💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › gustav-landauer-anarchism-socialism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 10:34:50. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Anarchism — Socialism Author: Gustav Landauer Date: 1895 Language: en Topics: anarchism, labor, socialism Source: Journal for Anarchism and Socialism Notes: From Gustav Landauer, Revolution and Other Writings: A Political Reader (Gabriel Kuhn, Trans., ed.), Oakland: PM Press, 2010): p. 70–74.
Journal for Anarchism and Socialism — this is what our paper says.
Anarchism is the goal that we pursue: the absence of domination and of
the state; the freedom of the individual. Socialism is the means by
which we want to reach and secure this freedom: solidarity, sharing, and
cooperative labor.
Some people say that we have turned things upside down by making
anarchism our goal and socialism our means. They see anarchy as
something negative, as the absence of institutions, while socialism
indicates a positive social order. They think that the positive part
should constitute the goal, and the negative the means that can help us
to destroy whatever keeps us from attaining the goal. These people fail
to understand that anarchy is not just an abstract concept of freedom
but that our notions of a free life and of free activity include much
that is concrete and positive. There will be work — purposeful and
fairly distributed; but it will only be a means to develop and
strengthen our rich natural forces, to impact our fellow human beings,
culture, and nature, and to enjoy society’s riches to the fullest.
Anyone who is not blinded by the dogmas of the political parties will
recognize that anarchism and socialism are not opposed but co-dependent.
True cooperative labor and true community can only exist where
individuals are free, and free individuals can only exist where our
needs are met by brotherly solidarity.
It is mandatory to fight the false social democratic claims that
anarchism and socialism are as opposed as “fire and water.” Those who
make such claims usually argue thus: Socialism means “socialization.”
This means in turn that society — a vague term usually encompassing all
human beings who inhabit the earth — will be amalgamated, unified, and
centralized. The so-called “interests of humanity” become the highest
law, and the specific interests of certain social groups and individuals
become secondary. Anarchism, on the other hand, means individualism,
i.e., the desire of individuals to assert power without limits; it
spells atomization and egoism. As a result, we have incompatible
opposites: socialization and individual sacrifice on the one hand;
individualization and self-centeredness on the other.
I think that it is possible to illustrate the shortcomings of these
assumptions by a simple allegory. Let us imagine a town that experiences
both sunshine and rain. If someone suggested that the only way to
protect the town against rain is to build a huge roof that covers
everything and that will always be there whether it rains or not, then
this would be a “socialist” solution according to the social democrats.
On the other hand, if someone suggested that, in the case of rain, each
individual should grab one of the town’s umbrellas and that those who
come too late are simply unlucky, then this would be an “anarchist”
solution. For us anarchist socialists both solutions appear ridiculous.
Neither do we want to force all individuals under a common roof nor do
we want to end up in fistfights over umbrellas. When it is useful, we
can share a common roof — as long as it can be removed when it is not
useful. At the same time, all individuals can have their own umbrellas,
as long as they know how to handle them. And with regard to those who
want to get wet — well, we will not force them to stay dry.
Leaving allegories aside, what we need is the following: associations of
humankind in affairs that concern the interests of humankind;
associations of a particular people in affairs that concern the
interests of a particular people; associations of particular social
groups in affairs that concern particular social groups; associations of
two people in affairs that concern the interests of two people;
individualization in affairs that concern the interests of the
individual.
Instead of both the national state and of the world state that the
social democrats dream of, we anarchists want a free order of multiple,
intertwined, colorful associations and companies. This order will be
based upon the principle that all individuals are closest to their own
interests, and that their shirts are closer to them than their jackets.
It will rarely be necessary to address all of humankind in order to deal
with a specific problem. Hence, there is no need for a global parliament
or any other global institution.
There are affairs that concern all of humankind, but in such cases the
different groups will find ways to reach common solutions. Let us take
the matter of international transport and its intricate train schedules
as an example. Here, the representatives of each country find solutions
despite the absence of a higher coordinating power. The reason is
simple: necessity demands it. It is hence hardly surprising that I find
the Reichskursbuch the only bureaucratic publication worth reading. [1]
I am convinced that this book will receive more honors in the future
than the law books of all nations combined!
Other affairs that will need global attention are measurements,
scientific and technical terms, and statistics, which are of great
importance for economic planning and other purposes. (Although, they are
much less important than what the social democrats think, who want to
make them the throne on which to build the people’s global domination.)
Those who are not condemned to ignorance by the conditions that the
powerful force upon them will soon make appropriate use of statistics
without any global institution. There will probably be a global
organization of some kind that compiles and compares different
statistical data, but it will not play a very significant role and will
never constitute a powerful political force.
Are there common interests within a nation? There are some: language,
literature, arts, customs, and rituals all have specific national
characteristics. However, in a world without domination, without
“annexed territories” and the concept of “national land” (land that has
to be defended and enlarged), such interests will not mean what they
mean today. The concept of “national labor,” for example, will disappear
altogether. Labor will be structured in ways that do not follow language
or ethnography. For labor conditions in local communities, both
geography and geology are very important. But what do our nation states
have to do with these realities? (As far as the differences in language
go, they pose much less of a challenge than generally imagined.)
Speaking of labor, there are different currents within the anarchist
camp. Some anarchists propagate the right to free consumption. They
believe that all individuals shall produce according to their abilities
and consume according to their needs. They maintain that no one but the
individual can know what his or her abilities and needs are. The vision
is to have storehouses filled by voluntary labor according to people’s
needs. The labor will be done because each individual will understand
that the satisfaction of everyone’s needs demands a collective effort.
Statistics and information on labor conditions in specific communities
will provide the guidelines for how much to produce and for how much
work will be necessary, taking into account both the technology and the
overall workforce. The need for laborers will be announced publicly to
all those who are eligible. Those who refuse to work — entirely or
partly — even though they could, will be socially ostracized.
I think that this is an accurate and unbiased summary of the ideas of
the communists. I now want to explain why I consider these notions of
labor organization insufficient and unjust.
I do not deem them impossible. I believe that communism and the right to
free consumption can exist. However, I do believe that many people will
choose not to work. Social ostracization will matter little to them —
they can be assured of mutual support and respect among their peers.
This is not the biggest problem though. The biggest problem is that a
new moral authority will be created; a moral authority that declares
those the “best human beings” who work the hardest, who are ready to do
the most difficult and the dirtiest work, and who make sacrifices for
the weak, the lazy, and the freeloaders. The constraint of such a
morality and the social rewards it promises will be far worse and far
more dangerous than the most acceptable constraint we know: egoism. I
have reached this opinion after a lot of contemplation. A society based
on the constraint of morality will be far more one-dimensional and
unjust than a society based on the constraint of self-interest.
Anarchists who share this opinion see a connection between the labor of
individuals and their consumption. They want to organize labor on the
basis of natural egoism. This means that those who work will primarily
work for themselves. In other words, those who join a particular line of
work will do so because they expect certain personal advantages from it;
those who work more than others will do so because they have more needs
to satisfy; those who do the most difficult and the dirtiest work (work
that will always have to be done, even if in a less gruesome manner than
today) will do so because — contrary to today — this work will be the
most valued and highest paid.
The critique of this kind of organization of labor is mainly three-fold:
first, one sees it as an injustice against the intellectually or
physically weak; second, one is afraid that individual riches will be
accumulated and that new forms of exploitation will arise; third, one is
concerned that an exclusive class of producers will gain and defend
privileges.
I consider all of these concerns unfounded. It is true that there will
be a differentiation of labor. However, if people are well educated and
their talents well nourished, then everyone will easily find work that
suits his or her qualifications. Some will find intellectual labor
suitable for them, some manual labor, etc. Those who are unable to work
— the disabled, the old — will be provided for in many ways, just like
children are provided for. The principle of mutual aid will be central.
It will be impossible for individuals to accumulate riches leading to
exploitation, as everyone in an anarchist society will understand that
common usage of the land and the means of production is in their
individual interest. As a result, those who work the hardest might gain
advantages in terms of personal property, but they will not gain any
means of exploitation.
Finally, no group would gain anything by becoming exclusive. They would
instantly be boycotted. If a certain group were ever to gain an
advantage in a certain area of production, new producers would appear
and it would not be long before a fair balance was reestablished. When
workers come and go freely and when there is truly free competition
among equal men, then permanent inequalities are rendered impossible.
It is not inconceivable that the organization of labor, as I have
outlined it above, might take two forms simultaneously in different
regions or in different fields of labor. Practical experience will soon
determine the form that is most feasible. In any case, the goal of both
forms is the same: the freedom of the individual on the basis of
economic solidarity. There is no reason to argue about the
organizational details of the future society. It is much more important
to combine our forces to establish the social conditions allowing for
the practical experiences that will determine these matters.
Anarchy is no lifeless system of ready-made thoughts. Anarchy is life;
the life that awaits us after we have freed ourselves from the yoke.
Â
[1] Reichskursbuch: former national German train schedule.