💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › john-zerzan-time-and-its-discontents.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 11:40:34. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Time and its Discontents
Author: John Zerzan
Language: en
Topics: alienation, anti-civ
Source: Retrieved on February 11th, 2009 from http://www.primitivism.com/time.htm

John Zerzan

Time and its Discontents

The dimension of time seems to be attracting great notice, to judge from

the number of recent movies that focus on it, such as Back to the

Future, Terminator, Peggy Sue Got Married, etc. Stephen Hawking’s A

Brief History of Time (1989) was a best-seller and became, even more

surprisingly, a popular film. Remarkable, in addition to the number of

books that deal with time, are the larger number which don’t, really,

but which feature the word in their titles nonetheless, such as Virginia

Spate’s The Color of Time: Claude Monet (1992). Such references have to

do, albeit indirectly, with the sudden, panicky awareness of time, the

frightening sense of our being tied to it. Time is increasingly a key

manifestation of the estrangement and humiliation that characterize

modern existence. It illuminates the entire, deformed landscape and will

do so ever more harshly until this landscape and all the forces that

shape it are changed beyond recognizing.

This contribution to the subject has little to do with time’s

fascination for film-makers or TV producers, or with the current

academic interest in geologic conceptions of time, the history of clock

technology and the sociology of time, or with personal observations and

counsels on its use. Neither aspects nor excesses of time deserve as

much attention as time’s inner meaning and logic. For despite the fact

that time’s perplexing character has become, in John Michon’s

estimation, “almost an intellectual obsession” (1988), society is

plainly incapable of dealing with it.

With time we confront a philosophical enigma, a psychological mystery,

and a puzzle of logic. Not surprisingly, considering the massive

reification involved, some have doubted its existence since humanity

began distinguishing “time itself” from visible and tangible changes in

the world. As Michael Ende (1984) put it: “There is in the world a great

and yet ordinary secret. All of us are part of it, everyone is aware of

it, but very few ever think of it. Most of us just accept it and never

wonder over it. This secret is time.”

Just what is “time”? Spengler declared that no one should be allowed to

ask. The physicist Richard Feynman (1988) answered, “Don’t even ask me.

It’s just too hard to think about.” Empirically as much as in theory,

the laboratory is powerless to reveal the flow of time, since no

instrument exists that can register its passage. But why do we have such

a strong sense that time does pass, ineluctably and in one particular

direction, if it really doesn’t? Why does this “illusion” have such a

hold over us? We might just as well ask why alienation has such a hold

over us. The passage of time is intimately familiar, the concept of time

mockingly elusive; why should this appear bizarre, in a world whose

survival depends on the mystification of its most basic categories?

We have gone along with the substantiation of time so that it seems a

fact of nature, a power existing in its own right. The growth of a sense

of time—the acceptance of time—is a process of adaptation to an ever

more reified world. It is a constructed dimension, the most elemental

aspect of culture. Time’s inexorable nature provides the ultimate model

of domination.

The further we go in time the worse it gets. We inhabit an age of the

disintegration of experience, according to Adorno. The pressure of time,

like that of its essential progenitor, division of labor, fragments and

disperses all before it. Uniformity, equivalence, separation are

byproducts of time’s harsh force. The intrinsic beauty and meaning of

that fragment of the world that is not-yet-culture moves steadily toward

annihilation under a single cultures-wide clock. Paul Ricoeur’s

assertion (1985) that “we are not capable of producing a concept of time

that is at once cosmological, biological, historical and individual,”

fails to notice how they are converging.

Concerning this “fiction” that upholds and accompanies all the forms of

imprisonment, “the world is filled with propaganda alleging its

existence,” as Bernard Aaronson (1972) put it so well. “All awareness,”

wrote the poet Denise Levertov (1974), “is an awareness of time,”

showing just how deeply alienated we are in time. We have become

regimented under its empire, as time and alienation continue to deepen

their intrusion, their debasement of everyday life. “Does this mean,” as

David Carr (1988) asks, “that the ‘struggle’ of existence is to overcome

time itself?” It may be that exactly this is the last enemy to be

overcome.

In coming to grips with this ubiquitous yet phantom adversary, it is

somewhat easier to say what time is not. It is not synonymous, for

fairly obvious reasons, with change. Nor is it sequence, or order of

succession. Pavlov’s dog, for instance, must have learned that the sound

of the bell was followed by feeding; how else could it have been

conditioned to salivate at that sound? But dogs do not possess time

consciousness, so before and after cannot be said to constitute time.

Somewhat related are inadequate attempts to account for our all but

inescapable sense of time. The neurologist Gooddy (1988), rather along

the lines of Kant, describes it as one of our “subconscious assumptions

about the world.” Some have described it, no more helpfully, as a

product of the imagination, and the philosopher J.J.C. Smart (1980)

decided that it is a feeling that “arises out of metaphysical

confusion.” McTaggart (1908), F.H. Bradley (1930), and Dummett (1978)

have been among 20^(th) century thinkers who have decided against the

existence of time because of its logically contradictory features, but

it seems fairly plain that the presence of time has far deeper causes

than mere mental confusion.

There is nothing even remotely similar to time. It is as unnatural and

yet as universal as alienation. Chacalos (1988) points out that the

present is a notion just as puzzling and intractable as time itself.

What is the present? We know that it is always now; one is confined to

it, in an important sense, and can experience no other “part” of time.

We speak confidently of other parts, however, which we call “past” and

“future.” But whereas things that exist in space elsewhere than here

continue to exist, things that don’t exist now, as Sklar (1992)

observes, don’t really exist at all.

Time necessarily flows; without its passage there would be no sense of

time. Whatever flows, though, flows with respect to time. Time therefore

flows with respect to itself, which is meaningless owing to the fact

that nothing can flow with respect to itself. No vocabulary is available

for the abstract explication of time apart from a vocabulary in which

time is already presupposed. What is necessary is to put all the givens

into question. Metaphysics, with a narrowness that division of labor has

imposed from its inception, is too narrow for such a task.

What causes time to flow, what is it that moves it toward the future?

Whatever it is, it must be beyond our time, deeper and more powerful. It

must depend as Conly (1975) had it, “upon elemental forces which are

continually in operation.”

William Spanos (1987) has noted that certain Latin words for culture not

only signify agriculture or domestication, but are translations from

Greek terms for the spatial image of time. We are, at base,

“time-binders”, in Alfred Korzybski’s lexicon (1948); the species, due

to this characteristic, creates a symbolic class of life, an artificial

world. Time-binding reveals itself in an “enormous increase in the

control over nature.” Time becomes real because it has consequences, and

this efficacy has never been more painfully apparent.

Life, in its barest outline, is said to be a journey through time; that

it is a journey through alienation is the most public of secrets. “No

clock strikes for the happy one,” says a German proverb. Passing time,

once meaningless, is now the inescapable beat, restricting and coercing

us, mirroring blind authority itself. Guyau (1890) determined the flow

of time to be “the distinction between what one needs and what one has,”

and therefore “the incipience of regret.” Carpe diem, the maxim

counsels, but civilization forces us always to mortgage the present to

the future.

Time aims continually toward greater strictness of regularity and

universality. Capital’s technological world charts its progress by this,

could not exist in its absence. “The importance of time,” wrote Bertrand

Russell (1929), lies “rather in relation to our desires than in relation

to truth.” There is a longing that is as palpable as time has become.

The denial of desire can be gauged no more definitively than via the

vast construct we call time.

Time, like technology, is never neutral; it is, as Castoriadis (1991)

rightly judged, “always endowed with meaning.” Everything that

commentators like Ellul have said about technology, in fact, applies to

time, and more deeply. Both conditions are pervasive, omnipresent,

basic, and in general as taken for granted as alienation itself. Time,

like technology, is not only a determining fact but also the enveloping

element in which divided society develops. Similarly, it demands that

its subjects be painstaking, “realistic”, serious, and above all,

devoted to work. It is autonomous in its overall aspect, like

technology; it goes on forever of its own accord.

But like division of labor, which stands behind and sets in motion time

and technology, it is, after all, a socially learned phenomenon. Humans,

and the rest of the world, are synchronized to time and its technical

embodiment, rather than the reverse. Central to this dimension—as it is

to alienation per se—is the feeling of being a helpless spectator. Every

rebel, it follows, also rebels against time and its relentlessness.

Redemption must involve, in a very fundamental sense, redemption from

time.

Time and the Symbolic World

“Time is the accident of accidents,” according to Epicurus. Upon closer

examination, however, its genesis appears less mysterious. It has

occurred to many, in fact, that notions such as “the past,” “the

present,” and “the future” are more linguistic than actual or physical.

The neo-Freudian theorist Lacan, for example, decided that the time

experience is essentially an effect of language. A person with no

language would likely have no sense of the passage of time. R.A. Wilson

(1980), moving much closer to the point, suggested that language was

initiated by the need to express symbolic time. Gosseth (1972) argued

that the system of tenses found in Indo-European languages developed

along with consciousness of a universal or abstract time. Time and

language are coterminous, decided Derrida (1982): “to be in the one is

to be in the other.” Time is a symbolic construct immediately prior,

relatively speaking, to all the others and which requires language for

its actualization.

Paul Valéry (1962) referred to the fall of the species into time as

signalling alienation from nature; “by a sort of abuse, man creates

time,” he wrote. In the timeless epoch before this fall, which

constituted the overwhelming majority of our existence as humans, life,

as has often been said, had a rhythm but not a progression. It was the

state when the soul could “gather in the whole of its being,” in

Rousseau’s words, in the absence of temporal strictures, “where time is

nothing to the soul.” Activities themselves, usually of a leisurely

character, were the points of reference before time and civilization;

nature provided the necessary signals, quite independent of “time”.

Humanity must have been conscious of memories and purposes long before

any explicit distinctions were drawn among past, present, and future

(Fraser, 1988). Furthermore, as the linguist Whorf (1956) estimated,

“preliterate [‘primitive’] communities, far from being subrational, may

show the human mind functioning on a higher and more complex plane of

rationality than among civilized men.”

The largely hidden key to the symbolic world is time; indeed it is at

the origin of human symbolic activity. Time thus occasions the first

alienation, the route away from aboriginal richness and wholeness. “Out

of the simultaneity of experience, the event of Language,” says Charles

Simic (1971), “is an emergence into linear time.” Researchers such as

Zohar (1982) consider faculties of telepathy and precognition to have

been sacrificed for the sake of evolution into symbolic life. If this

sounds far-fetched, the sober positivist Freud (1932) viewed telepathy

as quite possibly “the original archaic means through which individuals

understand one another.” If the perception and apperception of time

relate to the very essence of cultural life (Gurevich 1976), the advent

of this time sense and its concomitant culture represent an

impoverishment, even a disfigurement, by time.

The consequences of this intrusion of time, via language, indicate that

the latter is no more innocent, neutral, or assumption-free than the

former. Time is not only, as Kant said, at the foundation of all our

representations, but, by this fact, also at the foundation of our

adaptation to a qualitatively reduced, symbolic world. Our experience in

this world is under an all-pervasive pressure to be representation, to

be almost unconsciously degraded into symbols and measurements. “Time”,

wrote the German mystic Meister Eckhart, “is what keeps the light from

reaching us.”

Time awareness is what empowers us to deal with our environment

symbolically; there is no time apart from this estrangement. It is by

means of progressive symbolization that time becomes naturalized,

becomes a given, is removed from the sphere of conscious cultural

production. “Time becomes human in the measure to which it becomes

actualized in narrative,” is another way of putting it (Ricoeur 1984).

The symbolic accretions in this process constitute a steady throttling

of instinctive desire; repression develops the sense of time unfolding.

Immediacy gives way, replaced by the mediations that make history

possible—language in the forefront.

One begins to see past such banalities as “time is an incomprehensible

quality of the given world” (Sebba 1991). Number, art, religion make

their appearances in this “given” world, disembodied phenomena of

reified life. These emerging rites, in turn, Gurevitch (1964) surmises,

lead to “the production of new symbolic contents, thus encouraging time

leaping forward.” Symbols, including time, of course, now have lives of

their own, in this cumulative, interacting progression. David Braine’s

The Reality of Time and the Existence of God (1988) is illustrative. It

argues that it is precisely time’s reality which proves the existence of

God; civilization’s perfect logic.

All ritual is an attempt, through symbolism, to return to the timeless

state. Ritual is a gesture of abstraction from that state, however, a

false step that only leads further away. The “timelessness” of number is

part of this trajectory, and contributes much to time as a fixed

concept. In fact, Blumenberg (1983) seems largely correct in assaying

that “time is not measured as something that has been present all along;

instead it is produced, for the first time, by measurement.” To express

time we must, in some way, quantify it; number is therefore essential.

Even where time has already appeared, a slowly more divided social

existence works toward its progressive reification only by means of

number. The sense of passing time is not keen among tribal peoples, for

example, who do not mark it with calendars or clocks.

Time: an original meaning of the word in ancient Greek is division.

Number, when added to time, makes the dividing or separating that much

more potent. The non-civilized often have considered it “unlucky” to

count living creatures, and generally resist adopting the practice (e.g.

Dobrizhoffer 1822). The intuition for number was far from spontaneous

and inevitable, but “already in early civilizations,” Schimmel (1992)

reports, “one feels that numbers are a reality having as it were a

magnetic power field around them.” It is not surprising that among

ancient cultures with the strongest emerging senses of time—Egyptian,

Babylonian, Mayan—we see numbers associated with ritual figures and

deities; indeed the Mayans and Babylonians both had number gods (Barrow

1992).

Much later the clock, with its face of numbers, encouraged society to

abstract and quantify the experience of time still further. Every clock

reading is a measurement that joins the clock watcher to the “flow of

time.” And we absently delude ourselves that we know what time is

because we know what time it is. If we did away with clocks, Shallis

(1982) reminds us, objective time would also disappear. More

fundamentally, if we did away with specialization and technology,

alienation would be banished.

The mathematizing of nature was the basis for the birth of modern

rationalism and science in the West. This had stemmed from demands for

number and measurement in connection with similar teachings about time,

in the service of mercantile capitalism. The continuity of number and

time as a geometrical locus were fundamental to the Scientific

Revolution, which projected Galileo’s dictum to measure all that is

measurable and make measurable that which is not. Mathematically

divisible time is necessary for the conquest of nature, and for even the

rudiments of modern technology.

From this point on, number-based symbolic time became crushingly real,

an abstract construction “removed from and even contrary to every

internal and external human experience” (Syzamosi 1986). Under its

pressure, money and language, merchandise and information have become

steadily less distinguishable, and division of labor more extreme.

To symbolize is to express time consciousness, for the symbol embodies

the structure of time (Darby 1982). Clearer still is Meerloo’s

formulation: “To understand a symbol and its development is to grasp

human history in a nutshell.” The contrast is the life of the

non-civilized, lived in a capacious present that cannot be reduced to

the single moment of the mathematical present. As the continual now gave

way to increasing reliance upon systems of significant symbols

(language, number, art, ritual, myth) dislodged from the now, the

further abstraction, history, began to develop. Historical time is no

more inherent in reality, no less an imposition on it, than the earlier,

less choate forms of time.

In a slowly more synthetic context, astronomical observation is invested

with new meanings. Once pursued for its own sake, it comes to provide

the vehicle for scheduling rituals and coordinating the activities of

complex society. With the help of the stars, the year and its divisions

exist as instruments of organizational authority (Leach 1954). The

formation of a calendar is basic to the formation of a civilization. The

calendar was the first symbolic artifact that regulated social behavior

by keeping track of time. And what is involved is not the control of

time but its opposite: enclosure by time in a world of very real

alienation. One recalls that our word comes from the Latin calends, the

first day of the month, when business accounts had to be settled.

Time to Pray, Time to Work

“No time is entirely present,” said the Stoic Chrysippus, and meanwhile

the concept of time was being further advanced by the underlying

Judeo-Christian tenet of a linear, irreversible path between creation

and salvation. This essentially historical view of time is the very core

of Christianity; all the basic notions of measurable, one-way time can

be found in St. Augustine’s (fifth century) writings. With the spread of

the new religion the strict regulation of time, on a practical plane,

was needed to help maintain the discipline of monastic life. Bells

summoning the monks to prayer eight times daily were heard far beyond

the confines of the cloister, and thus a measure of time regulation was

imposed on society at large. The population continued to exhibit “une

vaste indiffrance au temps” throughout the feudal era, according to Marc

Bloch (1940), but it is no accident that the first public clocks adorned

cathedrals in the West. Worth noting in this regard is the fact that the

calling of precise prayer times became the chief externalization of

medieval Islamic belief.

The invention of the mechanical clock was one of the most important

turning points in the history of science and technology; indeed of all

human art and culture (Synge 1959). The improvement in accuracy

presented authority with enhanced opportunities for oppression. An early

devotee of elaborate mechanical clocks, for example, was Duke Gian

Galeazzo Visconti, described in 1381 as “a sedate but crafty ruler with

a great love of order and precision” (Fraser 1988). As Weizenbaum (1976)

wrote, the clock began to create “literally a new reality...that was and

remains an impoverished version of the old one.”

A qualitative change was introduced. Even when nothing was happening,

time did not cease to flow. Events, from this era on, are put into this

homogeneous, objectively measured, moving envelope—and this unilinear

progression incited resistance. The most extreme were the chiliast, or

millenarian, movements, which appeared in various parts of Europe from

the 14^(th) into the 17^(th) centuries. These generally took the form of

peasant risings which aimed at recreating the primal egalitarian state

of nature and were explicitly opposed to historical time. These utopian

explosions were quelled, but remnants of earlier time concepts persisted

as a “lower” stratum of folk consciousness in many areas.

During the Renaissance, domination by time reached a new level as public

clocks now tolled all twenty-four hours of the day and added new hands

to mark the passing seconds. A keen sense of time’s all-consuming

presence is the great discovery of the age, and nothing portrays this

more graphically than the figure of Father Time. Renaissance art fused

the Greek god Kronos with the Roman god Saturn to form the familiar grim

deity representing the power of Time, armed with a fatal scythe

signifying his association with agriculture/domestication. The Dance of

Death and other medieval memento mori artifacts preceded Father Time,

but the subject is now time rather than death.

The seventeenth century was the first in which people thought of

themselves as inhabiting a particular century. One now needed to take

one’s bearings within time. Francis Bacon’s The Masculine Birth of Time

(1603) and A Discourse Concerning a New Planet (1605) embraced the

deepening dimension and revealed how a heightened sense of time could

serve the new scientific spirit. “To choose time is to save time,” he

wrote, and “Truth is the daughter of time.” Descartes followed,

introducing the idea of time as limitless. He was one of the first

advocates of the modern idea of progress, closely related to that of

unbounded linear time, and characteristically expressing itself in his

famous invitation that we become “masters and possessors of nature.”

Newton’s clockwork universe was the crowning achievement of the

Scientific Revolution in the seventeenth century, and was grounded in

his conception of “Absolute, true and mathematical time, of itself and

from its own nature, flowing equably without relation to anything

eternal.” Time is now the grand ruler, answering to no one, influenced

by nothing, completely independent of the environment: the model of

unassailable authority and perfect guarantor of unchanging alienation.

Classical Newtonian physics in fact remains, despite changes in science,

the dominant, everyday conception of time.

The appearance of independent, abstract time found its parallel in the

emergence of a growing, formally free working class forced to sell its

labor power as an abstract commodity on the market. Prior to the coming

of the factory system but already subject to time’s disciplinary power,

this labor force was the inverse of the monarch Time: free and

independent in name only. In Foucault’s judgment (1973), the West had

become a “carceral society” from this point on. Perhaps more directly to

the point is the Balkan proverb, “A clock is a lock.”

In 1749 Rousseau threw away his watch, a symbolic rejection of modern

science and civilization. Somewhat more in the dominant spirit of the

age, however, were the gifts of fifty-one watches to Marie Antoinette

upon her engagement. The word is certainly appropriate, as people had to

“watch” the time more and more; watches would soon become one of the

first consumer durables of the industrial era.

William Blake and Goethe both attacked Newton, the symbol of the new

time and science, for his distancing of life from the sensual, his

reduction of the natural to the measurable. Capitalist ideologue Adam

Smith, on the other hand, echoed and extended Newton, by calling for

greater rationalization and routinization. Smith, like Newton, labored

under the spell of an increasingly powerful and remorseless time in

promoting further division of labor as objective and absolute progress.

The Puritans had proclaimed waste of time the first and in principle the

deadliest of sins (Weber 1921); this became, about a century later, Ben

Franklin’s “Time is money.” The factory system was initiated by

clockmakers and the clock was the symbol and fountainhead of the order,

discipline and repression required to create an industrial proletariat.

Hegel’s grand system in the early 19^(th) century heralded the “push

into time” that is History’s momentum; time is our “destiny and

necessity,” he declared. Postone (1993) noted that the “progress” of

abstract time is closely tied to the “progress” of capitalism as a way

of life. Waves of industrialism drowned the resistance of the Luddites;

appraising this general period, Lyotard (1988) decided that “the illness

of time was now incurable.”

An increasingly complex class society requires an ever larger array of

time signals. Fights against time, as Thompson (1967) and Hohn (1984)

have pointed out, gave way to struggles over time; resistance to being

yoked to time and its inherent demands was defeated in general,

replaced, typically, by disputes over the fair determination of time

schedules or the length of the work day. (In an address to the First

International (July 28, 1868), Karl Marx advocated, by the way, age nine

as the time to begin work.)

The clock descended from the cathedral, to court and courthouse, next to

the bank and railway station, and finally to the wrist and pocket of

each decent citizen. Time had to become more “democratic” in order to

truly colonize subjectivity. The subjection of outer nature, as Adorno

and others have understood, is successful only in the measure of the

conquest of inner nature. The unleashing of the forces of production, to

put it another way, depended on time’s victory in its long-waged war on

freer consciousness. Industrialism brought with it a more complete

commodification of time, time in its most predatory form yet. It was

this that Giddens (1981) saw as “the key to the deepest transformations

of day-to-day social life that are brought about by the emergence of

capitalism.”

“Time marches on,” as the saying goes, in a world increasingly dependent

on time and a time increasingly unified. A single giant clock hangs over

the world and dominates. It pervades all; in its court there is no

appeal. The standardization of world time marks a victory for the

efficient/machine society, a universalism that undoes particularity as

surely as computers lead to homogenization of thought.

Paul Virilio (1986) has gone so far as to foresee that “the loss of

material space leads to the government of nothing but time.” A further

provocative notion posits a reversal of the birth of history out of

maturing time. Virilio (1991), in fact, finds us already living within a

system of technological temporality where history has been eclipsed.

“...the primary question becomes less one of relations to history than

one of relations to time.”

Such theoretical flights aside, however, there is ample evidence and

testimony as to time’s central role in society. In “Time — The Next

Source of Competitive Advantage” (July-August, 1988 Harvard Business

Review), George Stark, Jr. discusses it as pivotal in the positioning of

capital: “As a strategic weapon, time is the equivalent of money,

productivity, quality, even innovation.” Time management is certainly

not confined to the corporations; Levine’s 1985 study of publicly

accessible clocks in six countries demonstrated that their accuracy was

an exact gauge of the relative industrialization of national life. Paul

Adler’s January-February, 1993 Harvard Business Review offering,

“Time-and-Motion Regained,” nakedly champions the neo-Taylorist

standardization and regimentation of work: behind the well-publicized

“workplace democracy” window dressing in some factories remains the

“time-and-motion discipline and formal bureaucratic structures essential

for efficiency and quality in routine operations.”

Time in Literature

It is clear that the advent of writing facilitated the fixation of time

concepts and the beginning of history. But as the anthropologist Goody

(1991) points out, “oral cultures are often only too prepared to accept

these innovations.” They have already been conditioned, after all, by

language itself. McLuhan (1962) discussed how the coming of the printed

book, and mass literacy, reinforced the logic of linear time.

Life was steadily forced to adapt. “For now hath time made me his

numbering clock,” wrote Shakespeare in Richard II. “Time”, like “rich”,

was one of the favorite words of the Bard, a time-haunted figure. A

hundred years later, Defoe’s Robinson Crusoe reflected how little escape

from time seemed possible. Marooned on a desert island, Crusoe is deeply

concerned with the passage of time; keeping close track of his affairs,

even in such a setting, meant above all keeping track of the time,

especially as long as his pen and ink lasted.

Northrop Frye (1950) saw the “alliance of time and Western man” as the

defining characteristic of the novel. Ian Watt’s The Rise of the Novel

(1957) likewise focused on the new concern with time that stimulated the

novel’s emergence in the eighteenth century. As Jonathan Swift told it

in Gulliver’s Travels (1726), his protagonist never did anything without

looking at his watch. “He called it his oracle, and said it pointed out

the time for every action of his life.” The Lilliputians concluded that

the watch was Gulliver’s god. Sterne’s Tristram Shandy (1760), on the

eve of the Industrial Revolution, begins with the mother of Tristram

interrupting his father at the moment of their monthly coitus: “‘Pray,

my dear,’ quoth my mother, ‘have you not forgot to wind up the clock?’”

In the nineteenth century Poe satirized the authority of clocks, linking

them to bourgeois superficiality and obsession with order. Time is the

real subject of Flaubert’s novels, according to Hauser (1956), as Walter

Pater (1901) sought in literature the “wholly concrete moment” which

would “absorb past and future in an intense consciousness of the

present,” similar to Joyce’s celebration of “epiphanies”. In Marius the

Epicurean (1909), Pater depicts Marius suddenly realizing “the

possibility of a real world beyond time.” Meanwhile Swinburne looked for

a respite beyond “time-stricken lands” and Baudelaire declared his fear

and hatred of chronological time, the devouring foe.

The disorientation of an age wracked by time and subject to the

acceleration of history has led modern writers to deal with time from

new and extreme points of view. Proust delineated interrelationships

among events that transcended conventional temporal order and thus

violated Newtonian conceptions of causation. His thirteen-volume A la

Recherche du Temps Perdu (1925), usually rendered in English as

Remembrance of Things Past, is more literally and accurately translated

as Searching for Lost Time. In it he judges that “a minute freed from

the order of time has recreated in us...the individual freed from the

order of time,” and recognizes “the only environment in which one could

live and enjoy the essence of things, that is to say, entirely outside

time.”

Philosophy in the twentieth century has been largely preoccupied with

time. Consider the misguided attempts to locate authentic time by

thinkers as different as Bergson and Heidegger, or the latter’s virtual

deification of time. A.A. Mendilow’s Time and the Novel (1952) reveals

how the same intense interest has dominated the novels of the century,

in particular those of Joyce, Woolf, Conrad, James, Gide, Mann, and of

course, Proust. Other studies, such as Church’s Time and Reality (1962),

have expanded this list of novelists to include, among others, Kafka,

Sartre, Faulkner, and Vonnegut.

And of course time-struck literature cannot be confined to the novel.

T.S. Eliot’s poetry often expressed a yearning to escape time-bound,

time-ridden conventionality. “Burnt Norton” (1941) is a good example,

with these lines:

Time past and time future

Allow but a little consciousness.

To be conscious is not to be in time.

Samuel Beckett, early in his career (1931), wrote pointedly of “the

poisonous ingenuity of Time in the science of affliction.” The play

Waiting for Godot (1955) is an obvious candidate in this regard, and so

is his Murphy (1957), in which time becomes reversible in the mind of

the main character. When the clock may go either way, our sense of time,

and time itself, vanishes.

The Psychology of Time

Turning to what is commonly called psychology, we again come upon one of

the most fundamental questions: Is there really a phenomenon of time

that exists apart from any individual, or does it reside only in one’s

perceptions of it? Husserl, for example, failed to show why

consciousness in the modern world seems to inevitably constitute itself

in time. We know that experiences, like events of every other kind, are

neither past, present nor future in themselves.

Whereas there was little sociological interest in time until the 1970s,

the number of studies of time in the literature of psychology has

increased rapidly since 1930 (Lauer 1988). Time is perhaps hardest of

all to define “psychologically”. What is time? What is the experience of

time? What is alienation? What is the experience of alienation? If the

latter subject were not so neglected the obvious interrelationship would

be made clear.

Davies (1977) termed time’s passage “a psychological phenomenon of

mysterious origin” and concluded (1983), “the secret of mind will only

be solved when we understand the secret of time.” Given the artificial

separation of the individual from society, which defines their field, it

is inevitable that such psychologists and psychoanalysts as Eissler

(1955), Loewald (1962), Namnum (1972), and Morris (1983) have

encountered “great difficulties” in studying time!

At least a few partial insights have been achieved, however. Hartcollis

(1983), for instance, noted that time is not only an abstraction but a

feeling, while Korzybski (1948) had already taken this further with his

observation that “‘time’ is a feeling, produced by conditions of this

world....” In all our lives we are “waiting for Godot,” according to

Arlow (1986), who believed that our experience of time arises out of

unfulfilled emotional needs. Similarly, Reichenbach (1956) had termed

anti-time philosophies, like religion, “documents of emotional

dissatisfaction.” In Freudian terms, Bergler and Roheim (1946) saw the

passage of time as symbolizing separation periods originating in early

infancy. “The calendar is an ultimate materialization of separation

anxiety.” If informed by a critical interest in the social and

historical context, the implications of these undeveloped points could

become serious contributions. Confined to psychology, however, they

remain limited and even misleading.

In the world of alienation no adult can contrive or decree the freedom

from time that the child habitually enjoys—and must be made to lose.

Time training, the essence of schooling, is vitally important to

society. This training, as Fraser (1984) very cogently puts it, “bears

in almost paradigmatic form the features of a civilizing process.” A

patient of Joost Meerlo (1966) “expressed it sarcastically: ‘Time is

civilization,’ by which she meant that scheduling and meticulousness

were the great weapons used by adults to force the youngsters into

submission and servility.” Piaget’s studies (1946, 1952) could detect no

innate sense of time. Rather, the abstract notion of “time” is of

considerable difficulty to the young. It is not something they learn

automatically; there is no spontaneous orientation toward time (Hermelin

and O’Connor 1971, Voyat 1977).

Time and tidy are related etymologically, and our Newtonian idea of time

represents perfect and universal ordering. The cumulative weight of this

ever more pervasive pressure shows up in the increasing number of

patients with time anxiety symptoms (Lawson 1990). Dooley (1941)

referred to “the observed fact that people who are obsessive in

character, whatever their type of neurosis, are those who make most

extensive use of the sense of time....” Pettit’s “Anality and Time”

(1969) argued convincingly for the close connection between the two, as

Meerloo (1966), citing the character and achievements of Mussolini and

Eichmann, found “a definite connection between time compulsion and

fascistic aggression.”

Capek (1961) called time “a huge and chronic hallucination of the human

mind”; there are few experiences indeed that can be said to be timeless.

Orgasm, LSD, a life “flashing before one’s eyes” in a moment of extreme

danger...these are some of the rare, evanescent situations intense

enough to escape from time’s insistence.

Timelessness is the ideal of pleasure, wrote Marcuse (1955). The passage

of time, on the other hand, fosters the forgetting of what was and what

can be. It is the enemy of eros and deep ally of the order of

repression. The mental processes of the unconscious are in fact

timeless, decided Freud (1920). “...time does not change them in any way

and the idea of time cannot be applied to them.” Thus desire is already

outside of time. As Freud said in 1932: “There is nothing in the Id that

corresponds to the notion of time; there is no recognition of the

passage of time.”

Marie Bonaparte (1939) argued that time becomes ever more plastic and

obedient to the pleasure principle insofar as we loosen the bonds of

full ego control. Dreams are a form of thinking among non-civilized

peoples (Kracke 1987); this faculty must have once been much more

accessible to us. The Surrealists believed that reality could be much

more fully understood if we could make the connection to our

instinctive, subconscious experiences; Breton (1924), for example,

proclaimed the radical goal of a resolution of dream and conscious

reality.

When we dream the sense of time is virtually nonexistent, replaced by a

sensation of presentness. It should come as no surprise that dreams,

which ignore the rules of time, would attract the notice of those

searching for liberatory clues, or that the unconscious, with its

“storms of impulse” (Stern 1977), frightens those with a stake in the

neurosis we call civilization. Norman O. Brown (1959) saw the sense of

time or history as a function of repression; if repression were

abolished, he reasoned, we would be released from time. Similarly,

Coleridge (1801) recognized in the man of “methodical industry” the

origin and creator of time.

In his Critique of Cynical Reason (1987), Peter Sloterdijk called for

the “radical recognition of the Id without reservation,” a narcissistic

self-affirmation that would laugh in the face of morose society.

Narcissism has of course traditionally been cast as wicked, the “heresy

of self-love.” In reality that meant it was reserved for the ruling

classes, while all others (workers, women, slaves) had to practice

submission and self-effacement (Fine 1986). The narcissist symptoms are

feelings of emptiness, unreality, alienation, life as no more than a

succession of moments, accompanied by a longing for powerful autonomy

and self-esteem (Alford 1988, Grunberger 1979). Given the

appropriateness of these “symptoms” and desires it is little wonder that

narcissism can be seen as a potentially emancipatory force (Zweig 1980).

Its demand for total satisfaction is obviously a subversive

individualism, at a minimum.

The narcissist “hates time, denies time” (letter to author, Alford 1993)

and this, as always, provokes a severe reaction from the defenders of

time and authority. Psychiatrist E. Mark Stern (1977), for instance:

“Since time begins beyond one’s control one must correspond to its

demands.... Courage is the antithesis of narcissism.” This condition,

which certainly may include negative aspects, contains the germ of a

different reality principle, aiming at the non-time of perfection

wherein being and becoming are one and including, implicitly, a halt to

time.

Time in Science

I’m not a scientist but I do know that all things begin and end in

eternity.

The Man Who Fell to Earth, Walter Tevis

Science, for our purposes, does not comment on time and estrangement

with anywhere near the directness of, say, psychology. But science can

be re-construed to shed light on the topic at hand, because of the many

parallels between scientific theory and human affairs.

“Time,” decided N.A. Kozyrev (1971), “is the most important and the most

mysterious phenomenon of Nature. Its notion is beyond the grasp of

imagination.” Some scientists, in fact, have felt (e.g. Dingle 1966)

that “all the real problems associated with the notion of time are

independent of physics.” Science, and physics in particular, may indeed

not have the last word; it is another source of commentary, however,

though itself alienated and generally indirect.

Is “physical time” the same as the time of which we are conscious; if

not, how does it differ? In physics, time seems to be an undefined basic

dimension, as much a taken-for-granted given as it is outside the realm

of science. This is one way to remind ourselves that, as with every

other kind of thinking, scientific ideas are meaningless outside their

cultural context. They are symptoms of and symbol for the ways of living

that give rise to them. According to Nietzsche, all writing is

inherently metaphorical, even though science is rarely looked at this

way. Science has developed by drawing an increasingly sharp separation

between inner and outer worlds, between dream and “reality”. This has

been accomplished by the mathematization of nature, which has largely

meant that the scientist proceeds by a method that debars him or her

from the larger context, including the origins and significance of

his/her projects. Nonetheless, as H.P. Robinson (1964) stated, “the

cosmologies which humanity has set up at various times and in various

localities inevitably reflect the physical and intellectual environment,

including above all the interests and culture of each society.”

Subjective time, as P.C.W. Davies pointed out (1981), “possesses

apparent qualities that are absent from the ‘outside’ world and which

are fundamental to our conception of reality”—principally the “passing”

of time. Our sense of separation from the world owes largely to this

discrepancy. We exist in time (and alienation), but time is not found in

the physical world. The time variable, though useful to science, is a

theoretical construct. “The laws of science,” Stephen Hawking (1988)

explained, “do not distinguish between past and future.” Einstein had

gone further than this some thirty years earlier; in one of his last

letters, he wrote that “People like us, who believe in physics, know

that the distinction between past, present and future is only a

stubborn, persistent illusion.” But science partakes of society in other

ways concerning time, and very deeply. The more “rational” it becomes,

the more variations in time are suppressed. Theoretical physics

geometrizes time by conceiving it as a straight line, for example.

Science does not stand apart form the cultural history of time.

As implied above, however, physics does not contain the idea of a

present instant of time that passes (Park 1972). Furthermore, the

fundamental laws are not only completely reversible as to the ‘arrow of

time’—as Hawking noted—but “irreversible phenomena appear as the result

of the particular nature of our human cognition,” according to Watanabe

(1953). Once again we find human experience playing a decisive role,

even in this most “objective” realm. Zee (1992) put it this way: “Time

is that one concept in physics we can’t talk about without dragging in,

at some level, consciousness.”

Even in seemingly straightforward areas ambiguities exist where time is

concerned. While the complexity of the most complex species may

increase, for example, not all species become more complex, prompting

J.M. Smith (1972) to conclude that it is “difficult to say whether

evolution as a whole has a direction.”

In terms of the cosmos, it is argued, “time’s arrow” is automatically

indicated by the fact that the galaxies are receding away from each

other. But there seems to be virtual unanimity that as far as the basics

of physics are concerned, the “flow” of time is irrelevant and makes no

sense; fundamental physical laws are completely neutral with regard to

the direction of time (Mehlberg 1961, 1971, Landsberg 1982, Squires

1986, Watanabe 1953, 1956, Swinburne 1986, Morris 1984, Mallove 1987,

D’Espagnant 1989, etc.). Modern physics even provides scenarios in which

time ceases to exist and, in reverse, comes into existence. So why is

our world asymmetric in time? Why can’t it go backward as well as

forward? This is a paradox, inasmuch as the individual molecular

dynamics are all reversible. The main point, to which I will return

later, is that time’s arrow reveals itself as complexity develops, in

striking parallel with the social world.

The flow of time manifests itself in the context of future and past, and

they in turn depend on a referent known as the now. With Einstein and

relativity, it is clear that there is no universal present: we cannot

say it is “now” throughout the universe. There is no fixed interval at

all that is independent of the system to which it refers, just as

alienation is dependent on its context.

Time is thus robbed of the autonomy and objectivity it enjoyed in the

Newtonian world. It is definitely more individually delineated, in

Einstein’s revelations, than the absolute and universal monarch it had

been. Time is relative to specific conditions and varies according to

such factors as speed and gravitation. But if time has become more

“decentralized”, it has also colonized subjectivity more than ever

before. As time and alienation have become the rule throughout the

world, there is little solace in knowing that they are dependent on

varying circumstances. The relief comes in acting on this understanding;

it is the invariance of alienation that causes the Newtonian model of

independently flowing time to hold sway within us, long after its

theoretical foundations were eliminated by relativity.

Quantum theory, dealing with the smallest parts of the universe, is

known as the fundamental theory of matter. The core of quantum theory

follows other fundamental physical theories, like relativity, in making

no distinction in the direction of time (Coveny and Highfield 1990). A

basic premise is indeterminism, in which the movement of particles at

this level is a matter of probabilities. Along with such elements as

positrons, which can be regarded as electrons moving backward in time,

and tachyons, faster-than-light particles that generate effects and

contexts reversing the temporal order (Gribbin 1979, Lindley 1993),

quantum physics has raised fundamental questions about time and

causality. In the quantum microworld common acausal relationships have

been discovered that transcend time and put into question the very

notion of the ordering of events in time. There can be “connections and

correlations between very distant events in the absence of any

intermediary force or signal” which occur instantaneously (Zohar 1982,

Aspect 1982). The eminent American physicist John Wheeler has called

attention (1977, 1980, 1986) to phenomena in which action taken now

affects the course of events that have already happened.

Gleick (1992) summed up the situation as follows: “With simultaneity

gone, sequentiality was foundering, causality was under pressure, and

scientists generally felt themselves free to consider temporal

possibilities that would have seemed far-fetched a generation before.”

At least one approach in quantum physics has attempted to remove the

notion of time altogether (J.G. Taylor 1972); D. Park (1972), for

instance, said, “I prefer the atemporal representation to the temporal

one.”

The bewildering situation in science finds its match in the extremity of

the social world. Alienation, like time, produces ever greater oddities

and pressures: the most fundamental questions finally, almost

necessarily, emerge in both cases.

St. Augustine’s fifth century complaint was that he didn’t understand

what the measurement of time really consisted of. Einstein, admitting

the inadequacy of his comment, often defined time as “what a clock

measures.” Quantum physics, for its part, posits the inseparability of

measurer and what is measured. Via a process physicists don’t claim to

understand fully, the act of observation or measurement not only reveals

a particle’s condition but actually determines it (Pagels 1983). This

has prompted Wheeler (1984) to ask, “Is everything—including time—built

from nothingness by acts of observer-participancy?” Again a striking

parallel, for alienation, at every level and from its origin, requires

exactly such participation, virtually as a matter of definition.

Time’s arrow—irrevocable, one-direction-only time—is the monster that

has proven itself more terrifying than any physical projectile.

Directionless time is not time at all, and Cambel (1993) identifies time

directionality as “a primary characteristic of complex systems.” The

time-reversible behavior of atomic particles is “generally commuted into

behavior of the system that is irreversible,” concluded Schlegel (1961).

If not rooted in the micro world, where does time come from? Where does

our time-bound world come from? It is here that we encounter a

provocative analogy. The small scale world described by physics, with

its mysterious change into the macro world of complex systems, is

analogous to the “primitive” social world and the origins of division of

labor, leading to complex, class-divided society with its apparently

irreversible “progress”.

A generally held tenet of physical theory is that the arrow of time is

dependent on the Second Law of Thermodynamics (e.g. Reichenbach 1956),

which asserts that all systems tend toward ever greater disorder or

entropy. The past is thus more orderly than the future. Some proponents

of the Second Law (e.g. Boltzmann 1866) have found in entropic increase

the very meaning of the past-future distinction.

This general principle of irreversibility was developed in the middle

decades of the 19^(th) century, beginning with Carnot in 1824, when

industrial capitalism itself reached its apparent non-reversible point.

If evolution was the century’s optimistic application of irreversible

time, the Second Law of Thermodynamics was its pessimistic one. In its

original terms, it pictured a universe as an enormous heat engine

running down, where work became increasingly subject to inefficiency and

disorder. But nature, as Toda (1978) noticed, is not an engine, does not

work, and is not concerned with “order” or “disorder”. The cultural

aspect of this theory—namely, capital’s fear for its future—is hard to

miss.

One hundred and fifty years later, theoretical physicists realize that

the Second Law and its supposed explanation of the arrow of time cannot

be considered a solved problem (N‚eman 1982). Many supporters of

reversible time in nature consider the Second Law too superficial, a

secondary law not a primary one (e.g. Haken 1988, Penrose 1989). Others

(e.g. Sklar 1985) find the very concept of entropy ill-defined and

problematic, and, related to the charge of superficiality, it is argued

that the phenomena described by the Second Law can be ascribed to

particular initial conditions and do not represent the workings of a

general principle (Davies 1981, Barrow 1991). Furthermore, not every

pair of events that bear the “afterward” relation the one to the other

bear an entropic difference. The science of complexity (with a wider

scope than chaos theory) has discovered that not all systems tend toward

disorder (Lewin 1992), also contrary to the Second Law. Moreover,

isolated systems, in which no exchanges with the environment are

allowed, display the Second Law’s irreversible trend; even the universe

may not be such a closed system. Sklar (1974) points out that we don’t

know whether the total entropy of the universe is increasing,

decreasing, or remaining stationary.

Despite such aporias and objections, a movement toward an “irreversible

physics” based on the Second Law is underway, with quite interesting

implications. 1977 Nobel Laureate Ilya Prigogine seems to be the most

tireless and public advocate of the view that there is an innate

unidirectional time at all levels of existence. Whereas the fundamentals

of every major scientific theory, as noted, are neutral with respect to

time, Prigogine gives time a primary emphasis in the universe.

Irreversibility is for him and his like-minded fellow believers an

over-arching primal axiom. In supposedly nonpartisan science, the

question of time has clearly become a political matter.

Prigogine (1985), in a symposium sponsored by Honda and promoting such

projects as Artificial Intelligence: “Questions such as the origin of

life, the origin of the universe, or the origin of matter, can no longer

be discussed without recourse to irreversibility.” It is no coincidence

that non-scientist Alvin Toffler, America’s leading cheerleader for a

high-tech world, provided an enthusiastic forward for one of the basic

texts of the pro-time campaign, Prigogine and Stenger’s Order Out of

Chaos (1984). Prigogine disciple Ervin Laszlo, in a bid to legitimate

and extend the dogma of universally irreversible time, asks whether the

laws of nature are applicable to the human world. He soon answers, in

effect, his own disingenuous question (1985): “The general

irreversibility of technological innovation overrides the indeterminacy

of individual points of bifurcation and drives the processes of history

in the observed direction from primitive tribes to modern

techno-industrial states.” How “scientific”! This transposition from the

“laws of nature” to the social world could hardly be improved on as a

description of time, division of labor, and the mega-machine crushing

the autonomy or “reversibility” of human decision. Leggett (1987)

expressed this perfectly: “So it would seem that the arrow of time which

appears in the apparently impersonal subject of thermodynamics is

intimately related to what we, as human agents, can or cannot do.”

It is deliverance from “chaos” which Prigogine and others promise the

ruling system, using the model of irreversible time. Capital has always

reigned in fear of entropy or disorder. Resistance, especially

resistance to work, is the real entropy, which time, history, and

progress constantly seek to banish. Prigogine and Stenger (1984) wrote:

“Irreversibility is either true on all levels or none.” All or nothing,

always the ultimate stakes of the game.

Since civilization subjugated humanity we have had to live with the

melancholy idea that our highest aspirations are perhaps impossible in a

world of steadily mounting time. The more that pleasure and

understanding are deferred, moved out of reach—and this is the essence

of civilization—the more palpable is the dimension of time. Nostalgia

for the past, fascination with the idea of time travel, and the heated

quest for increased longevity are some of the symptoms of time sickness,

and there seems to be no ready cure. “What does not elapse in time is

the lapse of time itself,” as Merleau-Ponty (1945) realized.

In addition to the general antipathy at large, however, it is possible

to point out some recent specifics of opposition. The Society for the

Retardation of Time was established in 1990 and has a few hundred

members in four European countries. Less whimsical than it may sound,

its members are committed to reversing the contemporary acceleration of

time in everyday life, toward the aim of being allowed to live more

satisfying lives. Michael Theunissen’s Negative Theology of Time

appeared in 1991, aimed explicitly at what it sees as the ultimate human

enemy. This work has engendered a very lively debate in philosophical

circles (Penta 1993), due to its demand for a negative reconsideration

of time.

“Time is the one single movement appropriate to itself in all its

parts,” wrote Merleau-Ponty (1962). Here we see the fullness of

alienation in the separated world of capital. Time is thought of by us

before its parts; it thus reveals the totality. The crisis of time is

the crisis of the whole. Its triumph, apparently well established, was

in fact never complete as long as anyone could question the first

premises of its being.

Above Lake Silviplana, Nietzsche found the inspiration for Thus Spake

Zarathustra. “Six thousand feet above men and time...,” he wrote in his

journal. But time cannot be transcended by means of a lofty contempt for

humanity, because overcoming the alienation that it generates is not a

solitary project. In this sense I prefer Rexroth’s (1968) formulation:

“the only Absolute is the Community of Love with which Time ends.”

Can we put an end to time? Its movement can be seen as the master and

measure of a social existence that has become increasingly empty and

technicized. Averse to all that is spontaneous and immediate, time more

and more clearly reveals its bond with alienation. The scope of our

project of renewal must include the entire length of this joint

domination. Divided life will be replaced by the possibility of living

completely and wholly— timelessly—only when we erase the primary causes

of that division.

We have gone along with the substantiation of time so that it seems a

fact of nature, a power existing in its own right. The growth of a sense

of time—the acceptance of time—is a process of adaptation to an ever

more reified world. It is a constructed dimension, the most elemental

aspect of culture. Time’s inexorable nature provides the ultimate model

of domination.

All ritual is an attempt, through symbolism, to return to the timeless

state. Ritual is a gesture of abstraction from that state, however, a

false step that only leads further away. The “timelessness” of number is

part of this trajectory, and contributes much to time as a fixed

concept.

With the help of the stars, the year and its divisions exist as

instruments of organizational authority (Leach 1954). The formation of a

calendar is basic to the formation of a civilization. The calendar was

the first symbolic artifact that regulated social behavior by keeping

track of time. And what is involved is not the control of time but its

opposite: enclosure by time in a world of very real alienation.

In the world of alienation no adult can contrive or decree the freedom

from time that the child habitually enjoys—and must be made to lose.

Time training, the essence of schooling, is vitally important to

society. This training, as Fraser (1984) very cogently puts it, “bears

in almost paradigmatic form the features of a civilizing process.”