💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › ruth-kinna-power-in-anarchism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 13:40:05. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: Power in Anarchism Author: Ruth Kinna Date: 2011 Language: en Topics: power Source: Kinna, Ruth. “Anarchism, Power in.” In Encyclopedia of Power, edited by Keith Dowding, 18–19. Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE Reference, 2011. Gale eBooks (accessed June 22, 2021).
Power is a central issue in modern anarchist thought. Whereas anarchism
was traditionally linked to authority—or its rejection—anarchists now
talk in terms of power and counterpower. The change in emphasis is
linked to the emergence of “postanarchist” theory: anarchism that draws
on postmodern and poststructuralist thought, associated with Todd May,
Lewis Call, and Saul Newman.
The leading figures of 19^(th)- and early 20^(th)-century
anarchism—Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, Mikhail Bakunin, Peter Kropotkin—were
not unconcerned with power. On the contrary, even Proudhon, often
regarded as the most individualist of the three, talked enthusiastically
about the collective power of the workers. And many others defined
anarchism as the abolition of power. But the concept was not made
subject to sustained analysis—in contrast to law, authority, God, and
science, for example. When they talked about power, 19^(th)-century
writers usually had one of two things in mind: the repressive machinery
of the state or the liberating potential of collective actions. These
two aspects of power were typically counterposed such that collective
actions were believed to hold the key to the destruction of the state’s
capacity to repress. What was important in this analysis was the image
of power that it captured. On this account, power was about struggle
against physical force (or as Max Weber would put it, the state’s
monopoly of physical violence). Thus, the power of the state was
typically equated with police, armed forces, prisons, torture, corporal
and capital punishment—later on, surveillance—and the power of the
oppressed was variously identified with barricades, terrorist or
guerrilla actions, spontaneous revolt, the organization of peasants and
workers in syndicates, ethical change, and the development of other
nonhierarchical grassroots organizations. In the 1870s and 1880s, when
memories of the Paris Commune were still very fresh and optimism about
the prospects for European revolution high, the association between
power and physical force was strong (though Tolstoyan anarchists always
rejected the necessity and justifiability of this link). The same was
true in the early 20^(th) century, when anarchists were again engaged in
revolutionary war. Nestor Makhno, who led anarchist resistance against
counterrevolutionaries and Bolsheviks in the Ukraine during the civil
war, characterized revolutionary action as a capacity to conquer or
exterminate oppressors. The power of revolutionaries depended on overt
coercion. In the latter part of the 19^(th) century and again after the
defeat of the Republicans in the Spanish Civil War, the emphasis shifted
to the ethical and communitarian aspects of collective power: the
ability of oppressed groups to find ways of living, organizing, and
behaving—often explicitly nonviolent—that did not mimic the repressive
practices of the state. This way of thinking about power was resurgent
in the 1960s in the work of such anarchists as Colin Ward, George
Woodcock, and Paul Goodman. Capturing the change, Woodcock described the
old-style anarchists as “bellicose barricaders.” The new anarchists, he
suggested, “had forgotten Spain and had no use for the romanticism of
the dynamitero.... They were militant pacifists” (Woodcock, 1992,
45–46).
One of the premises of postanarchist thinking is that classical
anarchism (Woodcock’s old and new anarchists) has a narrowly structural
idea of power and wrongly considers that power can and must be
abolished. May distinguishes between “strategic” and “tactical”
philosophical approaches to power. The first—which captures the
classical anarchist position—assumes that power refers to the central
problematic, that it derives essentially or for the most part from the
site on which that problematic focuses (the economic system, the state,
etc.). In contrast, tactical political philosophy suggests, “there is no
center within which power is to be located.” Power might conglomerate
around particular sites, but these points of concentration are not
points of origin, and power extends to multiple sites as well as to the
interplay between them. Like May, Call draws on Michel Foucault to
elaborate his idea. Finding classical anarchists guilty of an obsession
with capital and the state, Call rejects the simplistic top-down model
of power to argue that it is present in any social relation. Power, he
adds, always implies resistance. But resistance, counterpower, or
antipower is nothing like the struggle of the classical anarchist, which
was motivated by ideas of emancipation and wrongly assumed the existence
of a human subject with free will. Why? Because on the one hand,
postanarchists characterize the repressive nature of capitalism in novel
ways, taking their lead from surrealists and situationists, and on the
other hand, they deny the possibility of achieving a condition of
liberation. Resistance, then, is about experimentation in everyday life
and escaping the deadening discourses and consciousness of bourgeois
capitalism through permanent resistance or, following Gilles Deleuze,
rhizomatic action.
The difference between the classical and the postanarchist positions
should not be exaggerated. Although postanarchists challenge the
rationalist epistemology of much 19^(th)- and 20^(th)-century anarchist
thought, the political significance of the revision is not as great as
sometimes claimed. Insofar as arguments about power are concerned, the
comparison between the two positions is misleading. Postanarchists have
accurately characterized the 19^(th)-century conception of power, but
overlooked the analyses of related concepts—notably authority— in which
the relational issues so central to contemporary thought were first
probed.
Ruth Kinna
See also Bakunin, Mikhail ; Collective Action Problem ; Foucault, Michel
; Kropotkin, Peter ; Revolution ; Revolutionary Cell Structure
Call, L. (2002). Postmodern anarchism. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books.
May, T. (1994). The political philosophy of poststructuralist anarchism.
University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press.
Newman, S. (2001). From Bakunin to Lacan: Anti-authoritarianism and the
dislocation of power. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books.
Woodcock, G. (1992). Anarchism revisited. In Anarchism and anarchists
(pp. 41–58). Kingston, Ontario, Canada: Quarry Press.