anti-Federalists. [9] The democracy which was then

universally despised is what is now called direct democracy, government

by the people over the people. "People" in "by the people" meant the

citizens: a minority consisting of some of the adult males. "People" in

"over the people" meant everybody. The citizenry assembled at intervals

to wield state power by majority vote. This system no longer exists

anywhere, and that makes it easier to believe in it, as Hegel observed.

Democracy only became respectable, in the 19th century, when its meaning

changed. Now it meant representative democracy, in which the

citizenry—now an electorate, but still a minority—from time to time

choose some of its rulers by majority vote (or rather, by the majority

of those actually voting—which is not the same thing). The elected

rulers appoint the rest of the rulers. As always, some rule, and all are

ruled. In the 19th century, when this system prevailed in only a few

nations, it acquired a few intellectually able proponents, such as John

Stuart Mill, but it also evoked some intellectually able opponents, such

as Herbert Spencer, Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, and Friedrich Nietzsche.

Democracy, as one of the ascendant political ideologies of the age,

accommodated itself to the others: to liberalism, nationalism,

socialism, and even Christianity. They in turn accommodated it, usually.

Improbably, the doctrines legitimated one another, usually.

The announced popularity of democracy is surely exaggerated. It’s a mile

wide and an inch deep. Aversion to authoritarian regimes is not

necessarily enthusiasm for democracy. In some of the post-Communist

democracies, democracy has already lost its charm. [10] In others, such

as Russia, democracy itself is already lost. Older democracies persist

more from apathy and force of habit than from genuine conviction. John

Zerzan reasonably asks: "Has there ever been so much incessant yammer

about democracy, and less real interest in it?" [11] Well, has there?

The idea of democracy has never been justified, merely glorified. None

of the older criticisms of democracy has been refuted, and neither has

any of the newer ones. They come from left, right, and center. Some of

these criticisms follow. They establish that democracy is irrational,

inefficient, unjust, and antithetical to the very values claimed for it:

liberty, equality, and fraternity. It does not even, for instance, imply

liberty. [12] Rather, the instinctive tendency of democracy is "to

despise individual rights and take little account of them." [13]

Democracy not only subverts community, it insults dignity, and it

affronts common sense. Not all of these violated values are important to

everyone, but some of them are important to anyone, except to someone to

whom nothing is important. That is why post-modernists are democrats.

In recent years, some intellectuals (academics and former radicals) have

tried to revive direct democracy as an ideal, and set it up as a viable

alternative to representative democracy. Their strenuous exertions

interest only themselves. Their efforts fail, for at least two reasons.

The first reason is that, as a matter of fact, "there is no reason to

believe that there has ever been an urban, purely direct democracy or

even a reasonable approximation of one. Every known instance has

involved a considerable admixture of representative democracy which has

sooner or later usually subordinated [direct] democracy where it didn’t

eliminate it altogether." [14] There is no space to prove it here, but

the evidence is ample. [15] Direct democracy is merely an abstract

ideal, a fantasy really, with no basis in historical experience.

According to Jean-Jacques Rousseau, who is falsely claimed to be an

advocate of direct democracy, "however small any State may be, civil

societies are always too populous to be under the immediate government

of all their members." [16]

The second reason is that the major objections to representative

democracy also apply to direct democracy, even if the latter is regarded

as an ideal form of pure majoritarian democracy. Some objections apply

to one version, some to the other, but most apply to both. There are

more than enough reasons to reject every version of democracy. Let us,

then, consider some of these objections.

Objections to Democracy

1. The majority isn’t always right.

As (among many others) Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, Henry David Thoreau,

Mikhail Bakunin, Benjamin Tucker, Errico Malatesta, and Emma Goldman

said—and does anybody disagree?—democracy does not assure correct

decisions. "The only thing special about majorities is that they are not

minorities." [17] There is no strength in numbers, or rather, there is

nothing but strength in numbers. Parties, families, corporations,

unions, nearly all voluntary associations are, by choice, oligarchic.

[18] Indeed, in assemblies whether direct or representative, in

electorates as in legislatures, the whole is less—even less—than the sum

of its parts. It is even mathematically demonstrable (but not by me)

that majority decision-making generates inefficient, socially wasteful,

more or less self-defeating decisions. [19]

Besides, after all, why should you, why should anyone, accept a decision

that you know is wrong? Surely the quality of its decisions has

something to do with the quality of the decision-making process.

2. Democracy does not as is promised, give everyone the right to

influence the decisions affecting her, because a person who voted on the

losing side had no influence on that decision.

As Henry David Thoreau wrote, "a minority is powerless while it conforms

to the majority; it is not even a minority then." [20] It is, in fact,

powerless, it is nothing. Thomas Hobbes anticipated Thoreau: "And if the

Representative consist of many men, the voyce of the greater number,

must be considered as the voyce of them all. For if the lesser number

pronounce (for example) in the Affirmative, and the greater in the

Negative, there will be Negatives more than enough to destroy the

Affirmatives; and thereby the excesse of Negatives, standing

uncontradicted, are the onely voyce the Representative hath." [21] "The

numerical majority," wrote John C. Calhoun, "is as truly a single

power—and excludes the negative as completely as the absolute government

of one or a few." [22]

3. Democracy especially in small constituencies, lends itself to the

disempowerment of permanent minorities, who occupy the same position in

the democracy as they would in a despotism.

It isn’t always the same momentary majority that rules, but often it is,

and shifting majorities only make it less likely, not unlikely, for some

group to be always opposed to the winning gang. [23] Under American

democracy, it has long been well-known, even to the U.S. Supreme Court

in 1938, that "discrete and insular minorities" are at a political

disadvantage beyond the mere fact (which is disadvantage enough) that

they are minorities. [24] And the smaller the constituency, the more

likely it is that many interests may be represented "by numbers so small

as to be less than the minimum necessary for defense of those interests

in any setting." [25]

4. Majority rule ignores the urgency of preferences.

Preference varies in intensity, but consent does not. Preference is more

or less, consent is yes or no. The vote of a person who has only a

slight preference for a candidate or measure counts the same as the vote

of someone passionately opposed, and so: "A majority with slight

preferences one way may outvote almost as many strong preferences the

other way." There could even be, as just noted, a permanently frustrated

minority, which is a source of instability, or even oppression. To put

it another way, the opportunity to influence a decision is not

proportionate to one’s legitimate interest in the outcome. [26]

Democratic theorists usually ignore the issue or, like John Rawls, wave

it away by dogmatizing that "this criticism rests upon the mistaken view

that the intensity of desire is a relevant consideration in enacting

legislation." [27] But, however embarrassing to democrats, "the

intensity question is absolutely vital to the stability of democratic

systems"—and it’s a question to which pure majoritarian democracy has no

answer. [28] Rousseau at least recognized the problem, although his

solution is impractical. He thought that "the more grave and important

the questions discussed, the nearer should the opinion that is to

prevail approach unanimity." [29] But there is no way in which to decide

a priori the importance of a question. First you have to decide how

important the question is, and the majority may well rule a question to

be unimportant to make sure that the question will be answered as that

majority wishes.

5. There are no self-evident democratic voting rules.

Majority or plurality? Proxy voting? Quorums? Are supermajorities

(three-fifths? two-thirds?) required for all, some, or none of the

decisions? Who sets the agenda? Are motions from the floor entertained?

Who decides who gets to speak, and for how long, and who gets the first

or last word? Who schedules the meeting? Who adjourns it? And who

decides, and by what rules, the answers to all these questions? "If the

participants disagree on the voting rules, they may first have to vote

on these rules. But they may disagree on how to vote on the voting

rules, which may make voting impossible as the decision on how to vote

is pushed further and further back." [30]

6. Collective, all-or-nothing balloting is irrational A decision made on

a momentous matter by a single vote is as valid as a unanimous vote on a

trifle. That extreme rarity, the one time one vote, one person’s will,

makes a difference, is the very same situation—monarchy, dictatorship,

one-man rule—that democracy is supposed to be an improvement on!

At all other times, of all the votes for the winning side, only one is

decisive, so the votes of all but one of the winners, like the votes of

all of the losers, might as well not have been cast.

7. Majority rule is not even what it purports to be: it rarely means

literally the majority of the people. [31]

Many people (such as children, foreigners, lunatics, transients, and

felons) are everywhere denied the right to vote. The disenfranchised are

never much short of being the majority, and sometimes they are the

majority. And since it rarely happens that every one of the eligible

voters votes every time, usually the resulting majority of a majority

means plurality rule, [32] in other words, the rule of the momentarily

largest minority, which might be rather small. The majority of a

majority is often, and the majority of a minority is always, a minority.

In order to cobble together majorities out of incoherent assemblies,

leaders usually wield literally decisive power. [33] Under any possible

government, a minority governs.

8. Whether voting by electoral districts or in popular assemblies,

decisions are arbitrary because the boundaries of the districts

determine the composition of their electorates, which determines the

decisions.

In a democracy, "the definition of the constituency within which the

count is taken is a matter of primary importance," but democratic theory

is unable to say who should be included in an electorate. [34] Redraw

the boundaries and the majority becomes a minority or vice versa,

although no one has changed his mind. The politicians who draw and

redraw the boundaries understand this very well.

9. Then there is the Voter’s Paradox, a technical but very real

contradiction in democracy discovered by Condorcet before the French

Revolution.

In every situation where two or more voters choose from three or more

alternatives, if the voters choose consistently, the majority preference

may be determined solely by the order in which the alternatives are

voted on. It can happen that A is preferred to B, B is preferred to C,

yet C is by the majority preferred to A! [35] This is no mere

theoretical possibility: it has happened in real votes. There are, in

fact, a number of these voting paradoxes. Under ideal conditions,

majority rule almost always produces these cyclical preference orders.

For this and other reasons, "the various equilibrium conditions for

majority rule are incompatible with even a very modest degree of

heterogeneity of tastes, and for most purposes are not significantly

less restrictive than the extreme condition of complete unanimity of

individual preferences." [36]

What that means is that whoever controls the agenda controls the vote,

or, at least, "that making agendas seems just about as significant as

actually passing legislation." [37] It is fitting that a 19th century

mathematician who wrote on this phenomenon (which he called "cyclical

majorities") is better known under his pen name, Lewis Carroll. [38] He

came by his sense of the absurd honestly.

10. Another well-known method for thwarting majority rule with voting is

logrolling.

Logrolling is an exchange of votes between factions. Each group votes

for the other group’s measure, a measure which would otherwise be

defeated because each group is in the minority. (Note that this is not a

compromise because the measures are unrelated. [39] The factions aren’t

splitting the difference.) In a sense, logrolling facilitates some

accommodation of the urgency of preferences, since a faction only trades

its votes for votes it values more highly—but it does so by bribery and

to the detriment of deliberative democracy. No majority really approves

of either measure enacted by logrolling, since if it did, there would be

no need for logrolling. And those whose votes are unnecessary can be

excluded from the logrolling process. [40] The practice is common to

representative and direct democracies. [41]

11. In the unlikely event a legislative body eschews logrolling, it may

succumb to gridlock.

Consider a typical political issue, the building of a highway. (A power

plant or a garbage dump might be an even better example.) Everyone wants

a road, but no one wants it in his back yard. If three groups want a

road—but not in their back yards, thank you—they will gang up to scotch

the project. [42] The road that everyone wants somewhere will not be

built anywhere. That is an even worse outcome than with logrolling,

where at least the road gets built somewhere, and might be of some use

to somebody. It isn’t easy to say which is worse, a democracy that

doesn’t govern, or a democracy that does.

12. Democracy, especially direct democracy, promotes disharmonious,

antisocial feelings.

The psychology of the ekklesia (assembly) is the psychology of the agora

(marketplace): "Voters and customers are essentially the same people.

Mr. Smith buys and votes; he is the same man in the supermarket and the

voting booth." [43] Capitalism and democracy rose to dominance together

as the goals of the same class, the bourgeoisie. Together they made a

common world of selfish individualism—an arena of competition, not a

field of cooperation. Democracy, like litigation, is an adversarial

decision method: "Majority rule belongs to a combat theory of politics.

It is a contest between opposing forces, and the outcome is victory for

one side and defeat for the other." Indeed, as Georg Simmel noticed,

majority rule is really the substituted equivalent of force. [44] "We

agree to try strength by counting heads instead of breaking heads. The

minority gives way not because it is convinced that it is wrong, but

because it is convinced that it is a minority." [45] Literally having to

face an opponent publicly may provoke aggression, anger, and competitive

feelings [46]

In a winner-take-all system there is no incentive to compensate or

conciliate defeated minorities, who have been told, in effect, that not

only are they not to get their way, they are also stigmatized as wrong.

The unaccountable majority is arrogant; the defeated minority is

resentful. [47] Coercive voting promotes polarization and hardens

positions. Deliberation "can bring differences to the surface, widening

rather than narrowing them." [48] These consequences, muted in systems

of large-scale, secret voting in not-too-frequent elections, are

accentuated in the imagined communal combination of very small

electorates, extremely frequent elections, and public voting. Citizens

will take their animosities and ulcers home with them and act them out

in everyday life. Elections are undesirable everywhere, but nowhere

would they be more destructive of community than in face-to-face

assemblies and neighborhoods.

13. Another source of majority irresponsibility and minority indignity

is the felt frivolity of voting its element of chance and arbitrariness.

As Thoreau (quoted by Emma Goldman) put it, ’All voting is a sort of

gaming, like checquers or backgammon, with a slight moral tinge to it, a

playing with right and wrong, with moral questions; and betting

naturally accompanies it." [49] Majority rule is majority roulette. The

popularity of student government and Model UN confirms that there is a

ludic, playing-around element to deliberative decision making which is

independent of its consequences. Here is an interest the delegates share

with each other, but not with their constituents. Voting is a contest,

officially umpired by the majority, with sometimes high stakes. To the

extent that the assembled citizens are playing games with each other, or

that winning for its own sake (or for how you play the game, for that

matter) plays any part in their motivation, the quality of decision

making is reduced still further and the humiliation of submission to

majority rule is that much deepened.

14. Under representative democracy with electoral districts,

malapportionment—the creation of districts with unequal populations—is

possible and, even if they are equal, gerrymandering is almost

inevitable.

Modern democrats agree with H.L. Mencken that "it must be plain that a

community whose votes, man for man, count for only half as much as the

votes of another community is one in which half of the citizens are, to

every practical intent, unable to vote at all." [50] Even if as

currently in the United States, districts are required to be nearly

equal in population, gerrymandering—the drawing of their boundaries so

as to favor some candidate or party is a standing temptation. Especially

since the incumbents do the drawing. Using the latest liberatory

technology—the computer—it’s easy to devise gerrymandered but

mathematically equal districts.

15. Direct democracy trying to avert this evil, embraces federalism,

which increases inequality.

If the neighborhood or face-to-face basic units were

autarchic—self-governing and self-sufficient—it would be nobody’s

business but theirs which people they included and how many. They could

go to hell in their own way. But schemes for direct democracy typically

call for a federal system with layers of "mandated and revocable

delegates, responsible to the base" by which the decisions of assemblies

are reconciled. Some delegates to the higher levels will potentially

speak for a different number of citizens than other delegates but cast

equal votes. In a federal system of units of unequal population, voting

equality for the units means voting inequality for individuals. The

federalist—but single-member—simple-plurality system evidently

contemplated by most direct democrats, including the syndicalists, is

the least proportionate of all voting systems. [51]

The inequality will be compounded at every higher level. The majority;

the majority of the majority; the majority of the majority of the

majority—the higher up you go, the greater the inequality. The more

often you multiply by a fraction, the smaller the number you arrive at.

"It is not possible," it is said, "to find a general answer to the

question of to what extent federalism may legitimately be allowed to

outweigh democracy." [52] Actually, there is a general answer to the

question. The answer is no. A direct democrat who claims that an

overarching confederal system produces majority decisions, [53] affirms

the impossible as an act of faith.

16. Direct democracy, to an even greater degree than representative

democracy, encourages emotional, irrational decision making. [54]

The face-to-face context of assembly politics engenders strong

interpersonal psychological influences which are, at best, extraneous to

decision making on the merits. The crowd is susceptible to orators and

stars, and intolerant of contradiction. [55] The speakers, in the

limited time allotted to them, tend to sacrifice reasoning to persuasion

whenever they have to choose, if they want to win. As Hobbes wrote, the

speakers begin not from true principles but from "commonly accepted

opinions, which are for the most part usually false, and they do not try

to make their discourse correspond to the nature of things but to the

passions of men’s hearts. The result is that votes are cast not on the

basis of correct reasoning but on emotional impulse." [56] "Pure

democracy, like pure rum, easily produces intoxication, and with it a

thousand mad pranks and foolishness." [57] Dissenters feel intimidated,

as they were, for instance, when the Athenian assembly voted for the

disastrous Sicilian expedition: "The result of this excessive enthusiasm

of the majority was that the few who were actually opposed to the

expedition were afraid of being thought unpatriotic if they voted

against it, and therefore kept quiet." [58]

17. A specific, experimentally validated emotional influence vitiating

democracy is group pressure to conform.

This was strikingly demonstrated in a famous experiment by social

psychologist Solomon Asch. Each of seven to nine experimental subjects

was asked to compare a series of lines, and in each case identify the

two lines that were equal in length. For each comparison it was obvious,

indeed extremely obvious, which lines matched—but time after time, every

member of the group gave the same wrong answer—except the only subject

who was unaware of the real purpose of the experiment. In these

circumstances, fifty-eight percent of the test subjects changed their

answer to agree with the unanimous majority. Even when subjects were

each given one ally, thirteen percent of the subjects agreed with the

group instead of the evidence of their senses. [59] Some of the

conformists actually changed their perceptions, but most of them simply

decided that the group must be right, no matter how strong was the

evidence to the contrary.

18. Another inherent flaw in direct democracy partly (not entirely) a

consequence of the previous one, is the inconstancy of policy.

This really covers two related arguments against democracy. What the

assembly does at one meeting it may undo at the next, whether because

citizens have had sober second thoughts (a good reason) or because a

different mix of people shows up (a bad reason). This often happened in

classical Athens, the only polity which has ever seriously tried to make

direct democracy work. For example, the assembly voted to give the

Mytilenians, whose revolt had been crushed, the Melian treatment: death

for all the men, slavery for the women and children. The judgment was

reversed the next day, the second ship dispatched to Mytilene happily

arrived first, and so only the Mytilenians held mainly responsible—over

1,000 of them—were executed. [60] Better, of course, to reverse a bad

decision than stick to it; but people are reluctant to publicly admit

they were wrong.

It is bad enough if the composition of the assembly fluctuates randomly

or because of politically extraneous factors, as the weather, for

instance, influences American election outcomes by influencing voter

turnout [61] (higher proportions of Democrats turn out in good weather).

But it might well turn on deliberate mobilization by a faction. This,

too, happened in Athens. The general Nicias, addressing the assembly in

opposition to the proposed Sicilian expedition, stated: "It is with real

alarm that I see this young man’s [Alcibiades’] party sitting at his

side in this assembly all called in to support him, and I, on my side,

call for the support of the older men among you." A line by the satiric

playwright Aristophanes also attests to bloc voting in the assembly.

[62]

Hobbes observed that "when the votes are sufficiently close for the

defeated to have hopes of winning a majority at a subsequent meeting if

a few men swing round to their way of thinking, their leaders get them

all together, and they hold a private discussion on how to revoke the

measure that has just been passed. They resolve among themselves to

attend the next meeting in large numbers and to be there first; they

arrange what each should say and in what order, so that the question may

be brought up again, and the decision that was made when their opponents

were there in strength may be reversed when they fail to show." [63]

Hobbes exactly describes how Samuel Adams manipulated another assembly,

the Boston town meeting, at prior private meetings of his faction at the

Caucus Club: "Caucusing involved the widest prevision of problems that

might arise and the narrowest choice of response to each possibility;

who would speak to any issue, and what he would say; with the clubmen’s

general consent guaranteed, ahead of time, to both choice of speaker and

what the speaker’s message would be." His cousin John Adams was

astonished, after many years of attending town meetings, to learn of

this: "There they drink flip [a rum drink], I suppose, and there they

choose a moderator who puts questions to the vote regularly, and

selectmen, assessors, wardens, fire wards, and representatives are

regularly chosen before they are chosen by the town." [64] Exactly the

same methods of manipulation were practiced in the Athenian assembly.

[65]

Direct democracy is well suited to machine politics: "The powerful town

meeting [in Boston] named the many municipal officials, determined taxes

and assessments, and adopted public service projects that were a rich

source of jobs and economic largesse. For years the original Caucus and

its allies in the Merchants Club had acted as the unofficial directing

body of the town meeting in which Caucus stalwart Sam Adams played a key

role." [66] This is democracy in action.

What Hobbes is talking about, as he proceeds to say, is faction, which

he defines as "a sort of effort and hard work, which they use to fashion

people." [67] James Madison famously argued that direct democracy

promotes factionalism. [68] But an organization of organizers of votes

serves a purpose (its own) in any assembly or legislature. Parties (the

euphemism for "factions") could play central roles in a direct

democracy, maybe greater roles than in representative democracy.°

Only regular high turnouts would minimize (not eliminate) these

capricious or manipulated reversals, since, if most citizens attend

every meeting, most of them who attend one meeting will attend another.

The polar possibilities are that all the same people, or all different

people, attend the next meeting. If it is all the same people, it is de

facto oligarchy. If it is all different people, it is chaos, the only

kind of "anarchy" consistent with direct democracy. It will usually turn

out to be closer to oligarchy.

Conclusion

Majority rule is as arbitrary as random decision, but not nearly as

fair. [69] For a voter, the only difference between the lottery [70] and

an election is that he might win the lottery. Better pure chance than

"pure democracy, or the immediate autocracy of the people," as Joel

Barlow described it. [71] A celebrant of Swiss direct democracy at its

height admits: "Corruption, factionalization, arbitrariness, violence,

disregard for law, and an obdurate conservatism that opposed all social

and economic progress were pathologies to some extent endemic to the

pure democratic life form." [72] Democracy in any form is irrational,

unjust, inefficient, capricious, divisive, and demeaning. Its direct and

representative versions, as we have seen, share many vices. Neither

version exhibits any clear advantage over the other. Each also has vices

peculiar to itself. Indeed the systems differ only in degree. Either

way, the worst tyranny is the tyranny of the majority, [73] as most

anarchists, and some conservatives, and some liberals, and even the more

honest democrats, have often said.

Is democracy nonetheless the best form of government? Even that is not

so obvious, after taking a hard look at just how bad it is. Its theory

is reducible to ruins in a few pages. The believers claim that democracy

promotes dialogue, but where is the dialogue about democracy itself?

Democrats ignore their critics, as if democracy is such a done deal, why

bother to defend it? They just take it for granted that somebody (Locke?

Rousseau? Lincoln? Churchill?) has long since made out a strong case for

democracy. Nobody ever did. That’s why you didn’t learn it in school.

You were just told to believe. The arguments for democracy—which aren’t

often articulated—are so flawed and flimsy, some of them even so silly,

[74] that pious democrats might be startled. [75]

Now, it may be that some of these criticisms of democratic government

are really criticisms of government itself. That does not detract from,

but rather enhances, their validity. That just means that democracy is

not so special after all, and that it has been found out.

VOTE NOBODY

NOBODY TELLS THE TRUTH.

Bob Black PO Box 3112 Albany NY 12203

[1] David Held, Models of Democrat), (2nd ed.; Stanford, CA: Stanford

University Press, 1996), 1; see also Tibor R. Machan, "Introduction: The

Democratic Ideal," Liberty and Democracy, ed. Tibor R. Machan (Stanford,

CA: Hoover Institute Press, 2002), xiii.

[2] Jacques Ellul, The Political Illusion, tr. Konrad Kellen (New York:

Alfred A. Knopf, 1967), 181.

[3] David Graeber (in the AK Press catalog 2008), quoted in Bob Black,

letter to the editors, Anarchy: A Journal of Desire Armed, No. 67 (Vol.

26, No. 2) (Spring-Summer 2009), 75.

[4] "Democracy is made identical with intellectual freedom, with

economic justice, with social welfare, with tolerance, with piety, moral

integrity, the dignity of man, and general civilized decency." Robert A.

Nisbet, Community and Power (London: Oxford University Press, 1962),

248.

[5] "The Soul of Man Under Socialism." The First Collected Edition of

the Works of Oscar Wilde, 1908-1922, ed. Robert Ross (repr. ed.; London:

Pall Mall, 1969), 8: 294. Wilde was a decadent anarchist dandy. Such

lifestyle anarchists despise democracy. See, e.g., Octave Mirbeau,

"Voters Strike!" in Rants and Incendiary Tracts, ed. Bob Black & Adam

Parfrey (New York: Amok Press & Port Townsend, WA: Loompanics Unlimited,

1989), 74-78.

[6] Ernest Barker, The Political Thought of Plato and Aristotle (New

York Dover, 1959), 13; M.I. Finley, Democrat.; Ancient and Modern (2nd

ed.; London: Hogarth Press, 1985), 5, 29; David Held, "Democracy: From

City-States to a Cosmopolitan Order," in Contemporary Political

Philosophy: An Anthology, ed. Robert E. Goodin & Philip Pettit (Malden,

Mk Blackwell Publishing, 2006), 80.

[7] G.W.F. Hegel, "On the English Reform Bill," Political Writings, ed.

Laurence Dickey & H.B. Nisbet (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

1999), 235.

[8] Bernard Bailyn, The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution

(Cambridge*. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1967), 282284;

Gordon S. Wood, The Creation of the American Republic, 17761787 (New

York & London: W.W. Norton & Company, 1972), 222-223, 409-413; see, e.g,

The Federalist, ed. Jacob E. Cooke (Hanover, NH: Wesleyan University

Press, 1961), 61 (No. 10) (James Madison); The Records of the Federal

Convention of 1787, ed. Max Farrand (New Haven, CT: Yale University

Press, 1911), 1: 2627 (Edmund Randolph), 48 (Elbridge Gerry), 49 (George

Mason), 288 (Alexander Hamilton). Randolph blamed America’s problems on

"the turbulence and follies of democracy:" Records, 1:5 1.

[9] Herbert J. Storing, What the Antifederalists Were For (Chicago, IL &

London: University of Chicago Press, 1981), 29.

[10] Ralf Dahrendorf, Reflections on the Revolution in Europe (New

Brunswick, NJ & London: Transaction Publishers, 2005), 168.

[11] John Zerzan, "No Way Out," Running on Emptiness: The Pathology of

Civilization (Los Angeles, CA: Feral House 2002), 204.

[12] Bertrand Russell, "The Prospects of Democracy," Mortals and Others:

American Essays 1929-1935, ed. Henry Ruja (London & New York: Routledge,

1996), 2: 24; James Fitzjames Stephen, Liberty Equality Fraternity

(Chicago IL & London: University of Chicago Press, 1991), 168.

[13] Alexis de Tocqueville, Democracy in America, ed. J.P. Mayer, tr.

George Lawrence (Garden City, New York Doubleday & Company, Anchor

Books, 1969), 699.

[14] Bob Black, Anarchy after Leftism (Columbia, MO: C.A.L. Press,

1997), 71. Representative democracy can also incorporate minor elements

of direct democracy, as it does, in the United States, with trial by

jury. But representative officials (judges) severely circumscribe the

jury. Robert C. Black, "FIJA: Monkeywrenching the Justice System?," UMKC

Law Review 66(1) (Fall 1997), 12-13.

[15] Bob Black, Nightmares of Reason (2010), chs. 14 & 15, available

online from The Anarchist Library.

[16] Jean-Jacques Rousseau, "Discourse on Political Economy," The Social

Contract and Discourses, tr. G.D.H. Cole (New York: E.P. Dutton and Sons

& London: J.M. Dent and Sons, 1950), 313.

[17] Loren E. Lomasky, "Default and Dynamic Democracy," in Liberty and

Democracy, 3.

[18] Clark Kerr, Unions and Union Leaders of Their Own Choosing (New

York The Fund for the Republic, 1957), 12. Similarly, Switzerland’s

democracy is the most participatory in the world, but the Swiss are not

" particularly participative in economic and social life." Wolf Linder,

Swiss Democracy (3rd ed., rev. & upci.; Basingstoke, Hamps., England &

New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2010), 127.

[19] Grant McConnell, Private Power and American Democracy (New York

Vintage Books, 1966), 120-127; James M. Buchanan & Gordon Tullock, The

Calculus of Consent: Logical Foundations of Constitutional Democracy

(Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press, 1962), 169; Elaine Spitz,

Majority Rule (Chatham, NJ: Chatham House Publishers, 1982); 153;

Michael Taylor, Community, Anarchy and Liberty (Cambridge: Cambridge

University Press, 1982), 54-55.

[20] Henry David Thoreau, "Civil Disobedience," in Walden and Civil

Disobedience (New York: Signet Classics, 1960), 231.

[21] Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, ed. C.B. Macpherson (Harmondsworth,

Middlesex, England: Pelican Books, 1968), 221.

[22] John C. Calhoun, Disquisitions on Government and Selections from

the Discourses (Indianapolis, IN & New York: Bobbs-Merrill Co., 1953),

29.

[23] Spitz, Majority Rule, 183; Juerg Steiner, "Decision-Making," in

Encyclopedia of Democratic Thought, ed. Paul Barry Clarke & Joe

Foweracker (London & New York Routledge, 2001), q/v "Decision-Making."

[24] United States v. Carolene Products Co., 304 U.S. 144, 152-53 n. 4

(1938).

[25] MacConnell, Private Power and American Democracy, 105 (quoted),

109.

[26] John Burnheim, Is Democracy Possible? Alternatives to Electoral

Politics (Cambridge, England: Polity Press, 1985), 83 (quoted); Jeremy

Waldron, The Dignity of Legislation (Cambridge & New York: Cambridge

University Press, 1999), 132, 142-143; Buchanan & Tullock, Calculus of

Consent, 125-127, 132-133; Robert A. Dahl, A Preface to Democratic

Theory (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1956), 91-99; Robert

A. Dahl, Dilemmas of Pluralist Democracy: Autonomy vs. Control (New

Haven, CT & London: Yale University Press, 1982), 88-89.

[27] John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (rev. ed.; Cambridge: Harvard

University Press, Belnap Press, 1999), 230.

[28] Benjamin Barber, The Conquest of Politics: Liberal Philosophy in

Democratic Times (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1988), 79

(quoted); Willmoore Kendall & George W. Carey, "The ’Intensity’ Problem

and Democratic Theory," American Political Science Review 62(1) (March

1968): 5-24.

[29] Rousseau, "The Social Contract," The Social Contract and

Discourses, 107.

[30] Steiner, "Decision-Making," 130.

[31] Spitz, Majority Rule, 3.

[32] John Stuart Mill, "Representative Government," in Utilitarianism,

Liberty and Representative Government (New York: E.P. Dutton and Company

& London: J.M. Dent and Sons, 1951), 346-347; Harold Barday, People

Without Government An Anthropology of Anarchism (London: Kahn & Averill

with Cienfuegos Press, 1982), 118; Linder, Swiss Democracy, 110.

[33] "The necessity for these leaders is evident, since, under the name

of heads of groups, they are met with in the assemblies of every

country. They are the real rulers of an assembly." Gustav Le Bon, The

Crowd (New York: Compass Books, 1960), 189.

[34] Peter J. Taylor, Graham Gudgin, & R.I. Johnston, "The Geography of

Representation: A Review of Recent Findings," in Electoral Laws and

Their Political Consequences, ed. Bernard Grofman Aren Lijphart (New

York: Agathon Press, 1986), 183-184; McConnell, Private Power and

American Democracy, 92 (quoted); Dahl, Dilemmas of Pluralist Democracy,

97-99; Bruce E. Cain, The Reapportionment Puzzle (Berkeley, CA:

University of California Press, 1984), 36-37.

[35] Kenneth Arrow, Social Choice and Individual Values (2d ed.; New

York: John Wiley & Sons, 1963), 2-3, 94-95; An Essay on the Application

of Probability Theory to Plurality Decision-Making (1785)," in

Condorcet: Foundations of Social Choice and Political Theory, tr. & ed.

lain McLean & Fiona Hewitt (Aldershot, Hants, England & Brookfield, VT:

Edward Elgar Publishing, 1994), 120130. A certain Rev. Dodgson invented

the notion of "None of the Above" as a ballot option. "A Method of

Taking Votes on More Than Two Issues," in The Political Pamphlets and

Letters of Charles Lutwidge Dodgson and Related Pieces: A Mathematical

Approach, ed. Francine F. Abeles (New York: Lewis Carroll Society of

North America, 2001), 95. Since Arrow’s Impossibility Theorem, "the

theoretical case that elections can assure desirable outcomes was dealt

a blow from which it is unlikely ever to recover fully." William R.

Keech, "Thinking About the Length and Renewability of Electoral Terms,"

in Electoral Laws and Their Political Consequences, 104.

[36] William H. Riker & Barry R. Weingast, "Constitutional Regulation of

Legislative Choice: The Political Consequences of Judicial Deference to

Legislatures," Working Papers in Political Science No. P-86-11

(Stanford, CA: Hoover Institution, 1986), 13-18 (real-life examples of

perpetual cyclical majorities); Hanno Nurmi, Voting Paradoxes and How to

Deal With Mem (Berlin, Germany: Springer, 1999); Peter C. Fishburn,

"Paradoxes of Voting," American Political Science Review 68(2) (June

1974): 537-546 (five more paradoxes); Gerald H. Kramer, "On a Class of

Equilibrium Conditions for Majority Rule," Econometrica 41(2) (March

1973), 285 (quoted). The only reason cyclical preference orders are not

more common in real life is the influence of other undemocratic

practices such as logrolling (see below).

[37] Ian Shapiro, "Three Fallacies Concerning Majorities, Minorities,

and Democratic Politics," in NOMOSXXIII.* Majorities and Minorities, ed.

John W Chapman & Alan Wertheimer (New York & London: New York University

Press, 1990), 97; William H. Riker, "Introduction," Agenda Formation,

ed. William H. Riker (Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press,

1993), 1 (quoted).

[38] "Method of Taking Votes on More Than Two Issues," 46-58; Robert

Paul Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism (New York Harper Torchbooks, 1970),

59-63; Arrow, Social Choice and Individual Values, 94.

[39] Buchanan & Tullock, Calculus of Consent, 132-133; Burnheim, Is

Democracy Possible?, 6; McConnell, Private Power and American Democracy,

111-112.

[40] John T. Noonan, Jr., Bribery (New York: Macmillan & London: Collier

Macmillan Publishers, 1984), 580; Clayton P. Gillette, "Equality and

Variety in the Delivery of Municipal Services," Harvard Law Review

100(1) (Nov. 1986), 959. In 12th century Italy, Genoa and Pistoia

prohibited logrolling in consular elections. Lauro Martines, Power and

Imagination: City-States in Renaissance Italy (New York: Alfred A.

Knopf, 1979), 29. Such laws are in vain: "The laws against logrolling

(probably passed in part through logrolling) have substantially no

effect on the functioning of democracy in countries which have adopted

them." Gordon Tullock, The Vote Motive (n.p.: The Institute of Economic

Affairs, 1976), 41. They only invite secrecy and hypocrisy. The

two-thirds majority of states for the adoption of the Thirteenth

Amendment to the U.S. Constitution abolishing slavery was obtained by

logrolling. Noonan, Bribery, 456-458.

[41] See, e.g., Tullock, The Vote Motive, 45-46. Referenda, another

expression of direct democracy, provide "the dearest example" of

logrolling, putting to a single vote unrelated measures grouped together

to appeal to a majority. Ibid., 48-49. Some state constitutions try to

prohibit induding more than one subject in each ballot proposal. These

provisions are notoriously ineffective They are also undemocratic

themselves, because the judiciary is then the final arbiter. In a

political system without checks and balances, democracy is tyranny. But

a political system with checks and balances is not a democracy.

[42] Nicholas Rescher, "Risking D: Problems of Political Decision,"

Public Affairs Quarterly 13(4) (Oct. 1999), 298.

[43] Tullock, Vote Motive, 5. Moral considerations aside (where they

belong), majority rule with logrolling may lead to inefficient

outcomes—peak efficiency requires, surprisingly, supermajorities:

"Majority rule is thus generally not optimal." Ibid., 51-55, 55

(quoted).

[44] "The Phenomenon of Outvoting," The Sociology of Georg Simmel, ed.

Kurt H. Wolff (New York: The Free Press & London: Collier-Macmillan,

1950), 241-242.

[45] Stephen, Liberty Equality Fraternity, 70.

[46] Spitz, Majority Rule, 192 (quoted); Arend Lijphart, Encyclopedia of

Democratic Thought, q/v "Consensus Democracy" (majoritarian democracy is

"exclusive, competitive and adversarial"); Jane L. Mansbridge, Beyond

Adversary Democracy (New York: Basic Books, 1980), 273. Mansbridge adds

that because it is distressing to face a hostile majority, the meeting

exerts pressure for conformity. Highly motivated militants may just wear

down and outlast the others: "The Lower and Weaker Faction, is the

firmer in Conjunction: And it is often scene, that a few, that are

Stiffe, doe tire out, a greater Number, that are more Moderate." Francis

Bacon, "Of Faction," The Essayes or Counsels, Civill and Morall, ed.

Michael Kiernan (Cambridge Harvard University Press, 1985), 155 (essay

no. LI.). Not the least of the many serious inequalities which inhere in

the assembly is the inequality between extraverts and introverts.

Assembly government discourages attendance by the kind of person who

does not like to be in the same room with, say, Murray Bookchin or Peter

Staudenmeier.

[47] "To see the proposal of a man whom we despise preferred to our own;

to see our wisdom ignored before our eyes; to incur certain enmity in an

uncertain struggle for empty glory; to hate and be hated because of

differences of opinion (which cannot be avoided, whether we win or

lose); to reveal our plans and wishes when there is no need to and to

get nothing by it; to neglect our private affairs. These, I say, are

disadvantages." Thomas Hobbes, On the Citizen, ed. & tr. Richard Tuck &

Michael Silverthorne (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), 120.

[48] Ian Shapiro, "Optimal Participation?" journal of Political

Philosophy 10(2) (June 2002), 198-199.

[49] Thoreau, "Civil Disobedience," 226, quoted in "Anarchism: What It

Really Stands For," Emma Goldman, Red Emma Speaks: Selected Writings and

Speeches, ed. Alix Kates Shulman (New York: Vintage Books, 1972), 60;

Waldron, Dignity of Legislation, 126-127.

[50] H.L. Mencken, Notes on Democracy (New York: Alfred A, Knopf, 1926),

89 (quoted); see also Dahl, Dilemmas of Pluralist Democracy: Autonomy,

83-84.

[51] Sally Burch, Encyclopedia of Democratic Thought, q/v "Electoral

Systems."

[52] Linder, Swiss Democracy, 84. In the Swiss system, the vote of one

citizen in Uri, a small rural canton, outweighs the votes of 34 citizens

in Zurich. Ibid., 81.

[53] E.g., Murray Bookchin, Anarchism, Marxism, and the Future of the

Left, 1993-1998 (Edinburgh, Scotland & San Francisco, CA: A.K. Press,

1999), 314.

[54] "The general characteristics of crowds are to be met with in

parliamentary assemblies: Intellectual simplicity, irritability,

suggestibility, the exaggeration of the sentiments and the

preponderating influence of a few leaders." Le Bon, The Crowd, 187.

[55] Robert Michels, Political Parties: A Sociological Study of the

Oligarchical Tendencies of Modern Democracy (New York The Free Press &

London: Collier-Macmillan Limited, 1962), 64, 98-102. For anyone who has

doubts about democracy, this is the first book to read.

[56] Hobbes, The Citizen, 123; see also Sigmund Freud, Group Psychology

and the Analysis of the Ego, tr. & ed. James Strachey (New York: W.W.

Norton & Company, 1959), 9; Le Bon, The Crowd 187.

[57] John Jay quoted in Lift of john fax ed. William Jay (New York J. &

J. Harper, 1833), 2: 315. Jay, co-author of The Federalist, was the

first Chief Justice of the U.S. Supreme Court.

[58] Thucydides, History of the Peloponnesian War, tr. Rex Warner

(London: Reagan Books, 1951), 425.

[59] Solomon E. Asch, Social Psychology (Englewood Cliffs, NJ:

Prentice-Hall, 1952), 458, 477.

[60] Finley, Democracy, 52; Hegel, "On the English Reform Bill," 235;

Thucydides, Peloponnesian War, 212-223.

[61] Russell Hardin, Encyclopedia of Democratic Thought,

"Participation."

[62] Thucydides, Peloponnesian War, 417 (quoted); "Ecclesiazusai,"

Aristophanes: Plays II, tr. Patric Dickinson (London: Oxford University

Press, 1970), 2: 256.

[63] Hobbes, On the Citizen, 124.

[64] Gary Wills, Inventing America: Jefferson’s Declaration of

Independence (Garden City, NY: Doubleday & Company, 1978), 20 (quoted),

23 (quoting John Adams). The Bostonians recreated the smoke-filled room

at the Continental Congress, where Jefferson noticed that "[Samuel

Adams] was constantly holding caucuses of distinguished men, among whom

was Richard Henry Lee, at which the generality of the measures pursued

were previously determined on, and at which the parts were assigned to

the different actors who afterwards appeared in them." Quoted in ibid.,

25.

[65] R.K.Sinclair, Democracy and Participation in Ancient Athens

(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998), 144-145.

[66] Richard Maxwell Brown, "Violence and the American Revolution," in

Essay; on the American Revolution, ed. Stephen G. Kurtz & James H.

Hutson (Chapel Hill, NC: University of North Carolina Press & New York

W.W. Norton & Co., 1973), 102.

[67] Hobbes, On the Citizen, 124.

[68] James Madison, The Federalist No. 10, at 56-57.

[69] Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism, 44-45.

[70] Thus "universal suffrage is in my eyes nothing but a lottery:"

Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, General Idea of the Revolution in the Nineteenth

Century, tr. John Beverley Robinson (London: Freedom Press, 1923), 141.

[71] Joel Barlow, "To His Fellow Citizens of the United States. Letter

II: On Certain Political Measures Proposed for Their Consideration," in

American Political Writing during the Founding Era, 1760-1805, ed.

Charles S Hyneman & Donald S. Lutz (2 vols.; Indianapolis, IN: Liberty

Fund, 1983), 2: 1106.

[72] Benjamin Barber, The Death of Communal Liberty (Princeton, NJ:

Princeton University Press, 1974), 197.

[73] e.g., Goldman,"The Individual, Society and the State," Red Emma

Speaks, 98; see also Robert L Hoffman, Revolutionary Justice: The Social

and Political Theory of P-J. Proudhon (Urbana, IL: University of

Illinois Press, 1972), 187. The expression is generally credited to

Alexis de Tocqueville (Democracy in America, 250) and it was further

popularized by John Stuart Mill; but it was used by at least one

Anti-Federalist in the Ratification debate. Wood, Creation of the

American Republic, 484 & n. 19. Certainly the idea was widespread then,

and since.

[74] For example, voluntary residence in a country is said to be "tacit"

consent to its democratic government. Love it or leave it! Incredibly,

most democrats fail to notice that if voluntary residence counts as

consent to be ruled, then it counts as consent to be ruled by any

government, despotic or democratic. Harry Brighouse, "Democracy and

Inequality," in Democratic Theory Today: Challenges for the 21st

Century, ed. April Carter & Geoffrey Stokes (Cambridge, England: Polity

Press, 2002), 56; J.P. Plamanatz, Consent, Freedom, and Political

Obligation (2nd ed.; London: Oxford University Press, 1968), 7-8; A.

John Simmons, Moral Principles and Political Obligations (Princeton, NJ:

Princeton University Press, 1979), 7374 & ch. 4. In the anthology

Democratic Theory Today, the eleven contributors—all of them college

professors—solemnly discuss civic republicanism, developmental

democracy, deliberative democracy, associative democracy, etc. Not one

of them pauses to justify democracy itself.

[75] See, e.g., William Godwin, Enquiry Concerning Political Justice,

ed. Isaac Kramnick (Harmondsworth, Middlesex, England: Penguin Books,

1976), 209-253; Crispin Sartwell, Against the State (Albany, NY: State

University of New York Press, 2008), 39-96 (quoted); Bob