đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș no-against-adult-supremacy-vol-1.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 12:55:31. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: NO! Against Adult Supremacy Vol. 1 Author: Samantha Godwin, Kathleen Nicole OâNeal, Cevin Soling, Damien Sojoyner, Marc Silverstein Language: en Topics: adult supremacy, parenting, child rights, child liberation, anti-oppression, unschooling, youth liberation, school, youth, kids, NO! Against Adult Supremacy Source: Retrieved on february 29, 2019 from https://stinneydistro.wordpress.com/index/
Sojoyner, Marc Silverstein
Excerpt: academia.edu/2046034/Childrens_Oppression_Rights_and_Liberation
(Citations Omitted)
The legal, political, scientific and media discourse prevalent in
previous generations promoted the idea that race and gender are
biologically determinate categories with biologically determined
attributes, characteristics, and social roles. Historically, many
anthropologists and psychologists believed they had found physical
evidence that non-white people had an inferior capacity for reason and
rationality. These supposed differences fit into an imperialist ideology
of a âwhite manâs burdenâ that justified the systematic oppression of
indigenous peoples through-out the world. Black people were said to be
intellectually and morally inferior to white people and as a result,
unable to take care of themselves without the supervision of their white
slave owners. The myth of a biological basis for male domination over
women has persisted for even longer. Both those who defended the
historical relegation of women to second class citizen status under the
law and the contemporary anti-feminist backlash have relied on a belief
(often backed by superficially scientific-looking evidence of the
inferior female mental capacities) that men are more capable, at least
on average, of fulfilling a variety of important social rules than are
women. Anti-Suffragette propaganda held that womenâs minds were not
suitable for politics or public life. These supposed mental differences
were said to causally explain why women were excluded from politics.
This reasoning was also used to normatively justify female exclusion
from politics as a necessary consequence of having to protect women in
general and from the burdens of public responsibility in particular.
In addition to the paternalistic justifications for white dominance over
black people and male dominance over womenâarguments that fit the
pattern of âgroup A must have legal power over group B for the best
interests and protection of group Bââthe white chauvinist and male
chauvinist ideologies also employed a somewhat different normative
justification: an appeal to the good of society, where the subordination
of black people and women was said to be necessary for society to
function. Defenders of slavery for instance claimed that the institution
of slavery was necessary for a functioning society and economy.
Similarly, the subordination of women to their husbands was widely held
to be necessary for the stability and wellbeing of the family, and
hence, society at large. In both instances, the biological differences
between subordinate and dominant demographic groups was said to both
causally explain the social relations of domination and subordination,
while also providing a normative justification for why those social
relations were good, natural, and desirable.
Today, the subordination of children to adults in general and their
parents in particular is similarly seen as being both caused and
justified by childrenâs inferior mental faculties. Both the paternalism
argument (children must be subordinate for their own good) and the
social necessity argument (children must be subordinate for the good of
society) are advanced to support the legal disabilities of children. The
parallels with âscientific racismâ and sexist neurological theories
should be obvious: we are frequently told that children and adolescents
are mentally inferior due to their underdeveloped brains, and this
inferiority renders them incapable of behaving rationally or
responsibly; in the past, precisely the same claims were advanced
against women and black people.
Many people will instinctively reply that the racists and male
chauvinists of nineteenth century were wrong about black people and
women, whereas our scientifically superior contemporary society is right
about children and adolescents. There are good reasons however not to
leap to this conclusion.
A chief way the black civil rights movement and womenâs rights movement
responded to racist and sexist stereotypes was not to deny that there
are discernable differences between races and genders that might
(mistakenly) be called upon to justify social hierarchies, but that
social hierarchies themselves produced these differences. In The
Mismeasure of Man, Stephen J. Gould argues that measurable
âintelligenceâ does not casually explain the inferior social status of
racial minority groups, rather the inferior social status of racial
minority groups contributes to their relatively worse average
performance on âintelligenceâ tests: the characteristics that racists
appealed to in order to causally explain the conditions of white
dominance could themselves be causally explained by the fact of living
under white dominance. In Guns, Germs, and Steel: The Fates of Human
Societies, Jared Diamond argued that Eurasians have been politically
dominant over the rest of the worldâs population not because of some
biological, cultural, intellectual or moral superiority, but because of
their geographic advantages; resources like horses, metals, and
sufficiently large populations to develop disease resistance
structurally advantaged them against populations who lacked those
resources.
Similar explanations have also been advanced for gender differences and
hierarchies. The cultural materialist anthropologist Marvin Harris
argued that patriarchal, male dominant family arrangements arose when
agricultural societies developed livestock driven iron plows: men were
better equipped for this type of more efficient farming that became
economically dominant, and so their social dominance followed from their
control of the most efficient means of production. In The Dialectic of
Sex (1970), Shulamith Firestone offers a different explanation where she
argues that while the physical differences between male and female roles
in reproduction explain how male dominance developedâthe feminine
character traits cited as reasons why male dominance should persist are
themselves products of female oppression.
The purpose of these arguments is not to show that it is impossible to
explain the status of subordinated demographic groups in reference to
their biological differences. Rather, it is to demonstrate that there
are social structural or material explanations that can also account for
the social hierarchy and the perceived differences between demographic
groups. Given two possible explanationsâ one sociological, the other
biologicalâwhere the variables are impossible to control for (we cannot
take a child and put him or her in some other experimental social
arrangement, nor can we put an adult in a social position identical to a
child in our society)âthere is no way for us to determine how much of
childrenâs childishness is the result of their innate attributes and how
much is the result of their social position.
What does it really mean when we say that a childâs brain is âstill
developingâ? This is often construed to suggest that the changes that go
on in a childâs brain over time are teleological in natureâ they begin
at a low level of development and lead to the end point of a superior
adult level of development, so we only give people adult rights and
responsibilities once they have fully reached that superior level. This
narrative however has minimal scientific support. The reality is that
there is no fixed adult level of brain development where brains
plateauârather brains continue to change over the course of someoneâs
lifetime. Myelin levels in the brain, often cited as âproofâ that the
teenage brain is still developing, not only continue to increase through
teenage years, but well into middle age, at which point they decline.
Psychologist Robert Epstein surveyed the literature on adolescent
neurology studies and concluded that they were misrepresented in the
popular press in several ways: the changes observed continue to take
place through our lives, and research has thus far only shown
correlations between behavior and neurology, but has not demonstrated
causality, and it is well known that experience can alter brain anatomy,
and studies are often simply misrepresented and overstated. Epstein
notes that while all of our behavior, thoughts and feelings are in some
way reflected physically in our brains, it does not follow that
something particular about our brains is the cause of those actions or
emotional states. According to Epstein, environments, studying, diet,
exercise, stress, and many other activities alter the brainâso if
adolescents have problems, pointing to brain differences does not show
that their brains caused the problems as the problems could cause the
brain differences. There are also numerous differences between child and
adult mental capacities where children actually have superior mental
abilities. Visual acuity peaks at the onset of puberty, and incidental
memory abilities peak near twelve years old before declining, so young
people actually have an organic advantage in learning new things.
Intelligence researchers J.C. Raven and David Wechsler using different
intelligence tests found that âraw intelligenceâ scores peak between age
thirteen and fifteen and decline through life. Needless to say these
differences between child and adult mental capacities have not been
prominent in political and media discourse about childrenâs capacities
and rights.
The focus on the difference between adults and children ignores what is
at stake from a social justice perspective in according children equal
rights. Even to the extent that there are significant natural
differences in capacity between most adults and most children, these
differences do not necessarily justify all or most of the social
structures that privilege adults against children. Just as biological
differences between men and women do not determine the specific
socio-economic (and, historically, legal) advantages of men over women
(such as coverture), the biological differences between adults and
children do not determine the form that childrenâs legal status takes
with regard to adults. Even if we were to grant for the sake of argument
that, implausibly, all people under the age of eighteen have inferior
mental capabilities to all those over eighteen, this is hardly an
argument for assigning civil rights only to those with superior mental
capabilities over eighteen. Reasonable people rightly recognize that
those allegedly (or even demonstrably) more rational and intelligent
should not enjoy greater rights than those with lesser capacities for
rationality and intelligenceâwe do not see legal caste hierarchies
arranged by IQ points or brain size as legitimate or just ways of
organizing a society.
Despite the considerable variability in the roles children have occupied
in society, people continue the mistake of thinking childrenâs status is
something inherent to children, rather than a condition imposed on them
by the state and society. For instance, in Schall v. Martin, the Supreme
Court permitted pretrial detention of children for longer periods than
permitted for adults, under the theory that such detention was not
punitive, but merely regulatory, in part because children have fewer
liberty interests than adultsâthey are always in some sort of custody
Do children really have fewer liberty interests as an inherent result of
their childhood, or has the state already deprived them of their liberty
under its âregulations?â It would seem that the Schall Court did not
find any pre-trial punishment of children because children are generally
treated in a way that would be recognized as punitive if applied to an
adult. In this case, the status of a childâs liberty is the result of a
childâs legal status, not a childâs biology.
It is dangerous from the viewpoint of someone concerned with wrongly
depriving others of liberty to assume that childrenâs apparent
capacities necessarily exclude them from possessing rights, when their
effective capabilities are constrained by the way they are treated in
society. If a child were capable of exercising equal rights competently,
how would we be able to recognize it in a society that deprives them of
any opportunity to do so? If we cannot tell whether or not children are
capable of exercising rights in a society that enables them to do so,
because we are only familiar with children in the context of a society,
which prevents them from exercising equal rights, then the assumption
that children are naturally incapable of having rights is unjustified.
Prevailing Attitudes Towards Children
There are additional reasons to be suspicious of the common impulse to
accept research that seems to confirm adult assumptions about children.
Dismissing out of hand the possibility that children could exercise
greater control over their lives is attractive, easy, and convenient. It
is convenient because it is easier for adults to deal with children if
children have few state-enforceable rights that can be mobilized against
adults when adults attempt to control their lives against their wishes.
Many adults also tend to just really like the idea that children are
child-like and profoundly unadult-like: that they are cute, innocent,
irresponsible, and dependent without the possibility of autonomy.
Educator and child rightsâ advocate John Holt writes:
When one person sees and deals with another not as a unique person but
as an example of a type, whether Celebrity, Black, Sex Symbol, Great
Genius, Artist, Saint, or whatever, he diminishes that person and makes
it hard for any natural relationship to grow between them. This is what
we do to children when we see them as Cute, Adorable, Innocent. For the
real child before us we substitute some idea of Childhood that we have
in our minds and deal with that. Often, when we label someone in this
way, we invest him with magical properties, sometimes bad, sometimes
good . . Men often do this to women they consider beautiful . . Having
turned the child into an ideal abstraction, many parents and teachers
tend to look at him much as Rocket Control in Houston looks at a moon
shot. They have a trajectory (life) all mapped out for this child, and
they are constantly monitoring him to see whether he is on the path or
whether he needs a little boost from this rocket (psychologist) here or
a sideways push from that rocket (learning specialist) there . . They
have their own precise notions of what a child should be. They tend to
slip very easily into condescending sentimentality as I have described.
Holtâs observation reveals what we in some ways already know, that
adults judge children according to what plans and expectations the
powerful adults in their lives, their parents and teachers, have for
them. If children are not under parental control, following a
parent-defined path rather than their own desires, adults judge them to
be out of control. If it is often thought that if children are left to
their own devices they will make a mess of their lives, this is in part
because parents, teachers and other adults presume to define what is
valuable in their childrenâs lives and what would constitute making a
mess of them. The widespread liberal belief that the state should remain
neutral between differing conceptions of the good is inconsistently
dropped when it comes to dealings with childrenâmost adults imagine
instead that there is either an objectively appropriate way for children
to behave, learn, and grow up, or that each parentâs subjective and
arbitrary preferences for their childrenâs conduct should be given force
despite also thinking that even a democratically elected state should
not impose its beliefs of how to live oneâs life on its citizenry
When children deviate from adult expectations, from the idealized
abstracted version of what a child is, it can cause cognitive
dissonance: the problem is felt to be with the child and not with the
idea of what a child should be and how children should act. To find an
example of this we need look no further than the way adults react with
horror to childrenâs use of foul language when the same language used by
an adult would leave them unfazed. Just as childrenâs apparent
capabilities and behaviors are limited by societal constraints, societal
views of children and the impressions they make on adults are similarly
informed by the social conventions that affect how adults think about
children. This is all the more reason to be skeptical of our own
intuitions about what children are capable of. Recent research strongly
suggests that older adults actually prefer reading articles that seem to
confirm inferior traits in young people. One way this could be explained
is that people in a position of privilege find it affirming and
convenient when they receive information that seems to confirm that
their privilege is natural and not arbitrary.
Since becoming involved with youth liberation, I have encountered an
attitude from a number of parents that has consistently left me baffled.
They have expressed this attitude in a variety of ways that probably
sounded like fine rhetoric to the person making the statements but which
has consistently struck me as either disingenuous or betraying a deep
lack of understanding of what youth liberation is really about.
Here is a sampling of the sort of statements to which I refer: âAs a
parent I am on the frontlines of advocating for children while you are
dealing with theory.â (This might be less disingenuous coming from
someone that attempts to put some sort of youth autonomy-centered
philosophy at the core of their parenting, but alas this person was not
such a parent.) âAs a parent, I can speak to my childâs need for
boundaries and discipline.â âYouâll feel differently when you are a
parent.â These statements are not only a prime example of the
authoritarian impulses of the people making them, they are also patently
absurd upon reflection. This is because parenting is not a qualification
for discussing the rights of youth, it is a conflict of interest.
One is often seen as bolstering his case when he takes a stand despite
having interests to the contrary. This is why the millionaire that
supports higher income tax rates, the poor person that doesnât believe
in government assistance for people like himself, the white person
speaking out in favor of affirmative action programs for racial
minorities, and the person of color who opposes affirmative action
programs tend to be seen as either a.) lacking a true appreciation of
their own self-interests or b.) acting from a higher and more noble set
of values than immediate self-interest but never as c.) deeply corrupted
by their own interests.
There are also individuals who come to make a judgment about a situation
as a more or less neutral party with nothing that she personally stands
to gain or lose depending on the outcome of the situation. We think of
the ideal judge and jury in a court case as having interests of this
type. Their very neutrality can bolster their claims about a situation.
Parents advocating for their ârightâ to arbitrarily punish their
children and control their lives are not taking either type of stand.
They are not taking a stand that goes against their self-interests and
they are not coming to a decision about their values from a place of
neutrality. Guardianship and minority give parents power at the expense
of their children. There is therefore nothing especially noble or wise
about parents arguing for the maintenance of these institutions in their
current form - it is simply one example among many of powerful people
attempting to protect their interests at the expense of those they have
power over. Saying âAs a parent I know what is best for my childâ is no
more noble than saying âAs a slave owner I know that emancipation
doesnât suit the Negroâ or âAs a logging executive I know that we donât
need environmental regulation.â Even if the statements were valid, we
would be right to be highly suspect about the motives of the person
making the claim.
When we hear someone speaking of his or her role as a parent as a
justification for beliefs about youth that many youth themselves would
likely find oppressive or even abusive we should never accept that as
good enough and we should never defer to their judgment on those grounds
alone. If anything, that personâs status as a parent should make us more
suspect about his or her motives for supporting youth oppression. When
discussing youth liberation, parenting is not a qualification. It is a
conflict of interest. It is important that no one ever trick us into
thinking of the position of a parent as necessarily pro-youth or even
neutral. We cannot be bullied into silence by those whose class position
vis a vis youth betrays their true motives for advocating for their
continued oppression.
You have been kidnapped and dragged off to a remote location where your
abductors have tied you to a chair. One of your captors is seated in
front of you. He holds up ten flash cards and informs you that he is
going to ask you a series of questions and the answers are printed on
the backs of the cards. He assures you that once he has finished asking
these questions, you will be released. There is a catch, though. For
every question you get wrong, he will signal his accomplice to cut off
one of your fingers. As he begins to read the first question, you notice
there is a mirror on the opposite wall where you can see the reflection
of the text on the card. Because you have been taught that cheating is
dishonest, you interrupt your kidnapper and let him know that you are
able to read the card and that he must conceal them better so that you
cannot inadvertently cheat. He adjusts himself accordingly and proceeds
to ask you a series of dry and uninspired questions on topics that hold
no interest for you, while his accomplice menacingly holds out a set of
cutting pliers.
While cheating is technically wrong, everyone should cringe at this
conception of morality because it fails to account for context. In this
example, cheating is not only justified, it is necessary because it aids
a helpless victim who has been involuntarily subjected to unreasonable
conditions. Unfortunately, this kind of clarity is absent when it comes
to compulsory education.
One of the most salient features of all public schools is the importance
of grades. Because grades are the currency and sole commodity of
schools, they are used both to motivate and punish. They are a major
component of a studentâs portfolio and have the potential to impact
their future. Educators might try to stress the value of âlearningâ over
grades, but that is a complete farce. When learning is not
commensurately represented by grades, students rightly feel cheated by
the system and become apathetic. To insist on valuing learning over
grades is offensively disingenuous and hypocritical. It is akin to
telling workers at McDonaldâs that they should care more about doing
their job than their salary
Students have no input regarding how or what they learn, and they are
alienated from the work they do at school. Except for a few rare
assignments, students are not inspired by their work, and any personal
attachment they could have is undermined by the fact that they must
compromise their efforts to meet the demands and expectations of the
person who grades their work.
Itâs important to bear in mind that students prepare for tests with the
intention that they will retain the material just long enough to take
the test and then forget most of what they learned soon afterwards. This
completely undermines the purpose and value of testing. Advocates of
testing who denigrate cheating conveniently fail to acknowledge this.
Testing demands that students view knowledge as a disposable commodity
that is only relevant when it is tested. This contributes to the process
of devaluing education.
The benefits of cheating are obvious â improved grades in an environment
where failure is not an opportunity for learning, but rather a badge of
shame. When students do poorly on a test, there is no reason for
students to review their responses because they will likely never be
tested on the same thing ever again. The test itself is largely
arbitrary and often not meaningful. Organizations such as FairTest are
devoted to sharing research that exposes the problems of bad testing
practices.
The main arguments against cheating in school are that it is unethical,
promotes bad habits, and impacts self-esteem through the attainment of
an unearned reward. None of these concerns are even remotely valid
because none consider the environment. Children are routinely rounded up
and forcibly placed in an institution where they are subjected to a
hierarchy that places them at the bottom. Like the hostage, they are
held captive even if they are not physically bound. They are deprived of
any power over their own lives, including the ability to pursue their
interests, and are subjected to a barrage of tests that have
consequences for each wrong answer.
Maintaining ethics is part of an unwritten contract of being a willing
participant in a community. Students placed in school against their will
and routinely disrespected have no obligation to adhere to the ethical
codes of their oppressors. Cheating is an act of resistance, and
resistance against oppressive powers should be encouraged and
celebrated, rather than deemed a âbad habitâ or an unethical act. The
concern regarding self-esteem that is highlighted by The Child Study
Center as promoting the âworst damage,â lacks any scientific support
whatsoever.
If students feel bad for cheating, it is because the environment has
created a set of conditions where cheating is necessary and justifiable.
For this same reason, many students are proud that they cheat. Cheating
often requires creativity in terms of execution as well as ingenuity to
avoid being caught. It also serves as a statement of disdain against an
arbitrary and repressive institution. For these reasons, cheating can be
a source for pride that boosts self-esteem. Given this construct,
cheating is not simply something many students do; it is something all
students in compulsory schools should do. Cheating is a moral
imperative.
Punishing students for cheating is completely misguided. People should
be most concerned about the student who does not cheat. They are the
ones who appear to have internalized their oppression and might lack the
necessary skills to rally and lobby against abuses of power that are
perpetrated by governing bodies. Cheating should be recognized as the
necessary and logical outcome of an arbitrary and oppressive
institution. Punishing students who cheat is yet another abuse of
autocratic power. In a healthy society, people ridicule and shame those
who force children to endure the kind of environment that demands they
must cheat.
Sojoyner
The analytical construction of the STPP provides an easy and accessible
narrative pertaining to prisons and public education. In general, the
STPP argument states that schools unfairly discipline non-white youth,
particularly Black youth, when compared to students of other races.
Studies demonstrate that Black students have higher rates of
suspensions, detentions, and expulsions than their peers (Wald & Losen,
2003). Further, there is increasing evidence that Black students within
the same schools are disproportionally given more severe forms of
discipline than their white peers for the exact same offenses (Jackson,
2012). The results of these forms of punishment often lead to Black
students either being pushed out of school or arrested on campus. Hence,
school discipline policies and legal constructs serve to funnel Black
youth through the STPP.
The history of STPP research and its associated campaign is complicated
by its development in the midst of anti-prison movements across the
United States. While decades-long organizing efforts by the likes of
Critical Resistance, A New Way of Life, and the Southern California
Library have explicit ties to historic, economic, political, and social
projects that aim to radically alter society through the abolishment of
prisons, the STPP discourse is not invested in the same goal. Further,
the STPP is framed ahistorically, often missing critical racial, class,
gendered, and sexed analyses that are needed to understand the root
causes, including the development of education malaise and subsequent
expansion of prisons within the United States. In this manner, the STPP
discourse cannot begin to address a central theme and line of inquiry
posed by Ruth Wilson Gilmore (2007) that is key to any analysis of
prisons:
This book is about the phenomenal growth of Californiaâs state prison
since 1982, it asks how, why, where, and to what effect one of the
planetâs richest and most diverse political economies has organized and
executed a prison-building and filling plan that government analysts
have called âthe biggestâŠin the history of the world.â (p. 5)
While community organizations across the country have been fighting to
identify and eradicate the multilayered connections between the nationâs
schools and prisons, this has not been the articulated aims of the STPP
discourse. For example, the central document that laid the groundwork
for the discursive framing of the STPP, Deconstructing the
School-to-Prison Pipeline (Wald & Losen, 2003), details a funneling
mechanism that transfers minoritized youth from schools to prisons but
neglects to interrogate the coalescence of schools and prisons including
the political, economic, racial, gendered, and sexed complexities that
undergird both of their foundations. This narrow understanding of the
relationship between schools and prisons has become increasingly
popularized within the past decade. Philanthropic organizations and
national and state government offices have highlighted the pipeline as a
reformist attempt to assuage the demands of community and neighborhood
organizing.The STPP discourse has not only been used by government
officials to describe the relationship between schools and prisons, it
has also been repackaged as a non-threatening, ubiquitous, rhetorical
device for community organizers.
This disturbing trend follows in an eerily similar path as the
development of the âSchools not Jailsâ campaign during the late 1990s.
As argued by Camille Acey (2000), the Schools not Jails movement
undercut the radical and valid critique that students and community
members had regarding the function of school in the United States.
According to Acey (2000):
The slogan âeducation not incarcerationâ grew out of the link between
university student anti-Proposition 209 activism and grass-roots high
school student activism. In the mid- to late 1990s, a number of student
walkouts and protests were led throughout the state of California. The
main emphasis of university students was on increasing access to the
university for poor, working-class communities of color and promoting
more relevant curricula. High school students from those communities
voiced concerns over insufficient educational resources, declining
economic opportunity, and the growing criminalization of their
generation. Often, many of the organizations came together to develop
more comprehensive, radical critiques of these issues and strategies for
political education. Though it is often believed that SNJ [Schools not
Jails] is a variation on âeducation not incarceration,â I would argue
that that it is a corruption. (p. 208)
In recent years, the co-optation of the STPP discourse has shifted the
conversation away from key historical issues that constituted the
generative core of radical community organizing. Over the past ten
years, conferences and workshops have convened non- profit
organizations, academic scholars, philanthropic foundations, and
legislative bodies to analyze causes and solutions to the STPP. To date,
the primary answer to the STPP has been to focus on student behavior and
policy transformation; that is, the response has been to focus on the
way that discipline policies are levied out based upon racialized
conceptualizations of student behavior (Kim, Losen, & Hewitt, 2010). An
underlying logic of these solutions is that by altering behaviors and
certain policies, students will no longer be pushed out or arrested.
Subsequently, these strategies would help to greatly reduce studentsâ
chances of being sent to prison.
While there is general agreement that Black students are unfairly
disciplined within the realm of public education and that predominately
Black schools are mired in a labyrinth of policing procedures, I argue
that the STPP framework provides an overdetermined, analytic model and
an undertheorized solution set to address issues that are both
historical in nature and extremely complex. Specifically, the STPP is a
concept that is predicated upon an analysis of power that follows an arc
whereby the supposed beholders of power have complete control of the
âotherââBlack youth. Similar to Cedric Robinsonâs (2007) critique of
Foucaultâs analysis of power, the same argument can be made with respect
to the STPP. Specifically, Robinson (2007) states:
It is as if systems of power never encounter the stranger, or that
strangers can be seamlessly abducted into a system of oppression. In our
own interrogations this amounts to the presumption that the exposing of
the invention of race subjects is a sufficient method for recognizing
and explaining difference. (p. xii)
The glaring problem with the STPPâs framework is that it never accounts
for the possibility that the structure of public education is responding
to the actions taken by Black students that are perceived to threaten
the status quo. In this regard, the criminalization of Black youth is
not only intentional, but it is in response to direct agitation on the
part of Black people. Thus, strategies to address the STPP that focus on
shifting behaviors serve to legitimate the idea that disciplining
student behavior is necessary, as long as the mechanisms do not push
students out of school or entail arrests.
While the STPP framework may challenge the basic tenant that the meting
out of discipline is disproportional, it fails to challenge the ethos of
anti-Blackness as foundational to the formation and enactment of school
discipline. Through a brief cull of the annals of contemporary history,
which the STPP framework completely disregards, I will demonstrate that
the modes of current school discipline (e.g., policing and expulsions)
have developed in an attempt to suppress assertions of Black culture,
Black autonomy, and Black liberation movements within schools. Very
simply, the attention to reforming student behavior belies the
complicity of state officials, private capital, and philanthropic
organizations to undermine efforts by Black communities to dictate the
parameters of Black education.
Recognizing that historical processes stretching back over two centuries
account for the education of Black people in the United States, the
basis of support for my argumentation rests on evidence amassed between
the 1940s and 1970s in Southern California. This time period was of
great significance as it marked a mass influx of Black migrants from the
U.S. South to California. Moreover, Los Angeles is important during this
moment as the site where intense violence was enacted upon Black
communal organizations that advocated for social change (Widener, 2010).
It was also during this time period in Los Angeles that education was a
hotly contested area in terms of the terrain of ideological governance.
That is, while Black communities in Los Angeles conceptualized and used
public education as a space to develop alternative models of cultural
expression and organizing, city officials, planners, and private capital
lobbied for and responded with brute force and policy tactics to
undermine liberation movements of Black Angelinos. Looking through two
important documentsâthe Welfare Planning Councilâs report on âYouth
Problems and Needs in the South Central Areaâ (WPC, 1961) and the
âPolice in Governmentâ course manual taught by officers within the Los
Angeles Police Department (LAPD) (Los Angeles Police Department, 1974)
in predominately Black high schoolsâwe achieve a nuanced understanding
of the complex relationship among Black communities, city leaders, and
public education.
In addition to the influx of Black migrants and the level of violence
enacted upon Black communal organizations in Los Angeles during this
time period, Southern California (and Los Angeles in particular) is a
critical site to examine because over the last 50 years, it has become
the region of choice in regards to the testing and development of models
that foster enclosure linkages between education and prisons. Ranging
from the highly marketed anti-drug âD.A.R.Eâ program to truancy tickets
that mandate arrests and carry exorbitant fines, policy makers in
Southern California have been at the cutting edge of creating policy and
perfecting extralegal measures to ensure the subjugation of Black
education.4 While these programs have been exported nationwide and
lauded as models of public safety and/or crime prevention, it is
necessary to understand the social and political context from which they
developed. It is only then that we can refine our analysis beyond
seductive, rhetorical devices and empty reformist concessions such as
the STPP. Moreover, understanding the social and political context
enables us to begin the âheavy liftingâ of developing concrete
strategies that explore the multifaceted nature of education and re-root
movements for social change back to Black communities.
Children in todayâs society are uniquely oppressed, but for the most
part their oppression goes unnoticed even by people who consider
themselves progressives or radicals. The fact that the relations between
children and adults are based on inequality and compulsion is considered
a separate issue from oppressions based on race, gender or sexual
orientation, because it is considered somehow natural. Children are seen
as incapable of making decisions for themselves and running their own
affairs, due to their supposed lack of experience and immaturity, and
therefore it is considered legitimate for adults to exercise some kind
of authority over them. Anarchism, which is based on the principles of
individual sovereignty, non-coercion, free association and mutual aid,
can play an important role in helping to formulate an anti-authoritarian
theory of parenting, education and child-rearing, and to begin the
process of liberating children from an oppressive society.
The first kind of authority that children face while growing up is that
of their parents. Parents have legal guardianship over their children
from the moment they are born until they turn 18. Most parents hold an
authoritarian and hierarchical view of their relation to their children.
They see their kids as their property, who are to be nurtured,
protected, kept in line, restrained, disciplined, rewarded or punished
as the parents see fit. Anarchists would oppose this conception of the
child, since children are not seen as autonomous individuals in their
own right, but mere appendages of their parents. Mikhail Bakunin, the
Russian anarchist, put it succintly: âChildren do not constitute
anyoneâs property: they are neither the property of the parents nor even
of society. They belong only to their own future freedom.â
Some parents use the justification that they are âover-protectiveâ or
they âcare about their children too muchâ to excuse the stifling
atmosphere of the nuclear family. It is with the nuclear family that
gender roles are created and re-inforced, and where authoritarian
ideologies are passed down to the next generation. Neurotic and
anti-social personality traits are also produced in children as a
consequence of the nuclear familyâs puritanical suppression of
sexuality. Oftentimes, parents will force their children to follow their
particular religion, i.e. Judaism, Christianity, etc. or political
affiliation, i.e. Republican, Democrat, etc. In the Jewish religion,
boys at 13 are usually pressured or outright coerced into having Bar
Mitzvahs, which is the sign of âbecoming a manâ. Hanukkah and Christmas
are religious celebrations which children are forced to partake in, and
they are not given any opportunity to make up their own mind about their
religious or political beliefs.
Around the age of 5, children are shipped off to schools, or âyouth
concentration campsâ as anarchist writer Bob Black accurately called
them. In these institutions children are monitored closely by their
teachers, who make sure to report any kind of âsuspiciousâ behavior. The
purpose of school is to thwart any signs of free-thought or
individuality, by forms of subtle or not-so-subtle coercion. If children
âmisbehaveâ, they are punished by being sent to the office, detention,
suspension, expulsion, or bad grades. In most private middle and high
schools, and in a growing number of public schools, there is a dress
code that children have to follow. Sometimes they are even forced to
tuck in their shirts or wear a belt. Tattoos, dyed hair, piercings and
other attempts to create an individual identity are often met with the
fierce hostility of principals and administrators.
The relation of the administration to the students is almost exactly
like that of a boss to his workers. He owns the institution, he sets the
âstandards of conductâ, and tries to create a âproductive work
environmentâ. It is not considered a good idea to question those in
authority, and the anger of the students are channeled into acceptable
forms such as student government or the official student union, which
are similar to modern AFL-CIO unions in the workplace. Student
government may call for minor reforms, but in no way calls into question
the very existence of schools, or the possibility of abolishing coercion
altogether, which the anarchist critique calls for.
It is also quite interesting how much schools and prisons have in common
with each other. In both prisons and schools, the following criteria
apply: an authoritarian structure, dress code, pass needed for going
from one part of the facility to another, emphasis on silence and order,
negative reinforcement, emphasis on behavior, extrinsic reward system,
loss of individual autonomy, abdridged freedoms, and little
participation in decision making.
This begs the question: what can children do to fight back against the
particular forms of oppression they face in their daily lives? The most
important thing is to create a subversive atmosphere in the home,
school, and workplace (high-school students are often forced to work in
shitty, low-paying jobs like McDonalds). Let other young people know how
you feel about parental coercion or about how you are treated by adults.
Class consciousness is essential. Children need to recognize that they
are a uniquely oppressed class vis a vis the oppressing class which
dictates the conditions of their existence. To paraphrase the Preamble
to the IWW Constitution, the oppressed class and the oppressing class
have nothing in common.
Disobedience can be expressed small ways (kind of like sabotage in the
workplace) by refusing to pledge allegiance, to participate in prayer
(in religious schools), or by choosing to write school essays on, for
example, Youth Revolt Throughout History, Emma Goldman, or the case of
Katie Sierra (a 15-year old anarchist suspended from school for wearing
homemade anti-war shirts and for trying to start up an anarchist club)
and deliver them in front of class. Educate yourself outside of school
by talking with others, reading, and sharing your ideas and experiences.
You can make flyers and distribute them or paste them up around the
school. You can start up a zine by yourself or with others, and
distribute it at school. High-school general strikes or Reclaim the
Streets can also be planned; even if they are over seemingly reformist
issues (curfew, uniforms, etc.), they have the possibility of
radicalizing more and more students.
There are many creative possibilities; for instance, a group of
anarchists close to where I live took a sign from a kennel that said
âObedience Trainingâ and unfurled it over a local high school. To the
extent that such things are successful, parents and administrators must
feel like they can not get away with stuff that they could get away with
before, that they are being closely watched and monitored by the
children they formerly oppressed, that they are slowly losing their grip
of power and authority over youth, and that youth are no longer an
amorphous mass of docile sheep, but class conscious, intelligent,
committed, and organized youth, who are prepared to take their lives
into their own hands and to abolish all masters once and for all.
Anarchism has a lot to offer youth liberation. Its basic principles of
anti-authoritarianism and non-coercion are powerful weapons in the
arsenal to free children from their state of slavery and bondage.
Anarchism also offers youth liberation the insight that it cannot be
content with just abolishing parental coercion, it must also create
liberatory alternatives. This is an example of the revolutionary dual
power strategy, where the new society is created out of the shell of the
old. Contrary to the official view, education does not equal schooling,
and kids can create a whole self-organized infrastructure of
counter-institutions for learning, growing, and developing themselves â
on a basis of full equality and freedom. Genuinely âfree skoolsâ can be
created, where classes are strictly voluntary, and children can choose
to study a particular subject with others, children or adults, who
happen to be an authority on the topic. As Colin Ward put it in his book
Anarchy in Action, they will be âschools no longerâ but popular
laboratories of liberation.