💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › georges-palante-anarchism-and-individualism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 10:38:31. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Anarchism and Individualism
Author: Georges Palante
Date: 1909
Language: en
Topics: anarchism, individualist
Source: http://www.marxists.org/archive/palante/1909/individualism.htm
Notes: Source: La Sensibilité individualiste. Paris, Alcan, 1909;  Translated: by Mitchell Abidor for marxists.org;  CopyLeft: Creative Commons (Attribute & ShareAlike) marxists.org 2006.

Georges Palante

Anarchism and Individualism

The words anarchism and individualism are frequently used as synonyms.

Many thinkers vastly different from each other are carelessly qualified

sometimes as anarchists, sometimes as individualists. It is thus that we

speak indifferently of Stirnerite anarchism or individualism, of

Nietzschean anarchism or individualism, of Barrésian anarchism or

individualism, etc. In other cases, though, this identification of the

two terms is not looked upon as possible. We commonly say Proudhonian

anarchism, Marxist anarchism, anarchist syndicalism. But we could not

say Proudhonian, Marxist, or syndicalist individualism. We can speak of

a Christian or Tolstoyan anarchism, but not of a Christian or Tolstoyan

individualism.

At other times the two terms have been melted together in one name:

anarchist individualism. Under this rubric M. Hasch designates a social

philosophy that it differentiates from anarchism properly so-called, and

whose great representative, according to him, are Goethe, Byron,

Humboldt, Schleiermacher, Carlyle, Emerson, Kierkegaard, Renan, Ibsen,

Stirner and Nietzsche. This philosophy can be summed up as the cult of

great men and the apotheosis of genius. It would seem to us to be

arguable whether the expression individualist anarchism can be used to

designate such a doctrine. The qualification of anarchist, in the

etymological sense, can be applied with difficulty to thinkers of the

race of Goethe, Carlyle, and Nietzsche, whose philosophy seems on the

contrary to be dominated by ideas of hierarchical organization and the

harmonious placing of values in a series. What is more, the epithet of

individualist can’t be applied with equal justice to all the thinkers we

have just named. If it is appropriate for designating the egotist,

nihilist and anti-idealist revolt of Stirner, it can with difficulty be

applied to the Hegelian, optimist and idealist philosophy of a Carlyle,

who clearly subordinates the individual to the idea.

There thus reigns a certain confusion concerning the use of the two

terms anarchism and individualism, as well as the systems of ideas and

sentiments that these terms designate. We would here like to attempt to

clarify the notion of individualism and determine its psychological and

sociological content by distinguishing it from anarchism...

Individualism is the sentiment of a profound, irreducible antinomy

between the individual and society. The individualist is he who, by

virtue of his temperament, is predisposed to feel in a particularly

acute fashion the ineluctable disharmonies between his intimate being

and his social milieu. At the same time, he is a man for whom life has

reserved some decisive occasion to remark this disharmony. Whether

through brutality, or the continuity of his experiences, for him it has

become clear that for the individual society is a perpetual creator of

constraints, humiliations and miseries, a kind of continuous generation

of human pain. In the name of his own experience and his personal

sensation of life the individualist feels he has the right to relegate

to the rank of utopia any ideal of a future society where the hoped-for

harmony between the individual and society will be established. Far from

the development of society diminishing evil, it does nothing but

intensify it by rendering the life of the individual more complicated,

more laborious and more difficult in the middle of the thousand gears of

an increasingly tyrannical social mechanism. Science itself, by

intensifying within the individual the consciousness of the vital

conditions made for him by society, arrives only at darkening his

intellectual and moral horizons. Qui auget scientiam augel et dolorem.

We see that individualism is essentially a social pessimism. Under its

most moderate form it admits that if life in society is not an absolute

evil and completely destructive of individuality, for the individualist

is at the very least a restrictive and oppressive condition, a necessary

evil and a last resort.

The individualists who respond to this description form a small morose

group whose rebellious, resigned or hopeless words contrast with the

fanfares for the future of optimistic sociologists. It is Vigny saying:

“The social order is always bad. From time to time it is bearable.

Between bad and bearable the dispute isn’t worth a drop of blood.” It’s

Schopenhauer seeing social life as the supreme flowering of human pain

and evil. It’s Stirner with his intellectual and moral solipsism

perpetually on his guard against the duperies of social idealism and the

intellectual and moral crystallization with which every organized

society threatens the individual. It is, at certain moments, an Amiel

with his painful stoicism that perceives society as a limitation and a

restriction of his free spiritual nature. It’s a David Thoreau, the

extremist disciple of Emerson, that “student of nature,” deciding to

stray from the ordinary paths of human activity and to become a

“wanderer,” worshipping independence and dreams. A “wanderer whose every

minute will be filled with more work than the entire lives of many men

with occupations.” It’s a Challemel-Lacour with his pessimistic

conception of society and progress. It is perhaps, at certain moments, a

Tarde, with an individualism colored with misanthropy that he somewhere

expresses: “It is possible that the flux of imitation has its banks and

that, by the very effect of its excessive deployment, the need for

sociability diminishes or rather alters and transforms itself into a

kind of general misanthropy, very compatible, incidentally, with a

moderate commercial circulation and a certain activity of industrial

exchanges reduced to the strict necessary, but above all appropriate to

reinforcing in each of us the distinctive traits of our inner

individuality.”

Even among those who, like M. Maurice Barrès, by dilettantism and

artistic posture, are averse to the accents of sharp revolt or

discouraged pessimism, individualism remains a sentiment of “the

impossibility that exists of harmonizing the private and the general I.”

It’s a determination to set free the first I, to cultivate it in what it

has of the most special, the most advanced, the most rummaged through,

both in detail and in depth. “The individualist,” says M. Barrès, “is he

who, through pride in his true I, which he isn’t able to set free,

ceaselessly wounds, soils, and denies what he has in common with the

mass of men...The dignity of the men of our race is exclusively attached

to certain shivers that the world doesn’t know and cannot see and which

we must multiply in ourselves.”

In all of them individualism is an attitude of sensibility that goes

from hostility and distrust to indifference and disdain vis-Ă -vis the

organized society in which we are forced to live, vis-Ă -vis its

uniformising rules, its monotonous repetitions, and its enslaving

constraints. It’s a desire to escape from it and to withdraw into

oneself. Above all, it is the profound sentiment of the “uniqueness of

the I,” of that which despite it all the I maintains of unrepressible

and impenetrable to social influences. As M. Tarde says, it is the

sentiment of the “profound and fleeting singularity of persons, of their

manner of being, or thinking, of feeling, which is only once and of an

instant.”

Is there any need to demonstrate how much this attitude differs from

anarchism? There is no doubt that in one sense anarchism proceeds from

individualism. It is, in fact, the anti-social revolt of a minority that

feels itself oppressed or disadvantaged by the current order of things.

But anarchism represents only the first moment of individualism, the

moment of faith and hope, of actions courageous and confident of

success. At its second moment individualism converts, as we have seen,

into social pessimism.

The passage from confidence to despair, from optimism to pessimism is

here, in great part, an affair of psychological temperament. There are

delicate souls that are easily wounded on contact with social realities

and consequently quick to be disillusioned, a Vigny or a Heine, for

example. We can say that these souls belong to the psychological type

that has been called “sensitive.” They feel that social determinism,

insofar as it is repressive of the individual, is particularly

tormenting and oppressive. But there are other souls who resist multiple

failures, who disregard even experience’s toughest examples and remain

unshakeable in their faith. These souls belong to the “active” type.

Such are the souls of the anarchist apostles: Bakunin, Kropotkin,

Reclus. Perhaps their imperturbable confidence in their ideal depends on

a lesser intellectual and emotional acuity. Reasons for doubt and

discouragement don’t strike them harshly enough to tarnish the abstract

ideal they’ve forged and to lead them to the final and logical step of

individualism: social pessimism.

Whatever the case, there can be no doubt concerning the optimism of

anarchist philosophy. That optimism is spread, often simplistically and

with naivety, in those volumes with blood red covers that form the

reading matter of propagandists by the deed. The shadow of the

optimistic Rousseau floats over all this literature.

Anarchist optimism consists in believing that social disharmonies, that

the antinomies that the current state of affairs present between the

individual and society, are not essential, but rather accidental and

provisional; that they will one day be resolved and will give place to

an era of harmony.

Anarchism rests on two principles that seem to complement each other,

but actually contradict each other. One is the principle that is

properly individualist or libertarian, formulated by Wilhelm von

Humboldt and chosen by Stuart Mill as the epigraph of his “Essay on

Liberty”: “The great principle is the essential and absolute importance

of human development in its richest diversity.” The other is the

humanist or altruist principle which is translated on the economic plane

by communist anarchism. That the individualist and humanist principles

negate each other is proven by logic and fact. Either the individualist

principle means nothing, or it is a demand in favor of that which

differs and is unequal in individuals, in favor of those traits that

make them different, separates them and, if need be, opposes them. On

the contrary, humanism aims at the assimilation of humanity. Following

the expression of M. Gide, its ideal is to make a reality of the

expression “our like.” In fact, at the current time we see the

antagonism of the two principles assert itself among the most insightful

theoreticians of anarchism, and that logical and necessary antagonism

cannot fail to bring about the breakup of anarchism as a political and

social doctrine.

Whatever the case and whatever difficulties might be met by he who wants

to reconcile the individualist and humanist principles, these two rival

and enemy principles meet at least at this one point: they are both

clearly optimistic. Humboldt’s principle is optimistic insofar as it

implicitly affirms the original goodness of human nature and the

legitimacy of its free blossoming. It sets itself up in opposition to

the Christian condemnation of our natural instincts, and we can

understand the reservations of M. Dupont-White, the translator of the

“Essay on Liberty,” had from the spiritualist and Christian point of

view (condemnation of the flesh) as concerns this principle.

The humanist principle is no less optimistic. Humanism, in fact, is

nothing but rendering divine of man in what he has of the general, of

humanity, and consequently of human society. As we see, anarchism,

optimistic as concerns the individual, is even more so as concerns

society. Anarchism supposes that individual freedoms, left to

themselves, will naturally harmonize and spontaneously realize the

anarchist ideal of free society.

In regard to these two opposing points of view, the Christian and

anarchist, what is the attitude of individualism? Individualism, a

realist philosophy, all lived life and immediate sensation, equally

repudiates these two metaphysics: one, Christian metaphysics, which a

priori affirms original evil, the other the rationalist and Rosseauist

metaphysic, that no less a priori affirms the original and essential

goodness of our nature. Individualism places itself before the facts.

And these latter make visible in the human being a bundle of instincts

in struggle with each other and, in human society, a grouping of

individuals also necessarily in struggle with each other. By the very

fact of his conditions of existence the human being is subject to the

law of struggle: internal struggle among his own instincts, external

struggle with his like. If recognizing the permanent and universal

character of egoism and struggle in human existence means being

pessimistic, then we must say that individualism is pessimistic. But we

must immediately add that the pessimism of individualism, a pessimism of

fact, an experimental pessimism, if you will, pessimism a posteriori, is

totally different from the theological pessimism that a priori

pronounces, in the name of dogma, the condemnation of human nature. What

is more, individualism separates itself every bit as much from

anarchism. If, with anarchism, it admits Humboldt’s principle as the

expression of a normal tendency necessary to our nature for its full

blossoming, at the same time it recognizes that this tendency is

condemned to never being satisfied because of the internal and external

disharmonies of our nature. In other words, it considers the harmonious

development of the individual and society as a utopia. Pessimistic as

concerns the individual, individualism is even more so as concerns

society: man is by his very nature disharmonious because of the internal

struggle of his instincts. But this disharmony is exacerbated by the

state of society which, through a painful paradox, represses our

instincts at the same time as it exasperates them. In fact, from the

rapprochement of individual wills-to-life is formed a collective

will-to-life which becomes immediately oppressive for the individual

will-to-life and opposes its flourishing with all its force. The state

of society thus pushes to its ultimate degree the disharmonies of our

nature. It exaggerates them and puts them in the poorest possible light.

Following the idea of Schopenhauer, society thus truly represents the

human will-to-life at its highest degree: struggle, lack of fulfillment,

and suffering.

From this opposition between anarchism and individualism flow others.

Anarchism believes in progress. Individualism is an attitude of thought

that we can call non-historical. It denies becoming, progress. It sees

the human will-to-life in an eternal present. Like Schopenhauer, with

whom he has more than one similarity, Stirner is a non-historical

spirit. He too believes that it is chimerical to expect something new

and great from tomorrow. Every social form, by the very fact that it

crystallizes, crushes the individual. For Stirner, there are no utopian

tomorrows, no “paradise at the end of our days.” There is nothing but

the egoist today. Stirner’s attitude before society is the same as that

of Schopenhauer before nature and life. With Schopenhauer the negation

of life remains metaphysical and, we might say, spiritual (we should

remember that Schopenhauer condemns suicide which, would be the material

and tangible negation). in the same way Stirner’s rebellion against

society is an entirely spiritual internal rebellion, all intention and

inner will. It is not, as is the case with Bakunin, an appeal to

pan-destruction. Regarding society, it is a simple act of distrust and

passive hostility, a mix of indifference and disdainful resignation. It

is not a question of the individual fighting against society, for

society will always be the stronger. It must thus be obeyed, obeyed like

a dog. But Stirner, while obeying, as a form of consolation, maintains

an immense intellectual contempt. This is more or less the attitude of

Vigny vis-a-vis nature and society. “A tranquil despair, without

convulsions of anger and without reproaches for heaven, this is wisdom

itself.” And again: “Silence would be the best criticism of life.”

Anarchism is an exaggerated and mad idealism. Individualism is summed up

in a trait common to Schopenhauer and Stirner: a pitiless realism. It

arrives at what a German writer calls a complete “dis-idealization”

(Entidealisierung) of life and society.

“An ideal is nothing but a pawn,” Stirner said. From this point of view

Stirner is the most authentic representative of individualism. His icy

word seizes souls with a shiver entirely different from that, fiery and

radiant, of a Nietzsche. Nietzsche remains an impenitent, imperious,

violent idealist. He idealizes superior humanity. Stirner represents the

most complete dis-idealization of nature and life, the most radical

philosophy of disenchantment that has appeared since Ecclesiastes.

Pessimist without measure or reservations, individualism is absolutely

anti-social, unlike anarchism, with which this is only relatively the

case (in relation to current society). Anarchism admits an antinomy

between the individual and the state, an antinomy it resolves by the

suppression of the state, but it does not see any inherent, irreducible

antinomy between the individual and society. This is because in its eyes

society represents a spontaneous growth (Spencer), while the state is an

artificial and authoritarian organization. In the eyes of an

individualist society is as tyrannical, if not more so, than the state.

Society, in fact, is nothing else but the mass of social ties of all

kinds (opinions, mores, usages, conventions, mutual surveillance, more

or less discreet espionage of the conduct of others, moral approval and

disapproval, etc.) Society thus understood constitutes a closely- knit

fabric of petty and great tyrannies, exigent, inevitable, incessant,

harassing, and pitiless, which penetrates into the details of individual

life more profoundly and continuously than statist constraints can. What

is more, if we look closely at this, statist tyranny and the tyranny of

mores proceed from the same root: the collective interest of a caste or

class that wishes to establish or to maintain its domination and

prestige. Opinion and mores are in part the residue of ancient caste

disciplines that are in the process of disappearing, in part the seed of

new social disciplines brought with them by the new leading caste in the

process of formation. This is why between state constraint and that of

opinion and mores there is only a difference in degree. Deep down they

have the same goal: the maintenance of a certain moral conformism useful

to the group, and the same procedures: the vexation and elimination of

the independent and the recalcitrant. The only difference is that

diffuse sanctions (opinions and mores) are more hypocritical than the

others. Proudhon was right to say that the state is nothing but a mirror

of society. It is only tyrannical because society is tyrannical. The

government, following a remark of Tolstoy’s, is a gathering of men who

exploit others and that favors the wicked and the cheaters If this is

the practice of government, this is also that of society. There is a

conformity between the two terms: state and society. The one is the same

as the other. The gregarious spirit, or the spirit of society, is no

less oppressive for the individual than the statist or priestly spirit,

which only maintain themselves thanks to and through it.

How strange! Stirner himself, on the question of the relations between

society and the state, seems to share the error of Spencer and Bakunin.

He protests against the intervention of the state in the acts of the

individual, but not against that of society. “Before the individual the

state girds itself with an aureole of sanctity. For example, it makes

laws concerning duels. Two men who agree to risk their lives in order to

settle an affair (whatever it might be) cannot execute their agreement

because the state doesn’t want it. They would expose themselves to

judicial pursuit and punishment. What becomes of the freedom of

self-determination? Things are completely different in those places,

like North America, where society decides to make the duelists suffer

certain disagreeable consequences of their act and takes form them, for

example, the credit they had previously enjoyed. The refusing of credit

is everyone’s affair, and if it pleases a society to deprive someone of

it for one reason or another, he who is struck by it cannot complain of

an attack on his liberty: society has done nothing but exercise its own.

The society of which we spoke leaves the individual perfectly free to

expose himself to the harmful or disagreeable consequences that result

from his way of acting, and leaves full and entire his freedom of will.

The state does exactly the contrary: it denies all legitimacy to the

will of the individual and only recognizes as legitimate its own will,

the will of the state.” Strange reasoning. The law doesn’t attack me. In

what way am I freer if society boycotts me? Such reasoning would

legitimize all the attacks of a public opinion infected by moral bigotry

against the individual. The legend of individual liberty in Anglo-Saxon

countries is built on this reasoning. Stirner himself feels the vice of

his reasoning, and a little further along he arrives at his celebrated

distinction between society and association. In the one (society) the

individual is taken as a means; in the other (association), he takes

himself as an end and treats the association as a means of personal

power and enjoyment: “You bring to the association all your might, all

your riches and make your presence felt In society you and your activity

are utilized. In the first you live as an egoist; in the second you live

as a man, i.e., religiously; you work in the Lord’s vineyard. You owe

society everything you have; you are its debtor and you are tormented

with social obligations. You owe nothing to the association. She serves

you and you leave it without scruples as soon as you no longer have any

advantages to draw from it...” “If society is more than you then you

will have it pass ahead of you and you will make yourself its servant.

The association is your tool, your weapon; it sharpens and multiplies

your natural strength. The association only exists for you and by you.

Society, on the contrary, claims you as its good and can exist without

you. In short, society is sacred and the association is your property;

society uses you and you use the association.

A vain distinction if ever there was one! Where should we fix the

boundary between society and association? As Stirner himself admitted,

doesn’t an association tend to crystallize into a society?

However we approach it, anarchism cannot reconcile the two antinomic

terms, society and individual liberty. The free society that it dreams

of is a contradiction in terms. It’s a piece of steel made of wood, a

stick without an end. Speaking of anarchists Nietzsche wrote: “We can

already read on all the walls and all the tables their word for the

future: Free society. Free society? To be sure. But I think you know, my

dear sirs, what we will build it with: Wood made of iron...”

Individualism is clearer and more honest than anarchism. It places the

state, society, and association on the same plane. It rejects them both

and as far as this is possible tosses them overboard. “All associations

have the defects of convents,” Vigny said.

Antisocial, individualism is openly immoralist. This is not true in an

absolute fashion. In a Vigny pessimistic individualism is reconciled

with a morally haughty stoicism, severe and pure. Even so, even in Vigny

an immoralist element remains: a tendency to dis-idealize society, to

separate and oppose the two terms society and morality, and to regard

society as a fatal generator of cowardice, unintelligence, and

hypocrisy. “Cinq mars, Stello, and Servitude et Grandeur militaires are

the songs of a kind of epic poem on disillusionment. But it is only

social and false things that I will destroy and illusions I will trample

on. I will raise on these ruins, on this dust, the sacred beauty of

enthusiasm, of love, and of honor.” It goes without saying that in a

Stirner or a Stendhal individualism is immoralist without scruples or

reservations. Anarchism is imbued with a crude moralism. Anarchist

morality, even without obligations or sanctions, is no less a morality.

At heart it is Christian morality, except for the pessimist element

contained in the latter. The anarchist supposes that those virtues

necessary to harmony will flourish on their own. Enemy of coercion, the

doctrine accords the faculty to take from the general stores even to the

lazy. But the anarchist is persuaded that in the future city the lazy

will be rare, or will not exist at all.

Optimistic and idealistic, imbued with humanism and moralism, anarchism

is a social dogmatism. It is a “cause” in the sense that Stirner gave

this word. A “cause” is one thing, “the simple attitude of an individual

soul” is another. A cause implies a common adherence to an idea, a

shared belief and a devotion to that belief. Such is not individualism.

Individualism is anti-dogmatic and little inclined to proselytism. It

would gladly take as its motto Stirner’s phrase: “I have set my affair

on nothing.” The true individualist doesn’t seek to communicate to

others his own sensation of life and society. What would be the good of

this? Omne individuum inefabile. Convinced of the diversity of

temperaments and the uselessness of a single rule, he would gladly say

with David Thoreau: “I would not have any one adopt my mode of living on

any account; for, beside that before he has fairly learned it I may have

found out another for myself, I desire that there may be as many

different persons in the world as possible; but I would have each one be

very careful to find out and pursue his own way, and not his father’s or

his mother’s or his neighbor’s instead.” The individualist knows that

there are temperaments that are refractory to individualism and that it

would be ridiculous to want to convince them. In the eyes of a thinker

in love with solitude and independence, a contemplative, a pure adept of

the inner life, like Vigny, social life and its agitations seem to be

something artificial, rigged, excluding any true and strongly felt

sentiments. And conversely, those who by their temperament feel an

imperious need for life and social action, those who throw themselves

into the melee, those who have political and social enthusiasm, those

who believe in the virtues of leagues and groups, those who have forever

on their lips the words “The Idea,” “The Cause,” those who believe that

tomorrow will bring something new and great, these people necessarily

misunderstand and disdain the contemplative, who lowers before the crowd

the harrow of which Vigny spoke. Inner life and social action are two

things that are mutually exclusive. The two kinds of souls are not made

to understand each other. As antitheses, we should read alongside each

other Schopenhauer’s “Aphorisms on the Wisdom of Life,” that bible of a

reserved, mistrustful, and sad individualism, or the Journal Intime of

Amiel. Or the Journal d’un Poète by Vigny. On the other side, we should

read a Benoit Malon, an Elisée Reclus or a Kropotkin, and we will see

the abyss that separates the two kinds of souls...