💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › petr-kropotkin-the-wage-system.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 13:24:35. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: The Wage System
Author: PĂ«tr Kropotkin
Date: 1920
Language: en
Topics: economics
Source: Retrieved on March 1st, 2009 from http://www.marxists.org/reference/archive/kropotkin-peter/1920/wage.htm
Notes: First Published: Freedom Pamphlets No. 1., New Edition. 1920. Transcribed by EndPage.com

PĂ«tr Kropotkin

The Wage System

I. Representative Government and Wages

In their plan for the reconstruction of society, the Collectivists

commit, in our opinion, a double error. Whilst speaking of the abolition

of the rule of capital, they wish, nevertheless, to maintain two

institutions which form the very basis of that rule, namely,

representative government and the wage system.

As for representative government, it remains absolutely incomprehensible

to us how intelligent men (and they are not wanting amongst the

Collectivists) can continue to be the partisans of national and

municipal parliaments, after all the lessons on this subject bestowed on

us by history, whether in England or in France, in Germany, Switzerland

or the United States. Whilst parliamentary rule is seen to be everywhere

falling to pieces; whilst its principles in themselves — and no longer

merely their applications — are being criticized in every direction, how

can intelligent men calling themselves Revolutionary Socialists, seek to

maintain a system already condemned to death?

Representative government is a system which was elaborated by the middle

class to make head against royalty and, at the same time, to maintain

and augment their domination of the workers. It is the characteristic

form of middle-class rule. But even its most ardent admirers have never

seriously contended that a parliament or municipal body does actually

represent a nation or a city; the more intelligent are aware that this

is impossible. By upholding parliamentary rule the middle class have

been simply seeking to oppose a dam between themselves and royalty, or

between themselves and the territorial aristocracy, without giving

liberty to the people. It is moreover plain that, as the people become

conscious of their interests, and as the variety of those interests

increases, the system becomes unworkable. And this is why the democrats

of all countries are seeking for different palliatives or correctives

and cannot find them. They are trying the Referendum, and discovering

that it is worthless; they prate of proportional representation, of the

representation of minorities, and other parliamentary utopias. In a

word, they are striving to discover the undiscoverable; that is to say,

a method of delegation which shall represent the myriad varied interests

of the nation; but they are being forced to recognize that they are upon

a false track, and confidence in government by delegation is passing

away.

It is only the Social Democrats and Collectivists who are not losing

this confidence, who are attempting to maintain so-called national

representation; and this is what we cannot understand.

If our Anarchist principles do not suit them, if they think them

inapplicable, they ought, at least, as it seems to us, to try to

discover what other system of organization could well correspond to a

society without capitalists or landlords. But to take the middle class

system — a system already in its decadence, a vicious system if ever

there was one — and to proclaim this system (with a few innocent

corrections, such as the imperative mandate, or the Referendum the

uselessness of which has been demonstrated already) good for a society

that has passed through the Social Revolution, is what seems to us

absolutely incomprehensible, unless under the name of Social Revolution

they understand something very different from Revolution, some petty

botching of existing, middle-class rule.

The same with regard to the wage system. After having pro-claimed the

abolition of private property and the possession in common of the

instruments of production, how can they sanction the maintenance of the

wage system under any form? And yet this is what the Collectivists are

doing when they praise the efficiency of labor notes.

That the English Socialists of the early part of this century should

invent labor notes is comprehensible. They were simply trying to

reconcile Capital and Labor. They repudiated all idea of laying violent

hands upon the property of the capitalists. They were so little of

revolutionaries that they declared themselves ready to submit even to

imperial rule, if that rule would favor their co-operative societies.

They remained middle class men at bottom, if charitable ones; and this

is why (Engels has said so in his preface to the Communist Manifesto of

1848) the Socialists of that period were to be found amongst the middle

class, whilst the advanced workmen were Communists.

If later Proudhon took up this same idea, that again is easy to

understand. What was he seeking in his Mutualist system, if not to

render capital less offensive, despite the maintenance of private

property, which he detested to the bottom of his heart, but which he

believed necessary to guarantee the individual against the state?

Further, if economists, belonging more or less to the middle class, also

admit labor notes, it is not surprising. It matters little to them

whether the worker be paid in labor notes or in coin stamped with the

effigy of king or republic. They want to save, in the coming overthrow,

private property in inhabited houses, the soil, the mills; or, at least,

in inhabited houses and the capital necessary for the production of

manufactures. And to maintain this property, labor notes will answer

very well.

If the labor note can be exchanged for jewels and carriages, the owner

of house property will willingly accept it as rent. And as long as the

inhabited house, the field and the mill belong to individual owners, so

long will it be requisite to pay them in some way before they will allow

you to work in their fields or their mills, or to lodge in their houses.

And it will also be requisite to pay wages to the worker, either in gold

or in paper money or in labor notes exchangeable for all sorts of

commodities.

But how can this new form of wages, the labor note, be sanctioned by

those who admit that houses, fields, mills are no longer private

property, that they belong to the commune or the nation?

II. The Collectivist Wage System

Let us examine more closely this system for the remuneration of labor,

as set forth by the English, French, German and Italian

Collectivists.[1]

It comes very much to this: Every one works, be it in fields, in

factories, in schools, in hospitals or what not. The working day is

regulated by the state, to which belong the soil, factories, means of

communication and all the rest. Each worker, having done a day’s work,

receives a labor note, stamped, let us say, with these words: eight

hours of labor. With this note he can procure any sort of goods in the

shops of the state or the various corporations. The note is divisible in

such a way that one hour’s worth of meat, ten minutes’ worth of matches,

or half-an-hour’s worth of tobacco can be purchased. Instead of saying:

“two pennyworth of soap,” after the Collectivist Revolution they will

say: “five minutes’ worth of soap.”

Most Collectivists, faithful to the distinction established by the

middle-class economists (and Marx also) between qualified (skilled) and

simple (unskilled) labor, tell us that qualified or professional toil

should be paid a certain number of times more than simple toil. Thus,

one hour of the doctor’s work should be considered as equivalent to two

or three hours of the work of the nurse, or three hours of that of the

navvy. “Professional or qualified labor will be a multiple of simple

labor,” says the Collectivist Grönlund, because this sort of labor

demands a longer or shorter apprenticeship.

Other Collectivists, the French Marxists for example, do not make this

distinction. They proclaim “equality of wages.” The doctor, the

schoolmaster and the professor will be paid (in labor notes) at the same

rate as the navvy. Eight hours spent in walking the hospitals will be

worth the same as eight hours spent in navvies’ work or in the mine or

the factory.

Some make a further concession; they admit that disagreeable, or

unhealthy labor, such as that in the sewers, should be paid at a higher

rate than work which is agreeable. One hour of service in the sewers may

count, they say, for two hours of the labor of the professor. Let us add

that certain Collectivists advocate the wholesale remuneration of trade

societies. Thus, one society may say: “Here are a hundred tons of steel.

To produce them one hundred workers of our society have taken ten days;

as our day consisted of eight hours, that makes eight thousand hours of

labor for one hundred tons of steel; eighty hours a ton.” Upon which the

State will pay them eight thousand labor notes of one hour each, and

these eight thousand notes will be distributed amongst the

fellow-workers in the foundry as seems best to themselves.

Or again, if one hundred miners have spent twenty days in hewing eight

thousand tons of coal, the coal will be worth two hours a ton, and the

sixteen thousand labor notes for one hour each received by the miners’

union will be divided amongst them as they think fair.

If there be disputes: if the miners protest and say that a ton of steel

ought to cost six hours of labor instead of eight; or if the professor

rate his day twice as high as the nurse; then the State must step in and

regulate their differences.

Such, in a few words, is the organization which the Collectivists desire

to see arising from the Social Revolution. As we have seen, their

principles are: collective property in the instruments of labor and

remuneration of each worker according to the time spent in productive

toil, taking into account the productiveness of his work. As for their

political system, it would be parliamentary rule, ameliorated by the

change of men in power, the imperative mandate, and the referendum —

i.e., the general vote of Yes or No upon questions submitted to the

popular decision.

Now, we must at once say that this system seems to us absolutely

incapable of realization.

The Collectivists begin by proclaiming a revolutionary principle — the

abolition of private property — and, as soon as proclaimed, they deny

it, by maintaining an organization of production and consumption

springing from private property.

They proclaim a revolutionary principle and ignore the consequences it

must necessarily bring about. They forget that the very fact of

abolishing individual property in the instruments of production (land,

factories, means of communication, capital) must cause society to set

out in a new direction; that it must change production from top to

bottom, change not only its methods but its ends; that all the everyday

relations between individuals must be modified as soon as land,

machinery and the rest are considered as common possessions.

They say: “No private property”; and immediately they hasten to maintain

private property in its everyday forms. “For productive purposes you are

a commune,” they say; “the fields, the tools, the machinery, all that

has been made up to this day — manufactures, railways, wharves, mines to

all of you in common. Not the slightest distinction will be made

concerning the share of each one in this collective property.

“But from tomorrow you are minutely to discuss the part that each one of

you is to take in making the new machines, digging the new mines. From

tomorrow you are to endeavor to weigh exactly the portion which will

accrue to each one from the new produce. You are to count your minutes

of work, you are to be on the watch lest one moment of your neighbor’s

toil may purchase more than yours.

“You are to calculate your hours and your minutes of labor, and since

the hour measures nothing, — since in one factory a workman can watch

four looms at once, whilst in another he only watches two, you are to

weigh the muscular force, the energy of brain, the energy of nerve

expended. You are scrupulously to count up the years of apprenticeship,

that you may value precisely the share of each one amongst you in the

production of the future. And all this, after you have declared that you

leave entirely out of your reckoning the share he has taken in the

past.”

Well, it is evident to us that a society cannot organize itself upon two

absolutely opposing principles, two principles which contradict one

another at every step. And the nation or the commune which should give

to itself such an organization would be forced either to return to

private property or else to transform itself immediately into a

communist society.

III. Unequal Remuneration

We have said that most Collectivist writers demand that in Socialist

society remuneration should be based upon a distinction between

qualified or professional labor and simple labor. They assert that an

hour of the engineer’s, the architect’s or the doctor’s work should be

counted as two or three hours’ work from the blacksmith, the mason or

the nurse. And the same distinction, say they, ought to be established

between workers whose trades require a longer or shorter apprenticeship

and those who are mere day laborers.

Yes, but to establish this distinction is to maintain all the in-

equalities of our existing society. It is to trace out beforehand a

demarcation between the worker and those who claim to rule him. It is

still to divide society into two clearly defined classes: an aristocracy

of knowledge above, a horny-handed democracy below; one class devoted to

the service of the other; one class toiling with its hands to nourish

and clothe the other, whilst that other profits by its leisure to learn

how to dominate those who toil for it.

This is to take the distinctive features of middle-class society and

sanction them by a social revolution. It is to erect into a principle an

abuse which to-day is condemned in the society that is breaking up.

We know very well what will be said in answer. We shall be told about

“Scientific Socialism.” The middle-class economists, and Marx: too, will

be cited to prove that there a good reason for a scale of wages, for the

“labor force” of the engineer costs society more than the “labor force”

of the navvy. And, indeed, have not the economists striven to prove

that, if the engineer is paid twenty times more than the navvy, it is

because the cost necessary to produce an engineer is more considerable

than that necessary to produce a navvy? And has not Marx maintained that

the like distinction between various sorts of manual labor is of equal

logical necessity? He could come to no other conclusion, since he took

up Ricardo’s theory of value and insisted that products exchange in

proportion to the quantity of the work socially necessary to produce

them.

But we know also how much of all this to believe. We know that if the

engineer, the scientist and the doctor are paid today ten or a hundred

times more than the laborer, and the weaver earns three times as much as

the toiler in the fields and ten times as much as a match girl, it is

not because what they receive is in proportion to their various costs of

production. Rather it is in proportion to the extent of monopoly in

education and in industry. The engineer, the scientist and the doctor

simply draw their profits from their own sort of capital — their degree,

their certificates — just as the manufacturer draws a profit from a

mill, or as a nobleman used to do from his birth and title.

When the employer pays the engineer twenty times more than the workman,

he makes this very simple calculation: if an engineer can save him

ÂŁ4,000 a year in cost of production, he will pay him ÂŁ800 a year to do

it. And if he sees a foreman is a clever sweater and can save him ÂŁ400

in handicraft, he at once offers him ÂŁ80 or ÂŁ90 a year. He expends ÂŁ100

where he counts upon gaining ÂŁ1,000; that is the essence of the

capitalist system. And the like holds good of the differences in various

trades.

Where then is the sense of talking of the cost of production of labor

force, and saying that a student who passes a merry youth at the

University, has a right to ten times higher wages than the son of a

miner who has pined in a pit since he was eleven? Or that a weaver has a

right to wages three or four times higher than those of an agricultural

laborer? The expenditure needed to produce a weaver is not four times as

great as the necessary cost of producing a field worker. The weaver

simply benefits by the advantageous position which industry enjoys in

Europe as compared with parts of the world where at present there is no

industrial development.

No one has ever estimated the real cost of production of labor force.

And if an idler costs society much more than an honest workman, it still

remains to be known if, when all is told (infant mortality amongst the

workers, the ravages of anaemia the premature deaths) a sturdy day

laborer does not cost society more than an artisan.

Are we to be told that, for example, the 1s. a day of a London workwoman

and the 3d. a day of the Auvergne peasant who blinds herself over

lace-making, represent the cost of production of these women? We are

perfectly aware that they often work for even less, but we know also

that they do it entirely because, thanks to our splendid social

organization, they would die of hunger without these ridiculous wages.

The existing scale of wages seems to us a highly complex product of

taxation, government interference, monopoly and capitalistic greed — in

a word, of the State and the capitalist system. In our opinion all the

theories made by economists about the scale of wages have been invented

after the event to justify existing injustices. It is needless to regard

them.

We are, however, certain to be informed that the Collectivist wage scale

will, at all events, be an improvement. “You must admit,” we shall be

told, “that it will, at least, be better to have a class of workers paid

at twice or three times the ordinary rate than to have Rothschilds, who

put into their pockets in one day more than a workman can in a year. It

will be a step towards equality.”

To us it seems a step away from it. To introduce into a Socialist

society the distinction between ordinary and professional labor would be

to sanction by the Revolution and erect into a principle a brutal fact,

to which we merely submit today, considering it all the while as unjust.

It would be acting after the manner of those gentlemen of the Fourth of

August, 1789, who proclaimed, in high sounding phraseology, the

abolition of feudal rights, and on the Eight of August sanctioned those

very rights by imposing upon the peasants the dues by which they were to

be redeemed from the nobles. Or again, like the Russian government at

the time of the emancipation of the serfs when it proclaimed that the

land henceforth belonged to the nobility, whereas previously it was

considered an abuse that the land which belonged to the peasants should

be bought and sold by private persons.

Or, to take a better known example, when the Commune of 1871 decided to

pay the members of the Communa1 Council 12s. 6d. a day, whilst the

National Guards on the rampart a had only 1s. 3d., certain persons

applauded this decision as an act of grand democratic equality. But, in

reality, the Commune did nothing thereby but sanction the ancient

inequality between officials and soldiers, governors and governed. For

an Opportunist parliament such a decision might have seemed splendid,

but for the Commune it was a negation of its own principles. The Commune

was false to its own revolutionary principle, and by that very fact

condemned it.

In the present state of society when we see Cabinet Ministers paying

themselves thousands a year, whilst the workman has to content himself

with less than a hundred; when we see the foreman paid twice or three

times as much as the ordinary hand, and when amongst workers themselves

there are all sorts of gradations from 7s. or 8s. a day down to the 3d.

of the sempstress, we disapprove the large salary of the minister, and

also the difference between the artisans eight-shillings and the

sempstress’ three-pence. And we say, “Let us have done with privileges

of education as well as of birth.” We are Anarchists just because such

privileges disgust us.

How can we then raise these privileges into a principle? How can we

proclaim that privileges of education are to be the basis of an equal

society, without striking a blow at that very Society. What is submitted

today, will be submitted to no longer in society based on equality. The

general above the soldier, the rich engineer above the workman, the

doctor above the nurse, already disgust us. Can we suffer them in a

society which starts by proclaiming equality?

Evidently not. The popular conscience, inspired by the idea of equality,

will revolt against such an injustice, it will not tolerate it. It is

not worth while to make the attempt.

That is why certain Collectivists, understanding the impossibility of

maintaining a scale of wages in a society inspired by the influences the

Revolution, zealously advocate equality in wages. But they only stumble

against fresh difficulties, and their equality of wages becomes a Utopia

as incapable of realization as the wage scale of the others. A society

that has seized upon all social wealth, and has plainly announced that

all have a right to this wealth, whatever may be the part they have

taken in creating it in the past, will be obliged to give up all idea of

wages, either in money or in labor notes.

IV. Equal Wages versus Communism

“To each according to his deeds,” say the Collectivists, or rather

according to his share of service rendered to society. And this is the

principle they recommend as the basis of economic organization, after

the Revolution shall have made all the instruments of labor and all that

is necessary for production common property!

Well, if the Social Revolution should be so unfortunate as to proclaim

this principle, it would be stemming the tide of human progress, it

would be leaving unsolved the huge social problem cast by past centuries

upon our shoulders.

It is true that in such a society as ours, where the more a man works

the less he is paid, this principle may seem, at first sight, all

aspiration towards justice. But at bottom it is but the consecration of

past injustice. It is with this principle that the wage system started,

to end where it is today, in crying inequalities and all the

abominations of the present state of things. And it has ended thus

because, from the day on which society began to value services in the

money or any other sort of wages, from the day on which it was said that

each should have only what he could succeed in getting paid for his

work, the whole history of Capitalism (the State aiding therein) was

written beforehand; its germ was enclosed in this principle.

Must we then return to our point of departure and pass once more through

the same process of capitalist evolution? These theorists seem to desire

it; but happily it is impossible; the Revolution will be Communistic; or

it will be drowned in blood, and must be begun all over again.

Service rendered to society, be it labor in factory or field, or moral

service, cannot be valued in monetary units. There cannot be an exact

measure of its value, either of what has been improperly called its

“value in exchange” or of its value in use. If we see two individuals,

both working for years, for five hours daily, for the community, at two

different occupations equally pleasing to them, we can say that, taken

all in all, their labors are roughly equivalent. But their work could

not be broken up into fractions, so that the product of each day, each

hour or each minute of the labor of one should be worth the produce of

each minute and each hour of that of the other.

Broadly speaking, we can say that a man who during his whole life

deprives himself of leisure for ten hours daily has given much more to

society than he who has deprived himself of but five hours a day, or has

not deprived himself of any leisure at all. But we cannot take what one

man has done during any two hours and say that this produce is worth

exactly twice as much as the produce of one hour’s work from another

individual, and reward each proportionately. To do this would be to

ignore all that is complex in the industry, the agriculture, the entire

life of society as it is; it would be to ignore the extent to which all

individual work is the outcome of the former and present labors of

society as a whole. It would be to fancy oneself in the Stone Age, when

we are living in the Age of Steel.

Go into a coal mine and see that man stationed at the huge machine that

hoists and lowers the cage. In his hand he holds a lever whereby to

check or reverse the action of the machinery. He lowers the handle, and

in a second the cage changes the direction of its giddy rush up or down

the shaft. His eyes are attentively fixed upon an indicator in front of

him which shows exactly the point the cage has reached; no sooner does

it touch the given level than at his gentlest pressure it stops dead

short, not a foot above or below the required place. And scarcely are

the full trucks discharged or the empties loaded before, at a touch to

the handle, the cage is again swinging up or down the shaft.

For eight or ten hours at a time he thus concentrates his attention. Let

his brain relax but for an instant, and the cage would fly up and

shatter the wheels, break the rope, crush the men, bring all the work of

the mine to a stand-still. Let him lose three seconds upon each reverse

of the lever and, in a mine with all the modern improvements, the output

will be reduced by from twenty to fifty tons a day.

Well, is it he who renders the greatest service in the mine? Or is it,

perhaps, that boy who rings from below the signal for the mounting of

the cage? Or is it the miner who risks his life every moment in the

depths of the mine and will end one day by being killed by fire-damp?

Or, again, the engineer who would lose the coal seam and set men hewing

bare rock, if he merely made a mistake in the addition of his

calculations? Or, finally, is it the owner, who has put all his

patrimony into the concern, and who perhaps has said, in opposition to

all previous anticipations: “Dig there, you will find excellent coal”?

All the workers engaged in the mine contribute to the raising of coal in

proportion to their strength, their energy, their knowledge their

intelligence and their skill. And we can say that all have the right to

live, to satisfy their needs, and even gratify their whims, after the

more imperious needs of every one are satisfied. But how can we exactly

value what they have each done?

Further, is the coal that they have extracted entirely the result of

their work? Is it not also the outcome of the work of the men who

constructed the railway leading to the mine, and the roads branching off

on all sides from the stations? And what of the work of those who have

tilled and sown the fields which supply the miners with food, smelted

the iron, cut the wood in the forest, made the machines which will

consume the coal, and so on?

No hard and fast line can be drawn between the work of one and the work

of another. To measure them by results leads to absurdity. To divide

them into fractions and measure them by hours of labor leads to

absurdity also. One course remains: not to measure them at all, but to

recognize the right of all who take part in productive labor first of

all to live, and then to enjoy the comforts of life.

Take any other branch of human activity, take our existence as a whole,

and say which of us can claim the highest reward for his deeds?

The doctor who has divined the disease or the nurse who has assured its

cure by her sanitary cares? The inventor of the first steam engine or

the boy who one day, tired of pulling the cord which formerly served to

open the valve admitting the steam beneath the piston, tied his cord to

the lever of the machine, and went to play with his companions, without

imagining that he had invented the mechanism essential to all modern

machinery — the automatic valve? The inventor of the locomotive or that

Newcastle workman who suggested that wooden sleepers should take the

place of the stones which were formerly put under the rails and threw

trains off the line by their want of elasticity? The driver of the

locomotive or the signalman who stops the train or opens the way for it?

To whom do we owe the trans-Atlantic cable? To the engineer who

persisted in declaring that the cable would transmit telegrams, whilst

the learned electricians declared that it was impossible? To Maury, the

scientist, who advised the disuse of thick cables and the substitution

of one no bigger than a walking stick? Or, after all, is it to those

volunteers, from no one knows where, who spent day and night on the deck

of the Great Eastern, minutely examining every yard of cable and taking

out the nails that the shareholders of the maritime companies had

stupidly caused to be driven through the isolating coat of the cable to

render it useless?

And, in a still wider field, the vast tract of human life, with its

joys, its sorrows, and its varied incidents, cannot each of us mention

some one who during his life has rendered him some service so great, so

important, that if it were proposed to value it in money he would be

filled with indignation? This service may have been a word, nothing but

a word in season, or it may have been months or years of devotion. Are

you going to estimate these, the most important of all services, in

labor notes? “The deeds of each”! But human societies could not live for

two successive generations, they would disappear in fifty years, if each

one did not give infinitely more than will be returned to him in money,

in “notes” or in civic rewards. It would be the extinction of the race

if the mother did not expend her life to preserve her children, if every

man did not give some things without counting the cost, if human beings

did not give most where they look for no reward.

If middle-class society is going to ruin; if we are today in a blind

alley from which there is no escape without applying axe and torch to

the institutions of the past, that is just because we have calculated

too much. It is just because we have allowed ourselves to be drawn into

giving that we may receive; because we have desired to make society into

a commercial company based upon debit and credit.

Moreover, the Collectivists know it. They vaguely comprehend that a

society cannot exist if it logically carries out the principle, “To each

according to his deeds.” They suspect that the needs (we are not

speaking of the whims) of the individual do not always correspond to his

deeds. Accordingly, De Paepe tells us:

“This eminently individualistic principle will be tempered by social

intervention for the purpose of the education of children and young

people (including their maintenance and nurture) and by social

organizations for the assistance of the sick and infirm, asylums for

aged workers, etc.”

Even Collectivists suspect that a man of forty, the father of three

children, has greater needs than a youth of twenty. They suspect that a

woman who is suckling her child and spends sleepless nights by its cot,

cannot get through so much work as a man who has enjoyed tranquil

slumber.

They seem to understand that a man or woman worn out by having perhaps,

worked over hard for society in general may find themselves incapable of

performing so many “deeds” as those who take their hours of labor

quietly and pocket their “notes” in the privileged offices of State

statisticians.

And they hasten to temper their principle. Oh, certainly, they say,

society will feed and bring up its children. Oh, certainly it will

assist the old and infirm. Oh, certainly needs not deeds will be the

measure of the cost which society will impose on itself to temper the

principle of deeds.

What, Charity? Yes, our old friend, “Christian Charity,” organized by

the State.

Improve the foundling hospital, organize insurance against age and

sickness, and the principle of deeds will be “tempered.” “Wound that

they may heal,” they can get no further.

Thus, then, after having forsworn Communism, after having sneered at

their ease at the formula, “To each according to his needs,” is it not

obvious that they, the great economists, also perceive that they have

forgotten something, i.e., the needs of the producers? And thereupon

they hasten to recognize these needs. Only it is to be the State by

which they are to be estimated, it is to be the State which will

undertake to find out if needs are disproportionate to deeds.

It is to be the State that will give alms to him who is willing to

recognize his inferiority. From thence to the Poor Law and the Workhouse

is but a stone’s throw.

There is but a stone’s throw for even this step-mother of a society

against which we are in revolt, has found it necessary to temper its

individualistic principle. It too has had to make concessions in a

Communistic sense, and in this same form of charity.

It also distributes halfpenny dinners to prevent the pillage of its

shops. It also builds hospitals, often bad enough, but sometimes

splendid, to prevent the ravages of contagious disease. It also after

having paid for nothing but the hours of labor, receives the children of

those whom it has itself reduced to the extremity of distress. It also

takes account of needs — as a charity.

Poverty, the existence of the poor, was the first cause of riches. This

it was which created the earliest capitalist. For, before the surplus

value, about which people are so fond of talking, could begin to be

accumulated it was necessary that there should be poverty-stricken

wretches who would consent to sell their labor force rather than die of

hunger. It is poverty that has made the rich. And if poverty had

advanced by such rapid strides by the end of the Middle Ages, it was

chiefly because the invasions and wars, the creation of States and the

development of their authority, the wealth gained by exploitation in the

East and many other causes of a like nature, broke the bonds which once

united agrarian and urban communities, and led them, in place of the

solidarity which they once practised, to adopt the principle of the

wage-system. Is this principle to be the outcome of the Revolution? Dare

we dignify by the name of a Social Revolution that name so dear to the

hungry, the suffering and the oppressed — the triumph of such a

principle as this?

It cannot be so. For, on the day when ancient institutions splinter into

fragments before the axe of the proletariat, voices will be heard

shouting: Bread for all! Lodging for all! Right for all to the comforts

of life!

And these voices will be heeded. The people will say to themselves: Let

us begin by satisfying our thirst for the life, the joy the liberty we

have never known. And when all have tasted happiness, we will set to

work; the work of demolishing the last vestiges of middle-class rule,

with its account-book morality, its philosophy of debit and credit, its

institutions of mine and shine. “While we throw down we shall be

building,” as Proudhon said; we shall build in the name of Communism and

of Anarchy.

 

[1] The Spanish Anarchists, who continue to call themselves

Collectivists, understand by this term common possession of the

instruments of labor and “liberty for each group to share the produce of

labor as they think fit”; on Communist principles or in any other way.