đŸ Archived View for library.inu.red âș file âș richard-gough-thomas-william-godwin.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 13:38:14. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content
âĄïž Next capture (2024-06-20)
-=-=-=-=-=-=-
Title: William Godwin Author: Richard Gough Thomas Date: 2019 Language: en Topics: William Godwin, biography Source: Retrieved on 7th August 2021 from https://es1lib.org/book/3711404/ae8c17
Revolutionary Lives is a series of short, critical biographies of
radical figures from throughout history. The books are sympathetic but
not sycophantic, and the intention is to present a balanced and, where
necessary, critical evaluation of the individualâs place in their
political field, putting their actions and achievements in context and
exploring issues raised by their lives, such as the use or rejection of
violence, nationalism, or gender in political activism. While
individuals are the subject of the books, their personal lives are dealt
with lightly except insofar as they mesh with political concerns. The
focus is on the contribution these revolutionaries made to history, an
examination of how far they achieved their aims in improving the lives
of the oppressed and exploited, and how they can continue to be an
inspiration for many today.
Series Editors:
Sarah Irving, Kingâs College, London
Professor Paul Le Blanc, La Roche College, Pittsburgh
My heartfelt thanks must go out to everyone involved with Newcastle
Universityâs William Godwin: Forms, Fears, Futures conference in 2017,
and the community of Godwin scholars across the world. I am immensely
grateful to Professor Mark Philp for his encouragement, and this book is
stronger and richer for the suggestions and advice of John-Erik Hansen.
Thanks must also go to David Castle and Robert Webb at Pluto Press for
their patience with a first-time author.
Finally, the book would never have been written without the urging of
Joshua M. Reynolds, or the support of Jen Edwards, Alex Burnett and
Angharad Thomas.
His contemporaries believed him to be the most important radical thinker
of their age. William Godwin (1756â1836) was a political philosopher in
the purest sense â he wrote no great revolutionary speeches, nor did he
ever issue a political manifesto. As the French Revolution careened from
popular uprising to government terror, and from Directory to despotism,
across the Channel British radicals pressed for parliamentary reform,
womenâs rights and greater religious freedom. Godwin went further,
questioning the most basic assumptions of government itself. Many of his
peers were tried or imprisoned for their activism but Godwin, a lifelong
critic of violence, and undeniably a theorist rather than an agitator,
endured decades of abuse in the government-backed press because no
political or criminal charges could ever be found against him.
William Godwin was an anarchist. He would not have understood the term
in the way we do. He regarded anarchy in its popular sense, as a synonym
for chaos. He recognised it as a creative chaos, however, and argued
that its principal danger was that it created the conditions that might
allow new (more brutal) authority to rise in its wake. Godwin was
critical of authority as a principle, not merely its implementation, and
believed that our ability to reason (if developed) would eventually make
laws and government unnecessary. Godwin explained his ideas in An
Enquiry Concerning Political Justice (1793), written at the height of
the French Revolution when it seemed as if the world had been pitched
into the kind of creative chaos where anything was possible. Political
Justice came to be regarded as one of the first major texts in the
history of anarchist thought, exemplifying what is now (loosely) defined
as âphilosophicalâ anarchism â the theoretical basis for
anti-authoritarian principles and political action. Godwin himself was
not a revolutionary. A quiet man, often shy among strangers, Godwin
wanted to change the world through writing and conversation, recognising
that educating people to reason for themselves was a more certain way of
making things better than imposing better things on them.
Figure 1 Godwin described James Northcoteâs 1803 portrait as âthe
principal memorandum of my corporal existence that will remain after my
death.â
(National Portrait Gallery, London)
âAnarchistâ is a word that conjures up images of revolutionary action,
be it via the symbolic violence of the Black Bloc or the peaceful
overthrow of the old social order in Catalonia at the beginning of the
Spanish Civil War. Yet it also describes a wide range of
anti-authoritarian political thought, on both the left and right, united
only by a common resistance to being told what to do. The word itself
has an image problem: its literal meaning is simply to be âwithout
rulersâ but we have been told for centuries that, without rulers, the
existing order of society would tear itself apart. We might cynically
observe that the existing order could do with a shake-up, but few of us
wish to do without order at all, and we have been led to believe that
order is maintained through the exercise of authority â of people giving
orders and other people following them, with consequences for stepping
too far out of line (because other people canât be trusted). Many
anarchists would argue that order is simply something that happens when
a group of people find out how to get along, and that most of the things
that authority claims to protect us from are indirectly caused by
authority in the first place (e.g. theft â which is caused by
inequality, which usually benefits those in power). Making statements
about âwhat anarchists thinkâ is, of course, a quixotic endeavour.
Anarchism is a philosophy, but one that naturally defies rigid
definitions. Anarchism has ideas, and it has thinkers, and it is easier
to write about âanarchismsâ (or the anarchism of a particular
individual) than it is to discuss every school of thought under its
umbrella.
If his contribution to anarchism were the sum of Godwinâs achievement,
he would be an interesting figure for historians and philosophers. He
was more: a novelist, historian and childrenâs writer of enormous
influence in his own time. His extensive diaries reveal his direct
connection to dozens of the most important names of his time in the
fields of literature, politics, science and art (too many to do justice
to in one book). Most importantly, he was the loving husband of Mary
Wollstonecraft â in the view of history, easily the most important
feminist writer and thinker of the eighteenth century â and the father
of Mary Shelley, a novelist of immense cultural significance. Their
lives are closely interlinked, but this book is an account of Godwinâs
life and thought, and can only tackle Wollstonecraft and her daughter
where their influence is crucial to Godwinâs story. Readers are referred
to Janet Toddâs Mary Wollstonecraft: A Revolutionary Life (2000) for the
most authoritative version of that writerâs life; biographies of Mary
Shelley are numerous but Anne K. Mellorâs Mary Shelley: Her Life, Her
Fiction, Her Monsters (1989) is a standard.
Godwinâs story is as much held in his writing as it is in his life, and
an extended discussion of his literary and philosophical works is
essential to communicating why the philosopher was such a crucial (and
controversial) figure in the culture of his time. This book attempts to
tell the story of Godwinâs life, from his rise to radical fame in the
1790s to obscurity and bankruptcy years later, and so draws extensively
on his letters and diaries (preserving his idiosyncratic spelling and
sometimes cryptic abbreviations). Yet it could not adequately do so
without explaining the theory of Political Justice or the ideas of The
Enquirer, nor could it explain the philosopherâs character without Caleb
Williams, St Leon, or his Memoir of Wollstonecraft. Godwinâs life was a
life in letters even more than it was a life in politics â his works
contributed to shaping the literary, historical and educational genres
that we take for granted today â and his ideas have influenced
generations of thinkers up to the present day.
William Godwin was born in 1756, the son of a Dissenting minister and
the grandson of another.
âDissenterâ was the name given to those Protestants who had opposed the
1662 Act of Uniformity; the Presbyterians, Baptists and
Congregationalists who refused to conform with Anglican strictures on
prayer, theology and the authority of the crown over the church. Their
descendants traced their lineage back to the âIndependentsâ of the Civil
War, defended (with reservations) the memory of Cromwell, and celebrated
the 1688 revolution as the first step on the road to religious and
political freedom.
Dissenters were found in all walks of life but, for a variety of
reasons, were well-represented among artisans and merchants of the
bigger towns and cities. The Test and Corporation Acts, requiring at
least occasional Anglican religious observance from public officials,
excluded Dissenters from parliament and municipal office. Though a small
number were willing to pay lip service to the Church of England in
exchange for their own seat at the table, the majority threw whatever
weight they had behind the liberal Whigs. Godwin in later life was
conscious of quite how much Dissenting culture had shaped him, how much
it coloured his attitudes to political and cultural developments and how
it affected the way he thought.
Godwin was the seventh of thirteen children, and many of his siblings
did not live to see adulthood. The philosopher remembered his father as
a warm-hearted (but far from clever) man, with a tendency towards
austerity and ill humour that were balanced by the vivacity of Godwinâs
mother.[1] Disputes within congregations â many Dissenting groups
reserved the right to reject ministers they could not see eye to eye
with â saw the family move from Wisbech in Cambridgeshire (where Godwin
was born) to Debenham in Suffolk, before finally settling in the small
village of Guestwick in Norfolk, in 1760. Somewhere either before or
after Williamâs birth, the already busy household took on a cousin,
Hannah Godwin (later Sothren), as a lodger. Hannah appears to have been
the young Williamâs most important friend in early childhood. It was
Hannah that introduced the future novelist to books and, in defiance of
his fatherâs particularly strict form of Calvinism, took him to the
theatre at the age of nine.
William was the only one of the surviving children that felt the call to
the ministry. The elder Godwin did not encourage his sonâs ambitions. As
a small boy, William had given sermons from atop a chair in the kitchen
and terrorised a schoolmate with descriptions of his damnation. The
young Godwin was clever, enthusiastic and precocious, signs that his
father took as symptoms of his arrogance. At the age of eleven, William
was taken from the local school at Hindolveston and sent to live as the
sole pupil of the Reverend Samuel Newton in Norwich. Williamâs new
teacher was far more educated, but a far stricter Calvinist (and
disciplinarian) than his father. Newton was a follower of Robert
Sandeman, who (as Godwin would later write) âafter Calvin had damned
ninety-nine in a hundred of mankind, has contrived a scheme for damning
ninety-nine in a hundred of the followers of Calvinâ.[2] The young
Godwin was whipped and berated for his pride, yet he formed a bond with
his tutor that would last until the ideas contained in Political Justice
drove a wedge between them.
Even writing forty years later, Godwinâs memories of Newton retained a
touch of anger. He was cold, âa very insufficient masterâ and âa
despotâ, but he shaped his pupilâs religious and political opinions for
many years to come.[3] In his unfinished autobiography, Godwin wrote:
âNewton was certainly my friend. His sentiments towards me were
singular. He always treated me as self-conceited and arrogant: yet he
had a high opinion of my talents.â[4] The two remained in correspondence
into the 1790s.
At fourteen, he withdrew from Newtonâs tutelage and returned to the
school at Hindolveston. Godwin described his time under Newton as âmore
vexatious than I could well endureâ but within a few months he was back
with Newton again, until his teacher dismissed him at the end of
1771.[5] Godwin returned home to work as an assistant at his former
school. His father died the next year and soon Williamâs mother was
organising his return to study. University was probably never
considered: again, Oxford and Cambridge required adherence to the Church
of England. Instead, Godwin would enrol at one of the countryâs many
Dissenting Academies â institutions that had grown up over the course of
the eighteenth century to provide an educated ministry for nonconformist
congregations (in the face of legal harassment by Anglicans and Tories)
but, in some cases, had developed a reputation for excellence that far
surpassed that of Englandâs ancient universities. Most students went on
to a religious calling, some even with the established church (such as
Thomas Malthus). The best of the academies taught according to the model
established by the pioneering Philip Doddridge (1702â51): teaching in
English rather than Latin and favouring critical reading and debate over
doctrinaire instruction. Godwinâs father had studied under Doddridge.
The scientist Joseph Priestley â who taught at Warrington from 1761â67 â
had been a student at Doddridgeâs Daventry Academy in the years
immediately after the teacherâs death. With a bursary from the
institutionâs sponsors, Godwin joined Londonâs Hoxton Academy in
September 1773.
Godwin spent five years at Hoxton under the direction of the Reverends
Abraham Rees and Andrew Kippis. Both were literary men, Rees an
encyclopaedist and Kippis a biographer. As teachers, they were happy to
debate with their students â Kippis too had been a student of Doddridge
â and the two menâs differing theological views suggest that the academy
embraced a variety of religious positions. We see in Godwinâs writing
his commitment to open discussion as the best means of discovering
truth, an idea that must have been born at Hoxton. It was his education
at Hoxton, Godwin wrote, that had inculcated the mode of fearless
intellectual enquiry that made him both famous and infamous in later
years: âfrom that time forward, I was indefatigable in my search for
truth â I was perpetually prompting myself with the principle, Sequar
veritatem âŠâ â he would follow truth, wherever it led.[6]
Godwin regarded himself as an outsider at the academy, his beliefs at
odds with those of the majority, but he nonetheless made lifelong
friends there. Kippis would later help Godwin find his feet as a
professional writer, but it was fellow student James Marshall who would
become Godwinâs colleague, confidant and even occasional scribe, until
Marshallâs death in 1832.
Godwin finished Hoxton in 1778, aged twenty-two. With a good reference
from the academy, he quickly found himself in what seems to have been a
temporary appointment as minister to a congregation in Ware,
Hertfordshire. It was here that Godwin made another friend â Joseph
Fawcett â who the philosopher would one day describe as one of his four
âprincipal oral instructorsâ.[7] Fawcett was a younger man, but
similarly educated and destined for the Dissenting ministry. Likely
influenced by the great American theologian Jonathan Edwards, who
considered only universal love â by extension, the love of God â to be a
virtue, Fawcett dismissed the importance of personal affection. Godwin
found the idea compelling, âwell adapted to the austerity and perfection
which Calvinism recommendsâ.[8] The sentiment was reinforced when he
read Edwards himself, but the idea remained with Godwin long after he
appeared to have left Calvinism behind.
Godwin left Ware for a period in London, before an appointment as
minister in Stowmarket, Suffolk at the beginning of 1780. For the first
year, he had few friends. In 1781 Godwin made the acquaintance of a new
arrival, a well-read textiles manufacturer called Frederic Norman, with
whom he was able to discuss contemporary French philosophy. The two
became fast friends and Godwin recounts that it was in this period that
he read dâHolbachâs SystĂšme de la Nature (1770) and experienced a series
of revolutions in his religious opinions. The book denies the existence
of free will and argues that belief in a higher power is merely the
product of fear and ignorance. This determinism, usually referred to in
the period as âthe law of necessityâ, was a profound influence on
Godwin. Edwards too had denied free will, albeit within the framework of
a divine plan â here Godwin must have begun to formulate his ideas of
cause and effect, eventually arriving at the idea that thoughts and
actions were usually the product of their intellectual context (thus,
caused by society) rather than the result of individual choices. These
theories would go on to have substantial influence on the philosophy
that underpinned Political Justice.
Godwin laboured on in Stowmarket for just over two years. The
circumstances of his departure suggest many things that would become
clear in his published works: since taking up the appointment, Godwin
had been in dispute with neighbouring ministers as to whether his right
to administer the sacraments derived from the congregation, or from more
established ministers. His flock had invited him to give communion and,
after discussing the matter with members of the group, Godwin agreed to
do so without asking for the approval of the other Dissenting ministers
of the county. His colleagues were scandalised by what they saw as the
young Godwinâs arrogance â there may have been some truth in this
characterisation, as the philosopherâs later account of the matter gives
the impression that he thought it easier to obtain forgiveness than
permission â but the principal at stake was a meaningful one. The
community had chosen their minister, and that was all that mattered. The
most senior minister in the area, the Reverend Thomas Harmer, wrote to
Godwin to explain that unless he acknowledged their authority, his own
would not be recognised outside the Stowmarket congregation. It seems
unlikely that this troubled Godwin. He returned to London in April 1782.
With help from Marshall, Godwin made his first foray into writing. He
planned his own periodical, a biographical series of great Englishmen,
but the first instalment quickly mushroomed into a book-length project.
The finished work, The History of the Life of William Pitt, Earl of
Chatham, was published anonymously in January 1783. The work went out
anonymously â not unusual in the period â but to later readers the marks
of Godwinâs authorship are obvious. The introduction makes impassioned
claims about impartiality and truth and of truthâs inexorable progress,
all sentiments that would colour his early work. The publisher
distributed the book to a number of major political figures, but it
seems to have made little impression. Though he continued to publish
throughout 1783, Godwin made another attempt at ministry, preaching at
Beacons-field (in Buckinghamshire) for the first half of the year.
None of Godwinâs works that year had significant impact, but all of them
contained signs of the ideas that were developing in his mind. A
pamphlet defending the perennial parliamentary rebel, Charles James Fox,
marked Godwinâs lifelong admiration for the worldly, profligate
politician who would one day prove instrumental in the abolition of the
slave trade. A collection of Godwinâs Beaconsfield sermons was
remarkable for suggesting that faith should be subordinated to reason.
Attempting to set himself up as a teacher, he convinced the publisher
Thomas Cadell to print his substantial (fifty-four-page) prospectus
outlining his approach to education. He failed to attract enough pupils
to make a start in the venture, but Godwin writes eloquently about the
power of literature as a moral teacher. Most interesting of all is a
work called The Herald of Literature. Seemingly intended to show off
Godwinâs skills as a literary reviewer, the Herald comprises of ten
reviews â each one an imaginary work by a well-known author. In each
case, Godwin provides lengthy âquotationsâ, making a fair imitation of
the more established authorâs style while offering his own praise or
censure as reviewer (which, perhaps in a spirit of fairness, is based on
general trends in that authorâs other works). The entire project is
audacious and speaks of Godwinâs dry (but sometimes absurd) sense of
humour.[9]
The Herald apparently led to more work in 1784. The publisher John
Murray gave Godwin work as a critic on his periodical (the English
Review) and commissioned him to translate the Jacobite Lord Lovatâs
memoirs from their original French. Godwin dashed off three novels the
same year, the shortest in only ten days. Damon and Delia, Italian
Letters and Imogen are in many ways typical romances of the period â
stories of rapacious aristocrats and virtuous damsels in peril. The
philosopher likely wrote what he thought would be quickly accepted by
publishers, as he and Marshall were often in desperate financial straits
at the time. Imogen, however, stands out as another example of Godwinâs
playfulness: like The Herald of Literature, the novel is another âhoaxâ,
discussing in its preface whether the work is a translation of an
ancient Welsh manuscript or a seventeenth century fabrication. Nobody is
likely to have been fooled by this; the âfound manuscriptâ was a
well-known device in historical novels of the time. Viewed through this
lens, the preface appears as a deliberately arch performance. Godwin
draws attention to the storyâs use of Milton (Godwin rarely missed an
opportunity to write about Milton) and makes extravagant comparisons
between the beauty of the âtranslationâ and the best of Virgil, Homer
and (another literary fake) Ossian. The preface gives us a taste of the
vanity that was the philosopherâs lifelong weakness, but it equally
displays a playfulness and self-awareness that many of Godwinâs later
critics missed.
Kippis suggested to the publisher George Robinson that he employ Godwin
as his assistant in compiling the New Annual Register. The Register was
a Whig and Dissenter-aligned âjournal of recordâ. For an annual fee,
Godwin became a political journalist. He researched his topics
diligently, listening to parliamentary debates from the gallery and
reporting with scrupulous fairness. His network of contacts grew. Godwin
compiled lists of people he met and people he wanted to meet. Judging by
the names presented and those underlined for emphasis, the philosopher
sought the acquaintance of writers, thinkers and legislators that he
admired rather than those that could advance him â the list he composed
between 1773 and 1794 implies that Godwin was keener to make the
acquaintance of actress Sarah Siddons and playwright Elizabeth Inchbald
than he was the great Edmund Burke. Through the English Review, Godwin
made the acquaintance of Joseph Priestley in early 1785. The Review
usually took a conservative line on religion and politics; called upon
to review Priestleyâs History of the Corruptions of Christianity, Godwin
attempted to criticise from a position of strict impartiality, but wrote
to the author to express his regard for Priestleyâs theological
argument. Priestley wrote back to say that he thought the original
review more than generous, and the two remained in occasional contact
until the scientist left for Philadelphia in 1794.
Godwinâs work on the Register (and another timely nod from Kippis)
blossomed into further work on a newly established Whig journal, the
Political Herald, in mid-1785. Godwin wrote letters for the Herald under
the pseudonym âMuciusâ, after the legendary Roman patriot who thrust his
hand into the fire to defy a king. The letters were an imitation of the
controversial Letters of Junius that had attacked the Grafton government
fifteen years earlier, the identity of the author still debated to this
day. As Mucius, Godwin attacked the Tories ferociously and in anonymous
articles criticised Britainâs exploitation of India. The Heraldâs
editor, Gilbert Stuart, died in August 1786. Godwin wrote to one of the
journalâs patrons, the playwright (and Foxite MP) Richard Brinsley
Sheridan, to request that he might succeed Stuart. Sheridan was
receptive but the discussion dragged on into the next year. Godwin was
offered the job but Sheridan proposed to pay the salary directly from
party funds. Perhaps concerned about the issue of editorial
independence, Godwin turned him down.
The connection with Sheridan brought the would-be editor more contacts,
but it was the publisher Robinson (who hosted parties for his book-trade
friends) who around this time introduced Godwin to another man who would
become a lifelong friend: the journalist, novelist and playwright,
Thomas Holcroft. From meagre beginnings and with little formal
education, Holcroft had toured Britain and Ireland as a travelling
player, and later visited France as a correspondent. Holcroft was
outspoken, forthright in his opinions and blunt to the point of
rudeness. An exacting memory and an appetite for learning made him a
vigorous conversationalist, delighting Godwin who valued sincerity and
intellectual honesty above all things. The two sometimes called on each
daily and could talk politics or religion into the small hours of the
morning. Holcroft was a radical and an atheist, and his arguments led
the already unorthodox Godwin to finally reject Christian faith in 1788
â the influence of others would eventually bring the philosopher back to
the idea of God, but the former minister had turned his back on
organised religion forever.
In these years, Godwin was a jobbing writer. He made a precarious living
from his journalism and pestered Robinson for an advance so that he
could write some âgreat workâ and make his name. He was occasionally a
tutor and in the summer of 1788 he took on his second cousin, the
twelve-year-old Thomas Cooper, as his resident pupil. The boy had
recently lost his father, the family broken up and parcelled out to
friends and relatives. Godwin, then living with Marshall, awkwardly
stepped into a parental role. Godwinâs relationship with Thomas was
fractious â Godwinâs tendency towards pedantry and a young boyâs
resentment at being foisted on a distant relative were an explosive
combination. Yet the tutor admired his pupilâs honesty, as surviving
notes between them show (Cooper vented his anger at Godwin on paper and
Godwin wrote back to commend him). The two remained together until
Cooper was seventeen, when he left to become an actor in Edinburgh. He
toured for some years and found success in the United States. Letters
home to Godwin indicate a lasting respect and affection between them.
Cooper would later describe Godwin as âmuch more than a common father âŠ
he has cherished and instructed meâ.[10] Their relationship provides
important insight into how Godwinâs ideas on youth and learning
developed over time. The philosopherâs notes imply that he attempted to
teach Cooper with the same strictness he had endured, only for his
charge to rebel against it. In his reflections on his experiences with
Cooper, we can see Godwin formulating the position that he would advance
in The Enquirer (1797) â that an open and honest relationship between
tutor and pupil was far more important than the specifics of what might
be taught.
Godwin was a habitual note-taker and recorder of events. He appears to
have written daily and his papers abound with pages of reflective
commentary on his own life and character. It was in 1788 that he began
keeping a regular diary (obviously a text of vast importance to his
biographers), meticulously recording what he read, what he wrote, and
who he met every day for the rest of his life.
Godwinâs diary also marks major events, both in his life and in the
world: 27 June 1789 records, prosaically, âRevolution in Franceâ. The
revolution would change the course of history, but the reaction to it in
Britain would shape the rest of Godwinâs life. In the first impressions
of Godwin and his associates, the revolution was a positive development.
Radicals enthusiastically waved the tricolour and sent messages of
support across the Channel. Many mainstream Whigs drew parallels between
the French Revolution and Britainâs âGloriousâ revolution of 1688 â
despotic France was finally catching up with the modern world, they
said, and would soon be on its way to parliamentary democracy and
constitutional monarchy. Godwin and his friends were swept up on this
great wave of enthusiasm; the philosopher later wrote that his âheart
beat high with great swelling sentiments of Libertyâ and, remembering
the great French thinkers he had imbibed since leaving Hoxton, âcould
not refrain from conceiving sanguine hopes of a revolution of which such
writings had been the precursorsâ.[11]
The Society for Commemorating the Glorious Revolution held an annual
dinner on the fifth of November, the anniversary of William of Orangeâs
landing in England. Godwin was a member, as were Kippis, Robinson and a
raft of other notables that the philosopher knew or admired. The day
before the anniversary in 1789, the society had heard a sermon by the
mathematician, philosopher and Dissenting minister Richard Price that
would become known as A Discourse on the Love of Our Country. Godwin did
not hear the sermon, though he knew Price and attended the dinner the
next day, but Priceâs address became instantly famous. Price claimed
that âcountryâ was not a spot of ground but a community of friends,
bound together by the same constitution of government and laws. To love
oneâs country was not a belief in its superiority, but a desire to do
good for those closest to us. To love oneâs country was to spread truth,
virtue and liberty (the chief blessings of human nature, Price said). A
country ignorant of these things deserved to be enlightened, a
government that did not respect them deserved no loyalty. Price
celebrated the principles of the Revolution Society that hosted him â
religious freedom, the right of the people to choose and dismiss
governments, and the right to resist the abuse of power. Though he
carefully defended the king as a public servant who ruled by the
peopleâs consent, he attacked the obvious inequalities of British
government:
When the representation is partial, a kingdom possesses liberty only
partially; and if extremely partial, it only gives a semblance of
liberty; but if not only extremely partial, but corruptly chosen, and
under corrupt influence after being chosen, it becomes a nuisance, and
produces the worst of all forms of government â a government by
corruption â a government carried on and supported by spreading venality
and profligacy through a kingdom.[12]
Price described the American and French revolutions as equally glorious
with Britainâs own and imagined kingdoms across Europe âstarting from
sleep, breaking their fettersâ and the light of freedom kindling âinto a
blaze that lays despotism in ashesâ.[13]
The sermon rode a wave of popular enthusiasm, yet the establishment
stood firm against the reforming movement in Britain. Attitudes began to
harden. In March 1790, Fox led a parliamentary bill to repeal the Test
Acts only to see it overwhelmingly voted down. When the French Assembly
decreed an end to noble titles, the Revolution Society debated their
abolition in Britain and voted in favour. In November, Burke published
his Reflections on the Revolution in France, a book which quickly proved
a rallying point for conservatives. In the past a supporter of American
independence, the shock of the French revolution had pushed Burke into
an increasingly reactionary position. He was uncertain whether France
was ready for democracy and feared the consequences of reforming
democracy too quickly in Britain. The Reflections are a defence of
tradition and institution as a means of holding together the nation
state. They are also conspicuously an attack on Price and the enthusiasm
of British reformers. Radical writers leapt to defend Price and the
revolution, among them Mary Wollstonecraft (then a member of Priceâs
congregation). A war of conservative and radical pamphlets raged for
months.
Still writing for the New Annual Register, Godwin devoted his main
effort that year to a play â St Dunstan. Verse drama was not Godwinâs
strongest suit and the piece never made it to the stage, but its themes
were clearly of the moment: St Dunstan depicts a politically powerful
church playing on the fears of the mighty to cement its own position.
The first part of Thomas Paineâs Rights of Man was published in March
1791. It was long thought that Godwin and Holcroft had a hand in
steering the book to publication â close reading of Godwinâs diary
suggests otherwise, but the philosopher later included a cryptic
reference to âPaineâs pamphletâ in a list of his early works. Like many
contemporary works Rights of Man begins as a reply to Burke, but it
quickly goes beyond that. Paine argues that human rights are not granted
by law, but are instead natural and universal, going so far as to argue
that the value of laws lies only in their power to protect the rights of
the individual. The author leans heavily on the French Assemblyâs
Declaration of the Rights of Man and the Citizen (1789), but makes no
apology in applying its logic to the British situation. Paine denounces
the monarchy as illegitimate, having usurped power by force of arms in
1066 and established itself on no better principle in the intervening
years. The book outlines a programme of progressive taxation, wider
employment, provision for the elderly, the sick and widowed, and free
education for children. Godwin wrote (perhaps to Paine himself, or
Holcroft â the passage has no address or date) that, âthe seeds of
revolution it contains are so vigorous in their stamina, that nothing
can overpower themâ.[14] The first intended publisher (the usually
redoubtable Joseph Johnson) had blanched at the possible backlash from
releasing such a book into the world and the publication had been
delayed until Paineâs friends found a bookseller willing to put his name
to it. Distributed widely, the book created a stir. The author refused
substantial offers to buy the copyright, turning down a small fortune so
that he could control the workâs fate. Paine later insisted that the
bookâs price be dropped to sixpence â well within the reach of any
reader â to great consternation in government circles. For a time, Paine
was the hero of radical London and the bĂȘte noire of conservatives
everywhere. The reaction began in earnest during the summer. In July,
âChurch and Kingâ rioters in Birmingham sacked a hotel hosting a dinner
celebrating Bastille Day as a prelude to four days of arson and violence
directed at Dissenters and critics of the government â later dubbed âthe
Priestley riotsâ, as Joseph Priestleyâs home was among those destroyed.
The authorities did little to quell the vandalism and the perpetrators
were selective in their attacks, leading to allegations that the affair
had been orchestrated by the government. Copycat violence occurred in
Nottingham, Manchester, Newcastle and Exeter over the next year and a
half.
The governmentâs organised campaign against the radicals was still some
months away and in the summer of 1791 it seemed as if Godwinâs fortunes
were changing for the better. He had proposed a great work on âpolitical
principlesâ to the publisher George Robinson at the end of June and
agreed a contract only a few days before the Birmingham riots. Robinson
agreed to pay Godwinâs expenses while the philosopher devoted himself
entirely to condensing the âbest and most liberal in the science of
politicsâ into a coherent system.[15] Godwin quit the New Annual
Register at the beginning of September and his diary records months of
dedicated reading, beginning with ethics and contemporary politics but
later turning to histories, works on education and literature for
insight. He wrote slowly but methodically, a few pages at a time. He
began drafting that September, but would not finish for another sixteen
months. The political debate raged around him, but Godwinâs work would
be one for the ages rather than a topical contribution. On 21 January
1793, France executed its king. The next day, Godwin put the finishing
touches to his magnum opus. France declared war on Britain a little over
a week later. Great political change was in the air. An Enquiry
Concerning Political Justice was published on 14 February 1793.
Political Justice is both a timeless classic of political philosophy and
a work clearly born in the revolutionary atmosphere of 1790s Europe. It
asks important questions about the right to self-determination and how
opinions or judgments are formed. It further questions fundamental
assumptions about the nature of authority, ownership and the relations
between individuals, in ways that remain challenging to this day. Yet
the arguments of Godwinâs book clearly emerge from a specifically
eighteenth-century context and look out on the future with the
clean-slate optimism that characterised the revolutionary period.
Political Justice is a difficult book to summarise. Not only is it a
long, dense work that encompasses a wide range of topics, Godwin revised
the book substantially only a few years after its initial publication
and revised it again a few years after that. Any discussion of Political
Justice must address the question of whether to privilege the
philosopherâs original argument or his final position â and later works
complicate this further, some offering commentary on (or further
revision to) the ideas articulated in Godwinâs magnum opus. The book
seems to acknowledge this, even in the preface to the first edition,
arguing that âthe best elementary treatises after a certain time are
reduced in their value by the operation of subsequent discoveriesâ, and
highlighting the development of the philosopherâs opinions over the
course of writing. That said, the core principles of Political Justice
remain consistent through each of its three editions and Godwinâs
revisions are more concerned with adding qualification and depth to the
argument than they are with changing anything fundamental in it. There
is one notable exception to this: the philosopherâs acceptance of a
positive role for affection in stimulating and guiding moral action (in
the later editions of Political Justice) that brought him many sneers
from his critics.
The first edition of Political Justice was a sizeable text. Weighing in
at around 800 pages over two large quarto volumes, the book sold at ÂŁ1
16s â not an astronomical price, but one far outside the purchasing
power of most people. This then was a book marketed as a serious
philosophical treatise rather than a political tract (Adam Smithâs
Wealth of Nations retailed at a similar price). Godwin would later claim
that he had avoided censorship (or worse) because the government did not
believe that an expensive book could be dangerous.[16] If the state had
indeed dismissed Godwinâs book, they would in time regret it: Political
Justice sold at least three thousand copies in its first edition and
reached even greater numbers of readers. Many small political societies
sprang up across Britain in the wake of the French Revolution, and a
number of them clubbed together to buy copies of Godwinâs book to read
aloud at meetings and discuss. Radical publishers like Thomas Spence
printed excerpts in their periodicals. At least one Dublin-based
publisher produced a pirate edition. Godwin was quickly celebrated as
the intellectual powerhouse of the radical movement. Looking back from
the distance of 1825, William Hazlitt wrote:
No work in our time gave such a blow to the philosophical mind of the
country as the celebrated Enquiry concerning Political Justice. Tom
Paine was considered for the time as a Tom Fool to him; Paley an old
woman; Edmund Burke a flashy sophist. Truth, moral truth, it was
supposed, had here taken up its abode, and these were the oracles of
thought.[17]
The two volumes of Political Justice provide a division between the
abstract and detailed sides of the philosopherâs argument. The first
volume sets out the theoretical position that Godwin had arrived at,
outlining what the philosopher saw as a handful of irrefutable
intellectual and moral principles about the nature of truth, happiness
and human understanding. The second volume applies those principles to
contemporary society and identifies the institutions and assumptions
that hold people back from moral and intellectual improvement. Godwinâs
vision is optimistic and forward-looking: happiness is good and pain is
evil â the most moral course of action is the one that brings happiness
without causing suffering. Everybody wants to be happy; evil actions are
simply mistakes, caused by incomplete information or insufficient
consideration on the part of the individual. The philosopherâs position
seems naĂŻve, but it allows him to frame moral error as something that
can be corrected through greater critical reasoning â in short, that we
can learn to be better people. In order to do this, Godwin argues, we
need to recognise that our understanding of the world is shaped by the
society we live in. Ignorance, inequality and privation may seem normal
to us but, as sources of unhappiness, they are wrongs that can be put
right if we critically evaluate (and correct) the things that cause
them. We have not yet done so, the philosopher suggests, because too few
people have been willing to look beyond the current system for answers.
The first volume of Political Justice uses a broad definition of both
âpoliticsâ and âjusticeâ. The philosopher implies that our actions are
political insomuch as they impact on the community (most things do).
Justice, Godwin says, encompasses all moral duty. âPolitical justiceâ is
then the operation of ethics within society, our moral responsibilities
towards the people around us. Central to the book is the idea of truth
as an ideal and an absolute. We should always strive to uncover the
truth. We should never practise deception. We can find the correct
answers to moral questions â perfect solutions that bring the greatest
possible happiness while causing no pain â if we are aware of all the
relevant variables and think about them hard enough (though Godwin
accepts that this rarely happens in real life). In this sense the
philosopher conflates truth with moral good. Things that we consider
morally âpureâ (honesty, altruism) are truths to be discovered through
deliberation and investigation. The philosopher writes about justice as
a kind of deduction, the method by which we find the fairest and most
benevolent course of action. It is important to note that, like many of
his Enlightenment predecessors, Godwin rejects the notion of innate
ideas. We are not born altruistic or selfish, but rather learn these
behaviours from the people around us. If this is so, then we all have
the potential to become happy, wise and benevolent people if we are
willing to think for ourselves and act according to our own reasoned
judgment rather than passively accepting consensus. Godwin goes further
than this, insisting that we have a moral duty to act according to our
own best judgment in all circumstances. The philosopher is clear about
the importance of discussing our ideas and issues with other people,
recognising that it can be difficult to uncover the right answers alone,
but he is adamant that we have a responsibility to make decisions as
individuals and not to take other peopleâs opinions as our own. The
search for truth is valuable in itself, we grow as individuals because
we reason and act on moral questions, and we diminish ourselves when we
obey without thinking.
Godwin considers the central principle of ethical decision-making to be
the responsibility of the individual to reflect upon the issue at hand
and determine whatever course of action will bring the most happiness
and the least pain. Moreover, we have a duty to take whatever action
will have the most positive long term effects (thus it is better to help
a stranger in need than it is to indulge a friend who is not â a
long-term relief from suffering is superior to a short-term
gratification). This seems to imply a certain amount of moral
arithmetic: a deliberation over the amount of discomfort we might be
willing to endure for the greater good. Godwin sees this as regrettable
and very difficult to avoid, yet the philosopher is not a relativist.
Political Justice is clear that absolute, unqualified, good exists and
that a thing cannot be considered truly good if it causes some amount of
pain (that is, evil). This distinction may seem academic â as imperfect
beings with imperfect knowledge, the best moral choice apparent to us
may be far from ideal â but because the philosopher believes that such
ideals exist, he is able to argue that we have a moral imperative to
seek out the unequivocally good course of action in any situation and
cannot claim to have done âthe right thingâ unless we are certain that
our choices have not led to evil in any degree. Godwin also considers
the imperative to do the greatest possible good to be one that takes
priority over all other concerns. Indeed, the philosopher argues that we
have no other moral obligations: we owe no debts to those who have
helped us in the past; we have only a duty to help those who need our
help in the future. Equally, the philosopher claims that a promise
should be considered no more than a statement of intent â if I give my
word to do a thing but find another course of action will lead to
greater happiness, it is my duty to do the latter. Godwin even goes so
far as to suggest that the imperative to do the greatest good supersedes
the bonds of love and friendship. True ethical reasoning (i.e. justice)
is impartial and looks only to the overall amount of good generated by
an action. The philosopher illustrates this in an example that came to
be known as âthe famous fire causeâ or âthe FĂ©nelon dilemmaâ. In the
example, Godwin argues that given the choice between saving the life of
the great educational thinker François Fénelon or that of his
chambermaid, we should save the former:
We are not connected with one or two percipient beings, but with a
society, a nation, and in some sense with the whole family of mankind.
Of consequence that life ought to be preferred which will be most
conducive to the general good. In saving the life of Fenelon, suppose at
the moment when he was conceiving the project of his immortal
Telemachus, I should be promoting the benefit of thousands, who have
been cured by the perusal of it of some error, vice and consequent
unhappiness. Nay, my benefit would extend farther than this, for every
individual thus cured has become a better member of society, and has
contributed in his turn to the happiness, the information and
improvement of others.[18]
Godwin goes on to specifically dismiss self-preservation or personal
ties in making such a decision â arguing that even if we ourselves were
the chambermaid, or if the servant were a family member, we should still
choose to protect the greater contribution to the general good. The
philosopherâs position was controversial, and many readers attacked its
apparent severity, but Godwin here does no more than to point out the
logical extent of his own argument. The philosopher himself raises the
objection that we might reasonably prefer to save a person of known
(good) moral character over a stranger whose achievements exist for us
in the abstract. Godwin concedes that this is understandable but is,
âfounded only in the present imperfection of human nature. It may serve
as an apology for my error, but can never turn error into truth. It will
always remain contrary to the strict and inflexible decisions of
justice.â[19] The FĂ©nelon dilemma earned Godwin the reputation of a
clear-sighted but dispassionate philosopher, and Godwinâs language here
implies a kind of stern pragmatism that readers even today find
alienating. Yet, although Godwin here makes a stark moral judgment, his
conclusion implies that he saw the correct choice in the dilemma as an
ideal and an absolute â we can accept that it is right to save the
person who will make the greatest contribution to human happiness, but
how might we accurately (and realistically) judge which person that is?
Godwin accepts that, in the present state of human understanding, we
probably canât. In the philosopherâs thought-experiment we are
omniscient (we know that FĂ©nelon is just imagining his greatest work);
in real life, we must make snap judgments based on the evidence in front
of us. The first edition of Political Justice is optimistic â it
imagines that humanity might one day acquire the knowledge and wisdom
required to make ideal moral choices, but its philosopher recognises
that such a day is a long way off. We will never reach it without the
gradual improvement of critical reason; something that Godwin says
cannot happen unless we develop the habit of exercising our private
judgment.
Godwin says that we have to make decisions for ourselves, but he urges
us to discuss issues with other people before we take action. This is
not a matter of forging a consensus â quite the opposite, since
responsibility for the decision remains with the individual â rather
that other people can help us (as an individual) to think critically. In
discussion with other people we can test ideas, learn from someone
elseâs experience, and benefit from an outsiderâs perspective, but the
philosopher is clear that there is a right and a wrong way to go about
this. Godwin holds that the best way to uncover the truth is through
one-to-one conversation. The philosopher has many reservations about
larger groups: they are often dominated by the loudest or boldest
voices, not the wisest. Equally, public debate encourages sophistry â it
is seen as a contest to be won rather than a means to uncover truth.
Godwin sees private conversation as offering few rewards beyond
intellectual satisfaction, thus both parties can be honest and open
about their ideas, leading to a productive critical discussion.
Godwin puts honesty and openness under the general heading of
âsincerityâ. Godwin argues that sincerity is our duty to always speak
the truth and to openly volunteer what we know in order to help others.
The philosopherâs justification for this is practical: we will advance
faster as a society if everyone shares what they know. Secrets hold us
back â they essentially ration useful knowledge â but Godwin does not
completely dismiss the idea of privacy. Though the philosopher believes
we should live our lives in the open, he also argues that we are
entitled to a sphere of discretion in our activities â I should not live
my life in secret, but neither should others interfere with it.
This duty to act according to our private judgment leads Godwin to
question the fundamental nature of authority. People who have proven
themselves to be good and wise are entitled to our respect and
consideration â we should listen to them, but we should not allow them
to tell us what to do. Nor can they really make us. Unless another
individual literally forces our hand, our actions are our own. To follow
anotherâs instructions is as much a conscious decision as any other,
which means that the âpowerâ of even the most tyrannical authority rests
on the acquiescence of the people it purports to rule. A tyrant might
threaten dire consequences to those who refuse to comply with their
orders, but the success or failure of this hinges on a mass of
individual assessments regarding the costs and benefits of compliance. A
more benign ruler might offer more palatable incentives for cooperation,
but Godwin sees the process as the same: the individual makes a choice
whether or not to acquiesce to authority, and always has (in principle)
the freedom to choose differently.
If this is the case, then what exactly is authority? In a democracy, we
might define authority as the power delegated to leaders by the consent
of the led but Godwin is sceptical that any large group of people can
really be of one mind. âLeadershipâ is essentially problematic: for all
a leader might be armed with the truth, swaying a crowd of strangers is
more likely to hinge upon the groupâs confidence in the speaker than it
is the rightness of his or her argument. In any body of people, each
individual will have constructed their own understanding of the
proposition in question. Some will have devised their own response, a
subset of those may agree wholly with the leader but many will differ on
points of detail. Others may not agree at all but find themselves
unwilling to dispute an apparently popular resolution. A number may have
no feelings about the topic at all, but will support the leaderâs
decisions out of loyalty or respect (and this is not as small-minded as
it may initially seem â we praise leaders who inspire trust and commend
those who show loyalty to people who deserve it). All of this means that
the apparent unanimity of any large group is probably an illusion. Such
a statement seems uncontroversial if we assume the groupâs compliance to
be an act of consent. Regardless of the individualâs exact opinion, by
going along with the consensus they demonstrate a tacit acceptance of
anotherâs judgment in place of their own. Godwin, however, considers a
consensus of this kind to be precarious: if a leader derives their
authority from the people under them, that authority evaporates if those
people choose to withdraw their consent. Furthermore, Godwin says, if we
have a duty to act according to our own reasoned judgment â and
authority cannot actually prevent us from doing so â then a leader that
claims to derive their authority from consent has no right to exert
authority over those who withdraw their consent. The philosopher goes on
to argue that we simply cannot, practically or ethically, delegate our
moral reasoning to someone else. Not only is adopting anotherâs opinions
an evasion of our moral responsibilities, but Godwin considers it
impossible for an individual to actually give up the ability to reason
ethically â we continue to think, and to hold opinions, even if our
behaviour is outwardly obedient. If this is so, Godwin argues, then one
cannot derive power from consent. An individual might grant a leader or
government the power to tell them what to do but, if that power can be
withdrawn the first time the individual disagrees with their orders,
said âpowerâ is little more than the right to make suggestions. The true
power of government lies in its ability to use force.
âI have deeply reflectedâ, suppose, âupon the nature of virtue, and am
convinced that a certain proceeding is incumbent on me. But the hangman,
supported by an act of parliament, assures me I am mistaken.â If I yield
my opinion to his dictum, my action becomes modified, and my character
too.[20]
Governments exist because they have the capacity and willingness to use
force against the individual in order to impose their will. Relatively
benign governments may use this power sparingly but, though Godwin
accepts that it is reasonable to use force to defend oneself and the
community, the philosopher cannot condone the use or threat of violence
to shape the behaviour of individuals. Few of us would sanction
bullying, intimidation, or repression in support of political goals; but
Godwin casts a net wide enough to question the validity of
government-backed law and order. Governments have no power to dictate
right and wrong. Authority, whether derived from a democratic consensus
or the barrel of a gun, cannot make an immoral proposition into a moral
one. âReason is the only legislatorâ, says Godwin: moral truths are also
intellectual truths, and governments are no more able to decree morality
than they are to declare that a triangle has four sides.[21] What
government can do is threaten (and deal out) consequences to those that
stray from the path it has laid out. The philosopher is quick to point
out that government has no moral right to do this. Since Godwin has
dismissed the idea that government derives its authority from the
peoplesâ consent, the philosopher implies that the use of force against
transgressors can never be more than an assertion that might makes
right. We might consider this uncharitable (certainly, few modern
governments see themselves this way) and many would argue that
non-tyrannical governments only offer force as a means to prevent or
punish acts that are injurious to the community â it will always be
necessary to maintain order. Even were we to accept this (and Godwin
does not), it would not lend government any further legitimacy. The
philosopher is clear that one cannot substitute authority for reason;
âbecause I say soâ is an almost universally inadequate justification.
Even in the case where government decrees something that is universally
held to be true (âmurder is wrongâ), it lacks the moral standing by
which to make that claim. The individual must still make a judgment on
the matter for themselves. For Godwin, the interference of government
actually makes the issue more problematic. Consider the hypothetical
example of an accidental killing: I know there are no witnesses to the
accident, so out of fear of being punished for murder, I commit
deliberate crimes (disposing of the body, perjury) to efface my error.
Later, I learn that the dead person was an outlaw with a bounty on their
head, so I produce the body and take credit for the killing. Though the
situation is unrealistic, it demonstrates how the threat of punishment
(or the hope of reward) has the potential to distort the individualâs
ethical reasoning.
We can never entirely ignore the prospect of reward or punishment.
Godwinâs account of this is complex: while it would be highly virtuous
to dismiss potential rewards and punishments as factors in the ethical
process, a far-sighted cost/benefit analysis might conclude that it was
reasonable to take steps to avoid punishment if said punishment would
prevent the individual from doing good in the future (we should stand up
for our principles, but martyrdom is not something to be considered
lightly). In either case the individual has been forced to acknowledge
the power of authority, even if only to discount it. Godwin argues that,
by offering incentives to shape behaviour, authority pollutes our
intentions and corrodes our ability to make moral judgments
independently (based purely on the evidence in front of us). Over time,
because authorityâs effects are ever-present, the individual becomes
used to authorityâs influence on the decision-making process despite its
lack of legitimacy. Individuals who are acculturated within such a
system are likely to be brought up with an understanding of the ability
of institutions or rulers to mete out consequences to a personâs
actions, but may never consider by what right they do so. The presence
and influence of authority become normal, and with them (Godwin says)
the habits of obedience.
Godwin argues forcefully that societies develop in response to the rules
and expectations that governments place on them. A state that mandates
military service will (over a few generations) create a martial
tradition. A state that restricts the freedom of the press signals to
the people that they should be cautious in their public statements. We
might make the counter-argument that governments are equally shaped by
the people â that laws and institutions grow out of societyâs needs and
wants â but this assumes a more participatory government than the
philosopher (who lived most of his life in a Britain where fewer than 5%
of the population could vote) was willing to credit. For Godwin a
government was as likely to be instituted through accident or force, as
it was by popular will. The philosopher thus begins volume two of
Political Justice with an analysis of what he sees as the main types of
government, and the cultures they create around themselves.
Godwin divides governments into three categories: monarchies,
aristocracies and democracies. Clearly we can see that many governments
include aspects of more than one type, so we must infer that each
category is meant to define the principal element of that polity. In
each case, the philosopher identifies the contradictions inherent to
each approach and the means by which each form of government works
around its flaws to maintain the status quo.
Monarchy is, in theory, the rule of one individual with absolute power,
but is in practice dependent on ministers to carry out the rulerâs
decrees. As observed in volume one, a lone individual lacks the capacity
to enforce their will beyond the personal level. In volume two the
philosopher extends this to the mechanics of leading a nation-state: how
could even the wisest and most benevolent monarch understand the wants
and needs of millions? Even with the best will in the world, a king or
queen cannot investigate the problems of every subject in sufficient
depth to be able to effectively help them. In practice, the monarch must
rely on ministers to tell them the kingdomâs problems and can only
respond to them in what Godwin sees as arbitrary ways (we see in
Political Justice an increasing scepticism about the value of âmacroâ
solutions compared with a detailed assessment of the specific case). The
health of the nation is dependent not only on the virtues of the
monarch, but on the probity of their subordinates. This, Godwin says,
creates its own problems: in a system that invests final authority in a
single person, the obvious route to success is to curry favour with that
person. Such a system encourages ministers to attend to the monarchâs
needs ahead of those of the state and encourages the monarch to reward
flatterers before more honest public servants. As ministers control the
monarchâs view of the world, it would require an unusually clear-sighted
ruler to appoint advisors who could be relied upon to tell them the
truth about the world rather than a mutually agreeable version of it.
The system gives no incentive for ministers to do otherwise, and so the
court âbubbleâ becomes an intricate game of controlling access to the
monarch while mediating the monarchâs engagement with the kingdom. The
philosopher sees this system as self-perpetuating: those ministers that
rise to the top are those who are best at playing the game, and they in
turn promote subordinates with the same qualities. The only way for
monarchs to appoint honest ministers is to go outside the
monarchical-ministerial system entirely (assuming that from their
carefully managed perspective they know the option exists) but such
outsiders must neutralise, accommodate, or negotiate an entrenched
network of corruption and sycophancy in order to serve the public good.
Godwin discusses the monarchâs insulation from society at some length,
drawing on historical and topical examples to illustrate how the culture
that surrounds monarchy renders anyone groomed for the throne into the
worst possible candidate. Those who would seek to educate a future
monarch work in the knowledge that their pupil will one day hold the
power of life and death over them. Like royal ministers, royal tutors
are better off giving in to their chargesâ wants rather than addressing
their chargesâ needs. The spoilt pupil grows into a ruler who has never
known failure, never known adversity, and never been told ânoâ. They
have no basis on which they can relate to their subjects and no
experience of the world beyond the court. The philosopher argues,
however, that the trappings of monarchy facilitate its survival. Keeping
the monarchy separate from the people helps to disguise the machinery of
government, presenting the illusion that the fate of the nation rests on
the shoulders of one person. The ceremony and grandeur of the position
lend a further impression of authority â titles claim that the
instruments of state derive their power from the office of the monarch
(realistically, the positions are the reverse), while pageantry is
employed to âdazzle our sense and mislead our judgmentâ.[22] We are
encouraged to believe that one person can manage a nation, and Godwin
argues that this basic falsehood underwrites all others. Deep down we
know that monarchs are people like anyone else and, in indulging the
conceit that one person can (and should) rule millions, we dignify every
other form of dishonesty running through society. Further to this,
Godwin claims that monarchyâs culture of patronage and wealth trickles
down to pollute every level of the community. If power is transferred
through favour and authority demonstrated by ostentation, then
everything (conspicuously) has its price. The philosopher grimly quotes
Montesquieuâs adage that âwe must not expect under a monarchy to find
the people virtuousâ.[23]
Godwin dismisses various approaches to reforming monarchical government:
in what the philosopher calls âlimitedâ (implicitly, constitutional)
monarchy, the ruler is even more wedded to their ministers because they
have less power to replace them. Godwin argues that if a monarch is to
be part of a constitutional settlement, they must be accountable or else
a powerless figurehead (and the latter is dangerous because impotence
encourages either rebellion or depravity). Elective monarchy, Godwin
says, is known to be a source of political strife; the election of a
president for life has many similarities. Godwin questions the need for
a leader with executive powers at all. If a matter concerns the whole
community, the whole community deserves a say on it. If an executive is
necessary it should not have the ability to make arbitrary rulings. In
any case, the philosopher seems to regard any attempt to mitigate the
problems of monarchy as little more than an exercise in rebranding â
monarchy is synonymous with corruption and tyranny.
Aristocratic government is described by Godwin as the appointment of a
class of wise and benevolent leaders to act as moral shepherds to the
rest of community. This class is exempted from everyday work in order to
have the time to study moral questions on behalf of others, and
membership is often passed down from generation to generation. Though he
is even-handed in his explanation of aristocratic government as a model,
Godwin is scathing about the idea of hereditary distinction: âno
principle can present a deeper insult upon reason and justiceâ.[24] The
philosopher regards the idea of choosing leaders based on their ancestry
as absurd, but observes that a hereditary leadership caste is even more
problematic. If we allow the conceit that a leadership caste must have
more free time to facilitate contemplation and deliberation (Godwin does
not â arguing that a fair society would make that time available to all)
then we must consider what effect this would have on those who grow up
part of it. Godwin argues that a class that have led sheltered lives are
ill-equipped to provide moral leadership because they have little
opportunity to gain the life experience needed to be effective in that
role â we might reasonably ask if those who had never known normal work
would understand the moral dilemmas faced by those who experienced it
every day. The philosopher goes further, suggesting that a long-term
culture of ease encourages the accumulation of luxury and the associated
ability to dispense patronage:
Hence it appears, that to elect men to the rank of nobility is to elect
them to a post of moral danger and a means of depravity; but that to
constitute them hereditarily noble is to preclude them, bating a few
extraordinary accidents, from all the causes that generate ability and
virtue.[25]
Aristocracy is, in Godwinâs view, both ineffective and unjust.
Distinctions of class are arbitrary, and therefore wrong. The only
honours we should bestow are those we award for an individualâs own
merits, chiefly their contribution to the moral health of their
community. In an aristocratic system, the many support the few in return
for leadership that the system itself undermines. Godwin argues that the
dissolution of aristocracy is to everyoneâs benefit â those at the
bottom are freed from injustice, while those at the top are freed from
an enforced idleness (in some countries the nobility were barred from
many professions) that works to the detriment of their character.
Godwin defines democracy as a system of government that requires only
one regulating principle: the acknowledgment that all men are equal. In
a democracy, every individualâs voice should carry equal weight. Every
individual shares the same moral duty to the people around them, and
should hold the same stake in the fortunes of the community. The
philosopher is quick to identify the problems that arise from this.
While Godwin maintains that everyone has the same capacity for reason,
he accepts that reason is a faculty that is developed through experience
and reflection. If this is the case, then it is likely that the wiser
members of any given community will be outnumbered by the unwise. A
democratic society then is likely to be inconsistent in its decisions,
easily swayed by the unscrupulous, and may struggle to recognise ideas
of merit when they are proposed â all because the majority (who are
unused to thinking critically about political questions) have the power
to overrule an enlightened minority.
Yet Godwin argues that these problems are not inevitable and, even with
these flaws, democracy would be preferable to both monarchy and
aristocracy. Monarchy and aristocracy are forms of government predicated
on the assumption that the people are not fit to govern themselves;
before Godwin authoritarian thinkers from Hobbes to Burke had claimed
that, without leaders, society would tear itself apart. Godwin, in
contrast, counsels us not to assume that the character of the people in
a democracy would be the same as under other regimes â other modes of
government undermine the virtue and understanding of the populace (they
legitimise dishonesty and repress dissent) while democracy enshrines the
value of every voice and places individual reason above authority and
tradition. The philosopher asserts that human beings, if allowed to
develop the habits of critical reason, will almost certainly improve
morally and intellectually. Godwin has reservations about elections and
representation, so we must infer that what the philosopher describes
here are the benefits of direct democracy (that is, where the people
vote on every decision that affects the community) rather than a
panegyric to any existing method of government. Indeed, while Godwin
offers the possibility that representative democracy might actually
provide the benefits claimed of aristocracy â the superintendence of the
people by a group of wiser heads â any system that expects the
individual to delegate the use of their judgment is at odds with some of
the fundamental principles of Godwinâs philosophy.
For Godwin, a true democracy is an equal society. A democratic
government that grants more power to some than others is, the
philosopher says, a democracy in name only. Elected representatives â if
they are in fact necessary â should be regarded as no more than the
deputies of those who elected them. Godwin tackles the idea of economic
inequality in a later part of the book but notes in his discussion of
democracy that an equal society is one where all have access to the same
level of subsistence. For this reason, the philosopher asserts, a true
democracy would never fight wars for gain â a nation where everyone has
âenoughâ has no need to deprive its neighbours of territory or
resources. A democratic society may still need to protect itself from
undemocratic neighbours and thus, in-keeping with Godwinâs ideas on
common moral duties, every citizen has a responsibility to stand in
defence of the community. The philosopher rejects the need for a
standing army. Separating the soldier and the citizen is to the
detriment of society â it signals that to fight (and kill) is an
acceptable profession, but one that we must keep at armâs length in a
branch of the community with its own rules and expectations (i.e.
military discipline). In delegating responsibility for its own security,
the community invites soldiers to see themselves as the communityâs
protectors. Godwin considers such a relationship unhealthy â there are
obvious parallels with the principles of aristocracy, but the
philosopher here is considerably more blunt:
[the soldier] is cut off from the rest of the community, and has
sentiments and a rule of judgment peculiar to himself. He considers his
countrymen as indebted to him for their security; and, by an unavoidable
transition of reasoning, believes that in a double sense they are at his
mercy.[26]
The philosopher claims that a true nation-in-arms would be just as
effective as a professional military. Mobilised citizens, who understand
what they are fighting for and know that their cause is just, will
out-fight enemies who lack the same confidence and motivation (and
Godwin seems certain that only a democracy could really instil such
qualities). The philosopher sees military training as a very simple
matter, and claims that a democracy â since it will only ever need to
fight defensively â could very quickly drill its army to the same
standard as the invaders âon the jobâ. Godwin dismisses generalship as
quackery, asserting that a sufficiently educated and enquiring mind is
all that is needed to excel as a military leader. Even if a lack of
experienced generals were a disadvantage in war, Godwin says, it would
be a small price to pay for the nation to be unencumbered with a
military establishment in peacetime. If democracies are worse at
fighting wars, the philosopher says, it is a point in their favour.
Godwin has deep reservations about the idea of offensive military
operations, arguing that there can be no justification for a democracy
to march outside its own borders except to render assistance to (Godwin
does not say âliberateâ) oppressed neighbours. Democracyâs best weapon
against injustice is the printing press; the philosopher imagines
invading armies worn down and sprawling empires destabilised by
courageous (and truthful) publishing. Coming at the end of a century
where Britain had used military and naval aggression to carve out a
global empire and curb the economic expansion of its rivals, the
implications of the philosopherâs argument were radical. Put simply,
Godwin sees no justification for one community to interfere with the
affairs of another, unless for humanitarian reasons.
Godwin is critical of permanent government institutions, up to and
including parliaments or national assemblies. Though he accepts that
communities will sometimes need a forum for public deliberation, regular
meetings allow factions and cults of personality to develop â
encouraging individuals to cast their votes according to their loyalty
rather than their judgment. Godwin implies that it might be better if
assemblies were only called when they have something crucial to debate,
but it is the idea of a national assembly itself that leads the
philosopher to question the intellectual and moral basis of democratic
government itself.
Godwin regards voting as essentially problematic. Putting something to a
vote usually signals the end of debate. The philosopher considers the
purpose of discussion to be a collaborative search for truth â voting
turns discussion into a competition that can be won, diminishing the
importance of honesty and accuracy in favour of passion and rhetorical
skill. Godwin â perhaps naively â believes that the truth will always
eventually overcome persuasive flair, if the arguments are subjected to
enough scrutiny. He suggests that debates should take place in multiple
rounds, so as to allow time for reflection, and should continue until
the truth is found. Votes commit the community to a decision based on
the popularity of a measure rather than its fairness or necessity, thus
encouraging sophistry and dishonesty. Godwinâs ideal assembly seems to
be little more than a talking shop, since the philosopher resists the
most straightforward method by which the community might make decisions
final. What gradually emerges from this is that Godwin is fundamentally
uneasy with the principle of majority rule.
It seems as if it would be rare for matters put before a national
assembly to be resolved with unanimous agreement, but for Godwin this
does seem to be the only fair place for discussion to end. If a vote is
considered as the resolution of a matter, and does not result in
unanimous agreement, what is required of the minority party? In most
democratic systems the âlosingâ side of a vote is required to abide by
the majority decision, at least until the matter can be brought before
the house again. Godwin finds this unconscionable. Majority rule is not
unity and voting does not determine truth. The philosopher cannot see
any good reason why individuals who have voted against a measure should
be obliged to carry it out. The dilemma is most easily framed as a
matter of conscience: if an individual honestly believes a measure to be
harmful or immoral then we would not be surprised to see them refuse to
participate on ethical grounds. Godwinâs insistence on the sanctity of
individual judgment takes this one step further. If the intellectual and
moral development of community requires that the individual always be
allowed to exercise their private judgment, then the community must
respect the objections of any individual on any issue. A government that
expects the individual to conform against the dictates of their own
judgment actually holds the community back, because a community that
substitutes popular authority for the individualâs critical reason
teaches its citizens that their perception of truth is secondary to the
will of the majority. The latter point seems uncontroversial in the
context of genuine consensus. If (almost) everyone agrees that a measure
is right, it may be that it has been explored sufficiently and found to
be the best solution; the minority opinion may be inefficient or even
harmful. Godwin, however, cannot imagine an erroneous minority opinion
persisting for very long. Truth is, in the long term, irresistible â if
a thing can be shown to be right, then it will eventually win unanimous
agreement if the community is only patient (and, taking the long view,
there will be occasions when the minority position is the correct one â
time will allow it to eventually convince everyone else). A community
that insists that the majority is always right inhibits the intellectual
enquiries of its people by discouraging deviation from the norm:
In numerous assemblies a thousand motives influence our judgments,
independently of reason and evidence. Every man looks forward to the
effects which the opinions he avows will produce on his success. Every
man connects himself with some sect or party. The activity of his
thought is shackled at every turn by the fear that his associates may
disclaim him.[27]
A society that insists that its consensus is truth, and is willing to
overrule individual judgment in support of that, creates a culture of
intellectual timidity that resists moral and intellectual innovation.
For a conservative government this is clearly desirable, but Godwin
considers it an inevitable consequence of all political systems that
prevent the individual from carrying out their duty to think and act
independently. This puts the philosopher at odds with the rule of law,
since even democratic legislation constitutes the imposition of
consensus-based ethical guidelines intended to regulate behaviour.
Godwin argues that if a law is not morally self-evident (outlawing a
thing that is discernibly wrong) then breaking it is no crime. The
influence of authority cannot make an action more or less wrong, so laws
are at best descriptions of moral conduct (i.e. something we could have
worked out on our own) and at worst arbitrary or immoral restrictions on
individual freedom. The philosopher dryly observes that if laws were an
effective means of making people more moral, they would have done it by
now.
We might reasonably ask what the community should do if an individualâs
independent actions bring harm to those around them. We can infer from
the way Godwin discusses wrongdoing that he imagines that it would be an
unusual occurrence in communities that respected private judgment in the
way that he outlines â the philosopher is sure that, if given the
freedom to make every decision for themselves, people would mostly
choose to live at peace with their neighbours. Godwin argues that if we
take away external pressures on the individual that constrain their
choices, what remains are some basic calculations about how to be happy.
In Godwinâs view, living peacefully and altruistically is self-evidently
a better strategy than violence and theft. Setting aside the (quite
reasonable) position that cooperation is a happier, more sustainable,
way to live than predation; Godwin takes a different route. The
self-interest hypothesis claims that all actions can be traced back to
the individualâs (perhaps unconscious) self-love. Godwin notes that this
hypothesis justifies apparently altruistic acts through relatively
complex or abstract logic (Bernard de Mandeville, the eighteenth
centuryâs best-known theorist of self-interest, claimed that bravery was
merely a cover for oneâs shame at the idea of being thought a coward by
observers). If such complicated reasons can be used to explain
selfishness, Godwin says, then there is no reason why an individual left
to their own devices should not reason themselves into benevolent acts
instead. The ability to sympathise with others is, the philosopher
argues, one of the most basic elements of human understanding. We know
that, to be happy, we need the people around us to be happy too. If we
help others to be happy, we will be happy ourselves and others will
support our happiness in return. With sufficient reasoning, Godwin
argues, the individual will always arrive at the conclusion that the
altruistic course of action is the best one. According to this logic,
wrongdoing â anything that causes a non-trivial amount of unhappiness â
is the result of faulty reasoning, or reasoning based on inaccurate
information.
People make mistakes, and Godwin argues that it is better to have a
supportive environment to help people learn from them than it is for the
community to take retribution. The philosopher sees a need for juries to
investigate and admonish wrongdoers, but sees little point in punishing
an individual in the present for an error they made in the past. Causing
someone pain because they caused others pain will not undo what has
happened, nor is it likely to prevent it from happening again. Godwin
dismisses the idea of punishment as a deterrent â eighteenth-century
Britain dealt out harsh punishments for even minor crimes, to little
effect â and sees no role for it in reforming the individual. The
philosopher accepts that the community will sometimes need to restrain
people who are a danger to others (or themselves) but argues that
imprisoning someone to prevent them from committing crimes in the future
constitutes âpunishment upon suspicionâ â the first step on the road
towards tyranny.[28] Far better, Godwin says, to prevent crimes through
community vigilance than to lock people up for things they havenât done.
Punishment and restraint are both forms of coercion, which the
philosopher denounces in all its forms.
Let us reflect for a moment upon the species of argument, if argument it
is to be called, that coercion employs. It avers to its victim that he
must necessarily be in the wrong, because I am more vigorous and more
cunning than he. Will vigour and cunning be always on the side of truth?
⊠The thief that by main force surmounts the strength of his pursuers,
or by stratagem and ingenuity escapes from their toils, so far as this
argument is valid, proves the justice of his cause. Who can refrain from
indignation when he sees justice thus miserably prostituted?[29]
As Godwin sees it, forcing people into conformity is counterproductive.
Obedience is not belief; coercion has no power to convince someone of
the truth of a proposition, only the power to punish them if they are
seen to disagree. The philosopherâs arguments against the utility of
this have already been discussed. Fundamentally the philosopher believes
that authority has no power to reform, only to corrupt. If something is
true it can stand on its own merits; coercion can only alienate the mind
from truth, in order to put something in its place. There are situations
where coercion may be necessary to prevent a greater evil, but Godwin
considers such circumstances to be few and far between: resisting
violence, restraining someone in the midst of a crime, or defending the
community from an invader who promises to bring injustice to the
individual and their neighbours. Practicalities aside, the philosopher
insists that coercion should only ever be a temporary expedient, and an
individual responsibility. The alternative sets (for Godwin) a dangerous
precedent. Were we to look on coercion as a duty of the community, it
would impart a certain degree of legitimacy to the idea of using
coercion against the individual in order to serve the communityâs goals
â a position antithetical to the philosopherâs belief in the importance
of private judgment.
In any case, Godwin holds that an equal society would have little need
for coercion. What is implicit throughout the second volume of Political
Justice is that inequality in society persists because political
authority is willing and able to use coercive force to defend it â
central to this is the division of property. Laws of property assert and
protect the individualâs right to hold and distribute resources as they
see fit, assuming they have laid claim to them without breaking the law
themselves. We might expect Godwin to endorse this, since it seems to
defend the exercise of private judgment, but the philosopher considers
the accumulation of wealth to be morally wrong:
If justice have any meaning, nothing can be more iniquitous, than for
one man to possess superfluities, while there is a human being in
existence that is not adequately supplied with these.
Justice does not stop here. Every man is entitled, so far as the general
stock will suffice, not only to the means of being, but of well being.
It is unjust, if one man labour to the destruction of his health or his
life, that another man may abound in luxuries. It is unjust, if one man
be deprived of leisure to cultivate his rational powers, while another
man contributes not a single effort to add to the common stock.[30]
We cannot ethically claim more resources than we can reasonably use,
regardless of how hard we might have worked for them. Neither does our
own success allow us to assert the right to distribute resources to
others in any greater or lesser quantity than they need (we should
support those who cannot support themselves, but we have no right to
make ourselves into patrons). We could reasonably say that we have a
duty to use our private judgment in distributing what resources we have
acquired, but equally duty denies us the right to take more than we need
or give more than is needed. A greater share of resources converts
quickly into economic power â either through an unequal subdivision of
resources (favouring allies over others), or through the hoarding of
private luxuries. Godwin argues that the desire for these things stems
from our need to be admired and respected by others â we seek an obvious
symbol of our worth to display for strangers, or the gratitude of our
clients for having favoured them over others. In a society that has no
reason to covet wealth (i.e. one where no-one needs it to purchase basic
comforts, or to participate in community decisions) then the individual
can satisfy their desire for esteem through more virtuous pursuits.
Without a constant need to acquire, individuals will only need to work
as much as is needed to for subsistence. The burden of necessary jobs
like food production will be significantly lessened thanks to an
abundance of unengaged labour, as many specialist or mercantile
professions are no longer required. The rest of oneâs time can be spent
helping others, or improving oneself.
What Godwin advocates is the abolition of almost all forms of property.
We have as much right to an object as we have need for it:
What would denominate any thing my property? The fact, that it was
necessary to my welfare. My right would be coeval with the existence of
that necessity. The word property would probably remain; its
signification only would be modified. The mistake does not so properly
lie in the idea itself, as in the source from which it is traced. What I
have, if it be necessary for my use, is truly mine; what I have, though
the fruit of my own industry, if unnecessary, it is an usurpation for me
to retain.[31]
Interestingly, the author extends this logic to our relationships with
others. We cannot lay claim to another person, no matter how much we
like them, and we should not allow ourselves to become attached to other
people to any greater extent than they merit. The philosopher accepts
that we are all social creatures, but argues that we should never allow
ourselves to subsume our individual identity into concepts like family
or community (or expect others to do so either). My blood relatives are
not âmyâ family, and I am not obliged to favour them over others because
of any notion of shared identity. Godwin reserves particular ire for the
institution of marriage, which he seems to consider the worst offender
in this regard:
marriage is an affair of property, and the worst of all properties. So
long as two human beings are forbidden by positive institution to follow
the dictates of their own mind, prejudice is alive and vigorous. So long
as I seek to engross one woman to myself, and to prohibit my neighbour
from proving his superior desert and reaping the fruits of it, I am
guilty of the most odious of all monopolies.[32]
The philosopherâs words held (for eighteenth-century readers) literal
truth. The principle of coverture recognised husband and wife as a
single legal entity, with the wifeâs rights suspended for the duration
of the marriage. A married woman could not own her own property, or sign
agreements in her own name; divorce required a private act of
parliament. Godwin was certainly aware of this but, in-keeping with the
overall tone of Political Justice, chooses to criticise marriage on a
theoretical level.[33] The philosopher questions the ethical basis of
monogamy: the only ethical grounds on which to establish a preference
for one person over others is our perception of that personâs greater
merit â if that is the case, then what right do we have to deny the rest
of the world the friendship of our favourite?
The supposition that I must have a companion for life, is the result of
a complication of vices. It is the dictate of cowardice, and not of
fortitude. It flows from the desire of being loved and esteemed for
something that is not desert.[34]
Godwin, perhaps still a Dissenting minister at heart, dismisses sex as
âa very trivial objectâ and denies any meaningful link between sex and
âthe purest affectionâ.[35] In a society that has moved beyond
monopolising relationships, people will continue to procreate (because
it is necessary for the continuation for the species) but children will
be raised and educated by those best-suited to doing so (rather than
society assuming it to be the duty of biological parents). The
philosopher finds it hard to believe that people would cohabit on a
permanent basis, were we to do away with the laws and expectations that
accompany the current system of property. Godwin argues that the
tensions of living together will eventually make independent-minded
people unhappy, implicitly criticising the everyday compromises that we
make when living together (which may often clash with the philosopherâs
proposed duties to private judgment and impartiality).
Godwin regards all cooperation as a series of compromises. Working in
concert with a neighbour requires us to organise our time to the
convenience of both, and in doing so we curtail our own freedom of
action. The philosopher calls this an evil, though for Godwin this
simply means that it is a factor with only negative consequences (there
is no upside to being forced to plan around someone else, though another
personâs aid may be good in itself). The philosopherâs greatest concern
regards the individual compromising their independence of mind: it is
right for us to listen to others and absorb their ideas (through
conversation, reading) but we should not submit to anotherâs direction.
Even if our collaborator can show that their argument is correct in
every way, we must assimilate the proof ourselves and agree rather than
simply conceding to our partnerâs greater wisdom. Tellingly, Godwin
describes the practice of persuading someone to abandon negative
behaviours as a form of punishment.
Godwin imagines a future where advances in technology and learning allow
the individual to accomplish almost any practical task alone, but he
accepts that cooperation remains necessary until that becomes the norm.
Notably, Godwin does not see the community of the future as a primarily
cooperative society â he dismisses the needs for resources to be held in
common, since it is obvious to anyone possessed of sound judgment that
they should simply give away their surplus to anyone in need (and fairly
exchange goods or services for the same in kind). The philosopher seems
to imagine that every individual will eventually become self-reliant.
Godwin speculates that in the future everyone will be fed through only a
small individual investment of time and effort, since the end of
commerce and specialist employment will allow everyone to take part in
food production (thus saving thousands of work-hours). Since the
philosopher is critical of cooperation, however, we must infer that he
foresees this production being an individual activity. This perhaps
provides a glimpse of the future Godwin imagined: a society of peaceful,
independent farmers that respect wisdom but not authority. It bears a
passing resemblance to the Dissenting community of the philosopherâs
East Anglian childhood, albeit in an idealised form, but Godwinâs vision
does not look back to any kind of golden age â indeed, the philosopher
is highly invested in the idea of progress, and speculates that a
society committed to moral and intellectual improvement will one day
conquer disease and old age (interestingly, Godwin sees ageing as a
psychological problem as much as a physical one; greater happiness and
wisdom will allow us to live longer). Humanity will spread out, the
philosopher suggests, since much of the world remains uncultivated there
will be room for everyone.[36] Greater longevity will obviously lead to
an increase in population, but Godwin is grandly optimistic: perhaps
without unhappiness, disease, or privation, humanity might live forever.
Debate raged in the philosopherâs lifetime as to what âlifeâ was â vital
energy powering the body, consciousness, or the soul (to list only three
common positions) â and Godwin thoughtfully quotes Benjamin Franklinâs
speculation that mind might one day become omnipotent over matter.
Without any need to procreate, population would settle at a manageable
level. More importantly, existing boundaries on human improvement would
evaporate. Death would never again deprive us of an individualâs wisdom,
nor would each successive generation need to be brought âup to speedâ
before they could develop their own ideas. In short, the philosopher
imagines a form of intelligence explosion similar to that prophesied by
artificial intelligence evangelists centuries later.
The bookâs almost rapturous conclusion was in step with the radical
culture of the time. In France, the abolition of religion in favour of
reason was seriously discussed and attempts were made to de-Christianise
public buildings and dispense with the religious trappings of state
business. Across Europe, revolution was discussed in hushed tones as
ordinary people waited to see how events would play out and monarchs
raised armies to stamp out the French fire before it could spread.
Godwin saw that British society needed drastic reform, though he
remained a sceptic of revolutionary action. Most of his peers at the
time were in favour of change, but few seriously advocated violence.
Godwin maintained that the objective should be to change peopleâs minds,
not to force change upon them. He believed that it was necessary to show
people the problems that existed outside their experience â he resolved
to do this through fiction. He sat down to write his next novel only six
weeks after seeing Political Justice to the press. He called it Things
as They Are.
The government had begun to crack down on radical sentiments even before
the declaration of war against France, issuing a royal proclamation
against seditious writing in May 1792. Paine was tried in absentia on 11
December (he had fled to France months earlier). The prosecution claimed
that, in disseminating the Rights of Man so widely, Paine had
overstepped the boundaries of normal political debate â the implication
being that to address the general public (most of whom could not vote)
on political matters constituted an attempt to incite insurrection.
Thomas Erskine, speaking for the defence, argued that regardless of
whether or not one agreed with Paine, the exercise of free speech was
essential to the political health of the nation. The jury found Paine
guilty before they had even heard the prosecutionâs rebuttal. In the
late summer of 1793, an Edinburgh court sentenced two men (the lawyer
Thomas Muir and a minister, Thomas Palmer) to transportation for
campaigning on behalf of universal suffrage. The convicts were taken by
sea to London at the end of the year, where they were held on prison
hulks until they could be shipped to Australia. Godwin visited them
three times while they were at Woolwich, and wrote a letter complaining
about their treatment (under the pseudonym âValeriusâ) to the Morning
Chronicle. In December, government spies in Edinburgh arranged the
arrest of delegates to a convention on parliamentary reform, among them
Godwinâs friend Joseph Gerrald. They too were convicted and sentenced to
transportation. In May 1794, the government arrested leading members of
two reformist political groups (the Society for Constitutional
Information and the London Corresponding Society) on charges of high
treason. Among those charged was another of Godwinâs friends, the writer
and orator John Thelwall, as well as the veteran campaigner John Horne
Tooke. On 17 May, parliament voted to suspend Habeas Corpus, allowing
the authorities to make further arrests without charge.
Things as They Are; or The Adventures of Caleb Williams was completed in
the first week of the arrests. In the context of Paineâs prosecution,
the preface was confrontational:
What is now presented to the public is no refined and abstract
speculation; it is a study and delineation of things passing in the
moral world. It is but of late that the inestimable importance of
political principles has been adequately apprehended. It is now known to
philosophers that the spirit and character of the government intrudes
itself into every rank of society. But this is a truth highly worthy to
be communicated to persons whom books of philosophy and science are
never likely to reach. Accordingly it was proposed in the invention of
the following work, to comprehend, as far as the progressive nature of a
single story would allow, a general review of the modes of domestic and
unrecorded despotism, by which man becomes the destroyer of man.[37]
The publisher (B. Crosby) panicked, perhaps when the scale of the
treason arrests became clear, and the book was issued without a preface
at the end of May. Many readers have inferred from Godwinâs preface that
the novel was intended to spread the ideas of Political Justice to the
novel-reading public (âa truth highly worthy to be communicatedâ), but
this reading fails to acknowledge the depth of Caleb Williams as a
literary work. The novel is unequivocally a classic of Romantic-era
literature. As well as being one of the first great psychological
narratives â the story is told in the first person, and the mental
states of both protagonist and antagonist are crucial to the story â the
novel combines mystery, tragedy and political argument with outstanding
unity. Aspects of the novel are obviously inspired by conclusions Godwin
arrived at in writing his treatise: as the preface suggests, the work
explores the application of authority in everyday life (by employers,
within families) and its abuse; the novelâs climax exemplifies the
philosopherâs conviction that truth is always ultimately triumphant. The
relationship between the ideas of Political Justice and the ideas of
Caleb Williams is, however, far more complicated than a literal reading
of the preface might suggest.
The novel is a story of detection and pursuit. Caleb is a servant,
working as a librarian and secretary for the aristocratic Falkland, who
uncovers a dark secret from his employerâs past. Though Caleb makes no
attempt to expose him, Falkland frames Caleb for a crime to destroy his
credibility. Caleb is imprisoned but makes a daring escape. Falkland
employs a man to track Caleb down but, rather than attempt to recapture
him, Calebâs pursuer is tasked with ensuring that his quarry is unable
to flee the country but unable to settle anywhere within it â
distributing âpapersâ (implicitly a chapbook, the usual format of
popular âtrue crimeâ stories in the period) that depict him as a
notorious housebreaker and master of deception. Falkland offers Caleb
his freedom if he will sign a document exonerating his persecutor of his
secret crime, but Caleb refuses to perjure himself. Caleb eventually
forces a public confrontation and emerges victorious, yet is forever
haunted by Falklandâs destruction.
Many of the novelâs episodes qualify or question arguments found in
Political Justice. Falkland is widely held to be a wise and benevolent
landowner (the protagonist continues to respect him even after suffering
at his hands), and the case he makes in trying to persuade Caleb is that
his life is ultimately more valuable than that of his servant â society
makes a net gain if Caleb sacrifices his own honour to protect
Falklandâs. Godwin essentially complicates the FĂ©nelon dilemma by
bringing it into conflict with an equally important principle. Most
notably, the optimism of Political Justice is undermined by the novelâs
sense that truth does not necessarily bring happiness. Calebâs victory
is hollow because truth has destroyed a noble but misguided man. Caleb
Williamsâs greatest strength as a political novel is that it rarely
lectures. There are moments of polemic when it attacks obvious
injustice, but the text offers more questions than answers. Most
challenging is the question of the novelâs almost miraculous resolution.
Godwinâs original ending allowed tyranny to (believably) reassert
itself, and left Caleb mad and dying in a prison cell. The published
ending has stronger dramatic logic â it provides a satisfying conclusion
to Falklandâs character arc â but is altogether less realistic. The
novelâs original title, Things as They Are, encourages us to question
the believability of its conclusion. Should it be read as a statement
about the potential for change (âthings as they could beâ), or does it
prompt us to consider why the ending appears unrealistic despite being
morally sound? Godwin does not dictate an interpretation.
The novel was a resounding success, reviewers praised its power even
when they could not bring themselves to approve of its message. The size
of the initial print run is unknown, though as the work of a proven
author, it was probably respectable. Whatever the size, it sold quickly,
as Godwin was able to negotiate for a revised second edition (with a
braver publisher, who restored the preface) a year later.[38] The
philosopherâs fame increased further. The government had not yet turned
to arresting novelists, but Godwin began looking over his shoulder. He
declined to visit Thelwall in prison for fear of being arrested as an
associate, but sent him an (unsigned) letter of advice which the
hot-tempered Thelwall did not take well. The full indictment of those
arrested was published in October, with new names added to the list.
Among them was Holcroft, who proudly presented himself to the Lord Chief
Justice rather than waiting to be taken in. Godwin was in Warwickshire,
the guest of one his many new well-wishers (the scholar and clergyman,
Samuel Parr). As soon as the philosopher heard the news, he wrote to
Holcroftâs daughter instructing her to deliver his request to visit his
friend in Newgate prison and to alert Erskine (who was again leading the
defence) that he was the playwrightâs âprincipal friendâ (presumably for
the purposes of consultation â Holcroft was, at the time, a widower).
Holcroft himself replied in his usual argumentative manner, brushing off
any need for Godwinâs company and demanding that his friend focus on
whatever he could do for the greater cause. The philosopher quickly went
to work.
The law on treason was (literally) medieval, the statute unchanged since
1351. Since political authority of the time was vested in the body of
the monarch, the charge of treason usually pertained to direct threats
to the royal family. The governmentâs indictment claimed that, because
they wished to see the overthrow of the current regime, the defendants
were guilty of âimagining the kingâs deathâ â drawing a direct line from
the desire to see a change in Britainâs system of government, to the
revolutionary overthrow of that system, to the killing of the monarch.
Conservative and reactionary minds projected events in France onto the
British political landscape, refusing to acknowledge the very different
political context that had caused the downfall of the French monarchy.
The government asserted that only parliament and the king had the
authority to alter the nationâs political arrangements, thus to organise
an extra-parliamentary movement in support of reform was to act in
contempt of parliamentâs authority. Since this, in the minds of the
government, could only achieve its goals through revolution (and that
revolution must inevitably end in the death of the monarch), then a
popular movement for political reform must by extension be a plot to
kill the king. The indictment accepted that peaceful protest was not a
crime but asserted that the only legitimate outlet for this was to apply
to parliament for redress. By extension, any political agitation that
attempted to coerce parliament from outside (arguably this could include
mass demonstration or strike action) was a form of insurrection.
Godwin completed his response inside three days and rushed it to the
editor of the Morning Chronicle, where it was published on Monday 21
October, four days before the trial was due to begin. The publisher
James Kearsley also arranged for separate publication as a pamphlet, and
by the end of the day had been threatened with prosecution if he
continued to sell it. The radical Daniel Isaac Eaton (who had already
been prosecuted, and acquitted, for sedition that year) took over
distribution and organised another printing.
The governmentâs case rested on a broad, arguably elastic, definition of
treason. Godwinâs anonymous pamphlet, Cursory Strictures on the Charge
Delivered by Lord Chief Justice Eyre to the Grand Jury, October 2, 1794,
argued that the law was in fact quite specific in its definition. In
typically fair-minded language, Godwin performs a scholarly
demonstration of legal precedent â explaining how attempts to efforts by
one monarch to widen the definition of treason were invariably swept
away by their successors, thus creating no precedent for the
wide-ranging interpretation of the law the government sought to use. The
onus is on the government, Godwin argues, to show a direct relationship
between reformist activity and treasonous conspiracy â the law does not
allow one to encompass the other. Within a few days there was a
conservative reply, allegedly written by the judge Sir Francis Buller
(popularly believed to have been the origin of the term ârule of
thumbâ). Eaton published that too, and Godwinâs rebuttal. Cursory
Strictures struck a huge blow for the defence. The first trial was that
of London Corresponding Society Chair Thomas Hardy. The prosecutionâs
opening statement lasted nine hours, an hour of which was given over to
responding to Godwinâs pamphlet. Erskine for the defence argued that the
only people who had imagined the kingâs death were in government, that
their suspicion had projected a malicious conspiracy onto men exercising
their political rights. Hardy was acquitted after nine days in court.
Horne Tooke and Thelwall were also tried, and acquitted, after which
every other case was dismissed. The author of Cursory Strictures was a
hero in radical circles, though only a few were aware of the authorâs
identity. Horne Tooke did not learn of it until nearly a year later â
Godwin records that the politician kissed his hand in gratitude. The
philosopher was magnanimous in victory, and wrote (again, anonymously)
to Lord Chief Justice Eyre to apologise for any intemperate language he
had used in his pamphlets. It became clear that the case against the
reformers had been built from reports submitted by a spy within their
midst and the suspect, Charles Sinclair, was confronted on 24 November.
The alleged spy was ejected from their circle, but Godwin took it upon
himself a few weeks later to write to Sinclair with a list of specific
accusations against him and offering him the chance to clear his name
(though it is not clear if the letter was ever sent).
Godwin began the new year deeply engaged in revisions to Political
Justice. The philosopher frequently tinkered with his own work, but his
changes in the second edition of the text would be substantial. The
first volume of the original had gone to the printer while Godwin was
still working on the second. Despite the bookâs success, the philosopher
was not happy with its argument. Godwin later wrote that a scholar did
not truly understand a subject until they had written on it and, reading
the first edition of Political Justice, we can see how the philosopherâs
ideas take shape over the course of drafting the work. The tone of the
first volume is exploratory and questioning, the second clear and
authoritative. The philosopher must have been conscious of this, because
he seems to have returned to Political Justice within a few weeks of
sending Caleb Williams to the publisher. Revision stalled during the
Treason Trials in October 1794, but by the end of December Godwin was
back on the job. Looking back at the work a few years later, the
philosopher wrote:
The Enquiry Concerning Political Justice I apprehend to be blemished by
three errors: 1) Stoicism, or an inattention to the principle that
pleasure and pain are the only bases upon which morality can rest; 2)
Sandemanianism, or an inattention to the principle that feeling, and not
judgement is the cause of human actions; 3) the unqualified condemnation
of the private affections.
It will be seen how strongly these errors are connected with the
Calvinist system, which had been so deeply wrought in my mind in early
life, as to enable these errors long to survive the general system of
religious opinions of which they formed a part.[39]
Godwinâs clear-sightedness was not entirely the product of his own
reflection, however. True to what he had argued in the book, Godwinâs
ideas were refined by conversation. He had, of course, discussed the
themes of Political Justice with his peers while writing the first
edition, but his newfound celebrity as the philosopher of the radical
movement meant that his circle of friends had greatly expanded. Godwin
had been professionally well-connected before, with many contacts in the
world of publishing and on the forward-looking edge of the Whig
political establishment. Political Justice brought him a wealth of
personal connections, substantially broadening the number of people with
whom Godwin could discuss political and philosophical matters. Godwinâs
diary records a host of new contacts: the Whig clergyman and teacher
Samuel Parr; photography pioneer and pottery heir Thomas Wedgwood;
financier John King; playwright Elizabeth Inchbald; essayist Mary Hays;
and the poet William Wordsworth (he and Wordsworth did not get on). The
philosopher, as detailed as ever, often notes the topics that were
discussed. In the past, the majority of Godwinâs friends had been
radicals and Dissenters â people with the same perspective as the
philosopher himself â and while Godwin did not forget his old friends
(Holcroft and Marshall remained regular companions), the range of his
new acquaintances meant that he was able to discuss his ideas with
people who saw things differently.
Godwin discarded whole chapters from the original text and wrote new
ones in their place. The bulk of the changes occur in the first volume,
though Godwin made substantial amendments to the language of the later
books and culled some of the most speculative ideas from the conclusion.
The language of the second (and third) edition is more philosophical
than that of the original â many minor revisions are clarifications or
qualifications of statements made in the first edition, and the
philosopher adds considerable nuance to his explanation of how the mind
makes decisions. Most significant (which, as we see above, Godwin was
conscious of) is his new account of the role of the emotions in
motivating and channelling ethical actions.
In the first edition, Godwin had been certain that moral right was
interchangeable with intellectual accuracy, that the best ethical
response to any dilemma could be logically deduced and should be carried
out because it is identifiably the correct answer to the question at
hand. This, as the philosopher wrote above, was a remnant of his
training as a Sandemanian: the sect claimed that salvation derived from
understanding the truth of the divine word. With hindsight, the
philosopher recognised his own assumption â that we intrinsically want
to do what is correct, rather than what pleases us (perhaps assuming
that those sentiments were always interchangeable). This left Godwin
with the need to explain motivation without undermining his concept of
moral and intellectual truth. His answer to this problem is twofold:
first, the second edition acknowledges that ascertaining the âGodwinian
truthâ of a matter (i.e. the logically and morally correct response) is
far more difficult than the philosopher had previously suggested;
second, Godwin conceded that reasoning was not enough to motivate an
action on its own â we have to care about the outcome.
In short, uncovering a perfect truth probably requires perfect
perception. To deduce the ideal response to a moral dilemma, an
individual would need to begin with an open mind, yet understand every
variable of the situation, know the minds of the participants, and have
enough time to reflect upon the possible consequences of their decision.
In the second edition of Political Justice Godwin allows that time,
experience and the limits of human cognition mean that few decisions are
ever likely to meet this standard. The philosopherâs qualification
effectively places truth beyond the reach of mundane beings, rendering
it an abstract idea that seems to have little bearing on the moral
calculus of everyday life. Godwinâs solution is to reframe truth as an
ideal â a target for us to aim at, rather than a goal to be achieved.
This constitutes a major change to the philosopherâs position, but on an
abstract level rather than a practical one. Godwinâs principal interest
remains the moral and intellectual improvement of humanity but, in the
revisions to Political Justice, the philosopher now focuses on
improvement as a process rather than an end. In every edition Godwin
argues that individuals using their own judgment become wiser and more
virtuous through the exercise of reason. In the first edition, however,
the exercise of reason leads directly to truth â implying a kind of
end-state where, without restrictions on their reason, the populace
becomes sufficiently wise to always act in ways that maximise happiness
and eventually eliminate pain. The second edition recognises this as
unlikely, if not impossible. This should not concern us, Godwin says,
because the search for truth is valuable in itself. The philosopher
claims that humanity has a limitless capacity for improvement. It may be
impossible for us to perfectly deduce perfect answers, but the use of
reason leads to better answers with every application. Reason may not
usher us into an ideal world, but it certainly has the potential to make
a better one.
The second editionâs discussion of motivation and the emotions has more
practical impact on Godwinian ethics. The first edition presents moral
actions as essentially logical calculations â they are correct, and can
be proven to be so. The philosopherâs revised understanding of truth (as
seen above) renders this problematic; without an accurate picture of the
situation, our logic will be faulty. Godwinâs revised account of
improvement means that this is not intrinsically a disaster â we do the
best we can with the information we have, and fail better next time â
but it fails to explain why we choose to act morally in the first place.
The first edition was able to argue that, the individual having deduced
the truth, only perversity would explain why they would not choose to
take the identifiably best course of action. The second edition, having
undermined the certainty of this equation, instead argues that what
motivates decisions are the feelings we have towards the outcome.
All actions ultimately derive from the desire to be happy â at the most
basic level, to experience pleasure and avoid pain. Sympathy for the
people around us means that these desires are not purely atavistic (we
enjoy the happiness of others and share their pain). Reason organises
and directs our desires; even an entirely selfish person must learn to
prioritise needs over wants, and plan how to get them. Rather than
concede ground to the self-interest hypothesis, however, Godwin argues
that we very quickly develop a desire to do benevolent things (making
other people happy makes us happy) and find that reason confirms them to
be a productive and sensible use of our efforts â more so than selfish
acts because, if we reason that other people have the same emotional
needs as ourselves, we must recognise that an act that makes two people
happy is better than something that pleases only one. In time we come to
value benevolence itself rather than just its effects, becoming
genuinely altruistic and not just a good team player.[40] In the second
edition Godwin expands upon an idea that was hinted at in the first,
developing a hierarchy of pleasures that places basic sensual desires at
the bottom and benevolence at the top, arguing that more complex
pleasures (e.g. reading) were superior to purely physical experiences
because they could stimulate the mind and the emotions. Benevolent acts
are not only personally satisfying but also propagate greater happiness
around us, thus increasing our own pleasure further.
The revisions to Political Justice provide a straightforward explanation
of why we choose to do altruistic things, and certainly a more robust
one than the first edition. The philosopher realised, however, that the
revised account of motivation was at odds with the earlier editionâs
âunqualified condemnation of the private affectionsâ. The first edition
has a sort of austere clarity â our respect and esteem for others is
secondary to the demands of truth and justice. In his discussion of the
FĂ©nelon dilemma, Godwin treats affection as a distraction from our real
moral duties. Justice requires us to do whatever will bring the greatest
happiness, and to consider impartially the question of how happiness
might be increased. The philosopher argues that personal affection
encourages us to overvalue the moral worth of the people closest to us,
either because their benevolence impacts on us personally, or because we
are more familiar with their contribution than we are with that of
others. The second edition did not alter Godwinâs commitment to
impartiality â it is still better to save FĂ©nelon over the chambermaid
(now altered to valet) â but the philosopher acknowledged that the
uncertainty of knowledge made such clear moral choices unrealistic.
While some degree of uncertainty is inescapable, the revised Political
Justice implies that we should aim to make informed moral choices over
abstract ones. In absolute terms we should always help the person of
greatest moral worth, in the greatest need. In practical terms, we can
only help the person of greatest known moral worth, in the greatest need
that we are aware of. The revisions soften Godwinâs language
considerably here and, although the philosopher retains his insistence
that it would an error (albeit forgivable) to help a friend over a more
needy stranger, the second edition displays an acceptance that favouring
those of known moral calibre is a pragmatic compromise that still
significantly contributes to general happiness. This may seem only
sensible, but some critics at the time chose to see it as the
philosopher retreating from an unworkable ethical position. To some
extent Godwin agreed (as the revisions and subsequent essays show) and
was publicly candid about having reconsidered.
The second editionâs compromise opens the door to a more obvious change,
though the philosopher did not see the immediate significance of this
(and even his later discussions suggest that he did not consider its
impact revolutionary). Conservative critics had found the first
editionâs commitment to impartiality disconcerting, since it appeared to
argue that traditional values like loyalty, familialism, and patriotism
were actually distractions from proper moral reasoning. The first
edition had argued for the abolition of marriage, and that it was right
for parents to give up their children to other people if those people
would be better carers. The book had little to say about love or
friendship, preferring to code personal relationships in terms of mutual
regard and the respect due to individuals of proven moral quality. The
second (and third) edition did not alter this to any great extent but,
following through on the logic of the revisions, Godwin was forced to
concede that personal relationships were crucial to the spread of
happiness.
The philosopher discusses this in a number of essays written (mostly)
after the revisions to Political Justice: it is implicit in his writings
on teachers and pupils in The Enquirer (1797), forms an observation in
the preface to the novel St Leon (1799), and receives a detailed
explanation in a pamphlet entitled Thoughts Occasioned by the Perusal of
Dr Parrâs Spital Sermon (1801, now often referred to as the Reply to
Parr). What Godwin concludes is that, if our duty is to create as much
happiness as we are able, and that we should try our hardest to make
informed decisions about how to do so, then it follows that the most
effective use of our time and effort is to foster happiness among the
people we know best. We understand the needs of our friends, family and
neighbours better than we do those of strangers; we have a better
understanding of how deserving our friends are of our time â how likely
they are to do good as a result of our help. This serves to justify a
number of behaviours that many would take for granted â prioritising
family over friends, and friends over strangers â and within Godwinâs
thought it demonstrates the philosopherâs journey from the abstract to
the practical.
The political atmosphere of 1795 was heated. Emboldened by the failure
of the treason trials, membership of reformist and radical political
societies surged â the best known, the London Corresponding Society
(LCS), led by trial defendants Hardy, Thelwall and Tooke, claimed around
3,000. In June the LCS held a huge public meeting at St Georgeâs Fields
in Southwark calling for âliberty and breadâ. Estimates as to the size
of the meeting vary dramatically: the LCS claimed as many as 300,000
attendees (a third of the population of London) while more sober
assessments placed the figure as low as 40,000.[41] The government had
assembled the militia over on Clapham Common, in any case. The societyâs
address insisted on its loyalty to the king, and called upon him to
dismiss the unscrupulous ministers leading the nation to ruin. The
speech was less a petition than a warning. Another mass meeting in
October used stronger language, accusing the kingâs ministers of high
treason against the nation, and reminding the king himself that he ruled
by the peopleâs consent (because the Hanoverians had been invited to
Britain over the Stuarts). Three days later, during the state opening of
parliament on the 29^(th), demonstrators turned violent and the kingâs
coach was pelted with stones â the damage was severe enough that the
monarch believed he had been shot at and was forced to change to a
private carriage. The now empty state coach was torn apart by the
protestors.
Pittâs government leapt on these events as evidence that the nation was
in peril, that new laws were needed to protect the person of the king
and prevent violent insurrection. The True Briton, a reactionary
newspaper founded with government funds, reported that the attack had
been led by French agents.[42] The Archbishop of Canterbury authored a
prayer for Englandâs congregations (at the governmentâs behest) that
presented the violence as an assassination attempt. There were very few
actual arrests, which radicals took as a sign that the government had
orchestrated the affair themselves. Regardless, Pitt took the
opportunity to push through a repressive legislative programme banning
âseditious meetingsâ and redefining treason in order to facilitate
prosecutions. Pittâs laws are known to history as âthe Gagging Actsâ.
Holding a political lecture was to become a fineable offence, unless
approved by two magistrates. Other political meetings required
magistrates to be notified, and could be broken up if they were held to
be encouraging contempt for the government. Refusal to disperse was
punishable by death. The new law on treason made explicit the
interpretation used by the prosecution in the trials of the previous
year: that it was treasonous to express the intention to depose the
monarch, or to attempt to intimidate parliament.
The two acts prompted a wave of petitions and further mass meetings, in
London and across the country. Pamphlets, letters and essays flew back
and forth. Godwinâs contribution was critical of the legislation but
maintained the reservations that he had outlined against revolutionary
agitation in Political Justice. Godwinâs Considerations on Lord
Grenvilleâs and Mr Pittâs Bills depicts the two acts as an attack on
both free speech and free thought. The previous yearâs trials (and use
of informants) suggested that the government could use the new law to
prosecute any private discussion that did not endorse the existing
political order, in Godwinâs view essentially criminalising intellectual
enquiry. In his donnish, qualified, way the philosopher calls Pitt and
Grenville âenemies of scienceâ who threaten to plunge the country into a
new dark age.[43] Yet the philosopher is critical of both sides: while
he describes the radical movementâs complaints as justified he argues
that, even with the best of intentions, a passionate mass movement is
likely to spin violently out of control. It won him few friends. John
Thelwall took the pamphlet as a personal attack (one of Godwinâs
anonymous examples clearly refers to Thelwall, though the philosopher is
not unkind) and the two exchanged angry letters. Samuel Parr wrote to
express fulsome praise, but Godwinâs reply is a reminder of his
commitment to impartiality:
I have offended some of my democratical friends by the freedom of its
remarks, & could originally have no hope of its being acceptable to any
party. But I could not, consistently with my feelings, protest against
the tyranny of one party, without entering my caveat against the
imprudence of the other.
I should have been further gratified, if you had joined some censure to
your liberal commendation. Authors stand in need of both.[44]
Popular protest was to little avail, however, and the two bills were
passed in December. The LCS and other groups changed the way in which
they held meetings in order to sidestep the law, but memberships
dwindled rapidly. The radical movement continued, but without the energy
or public support it had enjoyed prior to the Gagging Acts. The chair of
the LCS committee fell to the gradualist Francis Place, who sought to
place the society on firm financial ground. The small number of
sympathetic MPs, led by Fox and Sheridan, continued their opposition
through conventional parliamentary means (before walking out of the
house in 1797) but distanced themselves from the popular societies. On
22 December, Godwin noted in his diary âexplanation w/Thelwalâ and the
two sparred (with less acrimony than in their private letters) in the
pages of Thelwallâs periodical, The Tribune. Their friendship was
properly restored some months later.
The year 1796 would see Godwin make many new friends, but one of them
would change the course of his life forever.
At the beginning of January, Mary Hays invited Godwin (with Holcroft in
tow) to take tea with her and meet her friend, Mary Wollstonecraft. The
philosopher was initially reluctant â he had met Wollstonecraft before
and they had departed âmutually displeased with each otherâ â but the
engagement was a success.[45] Like many of Godwinâs closest friends,
Wollstonecraft was a radical author. She had been a governess, teacher,
book critic and novelist, but Godwin knew her best from her political
treatise A Vindication of the Rights of Woman (1792). He wrote later:
When tried by the hoary and long-established laws of literary
composition, it can scarcely maintain its claim to be placed in the
first class of human productions. But when we consider the importance of
its doctrines, and the eminence of genius it displays, it seems not very
improbable that it will be read as long as the English language
endures.[46]
The Vindication is framed as an intervention into the debate over public
education in France prompted by the report of former bishop (later
ambassador, and eventually prime minister) Charles Maurice de
Talleyrand-PĂ©rigord. Talleyrand had recommended a comprehensive system
of schools organised by a central authority but, while he had argued for
the education of both sexes, he had advocated that women and girls be
trained for a subordinate role. The French constitution of 1791 did not
recognise women as citizens (and they would not receive full equality
under the law until the late twentieth century). Wollstonecraft begins
from the position that the supposed inferiority of women is a direct
result of their infantilisation by education and culture. If women
appear too ignorant and irrational to take part in the public sphere
alongside men, it is because society has kept them ignorant and denied
them the use of reason â the many negative behaviours attributed to
women (timidity, deceitfulness, emotional fragility) are learned
responses to a culture that shames, belittles, or ignores them when they
attempt to participate in the world beyond the domestic sphere. Even
were we to insist that the domestic sphere was the correct place for
women to focus their attentions, denying wives and mothers education (or
the agency to make their own decisions) can only have negative
consequences for children and families.
Wollstonecraft picks apart the most influential texts of the period on
the subject of womenâs education (she had published her own book on the
education of girls some years earlier). Rousseau comes in for particular
criticism â the Swiss philosopher argued that the ideal wife should
subordinate her entire identity to that of her husband â but
Wollstonecraft is able to show how even writers who are not hostile to
womenâs learning, such as John Gregory in A Fatherâs Legacy to his
Daughters (1774), participate in the expectations of womenâs conduct
that continue their oppression. Gregory understood an issue that
Wollstonecraft is determined to explode: that patriarchal culture values
what women appear to be, rather than what they are. Society expects a
woman to appear beautiful, deferent and chaste â teaching women to value
only the outward show of these attributes, because they are denied the
education necessary to interrogate them for whatever virtue they might
have. Wollstonecraft argues that virtue requires rational engagement;
ignorance of immoral things merely provides a trap for the unwary while
an educated understanding allows the conscious choice of good over bad.
It is not possible for women to become genuinely moral beings while they
are kept in perpetual childhood.
After the Vindication, Wollstonecraft had travelled to revolutionary
Paris. Mixing with the English-speaking circle there she met Gilbert
Imlay, an American adventurer and sometime novelist. They fell in love.
They did not marry, but Wollstonecraft assumed Imlayâs name and received
a certificate from the US ambassador (as Imlayâs âwifeâ) that freed her
from the restrictions that had been placed on British subjects in France
since the declaration of war in early 1793. In May 1794, the couple had
a child, Fanny. Imlayâs business dealings saw him travel extensively
and, in April 1795, mother and daughter moved to London to await him.
Imlay followed later, but Wollstonecraft realised that his affections
had cooled. Isolated and alone (she had only reluctantly returned to
Britain) the writer attempted suicide, possibly through an overdose of
laudanum. Upon her recovery, perhaps seeking a connection, she involved
herself in Imlayâs current venture â the American had helped to run a
shipment of French silver through the British naval blockade, but the
vessel had never arrived at its destination. The captain, Peder
Ellefsen, had resurfaced but the silver had not been recovered. Mary
travelled Scandinavia following sightings of the ship, and acted as
Imlayâs representative at Ellefsenâs trial. To this day it remains
unclear to what extent Imlay recouped his losses, but Wollstonecraftâs
journey was immortalised in her writing. Published as Letters Written
during a Short Residence in Sweden, Norway, and Denmark in January 1796,
the work describes the atmosphere of each country with a keen political
eye while remaining alive to the great emotional resonance of the
landscape. Godwin wrote that perhaps, âa book of travels that so
irresistibly seizes on the heart, never, in any other instance, found
its way from the pressâ.[47] She returned to Britain in October to find
that Imlay had taken up with another woman in her absence. She attempted
suicide once more, soaking her clothes in the rain before throwing
herself into the Thames. She was rescued by a boatman.
The meeting with Hays, Holcroft and Godwin came only a few weeks later.
From Godwinâs account she seems to have made no secret of her
unhappiness. The philosopher wrote that from their first reacquaintance
his âsympathy in her anguishâ was added to his respect for her as a
writer. They met again at a dinner party a week later. He obtained a
copy of her newly published Letters soon after that. âIf ever there was
a book calculated to make a man in love with its author, this appears to
me to be the book.â[48] The two made time to see each other:
Wollstonecraft called on the philosopher unannounced on 14 April, in
defiance of the social conventions of the time, and he visited her
weekly for the rest of the spring. They grew increasingly affectionate.
Godwin spent much of July visiting family and friends in East Anglia
(where he reconciled with Thelwall) and wrote Wollstonecraft a wryly
silly letter from Norwich:
Shall I write a love letter? May Lucifer fly away with me, if I do! No,
when I make love, it shall be with the eloquent tones of my voice, with
dying accents, with speaking glances (through the glass of my
spectacles), with all the witching of that irresistible, universal
passion. Curse on the mechanical, icy medium of pen & paper. When I make
love, it shall be in a storm, as Jupiter made love to Semele, & turned
her at once to a cinder. Do not these menaces terrify you?[49]
They became lovers in August. They met and talked, sent letters back and
forth, as they struggled to express their feelings for one another.
Godwin had clumsily courted women before, but genuine romance was a
shock to him. Wollstonecraft was more experienced, but knew the
knifeâs-edge balance of female propriety. Matters came to a head on the
17^(th), in a rapid exchange of letters. Wollstonecraft wrote that
morning:
I feel that I cannot speak clearly on the subject to you, let me then
briefly explain myself now I am alone. Yet, struggling as I have been a
long time to attain peace of mind (or apathy) I am afraid to trace
emotions to their source, which border on agony. [50]
Godwin wrote a confused reply:
For six & thirty hours I could think of nothing else. I longed
inexpressibly to have you in my arms Why did not I come to you? I am a
fool. I feared still that I might be deceiving myself as to your
feelings, & that I was feeding my mind with groundless presumptions. âŠ
Upon consideration I find in you one fault, & but one. You have the
feelings of nature, & you have the honesty to avow them. In all this you
do well. I am sure you do. But do not let them tyrannise over you.
Estimate every thing at its just value. It is best that we should be
friends in every sense of the word; but in the mean time let us be
friends.[51]
By the afternoon he had reconsidered and wrote again to beg for
forgiveness. Before the letter could be delivered, the proactive
Wollstonecraft had called on him to put her feelings directly. Godwinâs
diary records almost daily meetings from that point on. The entry for 21
August reads âchez moi, touteâ, a note that the philosopherâs
biographers have taken as a record of the first time the two made love.
They kept their affair private, and saw their friends separately. Godwin
helped to maintain the fiction of âMrs Imlayâ, addressing his letters to
that name while simultaneously recording the correspondence in his diary
under her real one. As writers, they read each otherâs work in draft â
Godwin did not spare his lover from the bruising criticism he gave
everyone else, but Wollstonecraft was more than willing to stand her
ground where it mattered.
In the latter part of the year, Wollstonecraft was reviewing again for
Joseph Johnsonâs Analytical Review and working on the novel that would
become The Wrongs of Woman (1798). Godwin was completing a series of
essays on education and literature, which was published as The Enquirer
in February 1797. Though the philosopher presented the work as the
conceptual opposite of Political Justice â an unsystematic collection of
observations on various topics rather than a philosophical investigation
â the book provides a significant insight into the direction of Godwinâs
thought. The Enquirerâs principal themes are reading and empathy, with a
particular interest in how the two overlap. Education was not explored
in detail in Political Justice, the philosopher was principally
concerned about its power to indoctrinate and saw little scope for it as
a method of moral and intellectual improvement. This initially seems
counter-intuitive â we improve by learning â but Godwinâs concerns stem
from what he saw as (formal) educationâs greater utility as a
conservative force than a progressive one. On their own terms,
authoritarian, didactic models of education are highly effective â they
impart an approved version of knowledge to a great number of learners,
without having to engage with anything outside the terms they have set.
Teaching someone to think critically is far more difficult. The Enquirer
identifies the paradox the philosopher saw at the heart of formal
education: how do we teach people to think for themselves?
Under the didactic model, teaching is relatively simple. The teacher
imparts knowledge to pupils, and the skill of teaching lies in creating
receptive learners. A more liberal version of this has the teacher
training learners how to access knowledge on their own. This would seem
to sidestep Godwinâs concerns about authority â it is not dictatorial â
but the teacherâs understanding places boundaries on what the student
can learn (I cannot guide you in learning things I know nothing about
and, without guidance on how to evaluate a subject critically, a student
doing research is merely swapping one fountain of knowledge for
another). For Godwin, this is insufficient. The philosopherâs vision of
moral and intellectual improvement requires the individual to outgrow
their predecessors, not merely to achieve the same standard. Godwinâs
ideal learner has the wisdom to respect the achievements of their
ancestors, but the spirit to challenge accepted ideas when they appear
lacking. The philosopher calls this genius â not some innate talent that
separates great minds from the herd but a capacity that lies dormant in
every individual, waiting to be awakened.
The Enquirer does not present a system of education. Godwinâs essays
offer few solutions but instead identify the philosophical issues that
accompany different methods of teaching and learning. There are
recurring themes: the relationship between teacher and student is
inherently unbalanced; human beings are social creatures and need to
share their ideas (in part, a need for esteem); our ideas and
achievements should be regarded with humility and we should not be
afraid to change our opinions when presented with better ones.
Wollstonecraftâs influence can be seen in the compromise Godwin offers
for formal education. Rejecting both individual tutoring and boarding
schools (the two most common methods in the period), the philosopher
suggests that small day schools may avoid the worst problems of either
method (Wollstonecraft had suggested the same in her own writing).
Godwin regards schooling as a necessary evil, the least worst of all the
systems tried: âall education is despotismâ, he writes, acknowledging
that teaching is something done to young people for their own good that
inculcates habits of obedience rather than enquiry.[52] For all its
faults, however, teaching encourages an intellectual rigour and
diversity of learning that few auto-didacts ever develop. Schooling
provides young people with a community of peers, which not only
socialises them but also offers a social space away from the teacherâs
authority â space to develop the personal identity necessary to
criticise or resist authority when needed.
Teaching remains an exercise of authority, which for Godwin renders it
both morally and intellectually problematic. The philosopher suggests
that reading affords the opportunity to educate without exerting
authority over the learner. The text may dictate any number of things,
but the reader is under no obligation to accept them. Indeed, all acts
of reading are in some way acts of interpretation (at the most basic
level, agreeing the meaning of words and sentences) and the reader can
learn from a text even if they reject its message. For this reason, the
philosopher dismisses the idea that books can ever genuinely corrupt
someone â a work may celebrate odious things, but it has no power to
make the reader emulate them. The author considers all literature to be
instructive because it enables the reader to exercise their imagination,
putting themselves in the place of the literary protagonist (fictional,
historical or authorial) to experience something akin to a simulation of
the characterâs experience. We feel what they feel, and learn from it.
In December 1796, Wollstonecraft began to suspect that she was pregnant
with Godwinâs child. The couple quarrelled. The notes that passed
between them afterwards show Godwin hurt by her apparent regrets, but
they patched things up quickly. Wollstonecraft was likely under pressure
to settle debts she had accrued during her separation from Imlay, and
the prospect of becoming an unmarried mother for the second time cannot
have aided her peace of mind. In the spring, Godwin borrowed money from
Thomas Wedgwood to pay Wollstonecraftâs creditors and the couple
resolved to marry. The wedding was held at St Pancras on 29 March, with
Marshall as the only witness. They moved in together at the Polygon in
Somers Town (then on the north edge of London) on 6 April, but Godwin
rented rooms a few streets away in order to have his own space to work.
They informed their friends slowly and with apparent reluctance.
Holcroft wished them the utmost happiness but was clearly saddened at
having been left out of the secret. An embarrassed letter from Godwin to
Wedgwood requested more money on Wollstonecraftâs behalf and attempted
to justify his marriage in the light of his vehement criticism of the
institution itself:
Nothing but a regard for the happiness of the individual, which I had no
right to injure, could have induced me to submit to an institution,
which I wish to see abolished, & which I would recommend to my fellow
men, never to practise, but with the greatest caution. Having done what
I thought necessary for the peace & respectability of the individual, I
hold myself no otherwise bound than I was before the ceremony took
place.[53]
Godwinâs anxiety regarding Wollstonecraftâs ârespectabilityâ was
well-founded. Though the marriage may have shielded her from some of the
opprobrium reserved for unmarried mothers, the pretence of her marriage
to Imlay was entirely exploded. According to Godwin, this was not any
great revelation: Wollstonecraft was candid in explaining her
relationship with Imlay, even to casual acquaintances, and did not seem
to fear it being widely known.[54] Godwin reports that Wollstonecraft
and her friends persisted in using âMrs Imlayâ out of convenience rather
than deception. Indeed, Godwinâs awkward attempt to irreverently inform
Mary Hays of their marriage refers to the wedding as the obvious way for
Wollstonecraft to drop the Imlay name, suggesting that they had
discussed the practical concerns of doing so.[55] Some of their
acquaintances took the opportunity to cut ties with the couple
regardless, which Godwin took as an adherence to the form of proper
behaviour rather than its spirit. Chief among those cutting ties was
Elizabeth Inchbald. Formerly a close friend of Godwin, rumour implied
that the playwright may have resented âlosingâ the philosopher to
another woman. Yet Inchbald was often guarded in her social and
political engagements (an important survival trait for a woman in the
highly public world of theatre) and may have thought the loss of
Godwinâs friendship an acceptable sacrifice to minimise her association
with any potential scandal.
Godwin and Wollstonecraft both took care to maintain a degree of
independence from one another. Godwinâs rented rooms were more than just
an office, and the philosopher sometimes slept there, the couple
communicating through notes and letters in much the same way as they had
before their marriage. They saw their friends separately (radical in a
time when many considered it improper for wives to speak to men without
their husbands present). Wollstonecraft wrote to their mutual friend
Amelia Alderson, âin short, I still mean to be independent, even to the
cultivating sentiments and principles in my childrenâs minds (should I
have more), which he disavowsâ.[56] Yet some degree of domesticity crept
in. The couple were happy and Godwin doted on Fanny, now his
stepdaughter. The notes suggest that their relationship thrived on blunt
honesty. Though Wollstonecraft expressed reservations about her
husbandâs doctrine of sincerity, she was open about her feelings.
Complaining of having missed an opportunity to walk in the country with
friends because of a prior engagement with Godwinâs sister, the couple
apparently argued. Wollstonecraft later wrote to him:
I am sorry we entered on an altercation this morning, which probably has
led us both to justify ourselves at the expence of the other. Perfect
confidence, and sincerity of action is, I am persuaded, incompatible
with the present state of reason. I am sorry for the bitterness of your
expressions when you denominated, what I think a just contempt of a
false principle of action, savage resentment, and the worst of vices,
not because I winced under the lash, but as it led me to infer that the
coquettish candour of vanity was a much less generous motive. I know
that respect is the shadow of wealth, and commonly obtained, when that
is wanted, by a criminal compliance with the prejudice of society.[57]
In June, Godwin took a trip to the Midlands to visit Wedgwood and see
his potteries. His letters home speak volumes about the sort of warm and
affectionate family the Godwins had so quickly become â most letters
feature a passage for Fanny, including an ongoing discussion about the
whereabouts of a misplaced toy. It is clear that Wollstonecraft missed
him dearly; her last letter before his return complains that the
tenderness of his letters had âevaporatedâ the longer he had been away
(he arrived home the next day).[58]
Wollstonecraft went into labour at 5 a.m. on Wednesday 30 August 1797.
She was confident, casually writing notes to Godwin (who had been sent
to his rooms until the birth was completed) until the pains encouraged
her to retire to bed. She was attended by an experienced midwife (Mrs
Blenkinsop of the Westminster Lying-In Hospital, a place for poorer
women) but the labour continued for many hours. Mary Wollstonecraft gave
birth to Mary Wollstonecraft Godwin at 11.20 p.m. Complications
presented themselves a few hours later: the mother had not expelled the
placenta. Still a concern today, in the eighteenth century it quickly
led to infection and death. Godwin summoned Blenkinsopâs surgeon
colleague, Dr Poignand, who removed the placenta surgically in the small
hours of the Thursday, causing significant blood loss. For
Wollstonecraft the experience was agonising. Godwin sent for another
doctor, his wifeâs friend George Fordyce, who pronounced âno particular
cause of alarmâ.[59] For a few days, life seemed to return to normal.
Godwin went about some pressing business on Friday, certain that his
wife was recovering strongly. On Sunday, Wollstonecraft was overcome
with fits of shivering so violent that she later described them as a
struggle between life and death. Some of the placenta apparently
remained and had become infected. Poignand and Fordyce were both
summoned again; Poignand refused to attend because another physician had
been consulted, but Fordyce (by Tuesday) had called in another doctor â
John Clark, Londonâs most senior midwifery practitioner â with a view to
further surgery. The doctors presumably decided against another
procedure, advising Godwin only to give his wife wine for the pain. By
Wednesday 6 September it was clear that Wollstonecraft was not long for
this world, but she throughout bore her suffering with patience and
calm. Godwin, by contrast, was far from his usual rational self. He
begged his friend Basil Montagu to find a new doctor. Montagu turned to
Godwinâs friend Anthony Carlisle. Carlisle was that day dining some
miles outside London, but Montagu tracked him down and brought him to
Wollstonecraftâs side. Carlisle stayed with them until the end. Godwinâs
account lists all those who visited or helped in his wifeâs last days.
She appeared to rally and held on until Sunday morning, twelve days
after having given birth. On her last full day she discussed with Godwin
what she wanted for her daughters, though what precisely was said we can
only infer from her writing. Godwinâs diary records her death simply
with the words â20 minutes before 8â, underlined twice. She was buried
at St Pancras, the church where they were married. Godwin was too
distraught to attend.
Godwin mourned Wollstonecraft as a fellow author. With the help of
Joseph Johnson and the Robinsons, he published the unfinished Wrongs of
Woman alongside some of her letters and fragments. At the same time, and
within days of the funeral, he was back at his desk writing
Wollstonecraftâs life story. He worked on it in bursts over the
subsequent weeks, finishing it in mid-November and publishing it through
Johnson in January 1798. The Memoirs of the Author of a Vindication of
the Rights of Woman are deeply personal, and distinctively Godwin. The
philosopherâs love and admiration for Wollstonecraft can be seen on
every page, but the text does not shy away from the bracing honesty that
characterised their relationship. Godwin told of her fatherâs cruelty
and her motherâs strictness; her fervent passion for her friend Fanny
Blood; her love for the (married) painter, Henry Fuseli; her child out
of wedlock with Imlay; and her two suicide attempts. Biography in the
period was primarily a celebration of the subjectâs life â no doubt
Godwin saw the work as such â but it was common to draw a veil over
episodes that might be deemed controversial. From the Memoirâs foreword
we might infer that the philosopherâs intention was to lay to rest
painful and misleading rumours about Wollstonecraftâs life by providing
the whole and unvarnished truth. Godwin hid nothing, nor did he flinch
from describing her flaws as well as the genius that he saw in her
character. For all the research that the philosopher attempted in
writing Wollstonecraftâs life (her sisters, among others, were not
forthcoming in their help) his portrait of her is subjective. The Memoir
paints Wollstonecraft as Godwin saw her, and in relation to how he saw
himself: she is a passionate, intuitive, imaginative spirit contrasted
with his rational, logical, sceptical intellect. He credits her with
teaching him the value of imagination. Godwin at times seems to
construct Wollstonecraft as a woman of sensibility â a mind, âalmost of
too fine a texture to encounter the vicissitudes of human affairs, to
whom pleasure is transport, and disappointment is agony
indescribableâ.[60] She might not have appreciated the description,
having rejected sensibility (in its negative sense, valuing the display
of emotion over reason) in the Vindication as a culture that enervated
women. In the Vindication Wollstonecraft argued that sensibility
celebrated the irrational â reinforcing existing stereotypes of womenâs
abilities â instead of encouraging women to think for themselves. Yet in
the Letters from Sweden the author offers a new kind of sensibility: the
combination of emotional literacy and critical thought that would come
to mark the literature of the new century.
Godwin regards Wollstonecraftâs sensibility to have been the force
behind her sound moral intuition. Godwinâs sketch of his wifeâs
character ties closely with the philosopherâs revised understanding of
ethical decision-making in Political Justice, both that we need to feel
in order to motivate moral actions, and that empathy is fundamental to
doing so. The philosopher began his revisions to Political Justice long
before he became reacquainted with Wollstonecraft in 1796, but in the
Memoir Godwin credits his wife with teaching him the meaning of feeling
and imagination.
We might observe that Godwinâs description of their contrasting but
complementary personalities falls into traditional gender roles â he
thinks, she feels â but the Memoir depicts their relationship as one of
equal respect and partnership. What is clear from the text is how much
the couple shared:
Mary rested her head upon the shoulder of her lover, hoping to find a
heart with which she might safely treasure her world of affection;
fearing to commit a mistake, yet, in spite of her melancholy experience,
fraught with that generous confidence, which, in a great soul, is never
extinguished. I had never loved till now; or, at least, had never
nourished a passion to the same growth, or met with an object so
consummately worthy.[61]
While the philosopher draws attention to the steps both took to preserve
their independence, consistent with Godwinâs views on cohabitation, his
description of their happiness strongly resembles Wollstonecraftâs views
on companionship. In the Vindication Wollstonecraft insists that men and
women are different, but morally and intellectually equal. Godwin would
come to adopt similar, but more problematic views.
The response to Godwinâs biography was hostile, sometimes violently so.
Conservative commentators revelled in what they considered the sordid
details of Wollstonecraftâs life, leaping on the details of her romantic
affairs as evidence of her flagrant immorality. A reactionary satire in
the pages of the Anti-Jacobin magazine insinuated that Godwin had
covered up further âcrimesâ, and slandered her as a traitor and a
prostitute. Less ideological critics affected shock at the candour of
Godwinâs writing. It was conventional to use biography as an apology for
an unconventional life, emphasising deathbed piety and repentance.
Nothing in the Memoir suggests that Godwin saw any need for forgiveness;
the philosopherâs pride in his wifeâs achievements is palpable, and his
commentary on her mistakes is not judgmental. The Memoir does not seek
pity, denying readers their traditional prerogative to absolve the
subjectâs âsinsâ as a precursor to acknowledging their contribution. A
work that confounds expectations often alienates readers, and so it was
for Godwinâs biography. The Memoir forced readers to either admire or
condemn its subject, and to admire Wollstonecraft was to reject
societyâs expectations regarding sex, marriage and gender. Few had the
courage. Some persons named in the biography threatened Godwin with
legal action, and Johnson hurriedly issued a second edition with names
excised. Godwin took the opportunity to rephrase or add a number of
passages on happiness and companionship, taking him still further away
from the austerity of the earliest Political Justice. Ironically, many
readers took the Memoirâs honesty as evidence of Godwinâs emotional
distance â imagining that some cold-hearted dedication to truth had
outweighed the ânaturalâ impulse to protect Wollstonecraftâs memory. The
abolitionist (and friend of Fuseli) William Roscoe wrote privately in
her honour:
Hard was thy fate in all the scenes of life,
As daughter, sister, parent, friend and wife
But harder still in death thy fate we own,
Mournâd by thy Godwin â with a heart of stone.[62]
Attacks on Godwin himself began to mount, and not simply as a result of
the Memoir. He was caricatured in fiction: a slew of reactionary novels
featured unfeeling philosophers as either villains or foils.[63]
Gillrayâs cartoons placed him among a rogueâs gallery of Jacobin
grotesques (his 1798 tableau âNew Moralityâ has a braying ass reading
from Political Justice; he appeared again in 1800âs âThe Apples and the
Horse-Turdsâ). Magazines and newspapers satirised him in verse. A
handful of conservative thinkers attempted to engage with and combat
Godwinâs ideas. In June 1798 Johnson published a short (initially
anonymous) work on population growth by a Surrey clergyman called Thomas
Robert Malthus. An Essay on the Principle of Population argued that
unchecked populations grew geometrically (doubling every generation) but
food production could only grow arithmetically â a slow increase that
was quickly outstripped by the number of mouths it needed to feed.
Malthus theorised that famine and disease were natural checks that
prevented significant overpopulation; the misery suffered by the poor in
times of want was unavoidable, he claimed, because attempts to alleviate
it only created the conditions for more serious crises in the future.
Malthus argued that Poor Relief caused inflation, making everyone
poorer, and that the multiplication of poor families inevitably led to
mass starvation in times of bad harvest. Much of the latter part of the
Essay was written in reply to Political Justice (and to a lesser extent,
The Enquirer). Malthusâs address to Godwin is collegial and flattering,
calling the philosopherâs system of equality, âby far the most beautiful
and engaging of any that has yet appearedâ.[64] Yet Malthus airily
rejects the majority of Godwinâs thesis, arguing that poverty and misery
are essentially natural phenomena rather than the product of social
inequality. He considers Godwinâs enlightened future to be dangerously
naĂŻve: the abolition of marriage would lead to rampant promiscuity and
uncontrolled population growth; the equalisation of property would only
demonstrate that there was insufficient usable land to support the
population in equal levels of comfort. Central to Malthusâs argument is
the assumption that a fair and just society would fail catastrophically
without the checks that present (unjust) society provides.
Godwin read the Essay with great interest and met its author at a dinner
party held by Johnson a week later. Malthus and Godwin seem to have
found much to discuss â they met again for breakfast the next day, and
exchanged letters in the following week. The correspondence serves as a
reminder as to how little empirical data existed on the subject at the
time: Godwin believes the population to be falling, Malthus claims that
it is increasing, but both base their assertions on (inaccurate)
information gathered by Richard Price over a decade earlier. Both men
would return to the debate many times over the subsequent years. Malthus
revised and expanded the Essay five times over the next thirty years,
each time adding more data to support his theory. The second edition
(1803) shows signs of Godwinâs influence, arguing that it might be
possible to actively manage the birth rate through âmoral restraintâ
(recalling Political Justiceâs speculation that people might simply
choose not to procreate if they saw no need), and their interactions
remained cordial for many years. Malthus was, however, fundamentally
conservative. He wrote to Godwin that:
Figure 2 James Gillrayâs cartoon, âNew morality; â or â the promisâd
installment of the high-priest of the Theophilanthropes, with the homage
of Leviathan and his suiteâ (1798). The print depicts a host of radical
celebrities of the period â the phrygian caps are a symbol of their
supposed adherence to French revolutionary ideas.
(National Portrait Gallery, London)
I only approve of the present form of society, because I cannot myself,
according to the laws of just theory, see any other form, that can,
consistent with individual freedom, equally promote cultivation and
population. Great improvements may take place in the state of society,
but I do not see how the present form, or system, can be radically &
essentially changed, without a danger of relapsing again into
barbarism.[65]
Their disagreement was equally fundamental. Malthus saw human beings as
short-sighted and selfish creatures who ran out of control without
forces (natural or man-made) to guide them. Godwin never wavered in his
belief that humanity could better itself through reason and compassion.
Less cordial were Godwinâs letters to James Mackintosh a few months
later. Mackintosh had been a prominent radical, author of one of the
best known replies to Burke, the pamphlet Vindicae Gallicae (1791). A
lawyer, in early 1799 he was scheduled to give a series of lectures at
Lincolnâs Inn on âthe Law of Nature and Nationsâ and sent the
preliminary Discourse to Godwin. The philosopher was horrified. Godwin
was probably aware that Mackintosh had gradually walked back from the
hotly pro-revolutionary position he had occupied a few years earlier but
the vehemence of Mackintoshâs attack on radical culture in the Discourse
left him reeling. In their correspondence, Mackintosh claimed that he
was critical of doctrines, not people, yet (without naming names) the
Discourse excoriates âpromulgators of absurd and monstrous systemsâ and
âsophists swelled with insolent conceitâ.[66] Godwin demanded to know
exactly who the lawyer meant by this, suspecting that Mackintoshâs
invective was aimed at him personally. The lawyer denied that Godwin was
his target, reiterating his friendship and respect over several letters,
but also implying that he saw the whole affair as an intellectual
sparring match:
With respect to you personally I could never mean to say anything unkind
or disrespectful â I had always highly esteemed both your acuteness &
benevolence. â You published opinions which you believed to be true &
most Salutary but which I had from the first thought mistakes of a most
dangerous tendency. â You did your duty in making public your opinions.
I do mine by attempting to refute them âŠ[67]
Godwin took the matter personally. He did not criticise Mackintosh for
his apostasy, he respected the right to change oneâs mind, but he was
obviously hurt by the abusiveness of the lawyerâs rhetoric.
Nevertheless, Godwin attended some of the lectures in person. The
philosopher felt increasingly isolated. He fell out with Basil Montagu,
amidst rumours that the younger man had joined the chorus of Godwinâs
critics (a charge Montagu only evasively denied). Holcroft took his
family to the continent in July 1799, in a bid to escape the reactionary
press, and would not return for three years. A letter to an unknown
friend reveals Godwinâs state of mind:
I am on the point of losing Holcroft, whom I am not at all inclined to
compare with you; if I lose you too, I shall have no instructor, no
adviser, no pilot, but, trusted to my own devices, shall be left to make
every day blunders as egregious as I am told I made in the publication
of the Memoirs, where I consulted neither.[68]
Around the same time that Holcroft left, the husband of Godwinâs friend
of some years Maria Reveley died suddenly. Reveley was a highly
accomplished and intelligent woman, one of the few to ever impress
Godwinâs peer Jeremy Bentham (her late husband had designed Benthamâs
panopticon) and later a close friend of Godwinâs daughter Mary. She and
Godwin had a complicated relationship; Godwin believed that she was in
love with him. He proposed marriage within a month of her husbandâs
death, but his series of agonised letters (two in July, another in
August, and a last-ditch attempt in November) had no effect.
Figure 3 John Opieâs 1797 portrait of Wollstonecraft watched over Godwin
as he worked at the Polygon, and later at Skinner Street.
Throughout all this, Godwin continued to write. No longer needing a
separate working space, he hung a portrait of Wollstonecraft above his
desk in the study of the home they had rented together at the Polygon.
His next project was another novel, a work of historical fantasy that
explores ideas about family and responsibility. It took almost two years
of his life: he put pen to paper a month after finishing the Memoir (on
31 December, 1797) and finished at the end of November 1799. St Leon: A
Tale of the Sixteenth Century is by far Godwinâs longest novel. No doubt
drained by the upheavals within his circle of friends, the philosopher
found the work an exhausting undertaking. He wrote to George Robinson
(the publisher) in September 1799 to explain his delays saying that he
âmight have completed it three times over by this time, had I been less
scrupulousâ. [69] Famously, when asked by Byron years later why he did
not write another novel, Godwin replied that the effort would kill him.
ââAnd what matter,â said Lord Byron; âwe should have another St
Leon.ââ[70]
The novel is perhaps best known for its preface. Much like the
introductions to his other fictional works, Godwin comments on some of
the sources that inspired him, and makes the customary authorâs apology
to the reader who does not find the work to their taste. In the preface
to St Leon, however, the apology touches on Godwinâs philosophical
works:
Some readers of my graver productions will perhaps, in perusing these
little volumes, accuse me of inconsistency; the affections and charities
of private life being every where in this publication a topic of the
warmest eulogium, while in the Enquiry concerning Political Justice they
seemed to be treated with no great degree of indulgence and favour. In
answer to this objection, all I think it necessary to say on the present
occasion is, that, for more than four years, I have been anxious for
opportunity and leisure to modify some of the earlier chapters of that
work in conformity to the sentiments inculcated in this. Not that I see
cause to make any change respecting the principle of justice, or any
thing else fundamental to the system there delivered; but that I
apprehend domestic and private affections inseparable from the nature of
man, and from what may be styled the culture of the heart, and am fully
persuaded that they are not incompatible with a profound and active
sense of justiceâŠ
To philosophers who had kept up with Godwinâs work, this was only really
a strengthening of the language used in the revised Political Justice
and The Enquirer. Casual readers were somewhat more surprised. The novel
won unlikely plaudits from the Anti-Jacobin Review, who commended
Godwinâs change of heart (it did not save the philosopher from a parody
novel â St Godwin â that made a mocking apology for the absurdity of his
doctrines).
The titular St Leon is entrusted with the Philosopherâs Stone by a
mysterious traveller, on the condition that he keep its existence a
secret even from his wife and children. The stone grants its user
unlimited wealth and eternal youth, but the protagonist resolves to use
its power for philanthropy rather than merely gain. St Leonâs wealth
brings him suspicion and harassment wherever he goes, however, and the
secret alienates him from his family. The novelâs major themes are all
ideas that were likely at the forefront of Godwinâs mind at the end of
the decade: St Leonâs wife, Marguerite de Damville, is commonly taken as
a portrait of Wollstonecraft (Holcroft certainly thought so) but the
saintly Marguerite resembles Wollstonecraft only insomuch as Godwin
aimed to depict them both as exemplary women. Margueriteâs wisdom and
patience temper St Leonâs passion and recklessness, much as the
philosopher contrasts Wollstonecraftâs intuition with his own judgment,
but direct parallels between them are few. Nevertheless, companionship
and affection are explored throughout the novel with a complexity that
defies any attempt to read the text as a straightforward celebration of
the family. The novel also alludes to Godwinâs persecution by the
state-sponsored reactionary movement. For all his faults, St Leon
attempts to do good for humanity â yet his actions are misconstrued and
his motives questioned. Like the defendants of 1794, the protagonist is
imprisoned for hypothetical crimes (he cannot have arrived at his money
honestly, therefore he must be locked up while the crime is uncovered)
and his home in Italy is destroyed in an attack that deliberately
recalls the Priestley Riots of 1792. As a mob burns the familyâs villa,
St Leonâs friend the Marchese exclaims:
⊠no innocence, and no merit, could defend a man from the unrelenting
antipathy of his fellows. He saw that there was a principle in the human
mind destined to be eternally at war with improvement and science. No
sooner did a man devote himself to the pursuit of discoveries which, if
ascertained, would prove the highest benefit to his species, than his
whole species became armed against him. ⊠He saw, in the transactions of
that night, a pledge of the eternal triumph of ignorance over
wisdom.[71]
The philosopher himself was not so pessimistic.
Godwin was not entirely bound to his desk in the two years he devoted to
St Leon. In 1798 he spent a few weeks in Bath, then the great tourist
resort (and marriage market) of middle- and upper-class England. He
attracted the attention of fellow novelist Harriet Lee; after Godwin
returned home the two enjoyed weeks of philosophical correspondence.
Godwin proposed marriage, but Lee congenially rejected him, citing the
differences in their religious beliefs (Lee was a pious member of the
Church of England) and Godwinâs status as a controversial figure.
Ironically, Godwin would soon have cause to revise his thoughts on
religion in the light of a new friendship.
The philosopher had first met Samuel Taylor Coleridge at a dinner held
by Holcroft in 1794. Coleridge had not been impressed, telling Thelwall
that Godwin âtalked futile sophisms in jejune languageâ and attacking
Political Justice in his philosophical lectures.[72] Coleridge wrote
many years later that he had only half-understood Godwinâs work at the
time, and that the fervour of his criticism had been more about his own
ignorance than anything found in Godwinâs ideas.[73] The two met again
at the end of 1799 while Godwin was on an extended trip through the Home
Counties visiting, among others, Charles James Fox and Sir Francis
Burdett. Their reacquaintance was evidently successful for, when Godwin
returned to London, Coleridge called at the Polygon (or otherwise
engaged him) regularly until Coleridge left London in April 1800.
Coleridge had gravitated from an orthodox Anglican upbringing to
Unitarianism in his early twenties, in part influenced by the scholar
William Frend.[74] Their discussions prompted Godwin to re-examine his
own beliefs:
I ceased to regard the name of Atheist with the same complacency I had
done for several preceding years, at the same time retaining the utmost
repugnance of understanding for the idea of an intelligent Creator and
Governor of the universe, which strikes my mind as the most irrational
and ridiculous anthropomorphism. My theism, if such I may be permitted
to call it, consists in a reverent and soothing contemplation of all
that is beautiful, grand, or mysterious in the system of the universe
âŠ[75]
Unitarianism, at its core, is a theological movement that denies the
mainstream Christian doctrine of the Holy Trinity â something that
remained an offence under English law until 1810. Unitarians consider
Jesus to have been a great prophet, but not God Incarnate. Many
Unitarians also reject ideas such as original sin or eternal damnation,
concepts that Godwin was himself critical of. The position that Godwin
describes in his thoughts above suggests a form of Pantheism, the belief
that divinity is found in all things, though the philosopherâs
discussion of this in the unfinished Genius of Christianity Unveiled
(written around 1835) describes a broader, only semi-religious, awe for
nature in its totality. Godwin sees nature as a system of mutually
supporting life underpinned by physical laws, something worthy of
admiration but beyond our ability to fully understand. We can (and
should) observe and record the operations of nature to better understand
them, but the origins of the universe are beyond human comprehension.
Godwin obviously rejects the idea of an intelligent creator, and
possibly the idea of spirit or divinity more generally, but neither is
he purely a materialist. The philosopher was gradually moving towards
this position from his first acquaintance with Coleridge to his final
years, as hinted in his subsequent writing on Greek myth (The Pantheon,
1806) and his unpublished essay âOf Religionâ (1818).
Coleridgeâs own religious views would change further over the years,
abandoning Unitarianism around 1805 in favour of an increasingly
complicated (but theoretically Trinitarian) theology influenced by
Spinoza, Schelling and Kant. Godwin found Coleridgeâs conversation
fascinating, and tolerated the younger manâs high-handedness and
inconsistency in return for their many discussions of philosophy,
religion and language. Godwin considered Coleridge the last of his four
âoral instructorsâ alongside Fawcett, Holcroft and George Dyson.
Coleridge introduced Godwin to Charles Lamb, then a young clerk for the
East India Company and occasional poet, but eventually to become one of
the most highly regarded essayists of the period. Like Coleridge, Lamb
was quickly converted from a critic of Godwin to a friend, writing to
another recent acquaintance, Thomas Manning that Godwin was âa
well-behaved decent manâ:
⊠nothing very brilliant about him or imposing as you might suppose;
quite another Guess sort of Gentleman from what your Anti Jacobins
Christians imagine himâ. I was well pleased to find he has neither horns
nor claws, quite a tame creature I assure you.[76]
Lamb had strong Unitarian sympathies, and some of his writing before
meeting Godwin suggests that, like many, Lamb thought that Political
Justice had put reason in Godâs place.[77] There is a certain truth to
this, as the first edition discusses reasoning and truth in the same
language that Godwinâs Dissenting forbears might have used to describe
faith and revelation. Perhaps expecting a de-Christianising Robespierre,
Lamb seems to have been disarmed by Godwinâs placidity and dry humour:
Lamb and his friend Charles Lloyd had been grotesqued in Gillrayâs âNew
Moralityâ cartoon alongside Godwin; when Lamb grew argumentative at
their first meeting, Godwin quietly asked him if he was the toad or the
frog. Lambâs answer is not recorded, but since he and Godwin met again
for breakfast the next day, he might have been amused.[78]
Godwinâs third major new friend in these years was William Hazlitt.
Hazlitt was over twenty years Godwinâs junior but the two had much in
common â both the sons of Dissenting ministers (Hazlittâs father had
preached at Wisbech after the Godwins had left in 1758), who were
educated at Dissenting Academies (by Andrew Kippis), but who ultimately
rejected Christianity in adult life. Hazlitt first met Godwin as a
student in 1794, probably through Holcroft, but the two began to meet
regularly when Hazlitt returned to London in early 1799. Though Hazlitt
was, at this time, training to become a painter under the tutelage of
his elder brother, he harboured the ambition to write. He would develop
into a formidable essayist and critic, and it was with Godwinâs help
that he would publish his first major work (An Essay on the Principles
of Human Action) in 1805.
All three of Godwinâs new friends seethed protectively at Mackintoshâs
lectures. Lamb called the lawyer Judas, though noted that at least the
Biblical betrayer had been decent enough to hang himself.[79] Perhaps
Mackintosh had felt some remorse: he had, after all, sent Godwin advance
warning of his assault and was quick to insist that he meant the
philosopher no ill will. Samuel Parrâs very public defection in April
1800 was another matter entirely.
Parr had, as an Anglican minister renowned for his learning, been asked
to give an Easter sermon before the Lord Mayor of London and the
governors of the Royal Hospital. Like Mackintosh, Parr took the
opportunity to denounce the âNew Philosophyâ and laud the status quo.
The idea of âuniversal philanthropyâ was dangerous, Parr argued, as it
steered the efforts of virtuous people away from helping those closest
to them. âThe community of mankindâ, Parr said, was a ârhetorical
ornamentâ and, while it was moral to help those in need regardless of
differences in culture or religion, it required too great an effort for
all but the most virtuous.[80] Parr argued that Christianity did not
confuse compassion with justice â the proper object of our benevolence
is the people that love us. Philanthropy, Parr implies, is best left to
those who have the means to help the least fortunate without diluting
what they provided to their nearest and dearest (i.e. men such as his
audience).
Godwin heard about the sermon second-hand and went in search of an
explanation. He called on 19 April, but Parr excused himself by saying
he was on his way out. When Godwin tried to call again on the 24^(th),
he was told that Parr was not in London. The philosopher wrote a proud
but wounded letter requesting some justification for Parrâs attack. Parr
had not replied to his letter about Mackintosh some months earlier, nor
to the copy of St Leon that Godwin had sent after it:
If however both my letter & my visits would have passed unnoticed, I am
entitled to conclude that you have altered your mind respecting me. In
that case, I should be glad you would answer to your own satisfaction,
what crime I am chargeable with, now in 1800, of which I had not been
guilty in 1794, when with so much kindness & zeal you sought my
acquaintance.[81]
Parr wrote a substantial answer a few days later. The letter praised
Mackintoshâs high character and called Godwinâs complaints offensive (he
claimed to have lost the philosopherâs earlier letter). He denied that
he had ever sought Godwinâs company, referring to his former politeness
as merely a dutiful respect to the philosopherâs intellect (this was
disingenuous; Parr said in a letter of September 1794 that he was
âambitious of [Godwinâs] friendshipâ).[82] He claimed to have read only
the preface of St Leon, and felt no curiosity to proceed further. Parr
wrote that he had been displeased by The Enquirerâs comments on
religion, shocked by the Memoir, and claimed that Godwinâs philosophy
had been a pernicious influence on the character of âtwo or three young
men, whose talents I esteemed, and whose virtues I lovedâ.[83] The
letter was clear that Parr did not wish to hear from the philosopher
again. The philosopher began a reply regardless, but does not appear to
have finished it. Godwin wrote that he felt âthe most pungent grief in
witnessing your disgrace; but since it must be so, I am well satisfied
to possess this evidence âŠâ[84] Parr returned his copy of St Leon in
October, with a formal â third-person â note that sought to imply that
he had not read it, though his family had. The matter might have ended
there, much as it had with Mackintosh, but Parr published his sermon in
early 1801 â including extensive notes (some five times the length of
the sermon itself) that quoted Godwin repeatedly and made it explicit
that the philosopher was the target of Parrâs criticism. The notes
reproduced a lengthy section of the preface to St Leon, commending
Godwinâs âmaturer reflectionâ and âcontritionâ but declaring that this
concession (Parr magnanimously refuses to call it such) undermines the
entirety of Godwinâs concept of justice.[85]
Godwin hit back with his own pamphlet a few months later. The Reply to
Parr began with the complaint that its author had endured a torrent âof
ribaldry, invective and intoleranceâ since the popular climate had
turned against the French Revolution and the cause of freedom.[86]
Stressing how widely Political Justice was praised upon its first
publication, Godwin asserts that the floodgates opened in mid-1797 â a
trickle of âtwo little skirmishing pamphletsâ quickly becoming a flood
of âscurrilitiesâ and âvulgar contumeliesâ in the anti-Jacobin press,
with Parrâs sermon bringing up the rear.[87] The philosopher names many
of the writers and works he feels have wronged him but specifically
exempts Malthus and the Essay for what Godwin saw as that workâs
respectable, collegial spirit. The philosopher insists that he had done
nothing more than advance peaceful ideas with intellectual humility:
I wrote my Enquiry Concerning Political Justice in the innocence of my
heart. I sought no overt effects; I abhorred all tumult; I entered my
protest against revolutions. Every impartial person who knows me, or has
attentively considered my writings, will acknowledge that it is the
fault of my character, rather to be too sceptical, than to incline too
much to play the dogmatist. I was by no means assured of the truth of my
own system. I wrote indeed with ardour; but I published with diffidence.
I knew that my speculations had led me out of the beaten track; and I
waited to be instructed by the comment of others as to the degree of
value which should be stamped upon them. That comment in the first
instance was highly flattering; yet I was not satisfied. I did not cease
to revise, to reconsider, or to enquire.[88]
Godwin (quite reasonably) felt that his ideas had been misrepresented.
He accused Mackintosh of calling him bloodthirsty and alleged that the
lawyer had avoided naming him only to sidestep the boundaries of decency
in his abuse. Of Parr, the philosopher is scathing: there is a rare note
of contempt in how Godwin describes the tardiness of Parrâs attack (âhe
has condescended to join a cry, after it had already become loud and
numerousâ).[89] The rest of essay seeks to clarify and defend Political
Justice, beginning with the philosopherâs revised position on the
domestic affections. Following Parr, Godwin quotes from the preface to
St Leon (âthough, from some cause, he [Parr] has not specified the book
from which the quotation is takenâ).[90] The philosopher sees no reason
why acknowledging the value of domestic affection should in any way
jeopardise the rest of his treatise â if it is our duty to create as
much good as we can, then doing good for those closest to us is
frequently the most effective use of our time. Godwin argues that most
of the actual differences between his position and Parrâs are matters of
emphasis: both agree that domestic benevolence is easy and universal
benevolence is hard, but while Parr holds the position that benevolence
outside our immediate circle should not be entered into without
prudence, Godwin argues that it is domestic benevolence that stands in
need of regulation (essentially, that we should not spoil our families
while others stand in need). The philosopher goes on to clarify his use
of the term âperfectibilityâ, âwhat I would now wish to call, changing
the term, without changing a particle of the meaning, the progressive
nature of man, in knowledge, in virtuous propensities, and in social
institutionsâ.[91] What follows is Godwinâs most pointed statement about
his own optimism. Normally conciliatory in reference to principled
conservatism (he refers to it in The Enquirer as a reluctance to gamble
existing achievements for new ones), the philosopher recognises in his
opponents an irreconcilable difference in their understanding of basic
human nature:
I know that Dr Parr and Mr Mackintosh look with horror upon this
doctrine of the progressive nature of man. They cling with all the
fervours of affection, to the opinion that vices, the weaknesses and the
follies which have hitherto existed in our species, will continue
undiminished as long as the earth shall endure. I do not envy them their
feelings. I love to contemplate the yet unexpanded powers and
capabilities of our nature, and to believe that they will one day be
unfolded to the infinite advantage and happiness of the inhabitants of
the globe. Long habit has so trained me to bow to the manifestations of
truth wherever I recognize them, that, if arguments were presented to me
sufficient to establish the uncomfortable doctrine of my antagonists, I
would weigh, I would revolve them, and I hope I should not fail to
submit to their authority. But, if my own doctrine is an error, and if I
am fated to die in it, I cannot afflict myself greatly with the
apprehension of a mistake, which cheers my solitude, which I carry with
me into crowds, and which adds somewhat to the pleasure and peace of
every day of my existence.[92]
The Reply continues this theme in response to Malthus, observing that
the economistâs conclusions (that inequality and suffering are
inevitable consequences of population growth) are easily turned to
conservative ends; indeed, âthe advocates of old establishments and old
abusesâ â Godwin uses this phrase to describe Parr elsewhere in the
essay â âcould not have found a doctrine, more to their hearts content,
more effectual to shut out all reform and improvement for everâ.[93] Yet
Godwinâs answer to Malthus was good-natured, suggesting that their
conversations in person had convinced him that they were colleagues in
solving the problem of population rather than scholarly rivals. Godwin
declared himself to be in agreement with the economistâs central theory
(that population multiplied until checked by the limits of subsistence)
but argued that its conclusions could be overcome â implicitly that the
gradual improvement of private judgment included the consideration of
sustainable population growth. Unwisely, Godwin discussed how societies
had historically taken steps to actively curb population growth,
principally through exposing unwanted babies to the elements. Though the
philosopher had only described (not advocated) such practices, his usual
detractors leapt upon this as further evidence of his monstrous,
Spartan, logic and Godwin felt the need to send an appalled letter to
the Monthly Magazine to protest his misrepresentation.[94]
The Reply to Parr is learned, passionate and, at times, waspishly
amusing. Responses were mixed, though many concurred that Godwin had
been treated poorly by his critics. The reactionary press was
undeterred, the British Critic asserting that the philosopher had got
off lightly (as such controversial opinions would have seen him
guillotined in France). The pamphlet definitely made an impact with
Malthus, however. The economist called on Godwin when he was next in
London a few months later. The second edition of the Essay on Population
features a short chapter responding to Godwinâs comments in the Reply,
agreeing that it was possible for individuals to reason themselves out
of procreating (carrying out a moral duty to not increase the population
unsustainably) but declaring that âMr. Godwinâs system of political
justiceâ was not conducive to its wide adoption.[95]
In the midst of all these controversies Godwin continued to write. In
concert with the ever-lengthening St Leon, Godwin had been working on
another play. In one respect, the theatre represented the opportunity to
make money â a successful play offered a source of continual revenue
rather than a one-off payment (as he would usually earn for a novel). In
another, perhaps more important, fashion the stage offered a wider
audience for Godwinâs ideas. Caleb Williams (by far the philosopherâs
greatest success) was by this time on its third edition in five years,
and had no doubt reached many thousands of readers, but Londonâs two
patent theatres (Drury Lane and Covent Garden) sold in excess of 10,000
tickets a week between them.[96] A play could reach a wider spectrum of
society than a novel, too, from the servants and sailors in the upper
gallery to the fashionable ladies and gentlemen in the boxes â new
novels were (relatively) expensive, and many avid readers relied on
subscription libraries to feed their interests.[97]
Godwinâs new play had been through several titles and, since finishing
the initial draft, had been passed through several friends in search of
feedback. Holcroft had read the play before departing for Europe, with
Godwin providing a set of guidelines for how his friend might phrase his
usual punishing criticism (Holcroft ignored it). Godwin read Coleridgeâs
verse tragedy Osorio, which bore a number of similarities to his own
play. Sheridan, who owned Drury Lane, had offered to stage Godwinâs
piece after an early glance at the manuscript in April 1799, but nothing
initially came of this. Godwin tried again, submitting it anonymously to
George Colman at the Haymarket Theatre (who had adapted Caleb Williams
for the stage as The Iron Chest, without the philosopherâs input) only
to have it rejected. Godwin spent the summer of 1800 in Ireland as the
guest of the Irish MP John Philpot Curran, where he was able to meet
Wollstonecraftâs onetime pupil, Lady Mountcashell. On his return he
tried Sheridan again, who passed him on to the great actor-manager of
the Theatre Royal, John Phillip Kemble, who accepted the play â but
quickly learned to regret it.
Antonio, or The Soldierâs Return is a verse tragedy that draws on
Elizabethan and Jacobean styles of drama. The titular protagonist
returns home from the wars to find that his sister has married against
his wishes, jilting his brave friend to whom she was betrothed. He
kidnaps her in a bid to salvage what he perceives as his familyâs honour
but is foiled by his sisterâs husband. The play concludes with Antonio
murdering his sister rather than allowing her to remain married. At a
time when the most successful plays leaned heavily on spectacle
(parades, costumes, action), Godwinâs piece relies on its poetry to make
the drama. The play seems constructed to make the audience listen and
think â as in any proper tragedy, each character has their own valid
complaints against the others, and the play does its best not to
distract from those arguments being heard. Antonio reflects Godwinâs
concerns about debate and rhetoric: each character is allowed to make
their case, and their opponents a rebuttal, the play does not permit any
one actor to sweep the audience along with them and dictate how the
story will be received. For all this seems intellectually sound, it
makes terrible theatre.
Kemble had reservations almost immediately but pestering from Godwin,
and implicit orders from Sheridan, persuaded Kemble both to produce and
take the lead role. The famous Sarah Siddons (who had been one of those
who dropped Wollstonecraft after her marriage to Godwin) played
Antonioâs sister, Helena. Afraid that the play would receive brickbats
just for having his name attached to it, Godwin asked the playwright
John Tobin to pose as the author. The philosopher was gratingly
confident, soliciting advice on what his share of the profits should be
and planning out how he would spend the money (on more books, according
to Lamb). Kemble twisted in an attempt to get out of the part, but to no
avail. The playâs sole performance (on 13 December 1800) was a disaster,
the night captured memorably in a later essay by Lamb:
Great expectations were formed. A philosopherâs first new play was a new
era. The night arrived. I was favoured with a seat in an advantageous
box, between the author and his friend Mâ. G. sate cheerful and
confident. In his friend M.âs looks, who had perused the manuscript, I
read some terror. Antonio in the person of John Philip Kemble at length
appeared, starched out in a ruff which no one could dispute, and in most
irreproachable mustachios. John always dressed most provokingly correct
on these occasions. The first act swept by, solemn and silent. It went
off, as G. assured M., exactly as the opening act of a piece â the
protasis â should do. The cue of the spectators was to be mute. ⊠The
second act (as in duty bound) rose a little in interest; but still John
kept his forces under â in policy, as G. would have it â and the
audience were most complacently attentive. The protasis, in fact, was
scarcely unfolded. The interest would warm in the next act, against
which a special incident was provided. M. wiped his cheek, flushed with
a friendly perspiration â âtis M.âs way of showing his zeal â âfrom
every pore of him a perfume falls ââ. I honour it above Alexanderâs. He
had once or twice during this act joined his palms in a feeble endeavour
to elicit a sound â they emitted a solitary noise without an echo â
there was no deep to answer to his deep. G. repeatedly begged him to be
quiet. ⊠A challenge was held forth upon the stage, and there was
promise of a fight. The pit roused themselves on this extraordinary
occasion, and, as their manner is, seemed disposed to make a ring, â
when suddenly Antonio, who was the challenged, turning the tables on the
hot challenger, Don Gusman (who by the way should have had his sister)
baulks his humour, and the pitâs reasonable expectation at the same
time, with some speeches out of the new philosophy against duelling. The
audience were here fairly caught â their courage was up, and on the
alert â a few blows, ding dong, as Râs the dramatist afterwards
expressed it to me, might have done the business â when their most
exquisite moral sense was suddenly called in to assist in the mortifying
negation of their own pleasure. They could not applaud, for
disappointment; they would not condemn, for moralityâs sake. The
interest stood stone still; and Johnâs manner was not at all calculated
to unpetrify it. It was Christmas time, and the atmosphere furnished
some pretext for asthmatic affections. One began to cough â his
neighbour sympathised with him â till a cough became epidemical.[98]
Reviews were universally negative. The London Chronicle, attempting some
consolation, suggested that it would make a reasonable closet drama
(i.e. a play to be read, not performed). Godwin enlisted Lambâs help in
revising the play once more and published it on 23 December. The reviews
were no better. The philosopher was not discouraged. At the suggestion
of Coleridge, he quickly began work on a new tragedy, Abbas, King of
Persia. He finished the first draft by April 1801 and sent the
manuscript off to his friend in the Lake District. Coleridge dragged his
feet in replying. He eventually confessed that his first round of
criticism had been irreverent and hurtful, and wrote that he had held
off returning the play to Godwin until he had revised his observations.
The notes Coleridge eventually dispatched were still far from gentle,
recommending an extensive rewrite and identifying every point in the
play the poet considered clichéd, flat, or vulgar. Godwin took his
friendâs criticism seriously, returning to the play directly and
continuing to revise the play even after he had submitted it to Thomas
Harris at Covent Garden at the end of August. This proved unsuccessful
and the play was submitted anonymously to Drury Lane for consideration
in September. Abbas shows Godwin making certain concessions to the
theatre arts: the play makes use of spectacle, but also criticises it.
From his letters to Coleridge it is clear that the use of such
techniques troubled him, that he feared pandering to the audienceâs
expectations would damage the play as a literary creation. The play was
potentially controversial, using the Sunni/Shiâa schism to discuss
religious conflict in a way that had obvious implications for
Protestant/Catholic strife in Ireland. In other aspects, the play
reflected the longstanding political conflict between the King (a
steadfast conservative) and the Prince of Wales (no radical, but an ally
of Fox and Sheridan). Sadly for Godwin, his concerns were academic:
Abbas was quickly rejected by both Covent Garden and Drury Lane. He
complained to Kemble. Over-stepping the mark in his assessment of his
own talent as a dramatist (âI think it scarcely fair that I should come
before them as an unknown noviceâŠâ), he received a brusque reply. Godwin
attempted to badger Kemble into accepting the play, begging for his
input on how to improve it. He wrote to Sheridan in the hope that the MP
would lean on his employee. It had no obvious effect. Kembleâs replies
were irate rather than hostile, but his rejection was emphatic,
repeating several times that he would reappraise the work if it was
revised, but not until then. This at least gave Godwin pause, and he
would not return to dramatic writing until a few years had passed; after
the first draft of Abbas he turned to writing the Reply to Parr. Also in
the offing was a proposed biography of Chaucer, but he was unable to
attend to that seriously until the end of the year. Events that year
would lead to a change in the philosopherâs living arrangements,
however, and a new focus for his ideas.
Godwinâs diary records âMeet Mrs Clairmontâ on 5 May 1801. Mary Jane
Clairmont was a neighbour at the Polygon with children of a similar age
to Godwinâs own. He visited her often, sometimes with the children and
sometimes without. The diary implies that they became lovers in July (it
reads âtea Clairmonts Xâ) but kept matters confidential. Much of what we
know about Mary Jane is second hand. She did not write daily notes to
Godwin, as Wollstonecraft had, and some of the letters she did write to
him are lost. Although an author in her own right, none of her works
have the vibrantly personal touch that we see in the rest of the
familyâs writing. She kept her past private. She spent some of her
childhood in France and fled to Spain during the revolution. She told
her children that their father had been a Swiss merchant known as Karl
Gaulis (which he later Anglicised to âClairmontâ) who had died in
Hamburg in 1798. Twentieth century research casts some doubt on this â
Gaulis appears to have died in Silesia in 1796, making it unlikely that
he was the father of Maryâs daughter Jane (born April 1798). In 2011,
genealogist Vicki Parslow Stafford was able to identify that Jane was
the illegitimate daughter of Sir John Lethbridge (a West Country
landowner), who provided occasional financial support for his daughter
until 1814.[99] Godwin knew she was not a widow, as she claimed to
others (she had been born Mary Vial, and the couple were married under
that name in 1802).[100] Many of the stories about their courtship are
apocryphal, dating from after the death of both, but legend has it that
Clairmont was the hunter: she flattered the philosopher extravagantly
and engineered opportunities for him to overhear her pining for him.
Godwinâs vanity and Clairmontâs later reputation for dishonesty give
credence to the stories, but our portrait of Clairmont owes much to
unflattering sources â Lamb found their affair ridiculous (he wrote in
September 1801, âthe Professor is grown quite juvenileâ) and rarely
missed the opportunity to mock her in his letters. Her soon-to-be
stepdaughter, the future Mary Shelley, would come to hate her.
In October 1801, Clairmont found herself pregnant with Godwinâs child.
The couple were married on 21 December â twice. Clairmont and Godwin
held a small ceremony in Shoreditch in the morning, with Marshall
(again) as witness, before proceeding to a second wedding in Whitechapel
the same day. The first records the marriage of Mary Clairmont, widow;
the second, Mary Vial, spinster. The exact reason for the second wedding
is unclear, but biographers have speculated that Clairmont sought a
degree of insurance to prevent the marriage being struck down if the
false statement of the first wedding (i.e. that she was a widow) was
ever uncovered. Godwin did not note the second occasion in his diary. It
is unclear as to when the baby was born, the philosopher does not record
it in his diary, but the child (a boy, William) did not survive long:
Godwin marks his death on 4 June. Clairmont was soon pregnant again and,
on 28 March 1803, delivered another baby boy â William Godwin Junior.
The Godwins were now an extensive clan: William, Mary Jane, Fanny (now
nine), Mary Janeâs son Charles (seven), Mary (five), Jane (later called
Claire, then aged four) and newborn William Junior.
The greatly expanded family was desperately short of money. The failure
of Antonio had already driven Godwin to write what he openly called
âbegging lettersâ to his richer friends.[101] He was finding it harder
to find work. Godwinâs regular publisher George Robinson died in 1801.
Clairmont spoke excellent French and German and turned this into
translation work, while preparing childrenâs books for the publisher
Benjamin Tabart. Inspired by Thomas Tyrwhittâs 1798 edition of the
Canterbury Tales, Godwin proposed a biography of Chaucer to the
up-andcoming publisher Richard Phillips. Phillips offered a contract
within days, perhaps thanks to an antiquarian interest of his own
(Phillips accompanied Godwin on a trip to visit the âChaucer houseâ at
Woodstock; the philosopher wrote to Clairmont of how dull the publisher
was on his own).[102]
More than simply a biography, the Life of Chaucer is a wide-ranging
cultural history of fourteenth-century England. The philosopher
researched deeply, with âalmost daily attendance at the British Museumâ
and venturing out of London to consult records in the Bodleian Library
and the Chaucer manuscripts held at Gonville and Caius College,
Cambridge.[103] Godwin sought to explore the world that had made the
poet, and throughout the work stresses the depth of feeling and
sentiment in Chaucerâs character to explain the quality and timelessness
of his poetry. The work contains a close reading of Chaucerâs
lesser-known works, searching for insight into the character of the poet
and placing him in context alongside the other greats of medieval verse.
The philosopher worked on his history doggedly for two whole years. The
Life of Chaucer is a mammoth work, and Godwinâs preface implies that the
philosopher was reined in by his publisher before he considered the book
complete. It is best known for its iconic statement about literature and
truth: commending Chaucerâs decision to abandon the legal profession,
Godwin opined that the sophistry that the law required would sit
uneasily with literary genius.
Above all, the poet, whose judgment should be clear, whose feelings
should be uniform and sound, whose sense should be alive to every
impression and hardened to none, who is the legislator of generations
and the moral instructor of the world, ought never to have been a
practising lawyer, or ought speedily to have quitted so dangerous an
engagement.[104]
The job of the literary artist was to keep a mind open to new
experiences and to grow the imagination. Godwin worked on the Life of
Chaucer alongside Bible Stories for Tabart. The preface of the latter
expands upon the hints expressed in the history â the development of the
imagination is not only the domain of literary genius, but an essential
part of the human mind.
Imagination is the ground-plot upon which the edifice of a sound
morality must be erected. Without imagination we may have a certain cold
and arid circle of principles, but we cannot have sentiments: we may
learn by rote a catalogue of rules, and repeat our lesson with the
exactness of a parrot, or play over our tricks with the docility of a
monkey; but we can neither ourselves love, nor be fitted to excite the
love of others.[105]
Godwin claimed that contemporary childrenâs books gave nothing to the
soul, perhaps teaching âpracticalâ lessons about the world, or simply
recommending obedience and piety, but not encouraging young people to
think about anything beyond the world immediately around them. The
intellectual and moral improvement of humanity â the central theme of
all Godwinâs philosophical works â requires that people be able to see
beyond âthings as they areâ. Implicit in all of Godwinâs writing is the
sense that a better world must be imagined before it can become
possible. More essentially, however, Godwin argues that we cannot
develop the capacity for critical moral reason without the ability to
imagine what others feel (i.e. empathy or sympathy). Godwin had been
edging towards a theory of how to develop this ever since he published
his Account of the Seminary in 1783. The answer lay in reading.
Continuing the line of thought he had advanced in The Enquirer, Godwin
argued here that reading was vital to allow people the experience of
imagining things that we cannot see, be they the thoughts of other
people or ideas that do not yet exist.
In the spring of 1804, Godwin began work on his third major novel:
Fleetwood; or, the New Man of Feeling. In Fleetwood, the philosopher
took on Rousseau. Fleetwood is a novel about education, but more
precisely it is a novel about the relationships between a learner and
his mentors and how a certain kind of education leaves an individual
ill-equipped to become a mentor themselves. Casimir Fleetwoodâs early
education is one of indulgence. As a boy he is allowed to roam freely
and explore the natural world. What formal education Casimir is given
comes from a private tutor whom he finds ridiculous, and no greater
scholarship is expected from him than that which he chooses to put his
mind to. We can easily draw comparisons between this and Emileâs
semi-pastoral education, but Godwin read Rousseau closely â Fleetwoodâs
narrative of his own early education is closer to the âreceivedâ account
of Rousseauâs system put forward by period commentators. Fleetwoodâs
real education comes at the hands of his mentors who, like Rousseauâs
preceptor, provide experiential moral lessons that shape the way he sees
the world. Albeit with the best of intentions, Fleetwoodâs mentors
manipulate him emotionally (winning his confidence with illiberal means,
as The Enquirer put it) in order to make him receptive to the teachings
they wish to impart. Fleetwood grows into an adult who knows how to
feel, but not how to reason.
Fleetwood is, in style, a confession narrative. As in Godwinâs other
novels the philosopher uses the first person to convey the protagonistâs
emotional turmoil, here culminating in a bizarre and gothic nervous
breakdown. Indeed, at various points in the novel we see hints of the
philosopherâs sense of the strange or absurd. Where Fleetwood differed
from the philosopherâs previous works was in Godwinâs assertion (in the
preface) that his narrator was a normal man, and that âat least one half
of the Englishmen now existing, who are of the same rank of life as my
heroâ, had experienced similar.[106] The philosopher goes on to imply
that his protagonistâs ultimate reaction to these mundane events is
exceptional but, predictably, Godwinâs critics took it as an attempt to
defame Englishmen everywhere. The Anti-Jacobin Review descended into an
ugly tirade against the late Wollstonecraft (though it must be said that
Godwin had mischievously named the novelâs only genuine villain after
the magazineâs editor). More seriously, the novel caused a breach with
Holcroft. Out of the blue, he sent a confused letter to Godwin:
I write to inform you that instead of seeing you at dinner tomorrow I
desire to never see you more, being determined never to have any further
intercourse with you of any kind.
T. Holcroft
Feb. 28, 1785.
P.S. I shall behave as becomes an honest and honourable man who
remembers not only what is due to others but himself. There are
indelible injuries that will not endure to be mentioned: such is the one
you have committed on the man who would have died to serve you.[107]
Godwin was mystified and had to ask Clairmont (who had seen Holcroft
that day) what offence he had given. Fleetwoodâs Mr Scarborough to some
extent represents the opposite extreme to the protagonistâs Rousseauvian
upbringing: drilling his son relentlessly, and always requiring
perfection, the son falls into a spiral of depression and dies.
Holcroftâs own son had committed suicide in 1789, and he read
Scarborough as an indictment of his parenting. Ironically, the
philosopher had partly based the character on himself. He wrote to
Marshall that Scarborough recalled his own failure as a mentor to Tom
Cooper, and that there was no connection to Holcroft at all (he reported
that he had solicited the opinions of at least twenty others, of whom
none had seen any parallel with Holcroft). Godwin made some effort to
explain matters to his friend, but to no avail. He wrote to Holcroft on
3 March that he would think of him as a dear friend who had died, rather
than remember his abrupt and irrational desertion. They would not speak
as friends for four years.
The critical response to Fleetwood was relatively lukewarm, and sales
did not approach those of Caleb Williams or St Leon (Phillips printed
nearly two thousand copies in his first run â a statement of remarkable
confidence in Godwinâs âdrawâ as a novelist â but a second printing was
not ordered until the copyright changed hands more than twenty-five
years later). It perhaps became clear that literature was not an
effective method of supporting a large family. Godwin proposed a
comprehensive history of England to Phillips and began work on it
shortly after Fleetwood was published. It was never completed. Though we
are not party to whatever discussions the couple had, Godwinâs
biographers have assumed that it was Clairmont that proposed the family
go into publishing for themselves. Mary Jane had worked on the editorial
side of childrenâs publishing for some years now, and probably had a
solid understanding of what the business required. Godwin borrowed more
money from the (now dying) Wedgwood, ostensibly to rectify his cash-flow
problems, and rented a house and shop on Hanway Street, allowing them to
retail books directly. Godwin would write, Clairmont would prepare the
work for printing, and an employee by the name of Thomas Hodgkins would
manage the shop. As with Bible Stories, Godwin was concerned that his
name would attract bad press, perhaps dooming the business from the
start. Their initial solution was to establish the venture in Hodgkinsâs
name (as the âJuvenile Libraryâ), and to publish Godwinâs writing under
a series of pseudonyms. Godwin also approached Lamb to write for them.
Childrenâs publishing combined Godwinâs financial needs with his
philosophical ones. The market for childrenâs books was not necessarily
a lucrative one, but it was consistent. Schools placed large orders and
demand was perennial, Godwin could attract investors with projected
returns rather than merely asking his friends for credit. More
importantly, childrenâs publishing allowed Godwin to put his educational
philosophy into practice. The philosopher could take his ideas to the
next generation of readers. He could even claim that his theories gave
the proposed Juvenile Library a distinctive place in the market â if
other childrenâs authors were offering mundane stories, he would provide
fantastic ones; where other childrenâs authors would provide role models
for children, he would encourage them to question who they wanted to be.
The books the Juvenile Library published in its first year exemplified
this. Written under the name âEdward Baldwinâ, Fables, Ancient and
Modern was Godwinâs adaptation of Aesop â a collection of short tales,
with each offering some lesson about morality or self-knowledge. Where
Godwinâs Fables differed was in the nature of the lesson.
Eighteenth-century versions of Aesop usually featured an explicit
âmoralâ; Samuel Croxallâs 1722 Fables of Aesop (which Godwin drew on for
his edition) sometimes adds a moral three or four times as long as the
fable itself. Godwinâs fables offer no explicit moral at all. While the
inference we are supposed to draw from some stories is clear, the
philosopher rarely seeks to dictate it. More often, the philosopher
engages the reader to ask what they might have done in the protagonistâs
position. Most interestingly, Godwin sometimes adjusts the details of
well-known fables so as to open them up for debate. The fable of the
farmer and the viper (in Godwin, âThe Good-Natured Man and the Adderâ)
is supposedly the origin of the phrase âto nurse a snake in oneâs bosomâ
and is commonly given the moral that some individuals are never worthy
of beneficence, or that it is in the nature of some to always do harm.
Croxall criticises the farmer in this example for showing benevolence to
an improper object. By contrast, Godwin has a neighbour (who has
previously benefitted from the farmerâs generosity) step in to save his
protagonist. The philosopher ends by seeming to impose a reading on the
fable, before undermining it with a note of scepticism about the story
as a whole:
The good-natured man learned a wise lesson from this adventure: he saw
how much mischief he had nearly brought upon himself by a kindness that
paid no attention to the different qualities of living creatures; but
then he saw that the life of his child had been saved by a person, to
whom he had once acted generously, without acting imprudently.
The only thing that puzzles me in this story is the behaviour of the
adder. It is contrary to the nature of all animals; for I have found it
almost an universal rule, that no creature will harm you, if you have
not first done that creature harm.[108]
The authorial voice in the Fables is affectionate and informal, as if
the stories were told to children at their fatherâs knee. Godwinâs son
Charles (then nine) is even addressed in the text. Some years earlier
Coleridge had written to Southey of the âcadaverous Silence of Godwinâs
childrenâ, which some have taken to indicate that the philosopher was a
strict or distant father, but this does not seem to tally with the
obvious warmth of Godwin as a childrenâs author.[109]
The second publication of 1805 was even less traditional. The Looking
Glass is a biography for children, the life story of Godwinâs friend and
illustrator William Mulready (at the time, still a teenager himself).
Rather than presenting a finished life of great deeds, Godwin (writing
as âTheophilius Marcliffeâ) tells how Mulreadyâs childhood shaped him
into a dedicated and hardworking artist. Although the work celebrates
its subjectâs determination and self-reliance, the story does not
diminish the support Mulready received from parents and mentors on his
journey. The artist is â realistically â shown to be a product of both
nature and nurture, in contrast to fictional childrenâs role models who
succeeded through innate reserves of selflessness, industry, or wisdom.
The book claims no such heroic qualities for its subject, attributing
his success to a simple love for his vocation â which, as the title
implies, is a virtue that the reader can look for within themselves.
The Juvenile Library struggled from the beginning. Perhaps not fully
understanding the undertaking before him Godwin had only borrowed ÂŁ100
from Wedgwood, money which quickly disappeared in the renting and
outfitting of the shop. The work they published was good, many remaining
in print long after the company went out of business and some still
regarded as classics of childrenâs literature: it was the Juvenile
Library that first published Charles and Mary Lambâs Tales from
Shakespeare (1807), and the first translation of Johann Wyssâs Swiss
Family Robinson (by Mary Jane Clairmont, 1814). Godwinâs pseudonyms were
apparently successful, his books receiving favourable notices in
conservative journals. Wedgwood died in July 1805, leaving Godwin
without a reliable financial backer. The philosopher borrowed heavily to
keep the shop afloat, but also used his own (still good) credit to help
those in greater need â letters show that around this time Godwin
borrowed money to bail his friend, the scientist William Nicholson, who
had been imprisoned for debt. The philosopherâs finances very quickly
became a tangled mess of debts both small and large. In the summer of
1807 both family and business moved to new premises in Skinner Street,
thanks to a loan from Curran. It was not a desirable location, only a
short distance from the Smithfield meat market and a stoneâs throw from
the Fleet prison, but it was a better shop front than Hanway Street and
provided more living space than the Polygon. The building had stood
empty before the Godwinâs moved in; its ownership was unclear. The
ambiguity must have amused Godwin â he had always argued that property
could only really belong to those who most needed it â and within a year
he had decided to exploit the situation by refusing to pay rent until
the ârightful ownersâ were identified. The philosopher was taking a
gamble, but it would be nearly ten years before any putative landlord
was able to call his bluff. At some point in 1807 it became apparent
that Hodgkins was taking money directly out of the business, possibly
stealing stock or taking shop revenue for himself. Exactly what happened
is unclear, but in August Godwinâs diary records him changing the locks
at Skinner Street and calling a constable in reference to â3
Hodgkinsesâ. Hodgkins was dismissed and the business re-established in
Clairmontâs name, as âM. J. Godwin and Companyâ, though retaining the
Juvenile Library title. By the summer of 1808, however, the shop was in
serious trouble â Godwin was convinced he would soon find himself in
debtorâs prison. With the help of Johnson and Marshall, Godwin attempted
to raise money through public subscription. The appeal went out to the
Whig party grandees, championed by Lord Holland (nephew of Charles James
Fox) and the Earl of Lauderdale (then a radical peer), and receiving
contributions from both the political and publishing worlds. It was
enough to save the business, but it did not clear Godwinâs debts or
prevent him from accruing new ones.
Godwinâs work rate in these years is impressive. In 1806 alone, the
philosopher authored two substantial histories for children (The History
of England and The Life of Lady Jane Grey), a book of Classical myths
(The Pantheon), and another play (Faulkener, which would be performed
the following year). Of these, only the drama was published under the
philosopherâs real name, allowing the philosopher to retreat from the
(frequently hostile) spotlight. Political fortunes were changing too:
Pitt had died in January 1806 and Grenville, seeking to form the
strongest government possible, had formed a coalition that embraced both
reformers and conservatives. Fox was foreign secretary, Erskine Lord
Chancellor, Sheridan was Treasurer of the Navy. The Anti-Jacobinâs
patron, George Canning, sat on the backbenches. The âMinistry of All the
Talentsâ did not last long â Fox died in September and the coalition
broke up in March 1807 â but it is remembered principally as the
government that brought about the abolition of the slave trade in the
British Empire. As the subscription had demonstrated, Godwinâs name
still carried weight in political circles. It became clear that the
philosopherâs reputation was international when former US Vice President
Aaron Burr paid a call in October 1808 and became a regular fixture at
Skinner Street for the rest of his time in London (Burr considered
himself a disciple of both Godwin and Wollstonecraft, but Godwinâs later
letters imply that the philosopher did not agree).
The failing business contributed to a decline in Godwinâs health. From
late 1807 the diary records three or four day periods of âdeliquiumâ, at
least once a year, for the next five years (and three outbreaks in
1814). It is not clear what this affliction was; the term describes a
fainting fit, and Godwin described his attacks to a physician in May
1808:
⊠each fit (of perfect insensibility) lasted about a minute. Air was of
no service to repel at fit, but hartshorn smelled to, or a draught of
hartshorn and water, seemed to drive them off, particularly in the last
days of an attack. If seized standing, I have fallen on the ground, and
I have repeatedly had the fits in bed. ⊠in every instance each single
fit seemed to find me and leave me in perfect health ⊠The approach of
the fit is not painful, but is rather entitled to the name of pleasure,
a gentle fading away of the senses; nor is the recovery painful, unless
I am teased in it by persons about me.[110]
The symptoms have been described as episodes of catalepsy. The
philosopher reported that the condition had affected him since his
twenties, but the diaryâs evidence makes it apparent that between 1807
and 1814 Godwin was more frequently affected than at any other point in
his life. If the ailment was in part psychological, then the sustained
stress of being both writer and publisher would have obviously
contributed to the problem.
On 19 March 1809 the philosopher was summoned to Holcroftâs bedside. His
friend was dying. When Godwin arrived, Holcroft was overcome with
emotion. He pressed his hand to his chest and said, âMy dear, dear
friendâ. Godwin visited him every day until Holcroftâs death on the
23^(rd), though the playwright was too weak to hold a conversation.[111]
Godwin and Marshall organised a subscription to help Holcroftâs wife and
children.
Hazlitt undertook a biography, beginning from the narrative Holcroft had
dictated from his deathbed. Hazlitt made extensive use of Holcroftâs
diary and letters, which he planned to publish separately, much to
Godwinâs consternation. In early 1810 he wrote a concerned letter to
Holcroftâs widow, Louisa. The controversy over the philosopherâs memoir
of Wollstonecraft had scarred him:
It is one thing for a man to write a journal, and another for that
journal to be given to the public. I am sure Mr Holcroft would never
have consented to this. I have always entertained the highest antipathy
to this violation of the confidence between man and man, that every idle
word, every thoughtless jest I make at anotherâs expense, shall be
carried home by the hearer, put in writing, and afterwards printed. This
part will cause fifty persons at least, who lived on friendly terms with
Mr Holcroft, to execrate his memory. It will make you many bitter
enemies, who will rejoice in your ruin, and be transported to see you
sunk in the last distress. Many parts are actionable.[112]
Many have taken this (and later letters) to indicate that Godwin had
reconsidered his views on sincerity. Relating the unvarnished truth
about the dead had proved explosive for the living. Equally, the
deceasedâs achievements could be obscured by a controversial life. Yet
we should be wary of inferring such a fundamental challenge to Godwinâs
philosophical principles based on an unguarded comment, for precisely
the reasons that he identifies in the letter.
Two or three detestable stories (lies, I can swear) are told of Mrs
Siddons; and Miss Smith, the actress, is quoted as the authority; that
is, Miss Smith, as other people do, who are desirous of amusing their
company, told these stories as she heard them, borne out with a sort of
saw, âYou have them as cheap as I.â The first meeting of Emma Smith and
Mr Holcroft occurs, and he sets her down, and Mr Hazlitt prints her, as
a young woman of no talents; I believe Mr Holcroft altered his opinion
on that subject.[113]
We have a duty to tell the truth that we know, but also to speak the
truth responsibly. If the truth we know is incomplete (perhaps lacking
context) then we may do potentially more harm than good. The rhetoric of
Political Justice, particularly in its first edition, implied that the
philosopher was untroubled by this (universal sincerity would wipe out
falsehood and ambiguity) but even in 1793 Godwin recognised that there
were good and bad ways to deliver the truth. Political Justice uses the
example of delivering bad news to someone on their deathbed, arguing
that, âin reality there is a mode in which under such circumstances
truth may safely be communicated; and, if it be not thus done, there is
perpetual danger that it may be done in a blunter wayâ.[114] The duty to
speak the truth remains absolute, but it must be done wisely. The
revised editions of Political Justice complicate this further by
acknowledging the difficulty of identifying objective truth at all.
Arguably, Godwin saw the diary as the publication of an incomplete truth
â he raised no objections to what Hazlitt had written about Holcroft â
that could only damage the playwrightâs memory. In a series of (probably
ill-tempered) meetings between Godwin, Hazlitt, Louisa Holcroft and
others, Godwin and Hazlitt seem to have hammered out which parts of the
diary were safe to include and which would only cause strife. The letter
above indicates that Godwin was most concerned by stories the diary
reported second hand. Such elements reflected more on the teller and the
subject (rather than Holcroft) which had the potential to be legally
problematic, but from a philosophical point of view their excision is
consistent with a commitment to accuracy over transparency. Godwin was
certain that some of the stories reported in the diary were untrue â
while it might have been honest to note that Holcroft had heard them,
the ethics of repeating them were questionable. Hazlittâs Memoirs of the
Late Thomas Holcroft were not published until 1816, and raised no
memorable controversy. Perhaps Godwinâs editing had been effective, or
perhaps the intervening years made Holcroftâs opinions more a historical
curiosity than anything to sue over. Most likely, Holcroftâs notorious
outspokenness in life had left no one surprised by the details in his
memoirs. Everything that was controversial about Holcroft (his politics,
his atheism, his mercurial temper) was already common knowledge.
A few months after Holcroftâs death, Godwinâs mother passed away at the
age of 87. The son travelled to Norfolk for the funeral. After the
service, he wrote a sad and probably heartfelt letter to Clairmont:
While my mother lived, I always felt to a certain degree as if I had
somebody who was my superior, and who exercised a mysterious protection
over me. I belonged to something â I hung to something â there is
nothing that has so much reverence and religion in it as affection to
parents. The knot is now severed, and I am, for the first time, at more
than fifty years of age, alone. You shall now be my mother; you have in
many instances been my protector and my guide âŠ[115]
Godwin and Clairmontâs relationship was volatile. She harangued him when
she was unhappy and sulked when she did not get her way. She lied to his
friends as a matter of habit, making up stories to cover his absences or
inability to take callers. He remonstrated with her patiently as often
as he could â when his anger showed she was liable to walk out until he
apologised (when he fully lost his temper with her in 1811, she moved
out of the house for several weeks). Clairmont was under the same strain
as Godwin in running the Juvenile Library and, where the philosopher put
definite boundaries on his space and time (he was usually writing
upstairs during the day, if not out paying calls), Mary Jane was usually
surrounded by children, customers, or Godwinâs friends and disciples. In
their rooms above, the philosopherâs portrait of Wollstonecraft was
mounted prominently in the study, a constant reminder that her husbandâs
friends considered her a poor substitute for the author of the
Vindication. Godwin always defended her, browbeating the likes of
Holcroft or Coleridge into apologising for their rudeness to her. In the
chaos that was no doubt possible at Skinner Street, she probably
appreciated his calm. His letters acknowledge that he relied heavily on
her support. They learned how to live with each other.
The Juvenile Library was, for much of its life, a troubled business.
Since late 1809, Francis Place (the former LCS chair and future
Chartist, a self-made man with a successful tailoring company) had
worked with Godwin to put the familyâs business on a sound footing. The
exact order of events is unclear but in early 1810 Godwin was calling on
Place as well as the financier John Lambert and perhaps, with their
advice, going through the Juvenile Libraryâs accounts in search of a
solution to the companyâs woes. Place estimated that, deducting the cost
of the Libraryâs liabilities from the value of its assets, the business
had a net worth of ÂŁ3,000. This was, relatively speaking, good news:
with a substantial injection of capital, the business could become
sustainably profitable. Place went in search of a backer and made the
acquaintance of a wealthy young man called Elton Hammond, who was eager
to use his fortune to help Godwin after having read what Political
Justice had to say about property. Through much of 1811 Godwin and Place
met weekly, perhaps trying to organise investors and guarantors for the
business. Place, Lambert and Hammond all made donations and Place
organised further monies through loans. Altogether their efforts raised
ÂŁ3,000, the amount Place believed would set the business on its feet. To
the businessmanâs surprise and dismay, the funds quickly evaporated.
It is most likely that the money disappeared into Godwinâs complicated
network of creditors. Both family and business had survived up to this
point through loans, borrowing money to make repayments of debts they
already owed â Godwinâs papers show nearly ÂŁ1,000 of repayments due in
the first quarter of 1811 alone. The threat of debtorâs prison probably
forced Godwin to use Place, Lambert and Hammondâs money to clear
existing debts rather than invest in the business as intended. Place had
his doubts, however. An instinctively frugal man, Place had forced
himself to overcome a lifelong distaste for borrowing when he had gone
into business for himself. He could only imagine that the money had been
somehow wasted (he referred to Clairmont as an âinfernal devilâ and
wished Godwin a more âprudentâ wife) and believed Godwin to have
presented him with false accounts in order to attract investment.[116]
This seems unlikely: the family lived as sparsely as seven people under
the same roof can be expected to. Another backer, Horace Smith, some
years later described them as living in âan almost primitive
simplicityâ.[117] Godwin ate little meat, believing that it contributed
to his ill health, and drank even less (occasions when Godwin drank rum
are recorded in the diary in Latin â it was the philosopherâs habit to
use other languages to note things he found embarrassing or
distasteful). Nor was calculated deception really a part of Godwinâs
character. His pseudonyms were an open secret; he readily sent copies of
his childrenâs books to well-wishers, and a spyâs report from 1813
indicates that the government were fully aware â and apparently
unconcerned â that the philosopher was writing and selling books for
children. Years of abuse had made him cautious and evasive; he had
learned the hard way that ambiguity was often safer than transparency,
but he was never comfortable with outright lies. Surviving in business
had taught him to flatter, to promise more than he could deliver, and to
beg if necessary. He had come to resemble the caricature of a shopkeeper
he presented in The Enquirer, âso much in the habit of exhibiting a
bended body, that he scarcely knows how to stand uprightâ.[118] The
philosopher had long ago identified his own everyday lack of resolve,
and nearly a decade of stress and ill health saw him usually willing to
take the path of least resistance if it allowed him to preserve his
usual calm. Despite all this, there is nothing other than Placeâs bad
feeling to suggest a conspiracy. Given how poorly the business was run
from the start, the fairest explanation is simply that Godwin had no
concept of how deeply in debt he was. Indeed, he wrote to Clairmont
while she was in Margate in May 1811 to confess that he had entirely
forgotten a bill for ÂŁ140 that he owed to Place himself.[119] The family
had spent so many years transferring, consolidating and postponing their
debts, they may not have known everyone they owed money to. Further
details in the Margate letter suggest that he was frequently surprised
when he received demands for repayment. Place on several occasions
angrily refused to give Godwin any more help with his finances, but
through a combination of reasoned argument, excuses and pleading, the
philosopher convinced Place to persist in his efforts until the
businessmanâs patience was finally exhausted in late 1814.
Godwinâs family was growing up, something that no doubt put increasing
strain on their finances. Fanny, now almost an adult, was pressed into
service at the shop. Godwin described her as quiet, sober and observing
in her manner. He was sincerely attached to her, having refused an offer
from Wollstonecraftâs sisters to take her away and educate her at
boarding school some years earlier. He noted his conversations with her
as he did his adult friends. Later events imply that she felt the stress
of running the Juvenile Library as acutely as he did. Godwin mostly
educated his daughters at home, but sent his sons to school. This is
more consistent than it seems: Godwinâs daughters followed a curriculum
similar to that of their brothers (languages, history, philosophy), an
education that few girlsâ schools would have offered. Charles and
William had been sent to Charterhouse, the London public school, though
William would find it an unhappy place and eventually move to Charles
Burneyâs school at Greenwich in 1814. In 1811, Charles left school to
become an apprentice at Archibald Constableâs publishing house in
Edinburgh. Mary was also bound for Scotland. She had, for some years,
experienced outbreaks of an unidentified skin condition on her right
arm. The renowned surgeon Henry Cline was consulted, but no course of
treatment proved particularly effective. The condition was probably
aggravated by the fraught atmosphere of the house; Mary was placed for a
time at a boarding school in Ramsgate, where she could bathe in the sea,
but she did not seem to enjoy the experience and returned home in
December 1811. Cline recommended more time by the sea and, in the summer
of 1812, Godwin arranged for Mary to stay with the family of William
Baxter (a well-wisher from the era of the 1794 Treason Trials) in
Dundee. Many of the future novelistâs biographers have inferred that the
real reason for Maryâs extended periods of convalescence was friction
with Clairmont: Fanny Derham in Maryâs 1835 novel Lodore spends her
childhood away from home for that reason, and the novelistâs letters as
an adult betray a profound dislike of her stepmother. Given the effects
of the familyâs strife on everyone else in the house however, this may
only have been one element out of many.
The extended âfamilyâ at Skinner Street included a succession of young
men that sought Godwinâs help and advice. The philosopher had always
attracted such. It usually began with an unsolicited letter, or a call
at the shop. John Arnot had arrived in this manner. Tom Turner had
turned up on 4 July 1803 (having written the same day) and been a
constant fixture for six years until Godwin had imposed strict ground
rules for when Turner was allowed to visit. The philosopher always
replied to the letters (though he sometimes took months to do so) and
offered support where he could. A young man named Patrickson had been a
promising pupil at Charterhouse but had become estranged from his family
â Godwin solicited help from richer friends to send Patrickson to
Cambridge University without his familyâs support, while simultaneously
counselling the youth on how to repair his relationship with his mother.
When Godwin received a letter from another such young man at the
beginning of January 1812, it came as no great surprise. The
correspondent was an ardent admirer who had only recently learned that
Godwin was still alive. The missive was passionate, but vague:
You will be surprised at hearing from a stranger. â No introduction has,
nor in all probability ever will authorize that which common thinkers
would call a liberty; it is however a liberty which althoâ not
sanctioned by custom is so far from being reprobated by reason, that the
dearest interests of mankind imperiously demand that a certain etiquette
of fashion should no longer keep âman at a distance from manâ and impose
its flimsy fancies between the free communication of intellect. The name
of Godwin has been used to excite in me feelings of reverence and
admiration, I have been accustomed to consider him a luminary too
dazzling for the darkness which surrounds him, and from the earliest
period of my knowledge of his principles I have ardently desired to
share on the footing of intimacy that intellect which I have delighted
to contemplate in its emanations. ⊠My course has been short but
eventful. I have seen much of human prejudice, suffered much from human
persecution; yet I see no reason hence inferable which should alter my
wishes for their renovation. The ill-treatment I have met with has more
than ever impressed the truth of my principles on my judgement. I am
young â I am ardent in the cause of philanthropy and truth, do not
suppose that this is vanity. I am not conscious that it influences this
portraiture. I imagine myself dispassionately describing the state of my
mind. I am young â you have gone before me, I doubt not are a veteran to
me in the years of persecution â is it strange that defying prejudice as
I have done, I should outstep the limits of customâs prescription, and
endeavor to make my desire useful by friendship with William
Godwin?[120]
The letter writer was nineteen-year-old Percy Bysshe Shelley. Godwin
wrote back swiftly, chiding Shelley for writing an introduction that
told him little about its author. Shelleyâs reply arrived a few days
later, explaining that he was âthe Son of a man of fortune in Sussexâ,
heir to ÂŁ6,000 a year, whose life had been changed by reading Political
Justice. He had given up fantastic tales (he had written two gothic
romances) in favour of atheism, and was writing âan inquiry into the
causes of the failure of the French revolution to benefit mankindâ.[121]
They exchanged more letters. Shelley explained his plan to take âthe
benevolent and tolerant deductions of Philosophyâ to Ireland to help
those who Catholicism had kept ignorant. He had written a pamphlet,
which he sent to Godwin (its size forced Godwin to pay the substantial
excess postage). The philosopher, who had already written Shelley a
letter of introduction to present to Curran, was concerned by what he
read. An Address, to the Irish People condemned religious intolerance
and declared that a religion was only as good as it helped people
towards virtue and wisdom. It celebrated universal brotherhood and
denounced violence. It exhorted the Irish to âthink, read and talkâ, to
reform themselves (improve, in a Godwinian sense, but Shelley lays
particular emphasis on resisting the vices the Irish were
stereotypically accused of) in order to present a moral example that
could not be denied the political rights that they were owed. Godwin
wrote back to commend the pamphletâs sentiments, but to caution against
its dissemination. The pamphlet proposed the establishment of a peaceful
association for moral and intellectual improvement (his next pamphlet
set down a programme for one). Godwin, still a critic of mass movements
and political parties, told Shelley that such an organisation was
intrinsically dangerous â even more so in the volatile context of Irish
politics.
⊠associations, organized societies, I firmly condemn, you may as well
tell the adder not to sting
You may as well use question with the wolf
You may as well for bid the mountain pines
To wag their high tops, and to make no noise,
When they are fretted with the gusts of heaven,
as tell organized societies of men, associated to obtain their rights,
and to extinguish oppression, prompted by a deep aversion to inequality,
luxury, enormous taxes and the evils of war, to be innocent, to employ
no violence, and calmly to await the progress of truth.[122]
Shelley replied that Godwin had given him much to think about, but the
poet continued down the same path, attending political meetings and
proudly sending a newspaper cutting to his mentor where he (Shelley) had
been mentioned. The philosopher grew increasingly alarmed, remonstrating
with Shelley to âsave yourself and the Irish people from the calamities
with which I see your mode of proceeding to be fraughtâ.[123] Godwinâs
letters eventually made an impression, and Shelley wrote (on 18 March)
to say he had withdrawn his publications and was leaving Dublin. He
admitted his short-sightedness but refused to accept that his pamphlets
had been dangerous. Godwin dryly observed that Shelley was only âhalf a
convertâ to his argument, but said that time would do the rest.[124]
They continued to correspond as Shelley and his wife Harriet visited
Wales and Devon.
The episode contrasts sharply with the disingenuous, âheartlessâ Godwin
of Placeâs description. The early letters to Shelley show the
philosopher instinctively falling into the role of teacher, willing to
speak plainly and critically to a complete stranger, and in no way awed
by his correspondentâs claims of great wealth or literary talent. He
also displays an obvious concern for Shelleyâs development and welfare,
something he expresses in advice that reflects both his trademark
gradualism and his experience of notoriety:
⊠it is highly improving for a man who is ever to write for the public,
that he should write much while he is young. It improves him equally in
the art of thinking, and of expressing his thoughts. Till we come to try
to put our own thoughts upon paper, we can have no notion how broke and
imperfect they are, or find where the imperfection lies. ⊠But I see no
necessary connection between writing and publishing, and least of all
with oneâs name. The life of a thinking man who does this, will be made
up of a series of Retractions. It is beautiful to correct our errors, to
make each day a comment on the last, and to grow perpetually wiser; but
all this need not be done before the public. ⊠Mankind will ascribe
little weight and authority to a versatile character, that makes a show
of his imperfections. How shall I rely upon a man, they cry, who is not
himself in his public character at all times the same? I have myself,
with all my caution, felt some of the effects of this.[125]
Godwin had argued since the 1790s that a willingness to change oneâs
mind was a sign of intellectual rigour but here he again acknowledges
how easily transparency can be (wilfully) misconstrued, to the detriment
of what the individual is trying to say. As in his letter to Louisa
Holcroft, Godwin endorses accuracy (or here, clarity) over the duty to
tell all the truth we know. The philosopher is happy to allow that his
correspondent may one day have some great insight to convey to the
community, but reflection and maturity will make it a better insight.
The communication of truth ultimately requires patience. Godwin almost
certainly did not see this as a retraction of his own â he never revises
his belief in sincerity as an absolute duty â but it does represent a
pragmatic compromise with the real world. He would come to make many
more in his relationship with Percy Shelley.
Shelley encouraged Godwin to visit him in Lynmouth, on the Devon coast.
For some months, Godwin declined the invitations, but finally at the end
of August he seems to have written to signal his acceptance. He set out
on 9 September. Events that week are unclear; the diary notes
cryptically âexecutionâ on the 8^(th) and records a flurry of calls to
Place, Longdill (Shelleyâs lawyer, who Godwin knew socially) and others,
followed by two calls on âBagleyâs bankerâ the following day before the
philosopher caught a coach to Slough. Godwinâs biographer William St
Clair has advanced the theory that the diary refers to an order of
execution and that one of the philosopherâs many creditors had sent
bailiffs to arrest him. While leaving London would certainly have kept
Godwin out of debtorâs prison (and perhaps allowed him to negotiate a
bail-out from Shelley), we have little evidence to suggest anything so
dramatic â Godwin probably gave Shelley advance notice of his journey
(the diary records âwrite to Shelleyâ on 31 August, and again on 7
September, but the letters themselves are no longer extant) and Godwinâs
letters to Clairmont while he was on the road make no mention of any
difficulties at home. The journey was long and, at the age of 56, quite
arduous â coach travel was notoriously uncomfortable, and the sea leg of
Godwinâs journey (from Bristol to Lynmouth) was interrupted by bad
weather. The philosopher arrived in Lynmouth on the had not been there
for three weeks. Godwin experienced another attack of âdeliquiumâ that
night, his second in as many days. He arrived back in London on the
evening of the 25^(th), suffering two further attacks on the road and
spending part of the journey as an âoutsideâ coach passenger (either
sitting on the roof or riding in the luggage basket) exposed to the
elements. The Shelleys arrived in London on 4 October and dined with the
Godwins the same day.
Shelley became Godwinâs almost daily companion during his first
fortnight in town. The philosopher recorded their topics of
conversation: âmatter & spirit; atheismâ on the 6^(th), âutility &
truth; partyâ on the 7^(th), âclergy; church govt; germanismâ on the
9^(th).[126] The two dined together frequently, sometimes with their
wives and sometimes not. Godwin treated the younger man as his student,
recommending things for him to read and shooting down what he considered
to be Shelleyâs wilder political or philosophical ideas. On 31 October,
Shelley presented his mentor with the manuscript of his first great
philosophical poem, Queen Mab. The workâs debt to Godwin is obvious â
describing a series of dream visions that look forward to a future where
humanity has outgrown tyranny through moral improvement, and lives at
peace with itself and nature. The philosopher read through the piece
that day, though he did not make notes until he read the published
version a year later.
The Shelleys departed London suddenly in mid-November, heading back to
Wales without telling Godwin of their plans. The philosopher took up his
pen once more, and their correspondence resumed. âYou have what appears
to me a false taste in poetryâ, Godwin wrote to Shelley on 10 December,
âYou love a perpetual sparkle and glittering, such as are to be found in
Darwin, and Southey, and Scott, and Campbell.â The philosopher advised
the young poet to read Milton, and that poet would prove a significant
influence on both men for some time to come.
In the new year, Godwin made another influential friend, the
philanthropist (later, socialist) Robert Owen. The two met at a dinner
held by the journalist, Daniel Stuart, at which Coleridge was also
present. Godwin and Owen had much to talk about and soon Owen was a
regular visitor and dinner guest at Skinner Street. Owen had little in
common with the passionate young men that usually sought the
philosopherâs acquaintance, however. In his early forties when he first
met Godwin, Owen was a successful industrialist and a follower of Jeremy
Bentham, and he had his own ideas but an open mind. Owen was a pioneer
of the industrial community â philanthropic endeavours to improve
workerâs conditions had steadily gained purchase over the eighteenth
century, but Owenâs textile mill at New Lanark was notable for its
comprehensive support of workerâs health, education, and economic
independence. At the time working on the essays that would form the
first edition of A New View of Society (1813), Owen allowed Godwin to
steer him away from a Benthamite conception of self-interest and towards
the idea of universal benevolence. Like Godwin, Owen held that people
were shaped by the world around them and that poverty, ignorance, and
exploitation prevented the majority of humanity from accessing the means
of moral improvement. In contrast to Godwin, however, Owen argued that
this placed a duty on institutions to provide those means; that it was
the responsibility of those in power to enable the improvement of
ordinary people. Recalling the strict routines of industrial production,
Owenâs vision is benevolently authoritarian and would go on to influence
the creation of the modern welfare state. Despite their radically
different conclusions, Owen considered Godwin to be one of his major
philosophical inspirations.
Around this time, Godwin began work on another biography. It was his
first full-length work for adults since finishing Faulkener nearly six
years earlier. The Lives of Edward and John Phillips, Nephews and Pupils
of Milton (1815) took nearly two years to complete. Conceptually, the
work is fascinating: Godwinâs book is, in part, a look at Milton from
the outside â an exploration of how and why the poetâs pupils came to
reject him as a religious teacher (both became critics of Puritanism)
but not as a literary one (both were accomplished poets and literary
critics). Based on contemporary accounts, including one by Edward
himself, Godwin imagines Milton as a passionate and powerful educator.
The brothers rejected his way of life, Godwin argues, in part because it
is in the nature of pupils to rebel â to seek out truth for oneself
rather than simply to receive it. Once out on their own, the brothers
found worldly temptations too strong to go back to the Puritan life (the
philosopher cannot help but criticise this as in some degree venal). Yet
the brothers found happiness (and success) as poets because their
education had awakened their potential.
Shelley returned to London in April, but made no attempt to see Godwin.
The two ran into one another on 8 June. Harriet and Percyâs first child,
Elizabeth Ianthe Shelley, was born later that month. On 4 August,
Shelley turned twenty-one. Now legally an adult, he could enter into
contracts without parental consent. Shelleyâs enthusiasm had led him to
commit to at least one expensive project already: a land-improvement
scheme where he had stayed in Wales. At the end of 1812, Place had told
Godwin that his only hope to avoid bankruptcy and prison was to convince
Shelley to provide him with a substantial sum of money. What
conversations Godwin and Shelley had over the subject are not recorded,
but the poet had frequently written of his desire to use his fortune to
support the less fortunate and (according to Place) Godwin was often
very persuasive. Regardless of whatever offers of support the poet might
have made, for a long time Shelley did nothing to actually raise
whatever money Godwin might have asked for. Shelleyâs father had already
granted him an allowance of ÂŁ200 a year (a comparable income to a
middle-class family of the period) but the poet would need to organise
other means if he wished to raise significant amounts of capital.
Shelleyâs family did not approve of his political agitation, or his
marriage, and restricted his access to their wealth in hopes of bringing
him under control.[127] The principal method of raising money open to
the poet was the selling of post-obituary bonds, essentially obtaining a
cash loan to be repaid (with considerable interest) when the recipient
came into their inheritance. This was a high-stakes business, as the
creditors were speculating on both the debtor surviving long enough to
inherit and the value of the estate when they did so. Shelley was a good
prospect: his grandfather (the current baronet) was eighty-two and his
father nearly sixty, but his constant travelling and willingness to
publish his work at his own expense (he arranged a private printing of
Queen Mab that year) meant that he was racking up significant debts. The
couple came and went from London continually in that year, allegedly to
stay ahead of creditors. On 10 December, Shelley turned up for breakfast
at Skinner Street without warning, was a near-constant presence for
nearly a week, and then left London for Windsor.
At the suggestion of either Place or John King, Godwin convinced Shelley
to auction a post-obit in order to raise money for the Juvenile Library.
The auction took place on 3 March 1814, with an ÂŁ8,000 bond offered to
the highest bidder. Godwinâs target was again in the region of ÂŁ3,000 â
the diary notes the figure ÂŁ3,860 around this time, without further
context â but the auction only raised ÂŁ2,593, and the purchasers raised
questions about the security of their investment. The final balance was
not paid over until 6 July. Worse for Godwin, Shelley decided to keep
half the money for himself. His reasons for doing so presented a more
immediate crisis for the family.
Mary had returned home from Dundee on 30 March. She and her sisters were
entranced by the handsome, charismatic young man who had won their
fatherâs respect and seemed poised to deliver the family from its
constant financial woes. For his own part, Shelley took particular
interest in Mary â he had seen little of her in the two years he had
known Godwin, meeting her almost for the first time when she was
sixteen. To Shelley, she must have seemed to embody the best qualities
of both her illustrious parents: her motherâs passion and her fatherâs
mind (he had, perhaps, read the Memoir). He wrote a poem to her dark
eyes and trembling lips. By mid-June, Shelley was at Skinner Street
every day, taking Mary on walks to her motherâs grave in St Pancras
churchyard (usually with Jane as chaperone). On 26 June, Mary declared
her love for him. Shelley went to Godwin, perhaps to ask for his
blessing. The poet was a vehement critic of marriage, and had only been
persuaded to marry Harriet through being made to see the punishment
society handed out to âfallenâ women. He had grown apart from Harriet,
he had met someone new. He looked into legally separating from his wife
(he asked Basil Montagu to find out what could be done), but he hoped to
live with Harriet as his friend and Mary as his lover. He seemed sure
that Godwin would approve, recalling the philosopherâs own critique of
marriage in Political Justice. The philosopher did not.
Precisely what Godwin thought is unknown. In late middle age he had made
his peace with the institution of marriage, allowing that it was
possible for two mutually complementary individuals to be happy
together, and that its evils were primarily problems of implementation
(his old bugbear, the law) rather than principle. He was also acutely
aware that the scandal of what Shelley was proposing would fall far
harder on Mary and Harriet than it would Percy. Godwinâs account of
their discussion says that he âexpostulated with him with all the energy
of which I was master and with so much effect that for the moment he
promised to give up his licentious love, and return to virtueâ.[128] The
exact order of events is ambiguous. Shelley biographers have
traditionally claimed that Percy took his news to Godwin the day after
Mary declared her love (27 June) and that the philosopher demanded that
Shelley stay away from Skinner Street. Godwinâs version of events places
the revelation on the day the bond was paid (6 July) and the implication
is that Shelley took his own share of the money to support both Harriet
and Mary. The diary records that Shelley remained a regular visitor to
Skinner Street between the 27 June and 6 July, but that all but one of
Godwinâs meetings with Shelley after the 6^(th) took place away from the
house (the one exception is where Harriet is also present). Godwin tried
in vain to bring Percy and Harriet closer together â Percy insisted that
his affection for Harriet was that of a brother; Harriet revealed that
she was again pregnant. Mary was confined to the house. Shelleyâs later
letters imply they either met or corresponded in secret. According to
Clairmont, at one point Shelley stormed the shop and pressed a bottle of
laudanum on Mary in the hope that she would join him in suicide.
Clairmontâs story presents Mary as one of the more level-headed members
of the family: while Jane shrieked upon Shelley producing a pistol, Mary
entreated the poet to calm himself and go home, promising her fidelity
on condition that he reasonable.[129]
In the small hours of 28 July, Mary and Jane crept out of the house to
meet Shelley waiting with a carriage. The trio escaped to Dover, booked
space on a small boat heading to France that night and were blown by
strong winds into Calais just before dawn. Clairmont gave chase and
caught up with them on the evening of the 29^(th). Shelley prevented her
from seeing Mary, but allowed her to talk to Jane. Clairmont
successfully convinced her daughter to come home, but in the morning
Shelley persuaded Jane that she should stay and Clairmont returned home
in defeat. Godwin recorded the elopement in his diary the way he
recorded a death in the family, simply by noting the time.
For a few weeks, it must have seemed as if one horror followed another.
Patrickson dined with them on 8 August. Cambridge was a soul-destroying
place for an outsider â without a gentlemanâs income, the young man was
ostracised and abused. Godwin had done his best to support his friend,
discussing the Stoics and sending money when he could. Patrickson
returned to Cambridge the next day, wrote a letter to Godwin telling of
his despair, and shot himself on 10 August. The same day, Godwinâs son
William ran away from home, almost certainly fleeing the atmosphere of
the house, and was missing for two nights. On the business side of
things, a deal to sell half the business for (another) ÂŁ3,000 stalled
over the value of the Juvenile Libraryâs copyrights. Godwin was forced
to write to Place to beg an extension on a loan of ÂŁ300. Ironically, the
family was experiencing cash-flow problems thanks to money owed them
(they had received only a third of the money due for a substantial order
of schoolbooks), but for Place it was the last straw. The businessman
wrote an angry letter that condemned the philosopherâs âmost selfishâ
conduct and claimed that he regretted ever trying to help him.[130]
Godwin accused Place of trying to heap further miseries on him, after
the events of the past few weeks, but over the course of their letters
his tone became more indignant. Place accused him of insincerity, Godwin
sent a high-handed reply that Place did not respond to. They did not see
each other again socially for nearly two years, and Charles Clairmont
(who returned home from Edinburgh in late 1814) was employed as a
go-between. The sale of the business finally fell through at the end of
September.
Shelley, Mary and Jane returned to England on 13 September. Their
adventures had taken them through a France shattered by Russian,
Prussian and Austrian armies (peace between the allies and France had
only been declared in April), down into picturesque Switzerland, and
returning back up the Rhine through Germany and the Netherlands. Mary
was now pregnant. Godwin refused to speak to the trio, Shelley sent a
letter on 16 September (Godwin notes it in his diary) but received no
reply. The rest of the family attempted to make contact: Clairmont and
Fanny ventured out to where the party were staying, but refused to speak
to Shelley. Charles later approached under cover of darkness and stayed
until three in the morning updating Shelley and his sisters on what had
happened in their absence. Godwin finally wrote to Shelley on 22
September, stating âwith bitter invectiveâ, according to Shelley, that
he wanted no more communication with them.[131] The situation dragged on
for months, as friends and family attempted in vain to heal the breach.
Shelley, like Godwin, was now being hounded by creditors. The poet lay
low, keeping lodgings away from Mary and Jane (who was experimenting
with new given names around this time, eventually settling on âClaireâ),
but writing to Mary almost daily to arrange meetings. Maryâs replies
blame Clairmont for their estrangement:
I detest Mrs. G she plagues my father out of his life & then â well no
matter â Why will not Godwin follow the obvious bent of his affections &
be reconciled to us â no his prejudices the world and she â do you not
hate her my love â all these forbid it â What am I to do trust to time
of course â for what else can I do?[132]
Mary underestimated the extent to which Godwin felt his children (and
student) had betrayed him. As he explained to his backer, John Taylor,
in a letter of 27 August, he had reposed âthe utmost confidenceâ in
Shelley, but the poet had played âtraitorâ. He had attempted to rouse,
âa sense of honor and natural affection in the mind of Maryâ, and
believed that he had succeeded. âThey both deceived meâ. He went on to
say, however:
I felt it however still to be my duty, not to desert myself, or so much
of my family as was yet left to me, and even to provide, if possible for
the hour of distress (which, I believe, is not far distant) when these
unworthy children shall seek the protection and aid of their
father.[133]
As in his angry dialogues with Mackintosh, Parr, and Place, when hurt,
the philosopher fell back on stiff-necked pride as a defence. Godwin was
perhaps waiting for his children to return chastened and penitent, but
this did not diminish his sense of duty towards them, nor perhaps his
love.
Whatever the reasons behind his long silence, Godwin was still willing
to accept Shelleyâs money. In early November, Godwin failed to repay
money he owed Lambert and called in a book auctioneer to help liquidate
his stock. With Charles Clairmont still keeping him informed of events,
Shelley stepped in to offer Lambert another post-obit and save the
business. The poet exposed himself to considerable risk in helping â
alerting Londonâs financiers as to his whereabouts might easily have led
to his arrest, and selling further post-obits essentially mortgaged his
future in exchange for dwindling returns. Nevertheless, further bonds
were offered to Place and other creditors. It is usually suggested that
Godwin took Shelleyâs aid as no more than his due, certainly the bailout
was consistent with the principles of utility and benevolence that both
men held (the Juvenile Library was a project that contributed to general
happiness, and Shelley had the means to help in its hour of need).
Equally, it could be argued that many of Godwinâs (current) financial
problems were a direct result of Shelleyâs sudden change of heart
regarding the earlier post-obit, thus the poet had a responsibility to
fix the mess he had created. Yet the simplest explanation is that Godwin
had little choice in the matter: the philosopher could choose to accept
Shelleyâs help, or be declared bankrupt and probably sent to gaol.
On 30 November, Harriet gave birth to a son. She named the boy Charles.
Shelley had tried repeatedly to persuade Harriet to come and live with
Mary, Claire and himself as a family. His wife refused. He offered
instead to support her financially, but at the time realistically lacked
the money to do so. Harriet told a friend that Godwin had corrupted
Shelley, and Mary believed that Harriet was involved in spreading
rumours about her father.[134] In the new year, Shelleyâs grandfather
died and the poet negotiated with his father (the new baronet) for money
to clear some of his debts and to increase his income. This was at least
partially successful, though the legal wrangling took a considerable
amount of time. Shelleyâs father provided his son with an annuity of
ÂŁ1,000 a year and a one-off payment of over ÂŁ4,000, granting him
considerable financial independence. The poet settled ÂŁ200 a year on
Harriet and authorised a ÂŁ300 bankerâs draft for Mary. On 22 February,
Mary gave birth to a girl. The baby was premature and died in less than
two weeks. The childâs death haunted her â she suffered nightmares for
years afterwards â but she was soon pregnant again.
Godwinâs Lives of Edward and John Phillips was published in May 1815, in
a print run of only 250 copies, of which fewer than 200 sold. The book
received a handful of positive reviews, however, including one from
Mackintosh. Two weeks later he had picked up his pen once more to
protest the Declaration of the Congress of Vienna (to which Britain was
a signatory) outlawing Napoleon for his return from exile. Godwin argued
that the allied nations had no right to intervene in the internal
affairs of France â if the French people chose Bonaparte over the
Bourbons, they could do so. Napoleon had demonstrated his willingness to
accept constitutional government and offered peace with the rest of
Europe, while the allied governments had already violated the treaty
that had exiled the Emperor a year earlier. Boldly, Godwin declared that
he was âtoo much the friend of man, and too little the citizen of a
particular countryâ to wish Britain victorious. His letter was published
in the Morning Chronicle on the 25^(th), but the philosopher continued
to write and authored a second letter, packaging the two together for
publication in a pamphlet. The work was printed on 22 June, the same day
that Napoleon abdicated for the second time. Godwin withdrew the
pamphlet. The moment had passed.
The Juvenile Library still lurched from one crisis to another. Finally,
desperately, he wrote to Shelley directly on 11 November. The poet wrote
back immediately, and the two conducted a terse correspondence on
finances for several months. On 24 January 1816, Mary gave birth to her
second child â a boy this time â which she named William, after her
father. Shelley told Godwin that he intended to take his new family to
Italy, sending the philosopher into a state of agitation. Godwin
summoned Tom Turner (who Shelley did not like) to advise him. The
letters thawed a little, but Godwin continued to pester Shelley for
money while refusing to see him face to face. Eventually Shelley
snapped:
My astonishment, and I will confess when I have been treated with most
harshness and cruelty by you, my indignation has been extreme, that,
knowing as you do my nature, any considerations should have prevailed on
you to have been thus harsh and cruel. I lamented also over my ruined
hopes, of all that your genius once taught me to expect from your
virtue, when I found that for yourself, your family, and your creditors,
you would submit to that communication with me which you once rejected
and abhorred, and which no pity for my poverty or sufferings, assumed
willingly for you, could avail to extort. Do not talk of forgiveness
again to me, for my blood boils in my veins, and my gall rises against
all that bears the human form, when I think of what I, their benefactor
and ardent lover, have endured of enmity and contempt from you and from
all mankind.[135]
Godwinâs response was not conciliatory, but neither did he bite back.
The next day he wrote plainly, âIf I understand you, you will accept no
kindness without approbations; and torture cannot wring from me an
approbation of the act that separated usâ. Shelley softened his tone.
Using money from Shelley, Godwin published new editions of Caleb
Williams and St Leon in the hope of generating quick profits.
In April, the philosopher travelled to Edinburgh to meet with Charlesâs
old employer, the publisher Archibald Constable, and was able to
negotiate a contract for a new novel. Constable introduced him to the
cityâs intellectual elite: Francis Jeffrey, editor of the Edinburgh
Review; Dugald Stewart, then Scotlandâs most prominent philosopher; and
Walter Scott, then known principally as a poet, but already on his way
to becoming the most successful novelist of the nineteenth century. All
three were Godwinâs ideological opponents, Tory writers who had joined
in the abuse of the philosopher and his work decades earlier, but Godwin
appears to have enjoyed their company regardless.[136] His journey back
took him through the Lake District, where he spent an awkward day or two
with Wordsworth (both were great friends of Coleridge, but neither was
keen on the other). When he arrived back in London, he found that
Shelley had delivered on his plan to leave the country. He left a letter
and instructions to provide Godwin with more money:
I respect you, I think well of you, better perhaps than of any other
person whom England contains, you were the philosopher who first
awakened, & who still as a philosopher to a very great degree regulate
my understanding. It is unfortunate for me that the part of your
character which is least excellent should have been met by my
convictions of what was right to do. But I have been too indignant, I
have been unjust to you. â forgive me. â burn those letters which
contain the records of my violence, & believe that however what you
erroneously call fame & honour separate us, I shall always feel towards
you as the most affectionate of friends.[137]
Godwin set to work on his new novel (eventually titled Mandeville) with
enthusiasm, but events soon took a darker turn. Sheridan died on 7 July.
It was the end of an era in both politics and the theatre. Godwin noted
his visits to the playwrightâs grave. He struggled to sleep at night.
Shelley, Mary and Claire returned to Britain in September. They had met
Byron in Switzerland and now Claire was pregnant with his child. They
spent a few days in London (Godwin still refused to see them, and
Claireâs letters imply she was keen for her pregnancy to remain a
secret) but the trio set up residence in Bath. Godwin began writing
letters about money again, desperately in need of ÂŁ300. Shelleyâs reply
was sympathetic but offered little:
I am exceedingly sorry to dissappoint you again. I cannot send you ÂŁ300
because I have not ÂŁ300 to send. I enclose within a few pounds the
wrecks of my late negotiation with my father.
In truth, I see no hope of my attaining speedily to such a situation of
affairs as should enable me to discharge my engagements towards you. My
fathers main design, in all the transactions which I have had with him,
has gone to tie me up from all such irregular applications of my
fortune. In this he might have failed had he not been seconded by
Longdill, & between them both I have been encompassed with such toils as
were impossible to be evaded. When I look back I do not see what else I
could have done than submit: what is called firmness would have, I
sincerely believe left me in total poverty.[138]
Fanny wrote to Mary the next day describing their fatherâs reaction:
âShelleyâs letter came like a thunderclap. I watched Papaâs countenance
while he read it (not knowing the contents), and I perceived that
Shelley had written in his most desponding manner.â[139] The sum that
Shelley offered fell short of what the family needed and, against
Godwinâs instructions, the cheque was made out in his name (Godwin
insisted that his name be kept off any promissory notes that Shelley
sent him, perhaps to keep a low profile from creditors). Fanny suddenly
left home on 7 October, taking a coach due west. She wrote to Godwin and
Mary separately the next day; both letters were alarming enough that,
when they arrived on the 9^(th), both Godwin and Shelley immediately
took to the road in search of Fanny. Godwin returned home at two in the
morning without further information. On the evening of the 9^(th), in a
small room above the Mackworth Arms, Swansea, Fanny committed suicide
with laudanum. Her last note read:
I have long determined that the best thing I could do was to put an end
to the existence of a being whose birth was unfortunate, and whose life
has only been a series of pain to those persons who have hurt their
health in endeavouring to promote her welfare. Perhaps to hear of my
death will give you pain, but you will soon have the blessing of
forgetting that such a creature ever existed as[140]
The last part of the page was torn off, where there might have been a
signature. The only identification she had were the initials M.W. on her
stays (her motherâs) and a G. on her stockings. Shelley arrived in
Swansea on 11 October; Godwin had reached Bath but did not attempt to
meet his daughters. He wrote to both Mary and Shelley about the need to
keep the matter quiet, forbidding Shelley from claiming the body. The
poet agreed, and Fanny was buried anonymously. Arriving home in London,
Godwin wrote to Shelley:
I did indeed expect it.
I cannot but thank you for your strong expressions of sympathy. I do not
see, however, that that sympathy can be of any service to me; but it is
best. My advice and earnest prayer is that you would avoid anything that
leads to publicity. Go not to Swansea; disturb not the silent dead; do
nothing to destroy the obscurity she so much desired that now rests upon
the event. It was, as I said, her last wish ⊠I said that your sympathy
could be of no service to me, but I retract the assertion; by observing
what I have just recommended to you, it may be of infinite service.
Godwin went on to write that he and Clairmont had contemplated telling
people that Fanny had gone to see her aunts in Ireland, and begged
Shelley to allow them the right to use their own discretion in the
matter. He thanked the poet for helping to keep the matter out of the
newspapers. They had not at that point told anyone what had happened.
Their son Charles, who had been travelling Europe since the spring, did
not receive the news until he returned home in the summer of 1817.
On 10 December Harriet Shelleyâs body was recovered from the Serpentine.
She had been missing for three weeks. Harriet had been pregnant, though
it was not clear who the father was. Her family responded in much the
same way the Godwins had, burying her under a false name. Shelley fought
for custody of their children, but her family resisted. Harrietâs last
wish had been that her sister Eliza take care of Ianthe (Charles was not
mentioned in her final letter), but the poetâs de facto abandonment of
his children â he had not seen Ianthe since 1814 â would have been
enough for the Westbrook family to believe that Shelley was not a
suitable guardian. Longdill advised the poet that marriage to Mary would
end âall pretences to detain the childrenâ and (implicitly) grant him
his full parental rights.[141]
Shelley wrote to Godwin informing him of Harrietâs death and, on 18
December, called at Skinner Street to discuss matters with Clairmont.
Godwin wrote to Mary on Christmas Eve, the first time he had done so
since the elopement. On Boxing Day, Godwin wrote to Shelley, and the day
after that Shelley called again. This time, Godwin received him. On the
28^(th), Godwin, Clairmont, Shelley and Mary met to discuss the
situation. The only account of the conversation is Clairmontâs:
allegedly Shelley acknowledged his engagement to Mary but asked for the
customary year of mourning for Harriet. On this he seemed intractable,
until Mary put her hand on his shoulder and informed him that she would
kill herself and their unborn child if he did not marry her promptly.
Clairmontâs story does not tally with the advice Shelley received from
Longdill, but it provides a neatly ironic reversal of the suicide pact
that she claimed the poet had proposed two years earlier. The truth of
the meeting is probably more prosaic, but Clairmontâs anecdote tells us
something about her assessment of Shelleyâs character: as mercurial,
prevaricating, and perhaps in need of a firm hand. Both Godwinâs and
Shelleyâs biographers have always regarded Mary Janeâs version of events
with some degree of scepticism â Clairmont was considered dishonest by
many of Godwinâs circle â but this, and the earlier suicide story, and
her account of many other events, suggest someone compelled to turn
events into a story (to tell âtall talesâ that suited her audience)
rather than someone who misled others maliciously.[142]
Regardless of the negotiations, Mary and Percy were married on 30
December. Shelley described the wedding as âmagical in its effectsâ, so
effective was it in healing the breach between the two households:
Mrs G and G were both present, and appeared to feel no little
satisfaction. Indeed Godwin throughout has shown the most polished and
cautious attentions to me and Mary. He seems to think no kindness too
great in compensation for what has past. I confess I am not entirely
deceived by this, though I cannot make my vanity wholly insensible to
certain attentions paid in a manner studiously flattering. Mrs. G.
presents herself to me in her real attributes of affectation, prejudice,
and heartless pride.[143]
The estrangement was, to all extents and purposes, over. Godwin and
Shelley would fight again in the future; Mary would at times keep her
father at armâs length; but never again would Godwin sever contact with
his daughter and son-in-law. Claire had her baby Alba (later renamed
Allegra) in January 1817. The matter remained a secret, for some time
the Shelleys maintained the fiction that Claire was looking after the
child of a friend, and nothing indicates that the Godwins were aware of
Albaâs parentage until her christening in March. Shelley lost his
custody battle the same month â the court decided against the poet on 17
March, the Westbrooksâ case against him hinging on Shelleyâs politics as
much as his actual neglect of his wife and children â but the matter was
not fully settled until a year later, when Ianthe and Charles were
placed in the care of a third party (a couple called the Humes), and
Shelley was only granted visiting rights under supervision. The Shelleys
and Claire settled in Marlow, outside London. They visited the Godwins,
and Godwin came to stay with them in the spring. Maryâs third child,
Clara, was born in September. The birth only briefly interrupted Maryâs
literary endeavours: through August to October she compiled A History of
a Six Weeks Tour (a collage of the trioâs travels in 1814), while
Shelley attempted to negotiate her a publisher for her first novel â
Frankenstein.
John Philpott Curran died in October. Godwin dedicated the
soon-to-be-finished Mandeville to his friendâs memory. The philosopherâs
dwindling circle of literary and political veterans began to overlap
with Shelleyâs network of new talents. Hazlitt argued politics all night
with Shelley and the poetâs confidant, Leigh Hunt. In November, Godwin
was introduced to a young John Keats when the latter called on Shelley
during dinner (Keatsâs friend, Charles Dilke, was an ardent admirer of
Political Justice; Keats himself had been greatly influenced by reading
âEdward Baldwinâsâ The Pantheon as a boy). Around the same time, the
philosopher acquired a new âstudentâ in the form of Henry Blanch Rosser.
Rosser would go on to prove an able research assistant.
Mandeville was finally published in December 1817. The story is set
during the period of the Commonwealth (the years between the execution
of Charles I and the Restoration). It is a dark, savage, novel about a
society coping with trauma. The world of Cromwellâs Interregnum is a
haunted one; every family has a father or brother or son that died a
hero in the wars, and that hero casts a shadow over the next generation.
The protagonistâs social ties place him among the Protestant Royalists,
a faction under constant pressure to prove its loyalty to the exiled
king because of its unwillingness to embrace the more Catholic culture
of his court. A series of humiliations encourage Charles Mandevilleâs
already burgeoning misanthropy. The emergence of a rival, Clifford, who
seems to be everything Charles is not, tests him further. As in all of
Godwinâs major fictional works, the novel recounts the protagonistâs
downward spiral in the first person. The narrative is self-consciously
literary: the text makes extensive use of Biblical and literary
quotation (primarily Miltonâs Comus) from period sources, Godwin making
a number of historical allusions in the text that point towards a
particular date of âcompositionâ (that is, when the protagonist
supposedly authored the manuscript) and providing a sophisticated
insight into the narratorâs mental space. The protagonistâs narration
becomes stranger and more incoherent over the course of the novel,
reaching a wild and gothic peak in the third volume, as his obsession
with Clifford overcomes whatever good was left within him.
The novel is an indictment of the obsession with martyrdom that Godwin
saw within Dissenting culture. Like the philosopher himself, the
protagonist was raised on stories of men and women who died bravely (and
usually gruesomely) for God. The protagonist searches for a death that
will give meaning to his life â in direct contrast to Clifford, who
celebrates life however he finds it. It is easy to infer a certain
amount of morbidity on the part of the author too â the deaths of
Sheridan and Curran while he was writing no doubt reminded Godwin of his
own mortality, but this seems trivial next to the lonely end of both
Fanny and Harriet. One of Mandevilleâs principal themes is that of
isolation; the suicides no doubt played on the philosopherâs mind.
A few weeks later, on 1 January 1818, Mary published Frankenstein with
Lackington and Co. It was a small print run, but the novel sold readily.
The work went out anonymously (not unusual at the time), but a page
before the preface dedicated the novel to Godwin, and reviewers quickly
detected the philosopherâs influence running through the text. It is
clearly a first novel. The 1818 version of Frankenstein is spiky in
places: readers often find it difficult to sympathise with the
characters, its literary references are poetic but improbable, and its
philosophical argument is highly ambiguous.[144] The debts to Godwin are
obvious: Frankenstein is a tale of persecution and pursuit (like Caleb
Williams), using alchemy as a plot device (like St Leon) and Switzerland
as its rural idyll (St Leon again, Fleetwood), and leaning heavily on
Milton for its poetic allusions (Mandeville). Many assumed that Shelley
had written the novel â he had written the preface â but the manuscript,
in Maryâs hand with Percyâs comments in the margin, displays editorial
interventions rather than a guiding hand. Few literary works spring out
of nothing, and listing Frankensteinâs influences does not detract from
its striking originality. That the novel takes a fantastic idea and uses
it to explore moral and political responsibility might reasonably place
it in Godwinâs literary âschoolâ, but Maryâs use of overlapping
narrative frames (the creature tells his story to Frankenstein, who
tells his story to Walton, who tells his story to us) show her
developing rather than simply imitating those literary techniques. The
storyâs lack of moral clarity â its principal characters are, at best,
antiheroes â also illustrates Maryâs independence from both her father
and husband philosophically. In Godwinâs novels, characters espouse
moral principles that they fail to live up to; in Frankenstein, the
principles themselves are open to question â high-mindedness is
indistinguishable from ambition, domestic values carry the suggestion of
incest, and it is the fate of a man and his creator to be locked into a
cycle of reciprocal suffering. Whereas Caleb Williams ended with a
victory for truth (however poignant), Frankenstein ends with mutual
annihilation.
Godwin continued to ask Shelley for money. The poet had his own
problems. Still hounded by his own creditors, Shelley was arrested for
debt at the beginning of October 1817 (how the situation was resolved is
unknown). Nevertheless, the poet replied to Godwinâs requests with
admirable patience. Perhaps Shelley understood the extent to which the
philosopherâs other sources of borrowing had dried up: Wedgwood, Johnson
and Curran were all dead; Place was adamant in his refusal to spend
money to help the Godwins (and not simply Godwin himself â Place had
turned down a business proposal from Charles in 1815); Lambert and other
creditors had gradually turned hostile in recent years. Shelley
continued to funnel money to Godwin â he also raised money for Leigh
Hunt â but his relationship with the philosopher gradually soured once
more. The letters that survive from this period veer between sympathy,
hostility, entitlement and distrust; but what is apparent in all of
Godwinâs letters about money is that the philosopher begs money to
support others rather than himself. His letters to Place stress the
difficulty of supporting a large family â Place dismissed this, implying
that Godwin had been under no obligation to adopt other menâs children â
but the businessman had earlier observed that Godwin sometimes borrowed
money in order to help people in greater need than himself, pushing
himself deeper into debt so that he could repay loans owed to friends
who urgently needed the money returned.[145] Godwinâs borrowing was
obviously financially unsound, but Placeâs comment suggests both a
tendency to respond short-sightedly to crisis and a willingness to take
great personal risks on behalf of others. At the end of 1817, it was
Marshall who was in need. Godwin immediately organised a subscription to
help him. While Shelley begged poverty, Godwin contributed ÂŁ13 to the
fund â an amount the philosopher almost certainly did not have to spare.
It was Place who settled the majority of Marshallâs debts, at Godwinâs
urging. When Place learned that the philosopher had also made a monetary
contribution it reignited all of their old arguments, compounding the
ill will he already felt towards Godwin.
In January, encouraged by Percyâs poor health and a determination to
present baby Allegra to her father, the Shelleys finally resolved on a
permanent move to Italy. Shelley had himself insured against the
possibility of dying before his father, a move that allowed him to sell
another post-obit. How much this raised is not clear (estimates range
from ÂŁ2,000 to ÂŁ4,500) but the sum liable is known to have been ÂŁ9,000.
Some of this money went to Godwin (again, how much is unknown), but
their surviving letters make it apparent that Shelley kept most of the
money for himself. Godwin was dismayed â the tone of their
correspondence implies that the philosopher did not trust Shelleyâs
reasons for holding on to the money he had borrowed, and proposed that
the money be held in a joint account that required their mutual
agreement to access. Ultimately, however, Godwin attempted to move past
the dispute:
Now to the main point. I will never again discuss with you any question
of this sort upon paper; but I do not desire the presence of any third
person.
Since our last conversation at Marlow, I have reflected much on the
subject. I am ashamed of the tone I have taken with you in all our late
conversations. I have played the part of a supplicant, and deserted that
of a philosopher. It was not thus I talked with you when I first knew
you. I will talk so no more. I will talk principles; I will talk
Political Justice; whether it makes for me or against me, no matter. I
am fully capable of this. I desire not to dictate. I know that every
manâs conduct ought to be regulated by his own judgement, such as it may
happen to be. But I hold it to be my duty once to state to you the
principles which belong to the case. Having done that, it is my duty to
forbear.[146]
Shelley did not reply. Godwin continued to write (the diary records
writing letters to Shelley throughout February), but there is no
evidence of any reply from the poet. The two did not see each other
again until 6 March, when Godwin dropped in to visit Mary and stayed
until Percy returned. Poet and philosopher were reconciled to some
extent; Godwinâs diary records Shelleyâs calls for several days after.
Godwin does not seem to have attended the christening of his
grandchildren on 9 March (ostensibly conducted to cement a formal record
of the childrenâs parentage, particularly relevant for Byronâs daughter
Allegra). The diary notes a call from Shelley with others, but not any
event â Godwin recorded weddings and funerals with the name of the
church, and we might expect to find that here if that were the case. It
is not possible to tell whether this indicates some continuing distance
between the two households, or if Godwin merely saw no need to attend.
The Shelleys left Britain on 12 March. Writing from Dover that day, the
poet authorised his banker to pay Godwin another ÂŁ150.
Skinner Street was now mostly empty. Of the children, only William
remained. William was intermittently at school â he had left the Burney
school at the end of 1817, and flitted from business school in Essex to
an apprenticeship under the architect Peter Nicholson the year after (he
would later try his hand at engineering before settling into journalism
in his early twenties). For a time, the Godwins hosted Clairmontâs
nephew Marc Valette (while he attended school in London) but the house
and shop were no longer the intellectual hub they had been during
Shelleyâs visits, or the early years of the Juvenile Library. On 23 June
1818 they received an eviction notice. Godwinâs refusal to pay rent had
finally prompted legal intervention, but the philosopher continued to
ignore the issue, allegedly closing the door on callers representing the
landlords. The tactic worked, and Godwin succeeded in dragging the
matter out for several more years.
Little Clara died in Venice in September. The family had travelled
around northern Italy at breakneck pace, the heat and the disruption
taxing the health of the whole party. Claire became ill, as did Shelley
(though he was convinced he had been poisoned), but Clara was
dangerously sick for weeks. The various illnesses may have been
unrelated to each other, but Mary blamed the fatigue of travel for the
dysentery and fever that eventually claimed the childâs life. Godwin
wrote to offer comfort, but his condolences were typically stoic:
I sincerely sympathise with you in the affliction which forms the
subject of your letter, and which I may consider as the first severe
trial of your constancy and the firmness of your temper that has
occurred to you in the course of your life. You should, however,
recollect that it is only persons of a very ordinary sort, and of a
pusillanimous disposition, that sink long under a calamity of this
nature.[147]
Godwin liked to imagine himself a purely rational creature. He knew that
he was not, but distress often prompted him to retreat into a protective
stoicism â he read Seneca when he was ill â that allowed him to pretend
that physical and emotional demands were merely a storm to be weathered
by those with greater things to address. It should come as no surprise
that he recommended the same outlook to his daughter, though his
autobiographical notes make it obvious that such fortitude was more
aspiration than reality. William Shelley, still only three years old,
died in Rome in June 1819, possibly a victim of the malaria epidemic
that swept the city that summer. Mary fell into a period of serious
depression. Shelley, perhaps struggling with grief himself but certainly
at a loss as to how to help his wife, asked Godwin to write to Mary. The
news struck the philosopher hard too, the diary noting âdepressionâ the
day after he received Shelleyâs letter. Yet Godwin did not understand
the depth of his daughterâs unhappiness: she had lost three children and
was pregnant with a fourth; Byron had taken his daughter Allegra and
refused Claire access; rumours regarding Claireâs intimacy with Shelley
still plagued them. The philosopher, coming from a family where at least
four of the children had died in infancy, tried tough love:
⊠allow me the privilege of a father, and a philosopher, in
expostulating with you on this depression. I cannot but consider it as
lowering your character in a memorable degree, and putting you quite
among the commonality and mob of your sex, when I thought I saw in you
symptoms entitling you to be ranked among those noble spirits that do
honour to our nature.[148]
Chiding her to remember that she had âall the goods of fortuneâ and
great potential of her own, Godwin argued forcefully that his daughter
not give up on life simply because she had lost an infant child. The
philosopherâs tone was strict but not, as Shelley later wrote,
hard-hearted (a hard-hearted father would not have written at all).
Exactly how Mary received her fatherâs admonition is unclear, but a
letter to her friend Amelia Curran shows that she derived no consolation
from it. Shelley himself was appalled at Godwinâs letters, not least
because they included side-swipes at the poetâs failings (the
philosopher was again in desperate need of money he believed Shelley had
promised to pay) and, after their next child was born (Percy Florence,
on 12 November 1819), he took to withholding Godwinâs letters from Mary
to preserve her peace of mind.[149]
Maryâs feelings of being torn between father and husband seem to find
their expression in her novel Mathilda, begun a few months after
Williamâs death. The novel reverses the dynamics of Maryâs own
relationships: the poet Woodville is the heroineâs platonic friend and
listener, her father the wild and impassioned suitor â a man who
confesses to an incestuous love for his daughter because he cannot bear
to lose the last image of her departed mother to another man. We should
naturally be wary of reading too much biographical insight into
Mathilda, though all of the authorâs novels draw on elements of her own
life. Mary sent the manuscript to Godwin to arrange its publication, but
the philosopher was so shocked by the work that he refused to pass the
manuscript on, or return it. The reactionary press had circulated
rumours for years that Mary, Claire and Percyâs relationship was somehow
incestuous; Shelley himself had needed to be discouraged from placing an
incestuous (brotherâsister) relationship at the centre of the poem Laon
and Cythna (later retitled The Revolt of Islam). Godwin wrote that he
found much to admire in Mathilda, but regarded the incest as
âdetestableâ. While it would be fair to criticise the philosopherâs
decision to suppress his daughterâs most challenging novel (it remained
unpublished until the late twentieth century), we might also sympathise
with Godwinâs refusal to give their enemies the ammunition for a fresh
round of assaults. Whether the philosopher acted out of cowardice or
protectiveness is a matter of perspective, but the decision illustrates
the man that Godwin had become.
The contrast between Godwinâs pragmatism in 1820 and the principled
stand of the 1790s encourages us to see a philosopher who had been
beaten down by the consequences of his earlier bravery and who was
quietly abandoning his principles to stay afloat. A key difference
between the 1790s and the 1810s, however, is the addition of a large
family and business to Godwinâs concerns. What so much of Godwinâs
relationship with Percy and Mary Shelley demonstrates is the
philosopherâs willingness to compromise in order to protect the people
around him. Godwin, as an individual, had lived the principles he
espoused to the best of his ability (he outlined his own failings in
writing on more than one occasion, and those shortcomings connect neatly
with things he was criticised for throughout his life). As a father,
husband and employer, he accepted a responsibility to accommodate
âthings as they areâ while still clinging on to the ideas that had made
him hero or villain to the reading public.
In an 1819 letter to Lady Caroline Lamb, Godwin declared himself retired
from practical politics. Seeking the philosopherâs endorsement for her
brother-in-lawâs parliamentary campaign, Lady Caroline wrote Godwin a
courtly letter that betrayed the assumption that his apparent
disengagement was a matter of principle:
My dear madam, â You have mistaken me. Mr G. Lamb has my sincere good
wishes. My creed is a short one. I am in principle a Republican, but in
practice a Whig.
But I am a philosopher: that is, a person desirous to become wise, and I
aim at that object by reading, by writing, and a little by conversation.
But I do not mix in the business of the world, and I am too old to alter
my course, even at the flattering invitation of Lady Caroline Lamb.[150]
A few months later, mounted troops killed over a dozen people at St
Peterâs Fields in Manchester as they attempted to arrest the leaders of
a mass meeting in support of parliamentary reform. The event quickly
became known as the Peterloo Massacre, and provoked horror among
reformers and radicals of every stripe (Godwinâs diary records âoutrage
at Manchesterâ). The atmosphere of the country became increasingly
hostile. Outbreaks of anti-government violence occurred in Huddersfield
and Burnley in the autumn, and the government responded with the Six
Acts â a series of bills restricting the right of the people to assemble
and extending taxes on publications to curtail printing by working-class
radicals. In February 1820, revolutionaries attempted to assassinate the
cabinet â the Cato Street Conspiracy â but were lured into a trap by
government spies. Godwin noted many of these events but did not, as he
had done in the 1790s or in 1815, reach for his pen to make public
comment. He may have suffered a stroke in November 1818 (the diary
merely notes âparalysisâ) and in December 1819 seems to have lost the
use of his left hand (âtorporâ). His health had deteriorated steadily
for over a decade; he recorded regular headaches and dizziness. Though
always a believer in quiet reform over revolutionary action, the
philosopher was finally too sick to join the (metaphorical) barricades.
Yet Godwin had always been more comfortable, and more confident, in the
realm of theory. The philosopher may have considered himself âretiredâ
but he was still a man of interest for parliamentarians and radical
thinkers, still sought after for his conversation on learned topics.
Godwin still believed in the power of conversation to effect change â in
late 1819 he wrote to and called on James Scarlett, the barrister tasked
with prosecuting the Peterloo demonstrators. The details of what they
might have discussed are lost, but Godwin might have been trying to
steer Scarlett to a position similar to the one the philosopher
expressed in the 1795 Considerations: critical of mass demonstration but
emphatically rejecting government repression.[151] His exchange of
letters with Lady Caroline Lamb began some years of friendship between
them; Godwin spent a few days as the familyâs guest in 1822. Lady
Carolineâs husband, the future Lord Melbourne, would eventually serve as
prime minister (and close confidant) to Queen Victoria. At the other end
of the spectrum, the philosopher had in recent years become a friend of
the satirist William Hone â a man whose deliberate provocation of the
establishment had seen him tried for blasphemy, and acquitted, in what
is now seen as a landmark case for British freedom of speech. Godwin
felt that he had one last philosophical contribution to make: the
comprehensive reply to Malthus that friends had urged him to write for
nearly two decades. As he wrote to Clairmont, on one of her trips to
Southend:
What matters what becomes of this miserable carcass, if I can live for
ever in true usefulness? And this must be the case in the present
instance: for whatever becomes of my individual book if I am right the
system of Malthus can never rise again, and the world is delivered for
ever from this accursed apology in favour of vice and misery, of
hard-heartedness and oppression.[152]
His old rival had not been idle in that time, and now enjoyed a position
as professor at the East India Companyâs training college at Haileybury.
Malthus had continued to revise and expand the Essay every few years
(1817 saw the publication of the fifth edition), and the mathematicianâs
language had hardened. The collegial discussion of the original essay
had gradually given way to a tone of authority, the debate with Godwin
was pushed into the background, and the Essay read more and more like a
justification of the status quo â in general, advocating the elimination
of all forms of welfare support outside private charity (Malthus quotes
the biblical âhe who does not work, neither shall he eatâ, with
approval). Most appallingly for Godwin, Malthus consciously did not
exempt children or the disabled from his rhetoric, arguing that
communities had no moral obligation to care for abandoned children
(indeed, that doing so only added to the underclass of the future) and
proposing legal penalties for children born out of wedlock.
With the help of his disciple, Rosser, Godwin spent two years
researching and writing his answer, publishing Of Population in November
1820. Time had given Godwin the space to question Malthusâs breezy
formula. No longer accepting an inevitable disparity between population
growth and food production, Godwin now sought to prove that societyâs
inequality was not a natural consequence of overpopulation. For all the
mathematician dressed his theory up as a law of nature, it rested on
patchy data. Now armed with two surveys worth of British census figures
(1801 and 1811) and writing to obtain comparable information from the
United States, Godwin was willing to argue that Britain was not, in
fact, overpopulated â its inequality was the direct result of political
and moral errors that Malthusâs theory apparently sought to absolve.
Since the Reply to Parr, Godwin and Malthusâs relationship had cooled.
It had been some years since the two had exchanged even coldly polite
letters, and the book betrays a certain anger at seeing Malthusâs theory
lauded for essentially telling the political and economic establishment
what it wanted to hear. Though Godwinâs argument carries considerable
moral force, two-thirds of the book is given over to the philosopherâs
own demographic research. Of Population uses census data from Sweden and
Paraguay to provide examples of places where good living conditions have
occurred alongside negligible population growth, while using information
gathered from sources in Massachusetts to argue that the doubling of
population Malthus observed in the US was the result of immigration
rather than an unrestricted birth rate.
Godwinâs argument can be described as counter-reactionary: the most
recent editions of Malthusâs Essay endorsed âthings as they areâ,
allowing Godwin to emphasise its distance from more traditional moral
values. Throughout the book Godwin co-opts conservative rhetoric,
describing the Essay as unchristian and reminding readers that, for all
it served to rationalise away criticism of contemporary society, it was
a work of philosophical âinnovationâ that true conservatives should
regard with suspicion. The philosopherâs argument is not entirely
successful â his appeals to religious values are hollow, though they do
expose the hypocrisy of those among Malthusâs defenders who were keen to
denounce heterodoxy when it did not benefit them. Godwin is on stronger
ground when he returns to progressive arguments; Malthusâs Essay
validates passivity and intellectual cowardice, asserting that attempts
to improve humanityâs lot are (at best) futile or (at worst)
counterproductive. What Godwin attempts to show is that such a
conclusion flies in the face of everything we know about ourselves as a
culture. Historical data suggests that we adapt ourselves (and our
communities) to the environment and the available resources,
advancements in knowledge suggest that we can rise to the challenge of
providing for larger populations in the future. Underlying Godwinâs
argument is the position that inequality is not a symptom of human
misery, but its principal cause.
Of Population did not strike the death blow that Godwin apparently hoped
it would. Malthusâs existing critics welcomed the addition of figures
that offered a different picture to those found in the Essay, and
commended Godwinâs challenge to the Essayâs principle argument regarding
the United States. Malthusâs supporters condemned the tone of Godwinâs
book, implied jealousy, and accused the philosopher of making personal
attacks on his opponent. The reasonable criticism was made that Godwinâs
Swedish data was open to interpretation, but there was little common
ground that would have allowed a more productive discussion. One
influential reader who remained unconvinced was US President James
Madison, who was forwarded a copy of Godwinâs book by ambassador Richard
Rush. Madison denounced Godwinâs argument on US immigration as a slight
on American fertility, though the President held his own complex
opinions on the subject of population that ran contrary to those of
Malthus.[153] The most abusive response came from Malthus himself,
however. Offered the chance to review the book (anonymously) in the
Edinburgh Review, Malthus denounced Of Population as âthe poorest and
most old-womanish performance that has fallen from the pen of any writer
of name, since we first commenced our critical careerâ. The
mathematician used his platform to accuse Godwin of misrepresentation,
and asserted that the philosopherâs research only served to make his own
thesis incontrovertible.[154] Godwin had never been impressed with
authors who wrote from the cover of anonymity to praise their own work
(he had briefly fallen out with Coleridge on the subject, fifteen years
earlier) and, on learning of the review, he complained of the abuse in a
letter to Mary. He did not see Malthus again until 12 December 1822, a
meeting the diary records as âsilentâ.
Poverty and misery became very real considerations for the Godwins when
they were finally evicted from Skinner Street in May 1822. After a
series of legal battles, spanning several years, a man called Read was
recognised as the lawful owner of the property. Court rulings also
established Readâs right to both evict his tenants and charge them for
years of backdated rent. Shelley had refused the Godwins his assistance
as far back as the summer of 1820, bitterly complaining of how little
difference his money had ever made. Read sent bailiffs to prevent them
from absconding with the Juvenile Libraryâs stock. William Junior
organised an immediate sale that allowed the family to salvage what was
left of the business and reopen the shop at 195 Strand at the beginning
of July.
On 4 August, news reached London that Shelley had drowned while sailing
on the Ligurian Sea. Godwin was hurt to have received the news
second-hand (from an agent of Leigh Hunt), not realising that Mary had
herself been close to death only a few weeks earlier after a miscarriage
left her bleeding uncontrollably. As she recovered, Mary wrote to her
father regularly (the letters have since been lost).
After months of negotiation, the courts ordered Godwin to pay just short
of ÂŁ400 in rent arrears. The ever-dependable Marshall stepped in to
persuade the publisher John Murray to organise a private subscription
fund to pay the philosopherâs debt. The amount raised fell short of what
was needed but the list of subscribers records a host of distinguished
names from Godwinâs career, both of friends and adversaries from the
literary and political world. Basil Montagu and Anthony Carlisle
contributed, as did Byron. Walter Scott sent ÂŁ10, on the understanding
that his gift would remain private. Charles Lamb and Tom Turner had
already given money to help the Juvenile Library escape Skinner Street.
Mackintosh helped the subscription fund go public with the aim of
raising more money. Mary volunteered the proceeds from her latest novel,
Valperga, which Godwin edited for her and was published in February
1823. The Edinburgh publisher John Anderson sent word of his interest in
publishing a new edition of The Enquirer. Read took what money had been
raised by subscription and agreed to receive the rest in instalments.
For a brief period, it seemed as if the storm had passed. Godwin was
busy at work writing another history (of the Civil War and the
Commonwealth), and Mary was finally on her way home.
Mary arrived back in London on 25 August, her father and brother waiting
for her on the wharf as she arrived. She described the new house to
Leigh Hunt as âdismalâ but âinfinitely better than the Skinner St.
oneâ.[155] The first of many stage adaptations of Frankenstein (Richard
Brinsley Peakeâs Presumption) was playing at the English Opera House
when she returned â Mary could expect no money from it, but Godwin
cannily arranged for the novel to be reprinted in order to capitalise on
the playâs success.[156] The play was a hit, spawning a host of
imitators and parodies, and cementing Frankensteinâs image in the
popular consciousness (many elements familiar to modern audiences from
James Whaleâs 1931 film originally derive from Peakeâs adaptation).
Peakeâs script dispenses with much of the novelâs complexity â the
creature is mute, and so unable to speak in its own defence â and
delivers an unambiguous warning against hubris, along with comic and
musical interludes. Mary, Godwin and William Junior saw the play a few
days after her return; Maryâs letter to Leigh Hunt records her
amusement.
The first volume of Godwinâs History of the Commonwealth appeared in
1824. Originally contracted by Henry Colburn to write two volumes, the
philosopher allowed his enthusiasm to get the better of him once again.
The final work spanned four volumes, the last mostly a study of Cromwell
as a statesman, that Colburn was forced to publish in stages (as each
volume was finished) until 1828. Godwinâs work is noteworthy for being
one of the earliest histories of the Civil War era to favour the
parliamentarian cause. For over a century, the standard text on the
period had been Clarendonâs History of the Rebellion â as a royalist
insider, the author had been present at many of the defining moments of
the struggle, but his bias was clear. The only work of similar authority
on the parliament side were the memoirs of Bulstrode Whitelock, but that
was an altogether less accessible and less comprehensive text, known
only to serious scholars of the period. Godwinâs history is a conscious
attempt to reset the balance. The philosopher was openly critical of
Charles I â previous histories, relying on Clarendonâs assessment of the
monarchâs intentions and motivations had erred on the side of sympathy â
but avoided partisanship by condemning the intolerance of the religious
independents on the other side. Godwin presented Cromwell as a complex
character: a spiritual man who wielded power ruthlessly, a man who had
fought to curtail the power of monarchy who found himself taking
dictatorial powers when he found parliament wanting. The philosopherâs
admiration for Cromwell is clear, but he does not shy away from
denouncing the Lord Protectorâs sometimes arbitrary use of authority.
The History was well-received but, as a large and expensive work, was
never destined to become a popular success. The Juvenile Library
struggled on until the nationwide financial crash of 1825, as
out-of-control speculation caused the collapse of many small or regional
banks â leaving businesses that ran on credit (as much of publishing
industry did) in dire straits. Bankruptcy came as a relief for Godwin.
The years of begging, arguing and dodging were finally over, and the
fall had come at a time when even the most respected publishers were in
danger of collapse. The Edinburgh publishers Archibald Constable and
James Ballantyne were both bankrupted, and Walter Scott was almost
ruined as a result. The family â now just really Godwin and Clairmont â
moved from the Strand to a house in Gower Place. William was now a
reporter for the Morning Chronicle, Mary engaged in a drawn-out battle
with her in-laws over her right to publish her husbandâs work and
custody of Percy Florence. Charles and Claire spent most of these years
in Europe (Charles mostly in Vienna; Claire working as a governess in
Moscow, and later Dresden) but made the time to return home and share
their experiences. Through Mary and William, Godwin was introduced to
another generation of writers: the American novelist James Fenimore
Cooper, novelist and future MP Edward Bulwer-Lytton, the adventurer (and
friend of Shelley) Edward Trelawny. Frances Wright (the abolitionist and
US social reformer) introduced herself, writing to Godwin about the
community she had built in Tennessee before she called at Gower Place
with Robert Dale Owen in tow. The philosopher was not always the centre
of attention, however, Robert Dale later confessed that he had become
smitten with Mary, and Mary herself joked at the suggestion of a romance
between herself and Godwinâs old friend Washington Irving.
Release from the stress of the Juvenile Library sparked a renaissance in
Godwinâs writing. Less than a week after he sent the final volume of the
History to his publisher, he had begun work on a new novel. Cloudesley,
published in March 1830, is a rambling story that meanders from
political intrigue in Russia to personal intrigue in Greece on its way
to another exploration of Godwinâs favourite theme â education, or
rather the relationship between mentor and student. The story was
inspired by the then famous Annesley case, where it was alleged that the
sixth Earl of Anglesey had stolen his title by arranging the kidnap of
the true heir. Though the titular Cloudesley participates in such a
crime, he seeks to atone by raising the heir himself, and the boy
undoubtedly grows into a better man under Cloudesleyâs guidance than he
would have done as an earl. The novelâs conclusion argues that love is a
more significant force than either blood or wealth. All the novelâs
conflicts stem from the pursuit of status poisoning the wellspring of
human affection, but love (familial love, respect and fraternity) is
ultimately triumphant. It is arguably the weakest of Godwinâs mature
novels. The work contains passages of great eloquence, but the narrative
itself wanders almost aimlessly (there are three stories within
Cloudesley, but only two of them are connected) before resolving itself
with relatively little excitement. Reviewers found it philosophically
interesting, but dramatically inert, and even Bulwer-Lytton (writing in
the New Monthly) was forced to concede that much of the first volume was
superfluous. Before Cloudesley had even been published, however, Godwin
was writing another collection of essays. Thoughts on Man (1831) is in
some ways a philosophical memoir, revisiting topics covered in Political
Justice and The Enquirer from nearly forty years distance. The
philosopher considered it âthe most faultless book I ever printedâ,
though perhaps few agreed â it was rejected by eleven publishers before
finding a home with Effingham Wilson.[157]
Little of what Godwin had to say was new to those who had kept current
with his work. At a time when parliamentary reform finally looked like a
real possibility, reviewers found Godwinâs criticism of secret ballots
quixotic â but it was a position he had held for decades. Philosophical
critics have leapt upon Godwinâs reconsideration of equality at birth
(i.e. the position espoused in earlier works â originally derived from
HelvĂ©tius â that all human beings were born with the same potential, and
that their environment made them different), but Godwin expresses this
so vaguely that it appears more an idle musing than a developed
position. In short, Godwin argues in Thoughts on Man that young people
do appear to be born better disposed towards some things than others
(say, languages, or mathematics, or making things) but that the details
of this do not become apparent until they are more developed. Crucially,
however, Godwin is firm that all young people have equal potential â it
is simply a matter of allowing them to find the field in which they can
excel. This obviously has political and philosophical implications, but
these are fully in tune with Godwinâs other positions. Thoughts on Man
does offer the philosopherâs longest discussion of gender and
relationships. Godwin regards men and women as naturally equal, but
argues that loving relationships (of all kinds) are based on inequality.
The philosopher begins from the love of parents for their children:
parents protect, teach and sacrifice for young people though there is no
real benefit to the parents themselves (Godwin considers biological ties
irrelevant). We love those who need us. Love between adults arises from
(complementary) difference. Godwin discusses adult relationships in
terms of superiors and inferiors, but also stresses that the gap between
partners must not be too great (they must be on the same level to
appreciate each other) encouraging us to read Godwinâs idea of love as
more about give and take than dominance and submission. Each partner
gives of themselves to supply what the other is lacking. The
philosopherâs principal example of this is the relationship between
Achilles and Patroclus â the famously wrathful hero in love with his
companionâs kindness and humanity. Godwin asserts that equals cannot
fully be at peace with one another, forever uneasy at exposing their
shortcomings to someone so much like themselves. The philosopher argues
that the inequality of loving relationships explains the development of
romantic chivalry. Where the ancients simply excluded women from the
public sphere, Godwin claims that medieval culture developed mutually
supportive roles for men and women (women holding moral authority, men
physical) that enshrined mutual deference and respect. The philosopher
strikes a Burkean note here, offering no judgment on how often medieval
(or contemporary) culture failed to reach this ideal. We should not,
however, read this as a simple endorsement of gender roles. Godwin
concludes that the purest love is based on mutual submission â and it is
clear from his letters to both Wollstonecraft and Clairmont that he
regarded them as his protectors as much as he was theirs.
What is most interesting about Thoughts on Man is its candour. Godwinâs
discussion of failure provides us with an insight into his thinking
process â the philosopher describes enlightenment as an attempt to take
control of oneâs own confusion, bringing what we think we know to the
test again and again until it becomes clear. In a later essay, Godwin
attempts to confront his own shyness and discusses the difficulty of
remaining true to oneâs own beliefs in the face of criticism.
Thoughts on Man may not have represented many new ideas, but Godwinâs
old ones were still in demand. In 1830 both Godwin and Mary were
approached by a breakaway publisher, Richard Bentley, looking to buy the
copyrights to their most successful novels. Bentley was one of the first
British publishers to make extensive use of stereotyping, allowing him
to commission large print runs for minimal cost and quickly reprint if
there was further demand.[158] The publisher bought the rights to Caleb
Williams, St Leon, Fleetwood and Frankenstein, printing new editions of
each work (Mary took the opportunity to significantly revise the text)
as part of his Standard Novels series alongside the works of Jane
Austen, James Fenimore Cooper and Victor Hugo. Dispensing with the wide
margins and large type used by other publishers, the Standard Novels
were small and affordable â Caleb Williams initially retailed at six
shillings, a third of what it cost in 1794 â allowing Godwinâs novels to
reach a far larger audience than had hitherto been possible.[159]
William died in September 1832, a victim of the cholera epidemic that
swept Britain that year. Godwin wrote that his son had spiralled from
perfect health to death in less than four days; his parents attended him
around the clock for the last two days of his life. He was twenty-nine
years old. William had led a short but troubled life; Godwinâs memoir
describes his fiery disposition and difficulties in settling down on a
career. He spent some time in prison (probably for debt) and apparently
married without telling the rest of his family. He left behind a novel,
Transfusion, which a grieving Godwin published (in 1835) with a preface
describing his sonâs character, and which speaks to the great pride the
philosopher took in the achievements of his often wayward son. The novel
itself feels unfinished; the story takes a turn for the fantastic in its
final chapters but ends with its best idea almost unused. Nonetheless,
the work speaks to the potential that Godwinâs preface describes â and
is notably closer in spirit to one of Maryâs novels than one of
Godwinâs.
Bentley published Godwinâs next novel, Deloraine, in 1833 (though using
the premium three-volume format, rather than as part of the Standard
Novels series). Deloraine combines themes from the philosopherâs most
successful novels â a man on the run, an exalted first wife and a
protagonist tragically consumed by jealousy regarding his second.
Poignantly, the narrator of Deloraine is eventually saved by the efforts
of his dutiful daughter. Godwinâs letters imply that, when writing of
the novel stalled, it was Maryâs input that provided the spark to get
the story moving again.[160] Father and daughter often worked in
partnership in these years, proposing ideas to each other and making use
of each otherâs publishing contacts. It was Godwin that introduced Mary
to Henry Colburn, who would publish her novels The Last Man (1826),
Perkin Warbeck (1830) and Lodore (1835).[161] Mary tried several times
(unsuccessfully) to leverage her closer relationship with John Murray to
her fatherâs benefit. Mary had less need than her father to make a
living by her pen, an agreement with Sir Timothy Shelley provided an
allowance to support Percy Florence on condition that she published
nothing controversial. This arrangement was a frequent source of grief
for Mary, as Shelleyâs father was more than willing to see his sonâs
literary works forgotten. Godwin and Clairmont were worse off, but they
struggled along as they always had. The political climate had changed,
however, and now Godwin had friends in high places.
In November 1830, the Duke of Wellingtonâs government had been unseated
by a vote of no confidence and replaced with a Whig administration led
by Earl Grey. Godwin had known Grey since the politician had been a
junior MP. William Lamb (Lord Melbourne) was home secretary, and Lord
Brougham (who had helped Shelley with his custody battle) was Lord
Chancellor. Godwin wrote regularly to them in the first few months of
their government, and frequently attempted to call on them â knowing the
philosopher, probably hoping to advise them on political matters. Greyâs
(later, Melbourneâs) government stood for four years, successfully
extending the right to vote with the Great Reform Act of 1832 and
finally outlawing slavery across the empire in 1833. Once the government
was well-established in 1832, Godwin wrote to Brougham to request a
sinecure (any of the largely honorary but still salaried positions that
was within the purview of an administration to grant to its supporters).
Perhaps to the philosopherâs surprise, his request was granted, and in
1833 Godwin was appointed to the role of office keeper and yeoman usher
of the receipt of the exchequer â a job that came with ÂŁ200 a year and a
house in New Palace Yard. Though the position entailed little actual
work, Godwin attempted to make himself useful, the sociologist Harriet
Martineau wrote of him taking her on a tour of parliament and providing
anecdotes from his decades of political and historical research. Asking
for and accepting a sinecure was obviously a compromise â he had railed
against the practice in Political Justice â but he probably felt the
need to provide for Clairmont and knew that, in his advanced age, the
government had little to gain from buying his support. The job was given
out of charity, and offered the chance for Godwin to live out his last
years in peace. The philosopher was at the theatre during the great fire
that destroyed the Palace of Westminster in October 1834, he returned to
find that Clairmont had single-handedly moved all of their books and
papers to a safe location. It would be amusing to claim that the great
philosophical anarchist was responsible for the destruction of
parliament (the fire started from the burning of tally sticks in his
department, the Exchequer) but such was Godwinâs affection for the
institution, he might not have seen the funny side. A few days before
the fire, the position of yeoman usher had officially been abolished.
Godwin had originally been told the job was for life, and he wrote
nervous letters to Lord Melbourne asking him to confirm this. In the
end, Melbourne was dismissed by the king before he came to decision. In
the end it was the new prime minister, the Conservative Sir Robert Peel,
that agreed that Godwin could stay. Peelâs letter is of particular
interest:
I will not defer the assurance, that whatever I can do consistently with
my public duty, to prevent a measure of Official Retrenchment from
bearing hardly upon one so far advanced in years, and so distinguished
by his literary character, I will do as well from a sense of Justice, as
from a grateful recollection of the pleasure I have derived from those
Works to which, with a just Pride, you have referred.[162]
The last work Godwin published in his lifetime was a piece of cultural
history. Lives of the Necromancers (1834) was an investigation into
peopleâs belief in magic before the modern era. Unlike the philosopherâs
other histories, Lives of the Necromancers is well-contained, discussing
a series of isolated episodes, cases and literary texts and drawing
conclusions from them. It is probably the most accessible of his
historical works. The work that Godwin left unfinished at the time of
his death was a collection of essays on religion under the title The
Genius of Christianity Unveiled. He left it to Mary to publish, as his
literary executor, but it was not printed until 1873. The essays form
the philosopherâs last statement on spirituality: he declares âa
religious senseâ to be essential to a healthy mind, the ability to be
awed and to accept that we as individuals are not the centre of the
universe. Religion itself, however, encroaches too far, playing on our
sense of awe (in the power of a creator) to justify a suspension of
reason (i.e. faith). Godwin argues that Christianity is an essentially
incoherent doctrine: an infinitely loving god that nevertheless
threatens eternal punishment, an omniscient god that demands formal
worship in addition to a pure heart. Yet Godwin concludes that religions
are human creations that only touch on true spirituality, our
understanding of our insignificance in the totality of nature. If there
is a purpose to life, Godwin says, it is to live â âfor there is no
work, nor device, nor knowledge, nor wisdom in the graveâ.[163]
Godwin recorded his meetings, reading and health until the last two
weeks of his life. The philosopher died on the evening of 7 April 1836;
his wife and daughter were by his side. He was buried alongside
Wollstonecraft in St Pancras Churchyard.
The notes that accompanied Godwinâs will asked Mary to publish The
Genius of Christianity Unveiled, but expressed a certain ambivalence
about the rest of his unpublished work. His wishes were pragmatic: âLet
all that are not presently printed be consigned to the flames. But for
the consideration of profit to be made, I should pass sentence of
condemnation on nearly the whole âŠâ[164] Mary did the reverse, sitting
on the religious essays while gathering her fatherâs notes, manuscripts
and letters about her in preparation to write Godwinâs biography. She
and Clairmont signed a contract with Henry Colburn within weeks of the
philosopherâs death, but the work was never completed (a rough draft of
Godwinâs life up to 1800 still survives). Mary turned her attentions to
editing an official edition of Shelleyâs poems in 1838, having finally
received Sir Timothyâs consent. With help from her friend Caroline
Norton and Edward Bulwer-Lytton, Mary helped to negotiate a pension from
the Royal Bounty Fund for Clairmont until the latterâs death in 1841.
Percy Florence inherited the Shelley title in 1844, forever freeing Mary
from financial concerns. In 1848 Percy Florence married Jane Gibson, who
would go on to play an enthusiastic role in protecting the familyâs
literary legacy.
In some ways the legacy was already well in hand. The 1832 Reform Act
had done away with many of parliamentâs worst abuses but had not
significantly extended the right to vote. The Chartist movement
campaigned, much as the radicals of the 1790s had, for wider suffrage
and a more democratic system of government. They appropriated Godwinâs
work for their own purposes: William Thomsonâs Chartist Circular
(1839â42) used selective quotations from Caleb Williams, focusing on the
protagonistâs fortitude and willingness to resist. The Chartist leader
Henry Vincent read Political Justice while imprisoned for sedition â he
was tutored on it by Godwinâs former ally, Francis Place â and upon
leaving prison renounced direct action in favour of âmoral forceâ and
reform through education. The same year (1841) Caleb Williams was
serialised in John Cunninghamâs Novel Newspaper, effectively bringing
the price of the novel to four pence and reaching tens of thousands of
readers. A year later, the radical publisher James Watson issued a
fourth edition of Political Justice, priced at only five shillings and
made available in numbers (i.e. as a partwork) at six pence.[165]
The nascent Communist movement also took an interest in Godwin. In The
Condition of the Working Class in England (1845) Engels declared Bentham
and Godwin to be âthe two great practical philosophers of latest dateâ
and that Godwin in particular was âalmost exclusively the property of
the proletariatâ â implicitly, that he believed Godwinâs readers were
exclusively Chartists and other working-class radicals, in contrast to
Benthamâs following among the âRadical bourgeoisieâ.[166] Engels
privately confessed to Marx that he found Bentham tedious. In a letter
regarding a planned âlibrary of political theoryâ for German activists,
Engels considered the work of Charles Fourier, Henri de Saint-Simon and
Robert Owen to be indispensable. Godwin failed to make the cut,
principally because Engels could not support the strongly individualist
conclusions of Political Justice (he says that Godwin regards society as
âa luxury articleâ) but also because he saw an overlap between the
arguments of Political Justice and Marxâs (never finished) Kritik der
Politik und National-Okonomie.[167]
Mary died in 1851, and Lady Jane Shelley exercised tight control over
the Shelley-Godwin papers after her mother-in-lawâs death. Her own book
on Shelley, Shelley Memorials from Authentic Sources (1859), portrays
Godwin as a calming influence on the poetâs wild genius, but largely
omits any ideas or events that might appear controversial (thus mostly
skipping the years 1814â16). The critic W. M. Rossetti alleged that Lady
Jane had burned many Shelley documents that showed the poet in a bad
light, and it seems apparent that (on the advice of the British
Libraryâs Richard Garnett) she trimmed or destroyed a number of letters.
It seems clear that Lady Jane wanted the family to be remembered,
however, and she sponsored detailed biographies of Godwin (by Charles
Kegan Paul in 1876) and Shelley (by Edward Dowden in 1886) â the latter
almost certainly to provide an accurate but sympathetic antidote to the
many sensationalist memoirs of the poet that had emerged since his
death. Kegan Paulâs biography makes extensive use of Godwinâs
correspondence and is still a useful resource today, though it is often
unclear or inaccurate on points of fact. The work displays great
sympathy for Wollstonecraft, casts Clairmont in the role of wicked
stepmother, and depicts the philosopher as an awkward, humourless man
who attempted to live by high-minded but impractical ideals. Kegan
Paulâs portrait was highly influential. Dowden, however, was far less
sympathetic in his assessment of Godwin. Shelleyâs biographer was
dismissive about Godwinâs ideas and considered the poetâs interest in
Political Justice âunluckyâ. Dowdenâs original manuscript had taken a
cruelly irreverent line in discussing Godwin as a philosopher, until the
family expressed their displeasure and he was encouraged to revise.[168]
Dowdenâs guide to Godwin seems to have been the intellectual historian
Sir Leslie Stephen â Stephen was nakedly hostile to Godwinâs ideas, and
preferred to belittle rather than engage with them. Stephenâs account of
the philosopher in his History of English Thought (1876) makes only a
superficial reading of Political Justice before descending into ad
hominem. Stephen would, however, provide the article on Godwin for the
first Dictionary of National Biography (he was its editor from 1885 to
1891). The essay leans heavily on Kegan Paul but introduces new
inaccuracies (presenting Stephenâs sneering conjectures as fact) while
it moralises about Godwinâs dishonesty and hubris. Stephenâs writing on
Godwin would not have been out of place in the Anti-Jacobin or the
British Critic, yet it was treated as the mainstream scholarly position.
Godwin had a new champion outside the mainstream, however. 1886 also saw
the foundation of the anarchist newspaper, Freedom, under the editorship
of Charlotte Wilson. Pyotr Alekseievich Kropotkin, Wilsonâs co-founder
and lead writer, opened the first issue with a statement that Godwin
would have approved of:
We are socialists, disbelievers in property, advocates of the equal
claims of all to work for the community as seems good â calling no-one
master, and of the equal claim to each to satisfy as seems good to them,
their natural needs from the stock of social wealth they have laboured
to produce ⊠We are anarchists, disbelievers in the government of the
many by the few in any shape and under any pretext.[169]
The newspaper made frequent use of Godwin in its early years. Kropotkin
firmly claimed Godwin for anarchism in his 1910 essay for the
Encyclopaedia Britannica, âeven though he did not give that name to the
ideas developed in his remarkable workâ.[170] For Kropotkin, as for
subsequent intellectual historians such as George Woodcock, Godwin stood
at the head of a long anti-authoritarian tradition. The philosopher was,
however, more readily embraced by (left-wing) anarchists than
(right-wing) libertarians. Kropotkin saw anarcho-communism as the
natural continuation of Godwinâs ideas, and identified Max Stirner as
the philosopherâs parallel for the individualist-anarchist school
favoured by the right. Affection for Godwinâs work among the
anti-authoritarian left continued throughout the twentieth century: H.
N. Brailsfordâs study Shelley, Godwin and their Circle (1913) is far
more interested in Political Justice than it is the circle of Romantic
poets (and may be the first critical work to stress the influence of
Protestant Dissent on Godwinâs early thought); Herbert Read urged a
revival of Godwinâs ideas in the wake of the Second World War as a
counterbalance to the ever-expanding statism of its victors (Read would
later influence the Green Anarchism of Murray Bookchin).[171] The
philosopherâs thoughts on education were a profound influence on the
anarchist social historian Colin Ward, and his lectures collected as
Talking Schools (1995) called for educationists to take note of Godwinâs
ideas.
Assessing Godwinâs impact on (right) libertarianism is rather more
difficult. Murray Rothbard, the central thinker of twentieth-century
anarcho-capitalism, dismissed Godwin as a proto-Communist, yet
mainstream US libertarianism commonly traces its intellectual heritage
back to Thomas Jefferson â who certainly read Godwin and who, during his
presidency, was satirised as the philosopherâs disciple.[172] Less
tenuously, Josiah Warrenâs concept of individual sovereignty (and
rejection of âcommunismâ) emerged from his first-hand experience of
Owenâs âCommunity of Equalityâ at New Harmony, Indiana. The pivotal
Benjamin Tucker (editor of the periodical Liberty, which published the
work of individualist thinkers from both sides of the left/right divide)
cited both Jefferson and Warren as key influences on his own ideas. The
uniquely American individualism that originates in the transcendentalism
of Henry David Thoreau (and which defies simple political
categorisation) can be traced partially to Coleridge.
Godwin would probably have been gratified to see the revival of academic
interest in his work in the mid-twentieth century. F. E. L. Priestleyâs
scholarly edition of Political Justice (1946) made the full text readily
available for the first time in nearly a century, creating the
conditions for greater and greater critical attention from the 1940s up
to the present day. John P. Clark was the first to write a comprehensive
summary of Godwinâs thought (The Philosophical Anarchism of William
Godwin, 1977), clarifying the philosopherâs positions on a variety of
issues through reference to the entire body of his work. Mark Philp, in
Godwinâs Political Justice (1986), drilled down into all three editions
of the treatise to identify what are now accepted as the workâs core
principles (the ideas that remain consistent across all versions of the
text) and attempting to explain the thinking behind Godwinâs revisions.
Philp also led the project that digitised Godwinâs diary, making it
possible to cross reference nearly forty years of his social
engagements, reading, writing, and private events. In the twenty-first
century the reappraisal of Godwinâs novels and his influence on period
fiction has been led by Pamela Clemit and Tilottama Rajan, resulting in
a new generation of critics looking closely at novels other than Caleb
Williams (Clemit has also been instrumental in publishing the
philosopherâs correspondence). Godwin has been the subject of three
comprehensive biographies: by Don Locke (1980), Peter Marshall (1984,
revised 2017) and William St Clair (1989); each has its own merits.
The philosopher has, for a century or more, been overshadowed by the
rest of his family. Without wishing to diminish the vital contribution
of Wollstonecraft to feminism, or of the Shelleys to literature, this
imbalance has done Godwin a disservice and (until recent years) ignored
his place at the centre of English Romanticism. Not only should we take
note of Godwin as a novelist and political thinker, but also consider
his pioneering work as a historian and childrenâs publisher. In both
fields, Godwinâs work was ahead of its time. The philosopherâs ideas on
education, long neglected, were arrived at independently by progressive
educationists in the mid-twentieth century; his theory of reading
appears to be borne out by modern cognitive psychology. Godwinâs ideas
remain challenging, however. The philosopher envisions the eventual
demise of authority, not through its revolutionary overthrow, but
because of its ultimate irrelevance to a post-scarcity society. Godwin
argues that a society that values individual judgment has unlimited
scope for progress. By contrast, the more a community seeks to manage
its people the more it gradually diminishes them. The philosopherâs
ideas would be demanding even if they did not question some of the basic
principles the states we live in are founded upon, but we should take
heart from Godwinâs own continual return to his own works in search of
clarity and accuracy.
As we have seen, Godwin revised many of his major works, not only to
better express his thoughts, but because those thoughts had been
reconsidered and themselves revised. The philosopher considered this
essential to serious intellectual endeavour, though it brought him
criticism from contemporaries (both friend and foe). Godwinâs detractors
have frequently leapt on his revisions as if the philosopher had in some
way surrendered, sometimes ignoring that his new position was as much a
challenge to convention as his old one. Critical friends (Shelley among
them) sometimes lamented the qualification of his most challenging or
controversial ideas â Godwin was always the first to recognise that big
ideas were usually also complex ones, and he refused to sacrifice
accuracy for the sake of rhetoric. The philosopher might have been
amused at how much ink has been spilled over the search for consistency
in his work, arguing that âthe active and independent mind, the genuine
lover of and enquirer after truth, will inevitably pass through certain
revolutions of opinionâ.[173] Some core principles remain consistent
throughout his work however: the duty to act according to private
judgment, the value of conversation as both a critical tool and source
of education, and the importance of empathy to moral action. The
philosopher subjected his own work to rigorous examination â the threads
that remain consistent are the most robust.
It is not uncommon to read in Godwin scholarship the opinion that such
and such a revision causes the collapse of his whole system. This
assumes that the philosopher was an architect of systems. Few, if any,
of Godwinâs works seek to offer a comprehensive account of their subject
â Political Justice is his most systematic, but it remains an enquiry
(an investigation) rather than a manifesto, focused on exploding the
intellectual and moral contradictions of political society while only
speculating on the possible gains of doing differently. Other works make
suggestions, but further works question them. Some have regarded
Godwinâs career as a steady retreat from the boldness of the arguments
he advanced in the 1790s, Godwin himself saw his revisions as
improvements. For all his occasional pomposity, the philosopher could
acknowledge his own shortcomings and was receptive to honest criticism.
In The Enquirer, Godwin wrote that for an adult to (ethically) gain the
confidence of a child was difficult and that one should expect to fail.
The sentiment could be extended to describe the philosopherâs approach
to any worthwhile venture: we should attempt to do the right thing and
expect to get it wrong. Even when we think we are successful, we must
examine our conclusions â discuss those conclusions with others â and
expect to find holes and mistakes in our work. But we must persevere:
It is the characteristic of ordinary minds to fly from one scheme to the
other. It is the characteristic of genius, though it fall, to rise
again, though it suffer defeats to persist, and though obliged to alter
and modify many of its judgments, never to part with that clearness of
spirit which attended their formation.[174]
Such is the progressive nature of humanity. Godwin did not subscribe to
notions of inexorable improvement, the betterment of humanity was in his
view contingent on our ability to foster critical reason and empathy in
future generations. His writing stands as testament to that, both his
great works and his little ones. His life was full of failures too,
mistakes and compromises that we might fairly criticise him for. Yet
after every failure, the philosopher was back at his desk writing
something new â rising again, hoping to awaken genius.
The following abbreviations are used in the notes that follow for
brevity:
Barrell, John. Imagining the Kingâs Death: Figurative Treason, Fantasies
of Regicide 1793â1796 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000).
Brailsford, H. N. Shelley, Godwin and their Circle (London: Williams &
Norgate, 1913).
Brown, Ford K. The Life of William Godwin (London: J. M. Dent & Sons,
1926).
Clark, John P. The Philosophical Anarchism of William Godwin (Princeton,
NJ: Princeton University Press, 1977).
Clemit, Pamela and A. A. Markley (eds). Mary Shelleyâs Literary Lives
and Other Writings (London: Routledge, 2002).
Coleridge, Samuel Taylor. Collected Letters of Samuel Taylor Coleridge,
6 volumes, ed. Earl Leslie Griggs (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1956).
Coleridge, Samuel Taylor. The Collected Works of Samuel Taylor
Coleridge, 16 volumes, ed. Barbara E. Rooke (Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press, 1969).
Dowden, Edward. The Life of Percy Bysshe Shelley (London: Kegan Paul,
Trench, 1886).
Dunlap, William. A History of the American Theatre (New York: J. & J.
Harper, 1832).
Engels, Friedrich. The Condition of the Working Class in England, in
Marx/Engels Collected Works, vol. 4 (London: Lawrence and Wishart,
1975).
Garnett, R. S. (ed.). Letters About Shelley: Interchanged by Three
Friends â Edward Dowden, Richard Garnett and Wm. Michael Rossetti
(London: Hodder and Stoughton, 1917).
Gilmartin, Kevin. Writing Against Revolution: Literary Conservatism in
Britain 1790â1832 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007).
Godwin, William, The Collected Novels and Memoirs of William Godwin,
edited by Pamela Clemit, Mark Philp and Maurice Hindle, 8 volumes
(London: Pickering, 1992).
Godwin, William. Fables Ancient and Modern, Volume 1, ed. Suzanne L.
Barnett and Katherine Bennett Gustafson (College Park, MD: Romantic
Circles, University of Maryland, 2014; retrieved from
www.rc.umd.edu/editions/godwin_fables/index.html
).
Godwin, William, The Letters of William Godwin, edited by Pamela Clemit,
2 volumes to date (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011).
Godwin, William. Life of Chaucer (London: Richard Phillips, 1803).
Godwin, William. Of Population (London: Longman, Hurst, Bees, Orme and
Brown, 1820).
Godwin, William, Political and Philosophical Writings of William Godwin,
edited by Mark Philp, Pamela Clemit and Martin Fitzpatrick, 7 volumes
(London: Pickering, 1993).
Godwin, William. Political Justice, ed. F. E. L. Priestley (Toronto:
University of Toronto Press, 1946).
Graham, Kenneth W. (ed.). William Godwin Reviewed: A Reception History
1783â1834 (New York: AMS Press, 2001).
Hazlitt, William. Complete Works of William Hazlitt, ed. P. P. Howe
(London: J. M. Dent and Sons, 1930â4).
Hazlitt, William. Life of Thomas Holcroft, ed. Elbridge Colby (New York:
Benjamin Bloom, 1968).
Huscher, Hubert. âThe Clairmont Enigmaâ, in KeatsâShelley Memorial
Bulletin, XI (1960), pp. 10â16.
James, Felicity. Charles Lamb, Coleridge and Wordsworth: Reading
Friendship in the 1790s (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2008).
Jones, Frederick L. (ed.). The Letters of Percy Bysshe Shelley, Vol. 1:
Shelley in England (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1964).
Kegan Paul, Charles. William Godwin, His Friends and Contemporaries
(London: Henry S. King & Co., 1876).
Lamb, Charles, and Mary Lamb. Letters of Charles and Mary Lamb, ed.
Edwin W. Marrs (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1976).
Lamb, Charles, and Mary Lamb. The Works of Charles and Mary Lamb, vol.
2, ed. E. V. Lucas (New York: AMS Press, 1968).
Lerche, Jr., Charles O. âJefferson and the Election of 1800: A Case
Study in the Political Smearâ, in The William and Mary Quarterly, 5(4)
(October 1948), pp. 467â91.
Locke, Don. A Fantasy of Reason (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1980).
Maginn, William. âWilliam Godwinâ, in âA Gallery of Illustrious Literary
Charactersâ, no. 53, Fraserâs Magazine, 10 (October 1834), p. 463.
Malthus, Thomas. Essay on the Principle of Population, 1^(st) edition,
in The Works of Thomas Robert Malthus, vol. 1, ed. E. A. Wrigley and
David Souden (London: Routledge, 1986), ch. 10.
Marshall, Peter. William Godwin: Philosopher, Novelist, Revolutionary
(Oakland, CA: PM Press, 2017).
McCoy, Drew R. âJefferson and Madison on Malthus: Population Growth in
Jeffersonian Political Economyâ, in The Virginia Magazine of History and
Biography, 88(3) (July 1980), pp. 259â76.
Mellor, Anne K. Mary Shelley: Her Life, Her Fiction, Her Monsters (New
York: Routledge, 1989).
Parr, Samuel. A Spital Sermon, preached at Christ Church, upon Easter
Tuesday, April 15, 1800, to Which are Added Notes (London: J. Mawman,
1801).
Peck, Walter. Shelley: His Life and Work, vol. 2 (London: Ernest Benn,
1927).
Philp, Mark. Godwinâs Political Justice (London: Duckworth, 1986).
Pollin, Burton R. âGodwinâs Letter to Ogilvie, Friend of Jefferson, and
the Federalist Propagandaâ, in Journal of the History of Ideas, 28(3)
(JulyâSeptember 1967), pp. 432â44.
Price, Richard. Discourse on the Love of Our Country (London: T. Cadell,
1789).
St Clair, William. The Godwins and the Shelleys: The Biography of a
Family (London: Faber & Faber, 1989).
St Clair, William. The Reading Nation in the Romantic Period (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2004).
Shelley, Jane (ed.). Shelley and Mary (privately printed, c. 1882; a
copy is held at the Bodleian Library).
Shelley, Mary. The Journals of Mary Shelley, 1814â1844, ed. Paula R.
Feldman and Diana Scott-Kilvert (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987).
Shelley, Mary. Letters of Mary Wollstonecraft Shelley, ed. Betty T.
Bennett, vol. 1 (Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1980).
Southey, C. C. (ed.). The Life and Correspondence of Robert Southey (New
York: Harper, 1851).
Stafford, Vicki Parslow. âClaire Clairmont, Mary Janeâs Daughter: New
Correspondence with Claireâs Fatherâ, retrieved from
https://sites.google.com/site/maryjanesdaughter
.
Todd, Janet. Mary Wollstonecraft: A Revolutionary Life (New York:
Columbia University Press, 2000).
Van Lennep, W., et al. (eds). The London Stage 1660â1800 (Carbondale,
IL: Southern Illinois University Press, 1968).
Ward, Colin. Talking Schools (London: Freedom Press, 1995).
Wollstonecraft, Mary. Collected Letters of Mary Wollstonecraft, edited
by Ralph M. Wardle (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1979).
Woodcock, George. William Godwin: A Biographical Study (London:
Porcupine Press, 1946).
[1] CNMG, vol. 1, p. 10.
[2] Ibid., p. 30.
[3] Ibid., p. 37.
[4] Ibid., p. 31.
[5] Ibid., p. 36.
[6] Ibid., p. 42.
[7] Autobiographical note, Abinger Collection, c.32, folio 34. The
Abinger Collection, held at the Bodleian Library, comprises the
correspondence and papers of three generations of the Godwin/Shelley
family (hereafter referred to as âMS Abingerâ).
[8] CNMG, vol. 1, p. 53.
[9] Godwin liked to depict himself as a man of logic and reason, a
description that critics and biographers took at face value and later
amplified. Godwinâs first twentieth-century biographer, Ford K. Brown,
insisted that Godwin was âpainfully devoid of humour and of tasteâ (The
Life of William Godwin, London: J. M. Dent & Sons, 1926, p. 33). In
contrast, his writing regularly displays notes of whimsy that do not
chime with the later caricature.
[10] To the theatre historian William Dunlap, quoted in Dunlap, A
History of the American Theatre (New York: J & J Harper, 1832), p. 182.
[11] Charles Kegan Paul, William Godwin, His Friends and Contemporaries
(London: Henry S. King & Co., 1876), vol. 1, p. 61.
[12] Price, Discourse on the Love of Our Country (London: T. Cadell,
1789), p. 40.
[13] Ibid., p. 50.
[14] Letter, n.d., MS Abinger, c.17, folio 29.
[15] William Godwin, Of Population (London: Longman, Hurst, Bees, Orme
and Brown, 1820), p. iv.
[16] Mary Shelley reported her fatherâs account of (then prime minister)
Pitt the Youngerâs opinion that, âa three guinea book could never do
much harm among those who had not three shillings to spareâ. Pamela
Clemit and A. A. Markley (eds), Mary Shelleyâs Literary Lives and Other
Writings (London: Routledge, 2002), vol. 4, p. 86.
[17] William Hazlitt, Spirit of the Age in Complete Works of William
Hazlitt, ed. P. P. Howe (London: J. M. Dent and Sons, 1930â4), vol. 11,
p. 17.
[18] PPWG, vol. 3, p. 50.
[19] Ibid., p. 51.
[20] Ibid., p. 75.
[21] Ibid., p. 95.
[22] Ibid., p. 231.
[23] Ibid., p. 240.
[24] Ibid., p. 250.
[25] Ibid., p. 253.
[26] Ibid., p. 289.
[27] Ibid., p. 307.
[28] Ibid., p. 377.
[29] Ibid., pp. 374â5.
[30] Ibid., p. 423.
[31] Ibid., p. 457.
[32] Ibid., p. 453.
[33] Though present in English common law for centuries, the widespread
recognition of coverture as a legal principle is thought to stem from
William Blackstoneâs Commentaries on the Laws of England (1765â9).
Godwinâs diary records his use of Blackstone throughout his research for
Political Justice.
[34] PPWG, vol. 3, p. 453.
[35] Ibid., p. 454.
[36] The philosopher is pulling ideas out of the air, at this point.
Godwin is, to some extent, right: estimates today place the world
population at under one billion for much of his life â but demography
was poorly understood at the time, and reliable data largely absent. The
first modern census of Britain was conducted in 1801.
[37] CNMG, vol. 3, p. 4.
[38] For a novel, a conservative first printing in the period was
usually 500 copies. An established author with a recent success behind
him may have warranted an initial print run twice that size. Caleb
Williams went to a second and third edition before the end of the decade
(we lack numbers for either of them), so it seems likely that the novel
sold several thousand copies in only a few years. To put these numbers
in context, Sir Walter Scottâs novel Waverley (1814), one of the
best-selling novels of the period, sold around 40,000 copies in Scottâs
lifetime.
[39] MS Abinger, c.38, folio 2.
[40] Godwin does not directly address why this should be, but we can
infer his position from his theory of knowledge as it appears in the
revised Political Justice. Proper intellectual rigour insists that we
consider every situation as a case in itself, without allowing our prior
experiences (perhaps, prejudices) to cloud our judgment. Yet we are
unlikely to ever have the full picture of a situation, and past
experience can fill in many of the gaps (X has always been true in the
past, and it explains Y). We are inclined to look for heuristics to help
us make quick judgments: acting with benevolence seems likely to
increase happiness, so it supplies a âgoodâ answer, if not necessarily
the âcorrectâ one (which, all other things being uncertain, may be
impossible to ascertain). Experience may come to reinforce this. We
ultimately come to value benevolence as good, rather than the effects of
benevolence.
[41] John Barrell, Imagining the Kingâs Death: Figurative Treason,
Fantasies of Regicide 1793â1796 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000),
p. 553.
[42] The True Briton was one of a number of periodicals founded or
supported by government money around this time. The Sun and The True
Briton were daily newspapers operated by the government pamphleteer John
Heriot. The British Critic and William Giffordâs Anti-Jacobin were
literary journals that published reactionary satire and hostile reviews
of books that strayed from the conservative line of church, king, and
family values. For more on this, see John Barrell, Imagining the Kingâs
Death and Kevin Gilmartin, Writing Against Revolution: Literary
Conservatism in Britain 1790â1832 (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 2007).
[43] PPWG, vol. 2, p. 149.
[44] Letters, vol. 1, p. 138.
[45] CNMG, vol. 1, p. 112.
[46] Ibid., p. 110.
[47] Ibid., p. 122.
[48] Ibid.
[49] Godwin to Mary Wollstonecraft, 13 July 1796, in Letters, vol. 1, p.
171.
[50] Wollstonecraft to William Godwin, 17 August 1796, in Mary
Wollstonecraft, Collected Letters of Mary Wollstonecraft, edited by
Ralph M. Wardle (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1979), pp. 336â7
(hereafter referred to as âLetters of Wollstonecraftâ).
[51] Godwin to Mary Wollstonecraft, 17 August 1796, in Letters, vol. 1,
pp. 173â4.
[52] PPWG, vol. 5, p. 107.
[53] Godwin to Thomas Wedgwood, 19 April 1797, in Letters, vol. 1, p.
199.
[54] CNMG, vol. 1, p. 130.
[55] Godwin to Mary Hays, 10 April 1797, in Letters, vol. 1, p. 197.
[56] She may have principally meant religion. Wollstonecraft was a
believer â she had been a member of Richard Priceâs congregation at
Newington Green â while Godwin at the time still regarded himself as an
atheist. Wollstonecraft to Amelia Alderson, 11 April 1797, in Letters of
Wollstonecraft, p. 389.
[57] Wollstonecraft to Godwin, 21 May 1797, in Letters of
Wollstonecraft, p. 394.
[58] Wollstonecraft to Godwin, 19 June 1797, ibid., pp. 398â9.
[59] CNMG, vol. 1. p. 135.
[60] Ibid., p. 117.
[61] Ibid., p. 129.
[62] Roscoe papers MS 3958A.
[63] The most successful of these, Isaac DâIsraeliâs Vaurien (1797), may
have amused Wollstonecraft with its depiction â she wrote a note to
Godwin that read, âThere is a good boy write me a review âŠâ (17 March
1797). Caricatures of Godwin, Wollstonecraft, and many of their friends,
appeared in conservative and reactionary fiction throughout the period.
The book historian M. O. Grenby attempts to align some of these
characters with real-life personages in The Anti-Jacobin Novel
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001), pp. 226â7.
[64] Malthus, Essay on the Principle of Population, 1^(st) edition, in
E. A. Wrigley and David Souden (eds), The Works of Thomas Robert
Malthus, vol. 1 (London: Routledge, 1986), ch. 10.
[65] Malthus to Godwin, 20 August 1798, quoted in Letters, vol. 2.
[66] Godwin to James Mackintosh, January 1799, ibid.
[67] Mackintosh to Godwin, January 1799, quoted in ibid., p. 71.
[68] Unaddressed letter, June or July 1799, ibid., pp. 83â4.
[69] Godwin to George Robinson, 14 September 1799, ibid.
[70] William Maginn, âWilliam Godwinâ, in âA Gallery of Illustrious
Literary Charactersâ, no. 53, Fraserâs Magazine, 10 (October 1834), p.
463.
[71] CNMG, vol. 4, p. 270.
[72] Coleridge to John Thelwall, 13 May 1796, in Earl Leslie Griggs
(ed.), Collected Letters of Samuel Taylor Coleridge, 6 volumes (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1956), vol. 1, p. 215. See also The Friend in
Barbara E. Rooke (ed.), The Collected Works of Samuel Taylor Coleridge,
16 volumes (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1969), vol. 4, p.
334â8.
[73] Coleridge to Godwin, 29 March 1811, ibid., vol. 3, p. 315.
[74] Godwin knew Frend well, the two were both frequently dinner guests
of Horne Tooke. Frend had been connected romantically with Mary Hays,
and her novel Memoirs of Emma Courtney (1796) draws on the experience â
Godwin appears in the novel as Emmaâs mentor, Mr Francis.
[75] CNMG, vol. 1, p. 53.
[76] Letters of Charles and Mary Lamb, vol. 1, p. 185.
[77] In the poem âLiving without God in the Worldâ (in Robert Southeyâs
Annual Anthology the previous year) the poet wrote that, âSome braver
spirits of a modern stamp/Affect a Godhead nearer âŠâ. This is discussed
in detail in Felicity James, Charles Lamb, Coleridge and Wordsworth:
Reading Friendship in the 1790s (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2008),
pp. 134â6.
[78] Reported by Robert Southey in C. C. Southey (ed.), The Life and
Correspondence of Robert Southey (New York: Harper, 1851), p. 536â7.
[79] Charles Lamb to Thomas Manning, August 1801, in Edwin W. Marrs
(ed.), Letters of Charles and Mary Lamb (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University
Press, 1976), vol. 1, p. 230.
[80] Samuel Parr, A Spital Sermon, preached at Christ Church, upon
Easter Tuesday, April 15, 1800, to Which are Added Notes (London: J.
Mawman, 1801), p. 4.
[81] Godwin to Samuel Parr, 24 April 1800, in Letters, vol. 2, p. 201.
[82] âPray come & see me â I admire your Talents â I love your
Philanthropy â I am ambitious of your friendshipâ. Parr to Godwin, 4
September 1794, MS Abinger, c.2, folio 47.
[83] Parr to Godwin, 29 April 1800, MS Abinger, c.5, folios 113â18.
[84] MS Abinger, c.21, folio 61.
[85] Parr, Spital Sermon, p. 52.
[86] PPWG, vol. 2, p. 165.
[87] Ibid., pp. 170â1.
[88] Ibid., p. 171.
[89] Ibid., p. 177.
[90] Ibid., p. 178.
[91] Ibid., p. 190.
[92] Ibid., pp. 190â1.
[93] Ibid., p. 198.
[94] Reproduced in ibid., pp. 211â3.
[95] This addition remained part of Malthusâs Essay even in its final,
definitive edition in 1826. See Wrigley and Souden, Works of Thomas
Robert Malthus, vol. 3, p. 55.
[96] Exact publication figures for Caleb Williams are unclear, though it
was obviously a resounding success for its first two publishers. For
context, St Leonâs initial print run of a thousand copies sold out in
less than two months but the novel did not reach a third printing until
1816.
[97] For more on theatre audiences, see W. Van Lennep et al. (eds) The
London Stage 1660â1800 (Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University
Press, 1968). Novel buying and circulating libraries are discussed at
length in William St Clair, The Reading Nation in the Romantic Period
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), which also contains
significant information on the early publication history of both Godwin
and Mary Shelleyâs work.
[98] Charles Lamb, âThe Old Actorsâ, London Magazine, April 1822, in E.
V. Lucas (ed.), The Works of Charles and Mary Lamb, vol. 2 (New York:
AMS Press, 1968), pp. 292â3.
[99] See Vicki Parslow Stafford, âClaire Clairmont, Mary Janeâs
Daughter: New Correspondence with Claireâs Fatherâ, retrieved from
https://sites.google.com/site/maryjanesdaughter
.
[100] For more on this, see Hubert Huscher, âThe Clairmont Enigmaâ in
Keatsâ Shelley Memorial Bulletin, XI (1960), pp. 10â16; and William St
Clair, The Godwins and the Shelleys: The Biography of a Family (London:
Faber & Faber, 1989), pp. 248â54.
[101] Godwin to unknown addressee, February or March 1801, in Letters,
vol. 2, p. 209â10.
[102] The âChaucer houseâ had been owned by the poetâs son, Sir Thomas
Chaucer in the fifteenth century. Godwinâs letter tells us that the
author believed his subject had resided there at some point, but there
is no evidence of this. Godwin to Mary Jane Godwin, 9 October 1801, in
Letters, vol. 2, pp. 241â4.
[103] Godwin, Life of Chaucer (London: Richard Phillips, 1803), vol. 1,
p. xix.
[104] Ibid., p. 370.
[105] PPWG, vol. 5, pp. 313â4.
[106] CNMG, vol. 5, p. 13.
[107] Quoted in a letter by Godwin explaining the situation to Marshall
the same day (the year appears to have been wrong in Holcroftâs
original), 28 February 1805, in Letters, vol. 2, p. 338.
[108] Godwin, Fables Ancient and Modern, Volume 1, ed. Suzanne L.
Barnett and Katherine Bennett Gustafson (College Park, MD: Romantic
Circles, University of Maryland, 2014; retrieved from
www.rc.umd.edu/editions/godwin_fables/index.html
), vol. 1, paras 292â3.
[109] Coleridge to Southey, 1799, in Coleridge, Collected Letters, vol.
1, p. 553.
[110] Godwin to Dr Edward Ash, 21 May 1808, MS Abinger, c.10, folios
64â5.
[111] The account of Holcroftâs final days comes from Hazlittâs Life of
Thomas Holcroft, ed. Elbridge Colby (New York: Benjamin Bloom, 1968),
vol. 2, p. 310.
[112] Godwin to Louisa Holcroft, undated, MS Abinger, c.19, folio 17b.
[113] MS Abinger, c.19, folio 17b.
[114] PPWG, vol. 3, p. 137.
[115] Godwin to Mary Jane Godwin, 21 August 1809, MS Abinger, c.42,
folio 40.
[116] From an account of Godwin and Shelley by Place (B. M. Add. MSS. 3,
145, 30â36) quoted in Walter Peck, Shelley: His Life and Work, vol. 2
(London: Ernest Benn, 1927), p. 416. In the manuscript, the criticism of
Clairmont is crossed out in pencil, probably by Placeâs son, who edited
his fatherâs papers for publication.
[117] âA Greybeardâs Gossip about a Literary Acquaintanceâ in New
Monthly Magazine (1848).
[118] PPWG, vol. 5, p. 174.
[119] Godwin to Mary Jane Godwin, 18 May 1811, quoted in Kegan Paul,
vol. 2, p. 182.
[120] Percy Shelley to Godwin, 3 January 1812, in Frederick L. Jones
(ed.), The Letters of Percy Bysshe Shelley, Vol. 1: Shelley in England
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1964), pp. 220â1 (hereafter referred
to as âLetters of Shelleyâ).
[121] Percy Shelley to Godwin, 10 January 1812, ibid., pp. 227â9.
[122] The quotation is from the Merchant of Venice, IV.i., ll. 73â7.
Letter, Godwin to Percy Shelley, 4 March 1812, CNMG, vol. 1, p. 70.
[123] Godwin to Percy Shelley, 14 March 1812, ibid., p. 74.
[124] Godwin to Percy Shelley, 30 March 1812, ibid., p. 77.
[125] Godwin to Percy Shelley, 4 March 1812, ibid., p. 72.
[126] We can infer further details of these conversations based on
Godwinâs philosophical interests. Matter and spirit probably refers to a
discussion of Berkeley and scepticism, as an unpublished essay of
Godwinâs shows the philosopher to be in tune with his predecessorâs
position on our perception of the physical world. Shelleyâs âatheismâ is
principally a rejection of organised religion and, like Godwin,
expressed religious views that could be described as pantheist. Utility
and truth probably relate to the ethics of Political Justice, which in
turn implies that âpartyâ refers to Godwinâs critique of political
factionalism in the same work. Their discussion of the church may be a
topical conversation, or relate to the episcopal conflicts of the
seventeenth century (including the English Civil War) which later became
one of Godwinâs major historical interests. âGermanismâ is a reference
to gothic fiction â the most lurid works of the period often traded on
some German connection, imitating the Schauerromane (shudder novels) of
central Europe, and the phrase became synonymous with the genre as a
whole. Godwin read one of Shelleyâs gothic romances (St Irvyne; or, The
Rosicrucian) in June that year.
[127] The Shelley family had only come by their baronetcy in 1806 and
the poetâs father was keen to maintain a respectable front. Harriet was
a lower-middle-class school friend of Shelleyâs sister; the couple had
eloped together in 1811.
[128] Godwin to John Taylor, 27 August 1814, Letters of Shelley, vol. 1,
p. 390, n. 3.
[129] Mary Jane Godwin to Lady Mountcashell, 20 August 1814, quoted in
Edward Dowden, The Life of Percy Bysshe Shelley (London: Kegan Paul,
Trench, 1886), vol. 2, appendix A, p. 544.
[130] Quoted in Don Locke, A Fantasy of Reason (London: Routledge &
Kegan Paul, 1980), p. 138.
[131] Percy Shelley to Harriet Shelley, 27 September 1814, Letters of
Shelley, vol. 1, p. 398.
[132] Mary Godwin to Percy Shelley, 28 October 1814, ibid., p. 414, n.
4.
[133] Godwin to John Taylor, 27 August 1814, held in the Huntington
Library in San Marino, California. The first section is quoted in
Letters of Shelley, vol. 1, p. 390, n. 3; the second, in William St
Clair, The Godwins and the Shelleys, p. 367.
[134] Mary Wollstonecraft Shelley (née Godwin) in Paula R. Feldman and
Diana Scott-Kilvert (eds), The Journals of Mary Shelley, 1814â1844,
Journal Book I, vol. 1 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987).
[135] Percy Shelley to William Godwin, 6 March 1816, in Letters of
Shelley, vol. 1, p. 459.
[136] Scott, who had written irreverent and dismissive reviews of so
many of Godwinâs books, later contributed money to a public subscription
for Godwin (though he asked his name not be recorded) out of respect for
his talents, though he said he could not condone his opinions.
[137] Percy Shelley to William Godwin, 3 May 1816, in Letters of
Shelley, vol. 1, pp. 472â3.
[138] Percy Shelley to William Godwin, 2 October 1816, ibid., p. 509.
[139] Fanny Godwin to Mary Godwin, 3 October 1816, ibid., p. 509, n. 2.
[140] Quoted in Kegan Paul, vol. 2, p. 242.
[141] Percy Shelley to Mary Godwin, 16 December 1816, in Letters of
Shelley, vol. 1, p. 520.
[142] Scholars have argued that Clairmont was prone to distort the truth
as an exercise in damage limitation, attempting to deflect criticism of
the family by offering more palatable versions of events to lessen the
scandal. Not all of her accounts make sense in this light, however, as
Mary Jane frequently gave inaccurate dates, or attributed actions to
different people, for no readily apparent reason. Mostly famously,
Clairmont told Lady Mountcashell that it was Marshall that pursued the
trio to Calais in 1814, rather than herself. It is usually asserted that
she did this to evade blame for failing to recover them, but since the
story she gave did not flatter her either, this seems a curious piece of
deception.
[143] Percy Shelley to Claire Clairmont, 30 December 1816, in Letters of
Shelley, vol. 1, p. 525.
[144] Mary published a substantially revised edition in 1831, and the
later text is the version more familiar to modern readers. The 1831
novel irons out some of the originalâs ambiguities; Walton is seen to
learn from Victorâs hubris, and the author removes any reference to
Elizabeth and Victor being blood relatives.
[145] Place, quoted in Locke, A Fantasy of Reason, p. 238.
[146] Godwin to Percy Shelley, 31 January 1818, quoted in Letters of
Shelley, vol. 1, p. 597.
[147] Godwin to Mary Shelley, 27 October 1818, MS Abinger, c.52, folio
13.
[148] Godwin to Mary Shelley, 9 September 1819, MS Abinger, c.45, folio
18.
[149] Shelley asserted that he did this with Maryâs consent, but the
poetâs letters are not always a complete account.
[150] Godwin to Caroline Lamb, 25 February 1819, MS Abinger, c.12, folio
43.
[151] If this was the case, then Godwin was unsuccessful â Scarlett
became increasingly conservative in later years, becoming an ally of the
Duke of Wellington against parliamentary reform. He became Baron Abinger
in 1835. Ironically, Percy Florence Shelleyâs adopted daughter, Bessie,
married Scarlettâs grandson and the Abinger family eventually inherited
the combined ShelleyâGodwin papers (now held at the Bodleian Library).
[152] Godwin to Clairmont, 31 August 1819, MS Abinger, c.43, folios 4â5.
[153] See Drew R. McCoy, âJefferson and Madison on Malthus: Population
Growth in Jeffersonian Political Economyâ in The Virginia Magazine of
History and Biography, 88(3) (July 1980), pp. 259â76.
[154] Thomas Robert Malthus, Edinburgh Review, 35 (1821), quoted in
Kenneth W. Graham (ed.), William Godwin Reviewed: A Reception History
1783â1834 (New York: AMS Press, 2001), p. 392.
[155] Mary Shelley to Leigh Hunt, 11 September 1823, in Betty T. Bennett
(ed.), Letters of Mary Wollstonecraft Shelley, vol. 1 (Baltimore, MD:
Johns Hopkins University Press, 1980), p. 378.
[156] It was common practice for theatres to âstealâ popular novels by
making enough changes to claim that copyright had not been violated.
George Colman had done exactly this with Caleb Williams, though he did
compensate Godwin with free entry to the Haymarket for years afterwards.
[157] The quotation comes from his notes for Mary on what to do with his
notes and unpublished writing (written 1834). MS Abinger, c.38, folio
13.
[158] Stereotyping is the process of casting whole pages as printing
plates, rather than using moveable type to assemble pages one at a time.
Stereotyping required a significant initial investment (making the
plates) but became more profitable the more copies were sold â British
publishers had previously only used the technology to produce books for
which there was perennial demand (Bibles, textbooks) â so Bentleyâs
offer displayed confidence in Godwinâs sales potential.
[159] The impact of this wider readership would become apparent after
the authorâs death. Both Caleb Williams and Frankenstein remained in
print until the end of the series in the mid-1850s, indicating
consistent sales as Bentley gradually cut prices (by the time it went
out of print, Frankenstein sold at 2s 6d), but the publisher never cut
to the level that would have facilitated the enormous popularity of
Scott or Byron (the works of both were readily available in sixpenny
editions by the Victorian era).
[160] Godwin to Mary Shelley, 13 April 1832, in Jane Shelley (ed.),
Shelley and Mary (privately printed, c. 1882; a copy is held at the
Bodleian Library), vol. 4, pp. 1161â2.
[161] Godwin helped to research Perkin Warbeck at the British Museum, as
we can see in his letters of the 13 August 1828, 29 May 1829 and 30 May
1829; Shelley and Mary, iv, pp. 1106CâD, 1122AâB.
[162] Sir Robert Peel to Godwin, 9 February 1835, quoted in Locke, A
Fantasy of Reason, p. 338.
[163] PPWG, vol. 7, p. 233.
[164] Note dated 30 June 1834, MS Abinger, c.38, folio 13.
[165] The impact of Watsonâs edition is hard to measure. No information
has been found regarding its sales or the size of its print run, nor is
there an identifiable surge in the public discussion of Political
Justice (references in newspapers, for example) that might suggest a
significantly expanded readership.
[166] Friedrich Engels, The Condition of the Working Class in England,
in Marx/Engels Collected Works, vol. 4 (London: Lawrence and Wishart,
1975), p. 528.
[167] Friedrich Engels to Karl Marx, 17 March 1845, in Marx/Engels
Collected Works, vol. 38 (London: Lawrence and Wishart, 1982), p. 27.
[168] Edward Dowden to Richard Garnett, 25 May 1885, in R. S. Garnett
(ed.), Letters About Shelley: Interchanged by Three Friends â Edward
Dowden, Richard Garnett and Wm. Michael Rossetti (London: Hodder and
Stoughton, 1917), pp. 113â14.
[169] Kropotkin, Freedom, 1(1) (October 1886). The journal continues to
this day as an online publication (
) and carries this passage as a strapline at the bottom of the page.
[170] Kropotkin, âAnarchismâ, in the Encyclopaedia Britannica, 11^(th)
edition (New York: Encyclopaedia Britannica, 1910), vol. 1, p. 915.
[171] Herbert Read, preface to George Woodcockâs William Godwin: A
Biographical Study (London: Porcupine Press, 1946), p. xi.
[172] See Charles O. Lerche, Jr. âJefferson and the Election of 1800: A
Case Study in the Political Smearâ, in The William and Mary Quarterly,
5(4) (October 1948), pp. 467â91; and Burton R. Pollin, âGodwinâs Letter
to Ogilvie, Friend of Jefferson, and the Federalist Propagandaâ, in
Journal of the History of Ideas, 28(3) (JulyâSeptember 1967), pp.
432â44.
[173] PPWG, vol. 5, p. 295.
[174] Godwin to James Ogilvie, n.d. 1797, published in the Washington
National Intelligencer (16 April 1802).