đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș gabriel-kuhn-the-meaning-of-anarchism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 10:34:33. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: The Meaning of Anarchism Author: Gabriel Kuhn Date: 2011 Language: en Topics: anarchism, anarchist movement, hierarchy, identity, philosophy, syndicalism Source: Retrieved on February 7, 2012 from http://anarchiststudies.org/node/529 Notes: From Perspectives
Michael Schmidt and Lucien van der Waltâs book Black Flame: The
Revolutionary Class Politics of Anarchism and Syndicalism published by
AK Press in 2009 has caused considerable debate within the anarchist
movement. While the debate itself is refreshing, it might not always be
conducted in the most productive of ways.
With respect to the book, two issues have to be separated. Black Flame
is an outstanding contribution to the historiography of anarchism. It
seems hard for anyone to deny that, no matter how strongly some might
object to the definition of anarchism presented in the book. So the
question of anarchismâs definition, which is at the center of the Black
Flame debate, must not be confused with disregarding the work itself.
In this spirit, the following remarks must be read as an attempt to
advance a discussion about the meaning of anarchism rather than as an
outright rejection of the definition proposed in Black Flame. In a
respectful exchange of ideas, we can hopefully all improve our
definitions, concepts, and the way we present them, and therefore
anarchism as a whole.
Fights over definitions often take on curious forms. It is impossible to
decide on a âcorrectâ definition outside of a commonly accepted
framework that provides commonly accepted criteria allowing to
distinguish between a âcorrectâ and an âincorrectâ definition. For the
most part, this works well in everyday language. If we give someone
directions and say, âYou will see a house as you come down the hillâ, no
one will answer, âHold on a second: whatâs your definition of a
âhouseâ?â Interestingly enough, if we were forced to define a âhouseâ,
our definitions might be quite diverse, but the common language we use â
what Wittgenstein calls a âlanguage gameâ, for those who are interested
in such things â provides clear enough criteria for us to not even need
a spelled-out definition in order to understand one another.
Things become more complicated with terms that are more complex and
abstract. If you tell someone, âMy new neighbor is an anarchist,â the
response quite likely might be, âWhat do you mean by âanarchistâ?â In
general, there seem to be three possible ways for the conversation to
proceed:
1. You present your definition, the person you are talking to says,
âOkay, I seeâ (whether your definition matches his or hers or not), and
thatâs it.
2. You present your definition, the person you are talking to says,
âInteresting, because my definition would be a different oneâ, and you
have an inspiring discussion about the different possibilities of
defining anarchism.
3. You present your definition, the person you are talking to says,
âThatâs the dumbest thing Iâve ever heardâ, and you end up having a
fight.
Personally, I see number three as the worst-case scenario.
Unfortunately, it is the form the Black Flame debate often takes â
which, again unfortunately, is nothing new in anarchist circles.
One of the problems is that without an accepted framework providing
commonly accepted rules for âcorrectâ and âincorrectâ definitions, there
is no end to the fighting. People appear to argue when, in fact, they
arenât really talking to one another because they move in different
frameworks (âlanguage gamesâ).
When trying to engage with the definition of anarchism provided by Black
Flame, a difficulty stems from the fact that subjective assessments and
general assumptions are often intertwined in the book, which can be
confusing. On the one hand, Schmidt and van der Walt âargue [that] the
most important strand in anarchism has always been syndicalismâ, they
âdevelop an understanding of the doctrine of anarchism and its originsâ,
they âreject the notion that anarchist currents can be found throughout
historyâ, they âchallenge the view that any philosophy or movement that
is hostile to the state, or in favour of individual freedom, can be
characterised as anarchistâ, and they conclude that âit is our view that
the term anarchism should be reserved for a particular rationalist and
revolutionary form of libertarian socialism that emerged in the second
half of the nineteenth centuryâ (all emphases mine).
On the other hand, they proclaim that âanarchism is a revolutionary,
internationalist, class struggle form of libertarian socialism [that]
first emerged in the First Internationalâ, that âsyndicalism is a
variant of anarchismâ, that âthere is only one anarchist traditionâ, and
that various thinkers and movements commonly considered anarchist
âcannot truly be called anarchistâ and are therefore ânot part of the
anarchist traditionâ.
Sometimes, the general assumptions and subjective assessments converge,
for example in the following statement: ââClass struggleâ anarchism,
sometimes called revolutionary or communist anarchism, is not a type of
anarchism; in our view, it is the only anarchismâ (emphasis mine).
Sometimes, the convergence leads to apparent arguments that are actually
mere tautologies: âNot only is it the case that anarchism did not exist
in the premodern world; it is also the case that it could not have, for
it is rooted in the social and intellectual revolutions of the modern
world.â
It has to be assumed that Schmidt and van der Walt would object to
subjective assessments playing a role in their definition of anarchism,
at least if we consider the following statement: â...we maintain that
the meaning of anarchism is neither arbitrary nor just a matter of
opinion.â However, the explanation that immediately follows is hardly
convincing and rather confirms the subjective element in their
definition: â...the historical record demonstrates that there is a core
set of beliefs.â Which âhistorical recordâ are we talking about? Asked
differently: how can we talk about a âhistorical recordâ if we do not
already have an understanding of what anarchism is? How would we know
what to look for? Obviously, much of what has been considered anarchist
historically falls outside of the Black Flame definition of anarchism.
In a similar manner, the following conclusion is only valid if you have
already decided what anarchism is: âGiven that antistatism is at best a
necessary component of anarchist thought, but not a sufficient basis on
which to classify a set of ideas or a particular thinker as part of the
anarchist tradition, it follows that Godwin, Stirner, and Tolstoy cannot
truly be considered anarchists.â If antistatism alone is not a
sufficient basis for anarchism, why would it follow that Godwin etc.
cannot truly be considered anarchist? Eliminating antistatism as the
exclusive criterion for anarchism only says what anarchism is not, but
gives no answer at all as to what it is. So, once again, how would we
know who to exclude if we do not already have an idea of what anarchism
is? We could just as well exclude Bakunin and Kropotkin and call
Benjamin Tucker the only true anarchist. Of course one could argue that
more self-identified anarchists were inspired by Bakunin and Kropotkin
than by Tucker, but this is a line of argumentation that Schmidt and van
der Walt clearly reject.
To paraphrase Schmidt and van der Walt, what they are basically saying
is: âHistorically, there is a core set of beliefs that defines what we
see as the broad anarchist tradition. It is this history that we will
therefore present as the history of anarchism.â This is a perfectly
legitimate approach â but it is based on a preconceived notion of
anarchism.
By no means do I mean to critique the authors for entertaining such a
notion, for it could not be any other way. Definitions are not about
discovering the (ideal) âtruthâ behind a (worldly) phenomenon and then
framing it into words â if one claimed the ability to do this, it would
be a crude form of Platonic thought unsuitable for antiauthoritarianism
by any standards. Hence, there is nothing wrong with having a subjective
approach. But the approach should be unambiguous to avoid confusion and
enable a clearer debate.
Some people worry that a definition becomes ârandomâ if a subjective
element enters the equation. But that is not the case at all. Of course
Schmidt and van der Walt have reasons for choosing the definition of
anarchism they chose. It might be most attractive to them, it might make
the most sense, it might take us the furthest in the struggle against
the state and capital. Whatever the reasons are, there are arguments for
them and these have to be taken seriously.
Before we look at the main arguments for the Black Flame definition of
anarchism, let us talk a little more about what we expect from a âgoodâ
definition. Also in this case, there is no randomness only because there
is lack of truth. If what English-speakers call a house is not truly a
âhouseâ (as in: not more so than a âmaisonâ or a âcameraâ), it doesnât
mean that you can just define the word âhouseâ in whatever way you want.
Well, you can, but you will soon realize that defining it as âa red
fireball with three armsâ is a bad definition â because no one will know
what you are talking about. The main criterion for a good definition
(beyond the Platonic world) is to ease communication â which also
includes analysis and research. Schmidt and van der Walt obviously hold
this view as well: âA good definition is one that highlights the
distinguishing features of a given category, does so in a coherent
fashion, and is able to differentiate that category from others, thereby
organizing knowledge as well as enabling effective analysis and
research.â
In everyday terms, a âgoodâ definition is âusefulâ and âmakes senseâ.
These seemingly trivial criteria go a long way. For example, defining a
house as âa red fireball with three armsâ doesnât make any sense and we
know it, even if we have a hard time coming up with a good definition of
âhouseâ ourselves. We could go through countless similar examples.
For the definition of a word to make sense, the following criteria
usually apply: the definition must not contradict the everyday usage of
the term entirely; it must emphasize the distinct characteristics of the
defined thing/phenomenon; it should not be too wide and not too narrow;
it must not be ideologically biased; it must not contain too many
ambiguous and contested terms, etc. All of these criteria should apply
to a good definition of anarchism too.
In the case of a complex and ideologically charged terms like
âanarchismâ, there are two other important aspects that donât
necessarily apply to a term like âhouseâ:
1. Identity. To be an âanarchistâ is important to many self-identified
anarchists. If someone says, âsorry, but youâre not really an
anarchistâ, itâs hard to just shrug your shoulders and walk away if
feeling affiliated with anarchism is a strong part of your identity. In
simple words, emotional factors come into play.
2. Politics. If we want to overthrow, undermine, or at least challenge
the ruling system, we want to use everything we can as a weapon â that
includes language. In this respect, it is important to consider the fact
that our definition of anarchism can impact the effectiveness of
revolutionary movements.
With this in mind, let us turn to the main Black Flame arguments for the
definition used in the book:
1. Coherence. Schmidt and van der Walt argue against âanarchism being
defined so loosely that it is not clear what should be included and what
should not, and why some things are included and others are not.â
I believe that Schmidt and van der Walt sometimes exaggerate the
differences between thinkers that are commonly considered as anarchists.
For example, I cannot see an âabyssâ between âthe notion of freedom
articulated by Stirner and that of the anarchists [read: the people
Schmidt and van der Walt consider anarchists]â.
I also think a claim like the following is hard to uphold: â...no
serious examination of Lao-tzu, the Anabaptists, and Bakunin can
maintain that they shared the same views and goals, so it is not clear
why they should be grouped togetherâ. Schmidt and van der Walt could
hardly argue that Bakunin, Malatesta, and Connolly shared the same
âviewsâ (perhaps no two anarchists do; in any case we need to at least
know what kind of views we are talking about). The category of âgoalsâ
is also difficult. Many anarchists share the same goals as Marxists, yet
they would never want to be in the same category. In short, whether we
can group people together or not doesnât depend on how many views and
goals they share, but which of their views and goals we want to consider
in this specific case of grouping people together. For example, if one
wants to group all people born in Austria together, Iâm afraid itâs
legitimate to put me in the same category as Arnold Schwarzenegger,
while I certainly hope that there arenât too many others we would share.
Nonetheless, I believe the âcoherence argumentâ to be strong. It is
probably true that âthe seven sages approach [referring to Paul
Eltzbacherâs classic book on anarchism, published in 1900] inevitably
creates the impression that anarchism is contradictory as well as
unfocused, and renders the theoretical analysis of anarchism a
frustrating task at bestâ. It is also true that a definition can be âso
loose as to be practically meaninglessâ, which is why I agree with
Schmidt and van der Walt that neither self-identification nor
antistatism serve as useful defining grounds for anarchism.
2. Clarity. Schmidt and van der Walt repeatedly stress that âwe must
have a clear understanding of what ideas we mean by anarchismâ.
This, in fact, is a curious argument once we take a closer look at Black
Flame. The reason is that the book never actually formulates a concise
âthis is itâ definition of anarchism. Instead, there are numerous
allusions and references that frame a definition. These include the
information that anarchism is âa libertarian type of socialismâ, stands
âagainst capitalism and landlordismâ, considers âindividual freedom and
individuality [...] extremely importantâ, favors a society that is
âclassless, egalitarian, participatory, and creativeâ as well as
ârational, democratic, and modernâ, envisions a âplanned economyâ,
contains âa deep respect for human rightsâ as well as âa profound
celebration of humankind and its potentialâ, struggles to âreplace
capitalism and the state with collective ownership of the means of
productionâ, pursues a society where âindividual freedom would be
harmonised with communal obligations through cooperationâ, emerged âfrom
within the socialist and working-class movement 150 years agoâ and
âagainst the backdrop of the Industrial Revolution and the rise of
capitalismâ, is âa child of the eighteenth-century Enlightenmentâ and
ânot a universal aspect of society or the psycheâ, and so on. I think it
is difficult to argue that this list makes a âclearâ definition. Albeit
very selective, it already contains at least fifteen terms that are
highly contested: what exactly does âlibertarianâ mean, or ârationalâ,
or âplanned economyâ, etc.? In short, while the Black Flame definition
of anarchism might be ânarrowâ, it is not necessarily âclearâ. Those are
two different things.
I should add that the authors cannot be criticized for not presenting a
clear definition of anarchism. After all, it is near impossible to
present a âclearâ definition of any more complex phenomenon. The only
thing the authors might be criticized for is to promise something that
practically no one can deliver.
3. Effectiveness. Schmidt and van der Walt claim that âby presenting
anarchism as vague and rather formless, it also makes it difficult to
consider how the broad anarchist tradition can inform contemporary
struggles against neoliberalismâ.
I am not sure if I find this argument convincing. If the âbroad
anarchist traditionâ can inform contemporary struggles, why would it not
do so only because some folks you donât consider anarchists are also
called anarchists by others? I suppose that this doesnât change the
ideas of the âbroad anarchist traditionâ, so if these ideas have the
potential to inform contemporary struggles, they shall do so regardless.
One could possibly argue that because of a âvague and rather formlessâ
perception of anarchism, people will never get to the ârealâ anarchism
buried underneath a lot of pretense, but thatâs a different kind of
argument â and a very bold one indeed, since it would not only imply
that many apparent anarchists are no real anarchists but also that they
have nothing to contribute to contemporary struggles. If that is the
opinion of the Black Flame authors, it would have to be supported more
strongly.
4. Organization. Schmidt and van der Walt write: âThe view that
anarchists and syndicalists will be strengthened by the formation of an
organisation that is open to all anarchist currents is also open to
question.â
This is an interesting argument because the aspect of strategy comes
into play. When Schmidt and van der Walt suggest that âsynthesistâ
anarchist organizations âoften have difficulties in operatingâ, we might
be at the core of the âpoliticalâ implications of anarchismâs
definition: which definition will allow for the most effective form of
anarchist organizing?
Intuitively, it seems right to suggest that an organization uniting
people who, fundamentally, share the same views, will operate better
than an organization uniting people with all sorts of different
perspectives. However, there are some problematic aspects in such an
assumption. These do not necessarily concern the fact that some
self-identified anarchists see formal organization per se as an affront
to the anarchist idea. Letâs put such views aside here for a moment and
focus on the question of whether organizations really become better if
we cut down on diversity? In my opinion, this is not the case. Diversity
also means critical intervention and creativity, essential features of
antiauthorianism.
Of course I donât want to romanticize. Too much âcritical interventionâ
and âdiversityâ can make organizing outright impossible, there is no
denying that. At the same time, the answer cannot be to only organize
with anarchists we have no disagreements with. The challenge for
anarchist organizing rather seems to develop forms of organizing that
turn diversity from a destructive threat to a productive tool. This is
tremendously difficult, but I think it is the only chance we have.
Furthermore, peopleâs views are only one factor that determine the
success or failure of organizations. Others include membership numbers,
organizational structure, community support, links to social movements,
individual dedication, personal maturity, etc. For example, many
platformist groups â a model for anarchist organizing that Schmidt and
van der Walt have clear sympathies for â have difficulties in operating,
too. On the other hand, anarchist-inspired organizations like Common
Ground Relief in New Orleans operate rather effectively, although they
arenât âunifying anarchists around clear objectives,â âelaborating a
shared set of strategic and tactical choicesâ, or âuniting energies
around a common programmeâ. A strong sense of solidarity can help
overcome many differences. It is therefore unfortunate that the value of
solidarity often disappears behind struggles of identity or mere
personal turf wars in anarchist debates.
There are a few other problems I see with the Black Flame definition of
anarchism.
1. The identity problem. As stated before, certain definitions have a
strong identity value; they are not just a question of logical
categorization but of emotional attachment. Heated arguments about
whether a band is âreallyâ punk or not is one example. When someone
says, âGreen Day is the best punk band everâ, punks with a strong
DIY-ethos might just shrug their shoulders and say, âWell, in my
definition, Green Day is not punk, but whateverâ, but it is
understandable if this does not always happen. They are not defending a
mere word, they are defending an identity.
2.
We are experiencing similar reactions with respect to Black Flame. If
anarchist identity wasnât important to people, non-anarchists in the
eyes of Schmidt and van der Walt could just say, âInteresting
definition, but I donât see it that way.â However, for many, this
doesnât work. If you have strongly identified as an anarchist for a long
time, you easily take it as an affront if someone comes along and says
youâre not. The sometimes categorical tone in Black Flame probably
doesnât help either. Needless to say, nor does the sometimes categorical
tone of the bookâs critics. As a result, the debates often turn sour
fast and make alliances between people impossible who, actually, have
very similar views and goals. This, to say the least, is unfortunate.
Sometimes, it is argued that the debates only get out of hand if there
is no common ground for alliance anyway. The differences in peopleâs
views are supposedly unbridgeable and this is the reason for the lack of
collaboration, not failed communication. In some cases, this might be
true. In others, I donât think it is.
Let us consider the debates about the significance of âclassâ, for
example. A lot has been said about the conflict between âclass struggleâ
and âlifestyleâ anarchists, a debate that Black Flame also refers to.
Some, including the Black Flame authors, suggest that the latter are so
fundamentally different from the former that they cannot be useful
comrades in the struggle against the state and capitalism. âLifestyleâ
anarchists are usually accused of neglecting class, while âclass
struggleâ anarchists are usually accused of neglecting all other forms
of oppression. Curiously enough, I have hardly ever met a âlifestyleâ
anarchist who flat-out denied the significance of class, and I have
hardly ever met a âclass struggleâ anarchist who flat-out denied the
significance of other forms of oppression. This is not what people fight
about. People fight about priorities, strategies, in the worst case
personal vanity. So how come these differences are perceived as so
fundamental that they make collaboration impossible? Is this really
inevitable?
In Black Flame, the authors express a number of views that I donât agree
with. For example, I have no problem with the term âanarcha-feminismâ
(with respect to a term like âsocial anarchismâ the authors concede
that, for clarity, its usage âis probably sometimes necessaryâ, although
they consider the term tautological â why does the same not apply to
âanarcha-feminismâ?); I donât think that stressing the specific
characteristics of, for example, racial and gender privilege fosters âan
identity politics that makes a virtue of fragmentation and pitting
different groups of workers against one anotherâ (in my opinion, the
stressing of these forms of privilege only adds important perspectives
that allow for an overall more differentiated analysis); I donât believe
that the very diverse phenomenon of âpostmodernismâ can be reduced to a
school of ârelativists for whom truth is a matter of opinionâ and who
âadopted an idealist form of determinismâ (despite all the nonsense that
happens under the postmodern label today, postmodernists have, for
example, successfully challenged authoritarian schools of thought).
However, despite such reservations, why should I draw the conclusion
that Schmidt and van der Walt are no comrades in the struggle against
the state and capital, or that it would be impossible to work with them?
Judging from the effort that went into their book, they are probably
great people to work with â at least if we consider commitment and
diligence a virtue. Of course we might encounter problems along the way,
but what does it say about the anarchist movement if we donât even try
because of this? Do we not leave for an exciting trip because we might
catch a cold, our car might break down, or we might not sleep that
comfortably every night? Without accepting challenges and without
stepping out of our comfort zones, it is unlikely that we will ever get
very far.
3. The exclusion problem. The Black Flame definition of anarchism
excludes many individuals, groups, and movements that are usually
considered anarchist and who consider themselves anarchist. The authors
acknowledge this, stating, âWe are aware that our approach contradicts
some long-standing definitionsâ. This is not necessarily a problem, but
you need to make a strong case for the exclusions, otherwise it is
hardly worth causing confusion to the point where basically all existing
histories of anarchism would have to be rewritten â not to mention the
many personal upsets you cause.
4.
Now, is the Black Flame case really strong? As I tried to sketch above,
not in my eyes. I think that Schmidt and van der Walt have a strong case
in arguing that some of the most common definitions of anarchism â
especially those based on mere self-definition and a crude understanding
of antistatism â are indeed too vague. Therefore, they also have a
strong case for proposing a different definition of anarchism. However,
I think that they end up with a definition that is too restrictive and
unconventional to be accepted. Why not call Proudhon or Tolstoy
anarchists and adjust your definition accordingly? I simply canât see
the harm it would cause.
In general, though, the question of which historical figures to include
in the anarchist movement is not the decisive one, and of rather
academic nature. For example, is it really important to argue about
whether Max Stirner was an anarchist or not? I have a much higher
opinion of Stirner the philosopher than Schmidt and van der Walt do, but
Stirner never called himself an anarchist and he was never part of a
social movement that used the name, so I guess I wouldnât care either
way.
The by far bigger concern are contemporary anarchists. I have been
active in the anarchist movement for more than twenty years, have met
with self-identified anarchist activists in numerous countries, and have
recently co-edited a German book on contemporary anarchism that includes
fifty interviews with anarchists from five continents. According to the
Black Flame definition of anarchism only a very small portion of the
people I have met, spoken to, and worked with would qualify as
anarchists. Of course, one could say that I move in the wrong circles.
This might be the case, but I would still like to point out that I am
neither an opponent nor a stranger to syndicalism. I am a member of the
Swedish SAC and consider syndicalism to be an extremely important part
of anarchist agitation and activism. However, I am willing to
acknowledge that this kind of struggle is, for a variety of reasons, not
a priority for many of todayâs self-identified anarchists. Does this
mean that they do not fight against the state and capitalism? No, they
just do it in different ways. And even if I might sometimes think that
their priorities are screwed, they are genuinely struggling for a world
of justice and equality in which individuals â all individuals â can
develop freely.
Now, given the abovementioned problems of self-identification and the
political significance of the definition of anarchism, I believe that
this struggle will suffer if we tell all these people that they are not
really anarchists. We will be considered arrogant, self-righteous, in
the worst case power-hungry. The movement will fight about labels
instead of discussing common strategies. We will strengthen sectarianism
rather than cooperation. Why not try to convince these folks of the
importance of the class struggle â if we believe in it â rather than
rejecting them as âlifestylistsâ? I simply cannot see the benefit,
although I concede that my belief in possible alliances might be
stronger than that of those who rather stress the âunbridgeable chasmsâ.
It is of course possible to say that we could still work with these
âfalse anarchistsâ and that it is just important to point out that they
are not anarchists. Apart from the fact that pointing this out might
make these folks not want to work with us, I think it is also important
to have a broad self-identified anarchist movement for three main
reasons:
a) You derive strength and inspiration from being part of a broad
movement of people who gather under the same banner.
b) You will be recognized as a strong social force, a fact that attracts
attention from the wider public, helps spread your ideas, and poses a
threat to those in power. âDivide and conquerâ is still one of the most
useful tools of domination. We might not like it that these kinds of
âidentity politicsâ are important for our struggle, but they are. In
postmodern times it is hip to eschew all labels. However, common labels
serve a political purpose. It is one reason why the definition of
anarchism matters for how effective we are as a movement.
3. The inclusion problem. Ironically, the Black Flame definition of
anarchism not only entails a problematic act of exclusion but also of
inclusion. Schmidt and van der Walt include many individuals in their
definition of anarchism who did not use the label themselves, although
they were fully aware of its existence. Some, like Daniel de Leon,
openly rejected it. Again, Schmidt and van der Walt know this, stating
that they âdo not use self-identification but rather ideas as the basis
for inclusion in the broad anarchist traditionâ. There is nothing to be
said against this, in principle. However, if we agree that a definition
has to be âusefulâ, how useful is it to include people who do not want
to be included? Can this really help to make anarchists a closer and
more tight-knit group, which is one apparent intention of the Black
Flame authors? Are we really going to have a more effective movement
with people who refuse to be a part of it?
There is a difference between making self-identification the only
criterion for being an anarchist and for making it one criterion for
being an anarchist. This also concerns basic issues of respect. Many SAC
members, for example â just like many members of other syndicalist
organizations â do not consider themselves to be anarchists, and they do
not consider the organization to be anarchist either. Is it really
appropriate to tell them, âWell, you might say whatever you want, but
you are an anarchist and you belong to an anarchist organizationâ? I
donât think that any attempt of âforced integrationâ can do the
anarchist movement any good.
I should probably finish with proposing a definition of anarchism
myself. I would go for âa credible commitment to a just and egalitarian
society without institutionalized authorityâ.
To be clear: this definition does not claim to capture the âtrueâ
meaning of anarchism. As stated above, I donât think any âtrueâ
definition exists. I favor this definition according to the main
criteria for good definitions outlined in this text, namely
communicative and political usefulness. Needless to say, better
definitions might exist according to these criteria. Other suggestions
will only take us further.
I would like to explain some of the implications of the proposed
definition as follows:
Of course, it is not an entirely âclearâ definition, as weâll always
fail to reach that standard. However, I will try to be more precise. The
term âcredibleâ includes an (inevitable) subjective moment, but its
meaning is fairly uncontested as most of us understand the same by it:
people say something and we believe that they really mean it. With a
âjustâ society, I mean a society in which all individuals are offered
the same possibilities (and truly, not just on paper) for free
development, i.e., economically, socially, culturally. With an
âegalitarianâ society, I mean a society in which no individuals or
groups hold special privileges of power. With âinstitutionalized
authorityâ, I mean authority that is not based on an immediate mandate
of the community that can be revoked at any time but rests on means of
oppression (the state, the military, etc.).
Demands for âclarityâ can cause endless chains of definitions, but I
hope that these qualifications allow the proposed definition of
anarchism to take on a fairly solid shape.
âAntistatismâ is obviously not a decisive criterion for this definition,
and âself-identificationâ is none at all â although, along the lines of
what has been argued above, I would add the following amendment: only
such individuals, organizations, and social movements should be called
âanarchistâ who use the name themselves or, at least, do not object to
it as a description for their politics. Of course, this doesnât mean
that we canât call individuals, organizations, and social movements
âinspired by anarchismâ or âembracing anarchist ideasâ, if we believe
that this is the case.
While the proposed definition is more precise than definitions merely
resting on âantistatismâ or âself-identificationâ, it still leaves room
to include most of the historical figures commonly considered
anarchists. Some, like Max Stirner, will always be controversial. The
dispute over whether he was committed to a just and egalitarian society
cannot be resolved here, and perhaps never will. However, as has been
stated, complete clarity is too much to ask for any definition, and
there will always be elements that straddle the boundaries. This is
inevitable. But is it a big problem? I donât think so.
Especially not because important distinctions can still be made. In the
case of the proposed definition, it is possible to draw strong lines
between anarchism and phenomena such as âanarcho-capitalismâ or
ânational anarchismâ. These are paradoxical neologisms that signify
schools of thought that fit nowhere into the proposed definition, mainly
because they have divisions between people built into their make-up that
undermine any meaningful sense of justice and egalitarianism. Hence,
there is not even âfamily resemblance,â to use another Wittgenstein
term.
In fact, I would like to close with quoting the aphorisms 66 and 67 of
Wittgensteinâs Philosophical Investigations, as I cannot think of a
better guideline for a useful definition of anarchism. May many new
propositions follow!
66. Consider for example the proceedings that we call âgamesâ. I mean
board-games, card-games, ball-games, Olympic games, and so on. What is
common to them all? â Donât say: âThere must be something common, or
they would not be called âgamesââ â but look and see whether there is
anything common to all. â For if you look at them you will not see
something that is common to all, but similarities, relationships, and a
whole series of them at that. To repeat: donât think, but look! â Look
for example at board-games, with their multifarious relationships. Now
pass to card-games; here you will find many correspondences with the
first group, but many common features drop out, and others appear. When
we pass next to ball-games, much that is common is retained, but much is
lost. â Are they all âamusingâ? Compare chess with noughts and crosses
[tic-tac-toe]. Or is there always winning and losing, or competition
between players? Think of patience. In ball games there is winning and
losing; but when a child throws a ball at the wall and catches it again,
this feature has disappeared. Look at the parts played by skill and
luck; and at the difference between skill in chess and skill in tennis.
Think now of games like ring-a-ring-a-roses; here is the element of
amusement, but how many other characteristic features have disappeared!
And we can go through the many, many other groups of games in the same
way; can see how similarities crop up and disappear.
And the result of this examination is: we see a complicated network of
similarities overlapping and cries-crossing: sometimes overall
similarities, sometimes similarities of detail.
67. I can think of no better expression to characterize these
similarities than âfamily resemblancesâ; for the various resemblances
between members of a family: build, features, colour of eyes, gait,
temperament, etc. etc. overlap and cries-cross in the same way. â And I
shall say: âgamesâ form a family.
And for instance the kinds of number form a family in the same way. Why
do we call something a ânumberâ? Well, perhaps because it has
a-direct-relationship with several things that have hitherto been called
number; and this can be said to give it an indirect relationship to
other things we call the same name. And we extend our concept of number
as in spinning a thread we twist fibre on fibre. And the strength of the
thread does not reside in the fact that some one fibre runs through its
whole length, but in the overlapping of many fibres.
But if someone wished to say: âThere is something common to all these
constructions-namely the disjunction of all their common propertiesâ â I
should reply: Now you are only playing with words. One might as well
say: âSomething runs through the whole thread â namely the continuous
overlapping of those fibres.ââ