đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș sasha-k-activism-and-anarcho-purism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 14:04:28. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: âActivismâ and âAnarcho-Purismâ Author: sasha k Language: en Topics: activism, Andrew X, Chris Dixon, J. Kellstadt, organization Source: Retrieved on September 1, 2009 from http://www.geocities.com/kk_abacus/kka/activist.html
âAfter Seattleâ (words that launched a thousand articles) there has been
much talk about how to keep âbuilding the movement.â In âRethinking
Radical Activism and Building the Movement,â Chris Dixon adds his
thoughts on the matter. After reading the article one is prompted to ask
what of âactivismâ is rethought and what is the movement to be built? In
fact, very little is rethought and a critical look at âactivismâ is
entirely absent from Dixonâs celebratory piece. Dixon focuses his
discussion around hope, a hope that he calls âcriticalâ; unfortunately,
the hope in Dixonâs article is mostly self-congratulatory and contains
almost no critical reflection.
The article contains two âcriticismsâ: 1. the movement, which for Dixon
started in Seattle, not in the third world, is mostly white, and 2.
Dixon is critical of any theoretical reflection on the contradiction of
the movement, what he calls âpuristâ anarchism. In linking these two
criticisms together, Dixon cuts off any discussion of tactics, strategy,
goals and, above all, of the role of the activist/organizer.
There has been much discussion in Europe and especially England about
the role of activists within society; in the U.S., due in a large part
to the anti-intellectual nature of the radical milieu, such a discussion
has mostly been precluded. (Time is certainly ripe for this discussion
in the U.S.) This untheoretical approach allows Dixon to talk in
extremely abstract terms. The most glaring example is his use of the
term âsocial change/transformationâ. In Dixonâs article social change
can mean anything at all; it can be change in any direction for
practically any goal as long as it is progressive: more or better of
something. But this abstractness is not an accidental omission; it is
central to the logic of his argument, it is central to the logic of the
activist mentality. The more abstract we are in our goals the more that
people join our parade: it is the mentality of numbers. This is the
Clintonification of anarchism â Clinton made the Democratic Party so
bland and middle of the road that even some Republicans could applaud or
join it and Dixon proposes doing the same for anarchism.
We need to ask what is the movement that Dixon wants to build? The
movement that Dixon is so enthused about is a movement of activists, of
specialists in social change, who stand above and outside of the
communities they organize. And for the most part this movement is a
collection of single-issue groups. If anything has been inspiring in the
U.S. over the last year or so it is that more people have begun to see
themselves as opposed to capitalism in its totality. Yet if we add up a
bunch of single-issue campaigns we donât get an anti-capitalist
movement, but a reformist movement full of contradictions and led by
activists. The movement of the exploited and excluded, which is
antagonistic to capitalism and the state, canât be built by welding
together a bunch of single issue groups; it is a movement that grows out
of our present social conditions and our desires for a different world.
However, it seems that to build a movement led by activists any tactic
or goal will do, no matter how contradictory. Dixon lists a set of
demands and goals of which none suggest any serious critique of
capitalism and the state in their totality: they include, âfighting
reactionary ballot measures,â âdemanding authentic public oversight of
police,â âbuilding art installations,â and âpainting graffiti.â As Dixon
states, âwe all choose a variety of tools, tactics, strategies, and
demands based on our circumstances and objectives.â And when oneâs
objectives remain vague enough any tool, tactic, strategy or demand will
do fine; in fact, they can be âseen as complementary.â They can be
âseenâ as such when we remain abstract and unreflective, but in reality
the contradictions remain. Yet for the activist it is the spectacle of
unity that is important.
If our tactics and strategies are truly to be âbased on our
circumstances [the capitalist social relations we are enmeshed within]
and our objectivesâ â for anarchists, presumably, the ending of
capitalism and the state, not just some general idea of social change â
we should be especially critical of tools, tactics and strategies that
contradict these objectives, that lead us in a different direction, or
that reproduce the very thing we are trying to eliminate from society.
For Dixon, however, the âcriticalâ in his âcritical hopeâ is a criticism
of being theoretical or reflexive in our understanding. He is critical
of making any distinction that might question the abstractness of his
conception of social change, any distinction that might force one to
make difficult decisions. While Dixon does state that a more theoretical
understanding of capitalism is important, for him this seems to remain a
separate project from that of organizing; thus practice and theory
become two separate worlds, as if one could be done without the other.
Dixon cuts off the very type of reflexive and theoretical discussion on
tactics, strategy and, above all, goals that we now need through the
coupling up of the rhetoric of white privilege with charges of
anarcho-purism. If you disagree with him it is probably because you are
a âwhite, middle-classâ male â and probably an anarcho-purist to boot â
so you have no right to talk. Such âpurist anarchistsâ are also
critiqued as âself-appointed bearers of a radical standard.â And the use
of âself-appointedâ is telling. In the activist world one needs to claim
some authentic, democratic position in order to take on the role of
âactivist,â âorganizerâ, or âtheorist.â The question is, âwho do you
represent?â for you canât just represent yourself. But we donât need
expert, specialized âtheorists,â we all need to be reflexive and
theoretical in our understanding of social change, not as some vague
concept but as something intimately connected to our own desires for a
different life. Unfortunately, it is to just such experts that Dixon
turns to bolster his argument: everyone he quotes is either an
âactivist,â âorganizer,â or, god forbid, âtheoristâ: only one of his
expert witnesses is even an anarchist, yet he is still identified as a
specialist â as if this were some academic paper â he is an âanarchist
writer.â
But who is an anarcho-purist? What is anarcho-purism? It is a term that
gets thrown about quite often these days, particularly in activist
circles. We should, therefore, try to make our thinking clear on this
matter. An anarcho-purism is always a morality as opposed to an ethics.
Morality is a statement, such as âthou shalt not,â instead of a question
posed in the moment. It is a set, blind standard that rules over
behavior. Anarcho-purism is a morality that tries to keep anarchism pure
and separate from certain tactics or from working with certain groups
for the sake of purity. Dixonâs use of the term âpurist anarchists,â
however, suggests not only that anarchism shouldnât be a morality â a
suggestion that I would definitely agree with â but that it shouldnât be
an ethics as well. In fact, following Dixonâs logic one would have to
conclude that anarchism should have almost no meaning at all.
An anarchist ethics is an affirmation, an affirmation of the creativity,
desire and power of the individual; it is an affirmation of the ability
of individuals to come together and decide their own fate without the
need of any imposed decision coming in from the outside whether in
âtotalitarianâ or âdemocraticâ form. As an ethics, it is both a way of
living and a way of relating to others: how can we come together â
combine â in a fashion that doesnât restrict, limit and suppress the
desire, creativity and active power of each other? This ethical question
is at the heart of anarchism. And it is just such a question that Dixon
wipes out as he wipes anarchism clean of any content. As an ethics,
anarchism recognizes that there is no escape from social life; the
anarchist ethic, after all, grows out of the movement of the exploited
and excluded, and it only remains vital within that movement. Living
this ethic will mean that one will come into conflict with imposed
social order, with hierarchy, with any archy or cracy. To live this
ethic is thus not always an easy choice, we canât make it into a
Snickers Bar; anyhow, no matter how drained of content anarchism becomes
the masses wonât run to sign up any day soon.
That said, it is also a simple fact of language that those who want to
reform the present system are called reformists. There are also many
people who wish to end the rule of capital and the state but unwittingly
use means that can only bring about a reform of the present system. It
is, therefore, obviously important to come to a clear understanding of
the results of our actions; this is what theory and critique are for,
and it should not be turned into a pleasant game of compliments. Yet, as
anarchists, we can work with them towards intermediate aims, while
always remaining clear as to how such aims tally with our ultimate
goals. There are, however, important limits â limits that are obscured
when we hold only an abstract conception of social change. Working to
âdemand authentic control over the policeâ might be a small step for
social change in some general sense, but ultimately it is a step
backwards as it strengthens the legitimacy of the police and of imposed
decision. That is of course, unless oneâs goal is nicer police and
âdemocratic control over our livesâ â the term âdemocratic,â which we
hear repeated over and over by activists these days, is another term
usually left unthinkingly abstract. âDirect democratic control over our
livesâ might make a nice slogan, but it is vague enough for most
politicians in Washington to use.
Secondly, working with those who attempt to limit my activities, my
power of acting, is a combination that would not work well. Strangely,
it is most often the activists who try to restrict the actions of others
â one only needs to look at D.A.N.âs role in Seattle, believing that
they could set rules of engagement for others. This is the ethical
question always posed to anarchists; when does combining with others
multiply our power to act towards our goals and when does it not? It is
an important question, not one to be ignored or vilified. None of this
means that there is only one way to act, but that just acting without
any thought is more often than not counter productive.
Maybe the investigation of white privilege needs first to turn its gaze
on the activist/organizerâs role as a specialist in social change.
Perhaps it is not that activists have been organizing the wrong people
or around the wrong issues, as Dixonâs article suggests, but that
organizing people is the wrong way to bring about a truly different
world. There has, however, been a discussion brewing on âactivismâ
especially since the J18 protests. Some of the more interesting articles
include Andrew Xâs âGive Up Activism,â J. Kellstadtâs âThe Necessity and
Impossibility of âAnti-Activismââ, and âPractice and Ideology in the
Direct Action Movementâ from Undercurrents. I will not repeat all their
arguments here, but hope to push the discussion forward.
In âGive Up Activism,â Andrew X critiques activism as a specialized role
separate from society and leading to an inadequate practice. Andrew X
argues, therefore, that the practice of activism must be given up.
â[T]acking capitalism will require not only a quantitative change (more
actions, more activists) but a qualitative one (we need to discover some
more effective form of operating).â This is the problem at the heart of
Dixonâs argument: it relies solely on getting more people involved, more
people organizing and organized, but lacks the reflection necessary to
begin to move us towards a qualitatively different practice. If
anything, Dixonâs arguments reinforce and celebrate the specialized role
of the activist as one who stands outside and above the masses â the
famous real people â to be organized. But, to use Dixonâs words, âwe can
do better.â As Andrew X states, âThe âactivistâ is a specialist or an
expert in social change â yet the harder we cling to this role and
notion of what we are, the more we actually impede the change we desire.
A real revolution will involve the breaking out of all preconceived
roles and the destruction of all specialism â the reclamation of our
lives. The seizing control over our own destines which is the act of
revolution will involve the creation of new selves and new forms of
interaction and community.â Andrew X, however, suggests that breaking
out of the role of the activist is no easy task, especially during low
points in the struggle against capitalism, but we must âconstantly try
to push at the boundaries of our limitations and constraints.â
In âThe Necessity and Impossibility of âAnti-Activismâ,â J. Kellstadt is
supportive but critical of Andrew Xâs discussion, thus the title of the
article. While Kellstadt also sees the limits of activism, s/he argues
that it is also impossible to simply give up activism. The most
suggestive aspect of Kellstadtâs article is that it both notes the
subjective elements of choice involved in being an activist and the
objective conditions of society that limit our ability to simply give up
activism: âI think that a rather high degree of ambivalence and the
ability to live the tension of seemingly irreconcilable contradictions
is central to the problems of formulating an âanti-activismâ and
âanti-politics.â In short, I argue that we must embrace simultaneously
the necessity and the impossibility of âgiving up activism.ââ Kellstadt
critiques Andrew X for being too subjectivist (that we could simply
âgive up activismâ): âthe collective human dynamics by which social
groups and professions (cops, priests, or activists) emerge out of the
division of labor cannot be denied or thrown over by acts of individual
will, which is the level at which Andrew X addresses the problem. The
âroleâ of the activist is not simply âself-imposed;â it is also
socially-imposed. Capitalist society produces activists the way it
produces other specialists, the way it produces, for example, that close
cousin of the activist, the intellectual.â Thus, while Kellstadt states
that we need to operate within the tension between the subjective and
the objective, her/his critique often falls back significantly into an
overly objectivist position. While committing ârole-suicideâ wonât make
the social position of âthe activistâ disappear, there are always
openings to different types of self-organization. We may not be able to
kill the role, but we are not stuck in it either; and, if we are to rid
ourselves of capitalism we need to struggle in a different way and not
celebrate the role of the activist.
Certainly âgiving up activismâ isnât revolution in itself; it wonât make
the social roles that are conditioned by our historical circumstances
disappear. Nor will it allow us to âtruly appropriate an authentic
self.â Struggling to organize ourselves in a qualitatively different
manner, however, can open the potential of insurrection to overthrow
capitalism and the state. For such a potential to open, hope lies not in
cheerleading, but in a much more critical and reflexive understanding of
our practices and forms of organization.