💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › ridhiman-balaji-accumulation-of-freedom.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 13:33:45. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Accumulation of Freedom
Author: Ridhiman Balaji
Date: October 20, 2020
Language: en
Topics: accumulation, freedom, economics, book review, Anarcho-Syndicalist Review
Source: Retrieved on 28th January 2021 from https://syndicalist.us/2020/10/20/accumulation-of-freedom-writings-on-anarchist-economics/
Notes: From Anarcho-Syndicalist Review #81, Winter 2021

Ridhiman Balaji

Accumulation of Freedom

Deric Shannon, Anthony Nocella & John Asimakopoulos, eds., Accumulation

of Freedom: Writings on Anarchist Economics. AK Press, 2012, 375 pp.,

$21, paperback.

Accumulation of Freedom is a collection of essays written by various

anarchists and libertarian socialists. They provide their own take on

issues such as revolutionary strategy, globalization, class, hegemony

and many others. Many of the contributors are anarcho-communists. The

book is very much a mixed bag; some essays are really good, while others

are quite bad. Accumulation begins with a preface by Kinna, who begins

by presenting a critique of mainstream economics, which many believe is

based on unrealistic assumptions. Kinna blames the ideology of

neoliberalism for the emergence of a global economic system in which

economic institutions such as the market are under-regulated and

ill-planned. Contrary to the “anarcho”-capitalism of Murray Rothbard,

Kinna argues “anarchism offers a strong and rich heritage of

anti-capitalist thinking.” (6) According to Kinna, neoliberal

globalization has produced three sets of problems: 1) Corporate

capitalism, 2) environmental and ecological costs of industrialization

and modernization, and 3) the unfairness of global market regulation

and, in particular, the Western bias of institutions such as the

International Monetary Fund and the World Trade Organization. Although

Kinna does a good job discussing issues raised by neoliberal capitalism,

readers would have also benefited from a discussion of potential

solutions to these problems.

The introductory essay by the editors, Anarchist Economics: A Holistic

View, discusses why anarchists oppose capitalism and the institution of

wage labor. The authors argue that anarchists generally accept a

traditional two-class analytical framework which divides people into two

categories: the working class and the ruling class. However, as the

authors point out, not everyone fits neatly into these categories, as

some have argued for the existence of a third class, such as the “the

middle class,” “the coordinator class,” “the techno-managerial class,”

etc. The editors then provide a brief overview of the three main

anarchist schools of thought: Mutualism (Proudhon), Collectivism

(Bakunin), and Communism (Kropotkin). Although the authors do a good job

of providing a brief overview of classical anarchism, their discussion

of Proudhon’s Mutualism is quite misleading. This is addressed later in

this review.

In Examining the History of Anarchist Economics to See the Future,

Spannos discusses key events in anarchist history. The essay is well

written, and Spannos’ decision to use Maurice Brinton’s account of how

the Bolsheviks dismantled workers’ control was a good choice. There is

not much discussion, however, of what role unions can or should play in

building a more emancipatory and liberatory society.

In Laying the Foundations: Proudhon’s Contribution to Anarchist

Economics, Iain McKay provides an excellent overview of Proudhon, making

a strong case for his continuing relevance. McKay’s essay is very useful

for first-time readers of Proudhon, with plenty of textual evidence.

However, I did not find McKay’s assertion that Marx’s account of

“exploitation” is essentially the same as Proudhon’s very convincing. As

I read him, Proudhon appears to be much more interested in theorizing in

terms of property, as opposed to Marx who puts forward a value-theoretic

critique of capitalism. For Proudhon, the value workers create is their

property [“the price is not sufficient: the labour of the workers has

created a value; now this value is their property” (McKay 2011, 114)]

Thus, what capitalists are really appropriating is workers’ property.

McKay’s assertion that “Proudhon was the first to expound many of the

key concepts of Marxist Economics” (68) is also not very convincing. If

McKay is suggesting that Proudhon came up with the notion of

“surplus-value” before Marx, then this point is not clearly established.

The problem for Proudhon, as I read him, is not that “workers [produce]

more value than they [receive] in wages” (66), rather that workers do

not enjoy the fruits of their labor. In other words, the problem is not

the size of the wage, rather that only capitalists profit from any

production opportunity undertaken even though the effort was a joint

collaboration between workers and capitalists.

McKay also interprets Proudhon to be an early proponent of what is known

in the Post-Keynesian school of thought as the “endogenous theory of

money.” (72) There are numerous problems with this assertion. First, the

problem with the “endogenous theory of money” is that its proponents use

a very different operating definition of “money” which, in my view,

obscures the way money and taxes actually function in capitalist

societies. According to the classical Quantity Theory of Money (Smith,

Ricardo), which Marx rejected, money is currency (cash), which serves

as 1) a measure of value and 2) a medium of exchange. Post-Keynesians

use a confusing conception of “money”. First, they define “money” as a

“unit-of-account”. Second, their definition of money is inclusive of

credit instruments and debt obligations (IOUs). This approach is

inimical to the medium of exchange character of money. On the question

of whether Proudhon was a proponent of the “endogenous theory of money,”

it is not immediately discernible from McKay’s comments whether this is

the case. Proudhon writes,

Indeed, in all possible societies, even communistic, there is need for a

measure of exchange, otherwise either the right of the producer, or that

of the consumer, is affected. Until values are generally constituted by

some method of association, there is need that one certain product,

selected from among all others, whose value seems to be the most

authentic, the best defined, the least alterable, and which combines

with this advantage durability and portability, be taken for the symbol,

that is to say, both for the instrument of circulation and the standard

of other values. (McKay 2011, 230. Emphasis Added)

Here we can see that Proudhon, following the Quantity Theory of Money,

thinks that money should be both “instrument of circulation” as well as

“the standard for other values.” This seems to suggest, contrary to

McKay, that Proudhon was not a proponent of the “endogenous theory of

money.” Nonetheless, McKay’s essay provides a very useful introduction

to Proudhon, while making a strong case that Kropotkin owes many ‘debts’

to Proudhon.

The essay Capitalism in the 2000s, by Volcano and Shannon is

problematic. It is unclear what differentiates “neoliberal capitalism”

from “non-neoliberal capitalism” and why this is relevant. The core

characteristic features of the neoliberal paradigm are not specified.

Although the authors do a good job scrutinizing the way globalization

occurs under capitalism, in some areas their discussion is not very

clear. They claim greater capital mobility has caused a “race to the

bottom.” (82) This is an empirical claim which depends crucially on

which part of the world you look at and what time period. They claim

workers are “forced to work for wages well below the standards set by

union victories in (over)developed countries.” (82) Perhaps this is true

of most developing countries, but what does greater capital mobility

have to do with this? Capitalists do not only seek low wages, they also

seek higher levels of productivity and higher rates of profit. The

authors are correct, however, that the discussion needs to shift from

“globalization” to a different kind of globalization. The authors also

discuss some polling data which appears to show increased interest in

“socialist alternatives.” (85) However, many of these attitudes are

contingent on the specific time period under examination. The victory of

Donald Trump over Hillary Clinton in 2016, as well as the recent loss of

Bernie Sanders in the Democratic primaries, indicates that conservative

attitudes remain fairly popular in the U.S. The victories of Modi in

India and Bolsanaro in Brazil, as well as other neo-fascists around the

world, suggest the global working-class has not been won over to

socialist ideas. The rest of the essay, however, does a good job

discussing many of the problems which arise under capitalism, such as

periodic crises, the feminization of poverty, and general ecological

unsustainability.

Fight to Win! Tools for Confronting Capital by Cochrane and Monaghan is

highly problematic. The major problem is that the authors recommend the

works of two radical institutionalist economists, Johnathan Nitzan and

Shimshon Bichler, who misrepresent Marx. For starters, it is unclear

what the authors mean by the notion of “Labor theory of value,” a term

which, in my view, does not accurately represent Marx’s value theory

(nor Ricardo’s or Smith’s). Indeed, the authors do not bother defining

the notion at all, it is simply presumed from the get-go that the term

is problematic. Then the authors introduce readers to the concept of

“Differential Accumulation” developed by Nitzan and Bichler. In their

books The Global Political Economy of Israel (2002) and Capital As Power

(2009), Nitzan and Bichler argue that capital is a “strategic power

institution,” and that “capital represents the complex assemblages of

assets under the control of particular capitalist entities, including

the means of production.” (98) For Nitzan and Bichler, accumulation of

capital represents the commodification of power, and claims of control

over social processes. Thus, Cochrane and Monaghan write, “given that

power can only be understood as a relation between two entities,

capitalists judge their accumulatory success in relative terms.” (99)

The writers use this concept to evaluate the success and failures of

three political-economic disruption campaigns: 1) Anti-sweatshop

targeting of Nike, 2) Take down SNC-Lavalin!, and 3) Stop Huntingdon

Animal Cruelty. Although these campaigns were successful in damaging

capitalist profits, they write, campaigns such as the anti-sweatshop

campaign “intentionally mimicked the hierarchical structure of the

corporations they targeted,” and their leadership structure “privileged

the type of male-dominated, competitive, and non-participatory

environments that anarchists are committed to eliminating.” (113)

Although Cochrane and Monaghan’s analysis is sharp and insightful,

readers should be aware that prominent Marx scholar Andrew Kliman has

debunked Nitzan and Bichler’s characterizations of Marx [see Value and

Crisis: Bichler and Nitzan versus Marx (2011)]. Moreover, Nitzan and

Bichler’s theoretical apparatus systematically neglects any discussion

of class.

The essay Escaping Capitalist Hegemony by Wright and Williams is very

interesting. The authors challenge the widely held belief that we live

in a “capitalist” world. Wright and Williams argue there is no such

thing as “capitalist hegemony” by pointing to already existing

non-capitalist economic spaces in contemporary society. By looking at

alternative forms of work, such as work that is non-exchanged and

non-monetized, or work that is monetized but not undertaken primarily

for profit-motivated purposes, Wright and Williams argue that

alternative non-capitalist economic practices are already prevalent in

western economies. However, the notion of “capitalism” is used very

loosely throughout the essay, obscuring the way capitalism actually

functions. Chapter 51 of Das Kapital provides useful criteria for

distinguishing capitalist modes of production from non-capitalist modes.

For Marx, there are two defining features of the capitalist mode of

production: production of commodities to satisfy human wants, and the

production of surplus value. Under this definition, virtually all of

what Wright and Williams are talking about, such as non-exchanged,

non-monetized work not undertaken primarily for profit-motivated

purposes, would fall within the purview of “capitalism.” This is not to

say such programs are undesirable, rather that they are not

“not-capitalist.” Furthermore, you cannot have “socialism” or

“not-capitalism” in one country. For instance, it is unreasonable to say

that Country A, such as China or Vietnam, is “socialist” or

“not-capitalist”, while these countries continue to trade and interact

with capitalist countries like the United States or Great Britain. This

assertion relies on a confusing conception of “capitalism.” Perhaps in

the future, there will be some overlap between capitalism and socialism

as there was between feudalism and capitalism, but we are nowhere near

the point where capitalism is coming to an end.

Asimakopoulos’ Globalized Contradictions of Capitalism and the

Imperative for Epochal Change argues that capitalism is destined to

collapse repeatedly unless the state uses violence to keep it in place.

(140) Asimakopoulos looks at SSA Theory developed by Kotz, McDonough and

Reich in their book Social Structures of Accumulation (1994). SSA

emphasizes the role of institutional arrangements on long-term economic

growth, as opposed to what Asimakopoulos calls

“deterministic-mechanistic Marxist economic theory.” (140) Asimakopoulos

examines the emergence of three regimes, financial regime, neoliberal

trade regime, and globally segmented labor markets, arguing that

hegemonic powers like the U.S. and the European Union are in a position

of global privilege. SSA theory incorporates neo-marxist perspectives

developed by Baran and Sweezy, in particular their ideas on

overproduction and underconsumption, as well as World-Systems Theory

developed by Andre Frank. The problem is that these perspectives shift

the discussion away from the exploitative relationship between

capitalists and workers, instead, looking at interactions among states,

like the U.S., or a conglomeration of states like the EU. Should

libertarian socialists express solidarity with “underprivileged” states

like India, China, Indonesia, etc.? Or should they express solidarity

with the international working-class? It is not the state which

appropriates surplus value from workers, rather it is capitalists. The

section on “The neoliberal trade regime” (144–146) is quite confusing.

Asimakopoulos spends a fair bit of time explaining the United States’

trade deficit with countries like Mexico and China, but it is unclear

why trade deficits are inherently undesirable. A trade deficit is only

half the picture, there is also a net inflow of capital from countries

that run trade surpluses with the U.S., such as China and Mexico. When

countries like China purchase U.S. securities like treasury bills, they

finance the government’s budget deficit and create employment

opportunities for workers in the U.S. Thus, Asimakopoulos presents an

incomplete picture of an interconnected world where current account

deficits are offset by capital account surpluses.

Hahnel’s essay The Economic Crisis and Libertarian Socialists does a

good job examining the United States’ lackluster response to the

2007–2008 financial crisis, and remains relevant in light of the

economic crises induced by the Covid-19 pandemic. It is important to

remember, however, that the Covid-19 recession is much bigger than the

Great Recession of 2007–2008. Although Hahnel does a good job of looking

at how the United States’ policy response to the crises was

insufficient, readers would have also benefited from a discussion of the

various ways in which the economy could have been restructured to be

made more democratic. Various conditions could have been attached to

firms that were bailed (GM, Chrysler), such as more representation on

the board of directors, increasing worker-equity through policies like

employee stock ownership plans, maximum wages for CEOs, and other such

policies to make the workplace more equitable and democratic.

In their essay, Education’s Diminishing Returns and Revolutionary

Potential in the United States and Beyond, Armaline and Armaline discuss

education policy, an important issue which is often neglected when

thinking about envisioning a new and better society. “The new generation

of workers, young adults, and graduates face a difficult economic

climate—all amidst rising costs for education, credit, general costs of

living, and record levels of national debt. As it seems, many will enter

the employment market carrying significant debt in comparison to

previous generations.” (180–181) The authors argue that school in many

ways remains a “false promise”, as it not only reproduces inequalities

along the lines of race, class and gender (183), but also maintains and

perpetuates global capitalism, since “public education is often a

mechanism to produce new generations of workers socialized for their

inclusion, typically as wage slaves, in the larger political economy.”

(183) Indeed, schools are coercive institutions which teach students to

conform to social, cultural and occupational hierarchies, rather than

“rather than critical independent thought necessary for personal

autonomy and democratic societies” (183). Many working-class students

perceive school to be irrelevant to “real life.” (186) Overall, the

authors do an outstanding job in criticizing the current state of public

education and pointing to some ways forward.

Gordon’s essay, Anarchist Economics in Practice, is also well-written

and very useful. Gordon provides an important discussion of actual

economic practices undertaken by anarchists, including abstention,

anarchist unions, workplace and university occupations, cooperatives and

communes, local currencies, Food Not Bombs, Free shops (“gift

economies”), DIY cultural production, and the electronic commons. As

Gordon writes, many of these practices are prefigurative, that is, the

methods by which these practices are undertaken aim to exemplify the

type of future society anarchists strive towards. However, as Gordon

writes, some practices such as local currency exchanges are not

sufficiently prefigurative:

Some readers may object to the inclusion of certain examples, which,

they may argue, do not in fact qualify as anarchist. Alternative

currencies and workers’ cooperatives, for example, would receive

criticism from anarcho-communists since they retain, respectively, the

use of symbolic means of exchange and the payment of wages. Thus they

are not only islands inside capitalism, but also not sufficiently

prefigurative of an anarchist-communist society— one in which there are

no wages, and products are not exchanged but distributed according to

need. (204–205)

Gordon also provides a useful discussion of revolutionary strategy. He

differentiates between three different outlooks: 1) constructive direct

action, 2) propaganda by the deed, 3) and the politics of collapse.

Indeed, as Gordon writes, “Constructive direct action means that

anarchists who seek a world based on different social relations

undertake their construction by themselves. On such an account, for

social change to be successful, the modes of organization that will

replace capitalism, the state, patriarchy, and so on must be prepared

and developed alongside (though not instead of) the attack on present

institutions.” (213) It is important to realize, as Gordon notes, that

“anarchist economic practices ultimately function within rather than

outside capitalism,” and so “are by no means entirely detached from the

capitalist economy.” (213) With respect to “propaganda of the deed,”

readers would have benefited from an explicit definition of the phrase.

As Gordon writes, the term has often been associated with destruction

and violence. However, its origins are quite different, and if one

interprets the term (as Gordon does) as “the actual implementation and

display of anarchist social relations” (214) then the term

“prefigurative politics” captures the essence of this phrase without any

of its negative connotations. In that respect, his discussion of

“propaganda of the deed” is redundant. Gordon’s discussion of “the

politics of collapse” also merits close attention. Gordon’s rhetoric

towards the end comes across as alarmist. He writes, “the converging

crises of the twenty-first century—climate change, financial meltdown,

and the imminent peak in oil production—may be the only hope for

large-scale social transformation.” (216, emphasis added) This type of

rhetoric has a tendency to dissuade activists from using their agency to

bring changes to the world. It conveys a sense of inevitability, that

things in the world occur due to the immutable “internal logic” of

institutions. This perspective denies the role of human agency which can

be used to create alternatives and bring changes to the world. The

actions of institutions, such as corporations that pollute the

environment, cannot be detached from the role humans played in enabling

them.

Readers will experience difficulties in understanding Kaltefleiter’s

essay. Kaltefleiter’s Currency and Café Anarchy is about money and

currency, but the basic issue is Kaltefleiter’s decision to use a theory

by Stuart Hall known as the encoding/decoding model of communication.

The theory, in my view, is unnecessarily complicated and not very useful

in this context. Money is an instrument that the ruling class uses to

subordinate workers. The question of how to encode or decode texts is,

in my view, a distraction. Furthermore, Kaltefleiter does not provide

readers with terminology that is adequately defined. As an example,

Kaltefleiter writes,

Popular and scholarly understandings of money tend to share some common

traits found in narratives of globalization and modernity dyads.

Cultural anthropologist Faidra Papavasiliou argues that money is a

“fact,” a reality that almost assumes the status of an agent, an agent

that is increasingly unified and uniform across sociocultural,

political, and economic boundaries. (226, emphasis added)

There is some interesting discussion of alternative forms of currency

(mediums of exchange), such as the Ithaca HOURS system in Ithaca, New

York. However, some of Kaltefleiter’s statements are prone to

misinterpretation. For instance,

The capitalist agenda contributes to what Heidegger referred to as the

loss of any meaningful distinction between “nearness” and “distance” and

contributes to a leveling down of human experience, which in turn spawns

an indifference that renders human experience monotonous and

one-dimensional. It is within this space of one-dimensionality that a

sense of community is lost unless local citizens take responsibilities

for charting their own forms of social change. (229, emphasis added)

One could misinterpret the sentence highlighted above as an injunction

to pursue ethno-centric policies. Local communities should assert

themselves, but only in the context of a wider project which calls for

solidarity with the global working-class. Finally, Kaltefleiter fails to

discuss some key issues like how debt is used as a system of bondage by

capitalists, or what remuneration of work would look like in a

post-capitalist society.

Occupy, Resist, Produce! Lessons from Latin America’s Occupied Factories

by Marie Trigona looks at movements across Latin America to occupy

factories and other places of work through direct action. Many of these

occupations occurred in Argentina, spreading in the wake of the

financial crisis of 2001. Trigona writes, “In Argentina, more than

13,000 people work in occupied factories and businesses, otherwise known

as recuperated enterprises.” (238). The occupation of BAUEN Hotel is

discussed in great detail, as is the occupation of FASINPAT, a ceramic

tile factory. Overall, Trigona does an excellent job highlighting

successful experiences of worker control. Indeed, as Trigona writes,

workplace occupations “provide a liberatory vision by sowing the seeds

for a new society today,” and by “challenging market systems of

domination, and questioning the legitimacy of private property.” (240)

Ernesto Aguilar’s essay, Call It an Uprising: People of Color and the

Third World Organize against Capitalism, is deficient in many respects.

The essay does not have an underlying thesis; rather there is a topic of

discussion: “the response of people of color to capitalism.” (257)

Moreover, Aguilar barely mentions classical anarchists (Proudhon,

Bakunin, Kropotkin), instead relying heavily on Marxists like István

Mészáros, C.L.R James, Vijay Prashad, etc. Aguilar writes,

As a movement that aims for libertarian socialism, anarchism must

account for the experiences of people of color because of their unique

role in (sometimes forcibly) building modern capitalism, as well as

maintaining it. Further, as a movement that aims to abolish all

hierarchical authority, anarchism requires an analysis of colonialism,

imperialism, and white supremacy in order to live up to its own aims.

Unfortunately, in much anarchist theorizing and movement building this

is notably absent. (258)

But how is “anarchism,” an ideology which includes a wide-ranging set of

ideas (from the Egoism/Individualism of Stirner to the Collectivism of

Bakunin), inattentive or inimical to “colonialism, imperialism and white

supremacy”? Aguilar doesn’t provide a sufficient justification. Instead,

Aguilar simply moves on to a different topic, globalization. Perhaps the

only unifying theme in Aguilar’s essay is the concept of “dignidad,” the

Spanish word for dignity. But dignity in relation to what? The

workplace? Race? Class? Aguilar is correct that many people of color

continue to fight against capitalism. But some of these people are also

reactionaries who do not want anything to do with socialism.

Furthermore, if states in the Global South such as Venezuela, Ecuador or

India, challenge the global hegemony of the U.S., it would be irrational

to interpret this as the people of those countries fighting against the

imperialism of The West. Thus, if (former) heads of states like Rafael

Correa challenge the legitimacy of Ecuador’s debts or reject U.S. trade

agreements, it does not follow that “people of color are challenging

capitalism and oppression.” (268)

Towards the end, Aguilar writes, “Radical white revolutionary tendencies

such as First World socialism and anarchism have not adequately

responded to the ways people of color and the Third World have taken on

capitalism.” He continues, “one of Marxism’s most stunning failures, and

a major obstacle to relevance beyond shorthand in the new millennium,

has been a chronic inability to understand race and to dismiss racial

oppression in favor of economism and reductionism. Such critiques

paradoxically reduce race and gender to personal identity and

competitors to class, thus missing their material basis and the ways

they intersect with class.” (270) One could argue that this is the case.

However, it is hardly reasonable to suggest that all Marxists uniformly

are economistic and reductionists. If anything, the shortcomings of some

Marxists warrant a more integrated approach to issues of “race” and

“class,” which Aguilar fails to offer.

Shannon’s essay, Chopping Off the Invisible Hand: Internal Problems with

Markets and Anarchist Theory, Strategy, and Vision, also suffers from

numerous drawbacks. Shannon argues that Proudhon’s Mutualism is

essentially a market form of socialism. While one can certainly

interpret Proudhon in this manner, Shannon does not provide textual

evidence to establish this claim. Instead Shannon assumes that this is

the case, and writes “Proudhon envisioned a world where these

worker-owned and self-managed firms would compete in a stateless

market—a socialist market that was regulated by a grand agro-industrial

federation.” (276) Relying heavily on Kevin Carson’s erroneous

presentation of Proudhon, Shannon argues that “expropriation of

surplus-value cannot occur without state coercion.” (277–278) This

statement is problematic on numerous grounds. On the one hand,

capitalists appropriate surplus value produced by workers, not

“expropriate.” On the other hand, it is not immediately clear that

Proudhon uses the same conception of exploitation as Marx. As mentioned

previously, I interpret Proudhon to be putting forward a

property-theoretic critique of capitalism. By contrast, Marx presents a

value-theoretic critique. For Proudhon, the value workers produce, is

their property. When capitalists unjustly appropriate additional value

produced by workers, Proudhon uses the term “collective force.” (67)

Unfortunately, Shannon relies heavily on the secondary literature: Kevin

Carson, Benjamin Tucker, Martin and Barrot. Shannon also unconvincingly

argues, following Joseph Kay, that cooperatives “as a demand under

capitalism” suffer from “self-exploitation.” (282) Shannon fails to make

a convincing argument, however, as his earlier discussion of Proudhon’s

conception of “exploitation” is based on Carson’s erroneous rendering of

Proudhon.

In Ditching Class: The Praxis of Anarchist Communist Economics, Nappolos

argues that the abolition of class exploitation should be the foundation

of any future socialist economy. He argues that libertarian communist

economics has the following four defining features: 1) A commitment to a

future economy based on the praxis of the revolutionary working class

and popular classes, 2) An economy based on the destruction of the wage

system of labor, and a de-linking of the value of labor in production

from the distribution of society’s wealth to its members, 3) Collective

control and management of the entire economy by the direct control of

workers and community members united in a council system of direct

democracy, 4) The abolition of intermediary institutions of power

governing the economy. (292) Nappolos discusses the concept of

“prescriptive economics,” which he defines as “attempts to lay out a

vision, in our case, of a post-capitalist economic system based on some

core values,” (292) and “praxis”, which Paulo Freire defined as

“reflection and action upon the world in order to transform it.” (293)

Nappolos writes, “Libertarian communist prescriptive economics has then

been shaped by belief in the potential leadership of the working class

and popular classes, and the commitment to prescriptive economics

reflecting both a strategy for achieving such an economy and a theory

which reflects our experiences in struggle.” (293)

Nappolos also discusses the experience of small and large scale

Libertarian Communist projects, such as Hungary in 1956, Ukrainian

communes under Nestor Makhno, Zapatistas, Argentinian factory seizures,

Israeli Kibbutz, as well as anarcho-syndicalists during the Spanish

Revolution. (294–296) He discusses the role of Gaston Leval, a Spanish

anarchist who participated in revolutionary communes across Spain.

Nappolos does a good job discussing the ways in which Spanish anarchists

realized their vision of a future egalitarian society in the very

methods they undertook to carry out their revolution. (297–300) With

respect to how distribution of goods in a libertarian communist society

might occur, Nappolos distinguishes between planned communist economies,

and emergent economies. Whereas in planned economies the distribution of

goods occurs through planned production, in an emergent economy,

distribution “relies on intuitions and lessons from seeing society as an

interdependent, living, and complex, organism-like body” (303) “The

motivation for this position,” argues Nappolos, “arises from two

sources. First there is a suspicion here about our ability to plan

successfully, consciously, and explicitly a full economy; and secondly

there is both support for and historical antecedents of a dynamic and

evolving form of self-planning in a communist society.” (303)

Toward the end, however, Nappolos runs into trouble:

During the Hungarian and Spanish revolutions, people were able to take

over the economy and in some instances in a very rapid period of time

convert existing production for private profit into a collectivized

economy for common use. This occurred initially outside of any single

unified planning apparatus. Distribution evolved out of countless

actions of individuals and groups which came to unify and reorganize to

meet the demands presented by the wars and communities. This isn’t to

say there wasn’t organization, but to say there is a difference between

organization that is structurally and historically open and has the

ability to produce emergent and evolving structure, versus extensively

planned organization that is predictive and fairly static. There is

little evidence to point to people living under such conditions guiding

their activities by adhering to such programs. We can understand the

activity of an economy as emergent out of problem-solving at countless

levels, and producing stability once equilibrium can be reached. This is

a problem that is unfortunately hidden from these discussions: how to

obtain equilibrium in a revolutionary context is in many ways a more

significant problem than that of abstract models of potential futures.

(303, emphasis added)

What does it mean to reach an “equilibrium” in a “revolutionary

context”? “Equilibrium” as a theoretical concept does not belong to

classical economics (Smith, Ricardo, Marx; rather it has been

popularized by neoclassical economists, but many proponents of classical

political economy feel it is not very useful. In fact, I would argue

that it is obscurantist, since it misrepresents relations of

exploitation based on one’s class position. How can there be an

“equilibrium,” “balance” or “stability” with respect to class

exploitation? Moreover, in his “critique of the wage system” Nappolos

misinterprets the fundamental issue with wage-labor. While he is correct

that communists reject wage-labor, the issue is not unfair remuneration

for work done, i.e. the problem is not is the magnitude of wages

$100/hour vs $1/hour. Rather, it is a matter of ending the hierarchical

and exploitative arrangement between bosses and workers. Under

capitalism, labor-power is commodified and treated as private property.

Capitalists have a monopoly on deriving use-value from labor-power by

virtue of their class position, workers cannot do the same. Workers must

sell their labor-power for the sake of their livelihood. Capitalists, on

the other hand, use the labor-power of workers to make profits, thereby

further enriching themselves. The objective is to eliminate this

asymmetry in one’s relationship to private property. Furthermore,

Nappolos fails to discuss workers’ control of the means of production.

Decision-making in large capitalist firms is highly centralized, falling

within the purview of the board of directors. These decisions are then

handed down to subordinates, who enjoy some degree of independence, but

nevertheless are compelled to follow directives from above. Will these

hierarchical and authoritarian social relationships exist in a

Libertarian Communist society?

Wayne Price’s essay, The Anarchist Method: An Experimental Approach to

Post-Capitalist Economies, addresses the question of what a libertarian

socialist economy might look like, and what method to pursue in order to

realize this objective. Price distinguishes the “anarchist method” from

the Utopian-Moral approach – exemplified by Saint-Simon, Robert Owen,

Fourier, Cabet, Proudhon – to the Marxist-Determinist approach,

exemplified by Marx and Engels. Price classifies Parecon (“participatory

economics”) as a part of the Utopian-Moral approach. Price argues that

the advantages of utopian models is that “[thinkers] start with a set of

moral values by which the present society may be condemned”, then move

on to “envision social institutions which could embody these values.”

(313) In other words, Utopian-Moral methods such as Parecon “offer a

yardstick by which to judge potential economies, as well as real ones,

so that radicals do not claim to be for freedom but accept some

totalitarian monstrosity.” (313) However, with the exception of Parecon,

Price argues that “historic utopian models were very undemocratic in

structure.” (314) Moreover, Price argues, “there is a problem in that

the utopian approach starts from values rather than from an analysis of

how capitalist society functions”, that is, “There is really no

necessary connection between any particular model and the dynamics of

capitalism (besides the moral critique).” (314) Furthermore, “The

visions of the possible futures do not point to any strategies for

getting to these futures”; “A program that does not say whether to be

revolutionary or reformist is not much of a guide to action.” (314)

Price contrasts the Utopian-moral method to the Marxist-Determinist

approach, as expounded by Marx and Engels. For the “original Marxists,”

Price argues, it was “necessary to analyze how capitalism was

developing, including its main drive mechanism: the capital-labor

relationship in production.” (314) The working-class revolution

“provided the basis of a strategy” and “indicated the emergence of a new

society out of that revolution.” (314) For Marx and Engels, Price

argues, the nature of this new society was only mentioned in passing

remarks, such as a few paragraphs in Marx’s “Critique of the Gotha

Program.” (314) For instance, Marx argued that workers would initially

be paid with “labor credits” and later be provided with goods freely

upon need. (315) “The goal of Marx and Engels,” writes Price, “was not

to implement a new social system.” Rather, “It was to see that the

working class overthrew the capitalist class and took power for itself.

Once this happened, the historical process would take care of further

social development.” (315) The advantage of the Marxist-Determinist

method for Price is that it is grounded in economic theory. He writes,

“It has an analysis of what forces are moving in the direction of a new

society and what ones are blocking them.” Furthermore, he writes, “It

leads to a strategy that identifies a specific change agent (the working

class, leading other oppressed groups).” (315) On the other hand, Price

argues, the Marxist-Determinist method “has no moral standard.” He

writes,

So when Marxist-led revolutions produce state-capitalist

totalitarianisms that murder tens of millions of workers and peasants,

very many Marxists support this as the result of the historical process

which has created “actually existing socialism.” Marx and Engels would

undoubtedly have been horrified by what developed in the Soviet Union

and other so-called communist countries. But a method without a moral

standard made it difficult for Marxists to not support these states.

(315)

Price contrasts both of these approaches with the “anarchist method,”

which, he writes, “starts from the doubt that every region and national

culture will choose the same version of libertarian socialist society.”

(316) As Malatesta writes, there will not be ‘one solution’, rather “a

thousand different and changing solutions in the same way as social

existence is different and varied in time and space.” (316)

Nevertheless, solutions tried must be non-exploitative and

non-oppressive. In other words, “they must ‘prevent the constitution and

consolidation of new privilege’ and ‘leave the way open for future

improvements.’” (317) Differing models of post-capitalist societies,

however, raises a different set of issues. One problem which Price

identifies is the method of coordination in the post-capitalist economy.

How will resources be distributed across the economy? Price points to

three proposals: a market, central-planning, and some sort of

non-centralized planning. (318) “In a pluralist, experimental,

post-capitalist world” writes Price, “different regions might experiment

with different types of economic coordination.” (319) Another issue

identified by Price, is the size of the economic unit. Price writes,

As internationalists, we are aware that the world is being knit together

by imperialist globalization. At the same time we know that much of this

worldwide centralization is not due to technical needs but to the need

of capitalists to control natural resources, to dominate world markets,

and to exploit the poorest workers in order to make the biggest profits.

To end the rule of states and bureaucracies, anarchists want as much as

possible of local, face-to-face democracy. This requires a degree of

economic decentralization. Indeed, any sort of economic planning would

be easier, and easier to make democratic, the smaller the units. Finally

it would also be easier to keep production and consumption in balance

with nature, the smaller the units are. (319)

Another issue discussed by Price, is that of technology. “Just as is

true of economic institutions,” writes Price, “productive technology

would have to be flexible, pluralistic, and experimental.” (320)

“Machinery and the methodology of production have been organized by the

processes of capitalism (and militarism) to serve its interests.

Technology would have to be completely reorganized and redeveloped over

time to meet the needs of a new society.” (320) Another key question is

reward for work. “In a fully communist society,” writes Price, “work

would be done only for the pleasure of doing it, or because people feel

a duty, or because of social pressure.” Price continues, “consumption

will be a right, based only on human need and unrelated to effort.”

(321) The rest of the essay discusses a “transitional society.”

(322–323) As Price notes, the notion of a ‘transitional society’ has

been used to justify all sorts of horrors for Stalinist totalitarian

dictatorships. (323) As Price writes, “This is not what Bakunin, or even

Marx, had in mind. It shows the need for a vision with moral values to

judge a new society.” He continues, “Neither Marx nor Bakunin/Guillaume

proposed a mechanism for going from a transitional phase to full

communism. One possibility might be to use the idea of a split economy

(a basic communism and a non-basic needs sector). As productivity grows,

the free communist sector might be deliberately expanded, until it

gradually includes all (or most) of the economy.” (323)

There are numerous issues with Price’s essay. First, Price fails to

distinguish a capitalist system from a non-capitalist system. What is a

“capitalist” system? (See my critique of the essay Escaping Capitalist

Hegemony by Wright and Williams above.) Furthermore, as someone who

identifies as an anarchist, I am not in agreement with Marx’s conception

of “the first phase of a communist society.” Marx’s position on the

legitimacy of the state has always been ambiguous. Can a society in

which harmful instrumentalization of the state persists be characterized

as “communist”? I and many other anarchists would say no. Furthermore,

it is necessary to draw a distinction between “the first phase of a

communist society” vs a “transitional society,” which are not the same

thing. The notion of a “transitional society” is in many ways a Leninist

concept, which I reject. In my reading of Marx, I have not come across

any discussion of a “transitional society,” but rather a direct

transition from capitalism to socialism vis a vis a proletarian

revolution. Marxists have, in my view, erroneously interpreted Marx as a

proponent of a so-called “transitional society.” The essential point is

that many people on the left find the concept of an intermediate

“transitional society” to be highly objectionable. We should strive for

a socialist society, not a “transitional society.”

The final essay by Albert, Porous Borders of Anarchist Vision and

Strategy, discusses participatory economics, or “Parecon,” which Albert

helped develop in tandem with Robin Hahnel. Albert argues an anarchist

society would forbid the systematic privileging of some people

materially or socially over others. He writes, “in an anarchist society

citizens should freely fulfill themselves without being systematically

subordinate to or systematically superior to other citizens. We should

each benefit from the same structural opportunities. We should each gain

from the gains others enjoy.” (327) Albert writes, while an anarchist

society should rule certain institutions out, freedom to own slaves, or

the freedom to hire wage-slaves, it should also rule in social

components deemed anarchistic. According to Albert, a positive

institutional vision would allow people to “have the information,

circumstances, inclinations, opportunity, and even the responsibility to

creatively and knowledgeably self-manage their own situations.” (329)

Albert argues that the first value which a future anarchist economy

should embody is that “people should have a say in decisions

proportionate to the degree those decisions affect them.” (329) Second,

“citizens should have a claim on society’s economic product that

increases if they do socially valued work longer, more intensely, or

under worse conditions.” (330) Third, “people should care about one

another’s well being rather than each of us trampling the rest or at the

least turning the other cheek to others’ difficulties.” (330) Fourth,

“people should have a wide range of options available and that when

making choices, diverse paths forward should be kept available or

experimented with.” (330) The fifth and sixth values, are that

humans and the rest of the environment ultimately constitute an entwined

community in which humans have to take responsibility not only for the

impact of our choices on ourselves but also on the rest of nature’s

domain – and, in turn, efficiency is the related idea that economic

activity should produce what people seek for fulfillment and development

without wasting assets we value, while furthering self-management,

equity, solidarity, diversity, and husbandry. (330)

Albert argues that an anarchist economic vision should propose specific

institutions because worthy economic values are essential but are not

convincing by themselves. In other words, people’s skepticism cannot

solely be dispelled by asserting worthy values; we must also “describe

institutions consistent with those preferred values.” Furthermore,

Albert argues, “values alone do not provide needed orientation for

strategy and tactics.” He writes, “Institutional insights that move us

toward effective strategic choices need to be shared and built upon,

rather than each actor having to start over repeatedly as if no one had

traveled similar ground before.” Thus, “parecon proposes a minimalist

institutional vision for establishing economic conditions that will

permit future people to self manage their own economic lives while also

being sufficient to overcome cynicism and inform strategy.” (331) A

potential minimalist structure for addressing equitable remuneration and

work apportionment are Balanced Job Complexes.

Moreover, Parecon thinks that economic allocation should occur according

to participatory planning, that is, “cooperative negotiation of economic

inputs and outputs by nested, self-managing workers’ and consumers’

councils.” (336) Albert rejects a pluralist approach, that is, a society

where economic allocation is based on a mixture of markets,

central-planning and participatory planning, since “If there are two,

three, or more different methods for allocating items, then the same

items will have different and conflicting relative prices depending

which method of allocation is consulted, and there will also be

different and conflicting logic and associated implications for behavior

operating as well, and the contradictions will more often than not

disrupt viable operations.” (335) Second, “if we self-consciously, or

even just inadvertently, include either markets or central planning or

any combination of the two as our means of allocation in a future

economy, these structures will subvert our other libertarian values and

aspirations, just like including corporate divisions of labor would

subvert our agendas, or including top-down rule would subvert our

agendas, or including remuneration for property would subvert our

agendas.” Thus, an anarchist vision, according to Albert, should reject

market and centrally planned allocation.

On the question of an “Anarchist Strategy,” Albert supports democratic

centralism as an organizational principle, but only as a means of

facilitating the creation of participatory communes and fostering

popular power. Under complicated circumstances, such as in the “early

stages of a transition process seeking self-management throughout

society” or a situation where a country is in a massive project to bring

about structural transformation, Albert argues that democratic

centralism could be justified. (340–342) Albert concludes by addressing

the necessity to overcome “not only capitalist, but also coordinator

mentalities and structures in our own projects and in society writ

large.” (343) It is crucial to recognize, Albert writes, that “there is

no single virtuous or effective anarchist strategy such that one size

fits all.”

On balance, Accumulation does a satisfactory job of providing

non-Marxist socialist perspectives on important issues which the left

should be concerned with. However, many of the essays rely heavily on

what Marxists have to say, or use other people’s erroneous depictions of

classical anarchists. Marie Trigona’s essay was my favorite out of the

entire collection.