💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › patricia-crone-ninth-century-muslim-anarchists.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 13:14:10. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-07-09)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: Ninth-Century Muslim Anarchists
Author: Patricia Crone
Date: 2000
Language: en
Topics: Islam
Source: https://www.hs.ias.edu/files/Crone_Articles/Crone_Ninth_Century_Muslim_Anarchists.pdf

Patricia Crone

Ninth-Century Muslim Anarchists

I: INTRODUCTION

The people with whom this paper is concerned were anarchists in the

simple sense of believers in an-archy, 'no government'. They were not

secularists, individualists, communists, social reformers,

revolutionaries or terrorists, merely thinkers who held that Muslim

society could function without what we would call the state. Their view

is, however, of great interest from the point of view of early Islamic

political thought and the history of anarchism alike. Since they are

largely unknown even to Islamicists and have yet to be discovered by

historians of anarchism, I am grateful for the opportunity to present

them to a wider public here. All the anarchists came from Basra in

southern Iraq or had their intellectual roots there, but they belonged

to two quite different groups. Most of them were Mu'tazilites, that is

members of a theological school of Basran origin distinguished by its

reliance on reason. Mu'tazilites were not necessarily, or even usually,

anarchists, but a ninth-century Mu'tazilite heresiographer presumed to

be Ja'far ibn Harb (d. 850) implies that belief in the non-necessity of

government was common among them in his days. Its adherents included

al-Asamm (d. 816 or 817), al-Nazzam (d. between 835 and 845),4 Hisham

al-Fuwat1 (d. 840s?) and his pupil 'Abbad ibn Sulayman (d. 870s?), all

of whom lived or began their careers in Basra, as well as the so-called

Mu'tazilite ascetics (sufiyyat al-muftazila), active in Baghdad. The

other anarchists were Kharijites, that is to say, members of a mainly

Basran sect which was notorious for its militant intolerance. The

Kharijites were not normally anarchists either, but one sub-sect was,

that is the Najdiyya, or Najadat, who had appeared in the seventh

century and who seem to have survived into the tenth, possibly in Basra

and possibly elsewhere. Whether Mu'tazilite or Kharijite, the views of

the anarchists have been poorly preserved. Numerous sources mention that

some Mu'tazilites and Kharijites denied the necessity of the imamate

(roughly translatable as legitimate government), but it was not until

van Ess published the heresiography now presumed to be Ja'far ibn Harb's

(generally referred to as Pseudo-Nashi') that their laconic statements

could be related to a context. This new source also provided a clue to

the identity of unnamed anarchists who appear in a fragmentary epistle

by al-Jahiz (d. 869), a famous litterateur and Mu'tazilite of the

non-anarchist variety: they can now be plausibly identified as

Mu'tazilites influenced by al-Asamm. In addition, van Ess has done an

immense amount of groundwork on the anarchists (without ever using that

term) in his Theologie und Gesellschaft, a monumental work which covers

the doctrinal developments of the early Islamic world in four volumes of

prosopography and analysis, and two of translations. Without

Pseudo-Nashi' and Theologie und Gesellschaft this article could not have

been written. But numerous problems of textual interpretation remain,

and this, in conjunction with the need to provide information for

readers in different fields, accounts for what may strike the reader as

annoyingly dense annotation. Anarchism in the simple sense of belief in

the dispensability of government appears to have a continuous history in

the West from the Bohemian Taborites of the 1420s onwards. Outside the

Western tradition it is difficult to find. There is a case for the view

that Chuang Tzu (fourth century BC) and other early Taoists should be

classified as anarchists, but much that looks like anarchism is not, and

the only non-Western example known to date apart from the Taoists

appears to be the Muslim thinkers under discussion here. As one would

expect, the three types of anarchist arrived at their convictions by

quite different intellectual routes, having started from different

premisses. The Taoists will have to be left aside here, but we may start

with a comparison of the Western and the Islamic routes.

II: THE WESTERN PREMISSES

Western anarchism, medieval or modern, has its ultimate origins in the

Western conviction that human society pre-dates the emergence of the

state. The Western tradition abounds in claims that once upon a time

humans lived together without coercive government in Paradise, the

golden age, the state of nature, in primitive societies or before the

development of agriculture. However formulated, the assumption is always

the same: state and society are not inseparable, let alone identical.

This may strike a modern reader as self-evident, but it is not. Its

history takes us back to the Stoics. To the early Greek philosophers,

including Plato and Aristotle, society and government developed together

as two sides of the same coin: take away the one and you took away the

other. But the Stoics distinguished between them in their famous

accounts of what society would look like if it were based on natural

law. Natural law was the right reason by which the universe was governed

and on which the wise man would model his life. A society based on such

reason would not have any law courts, private property, slavery,

marriage or war; in other words, it would not have any structures of

domination or organized violence: all these things were human

conventions, not part of natural law. (Many other conventional

institutions, including temples, education and coinage, would be absent

too.) The Stoics were not anarchists. Their message was not that all

these institutions could be, or ought to be, abolished. They did,

however, lay the foundations for anarchism by assigning human

sociability and human government to radically different sources: the one

was natural, rational and good; the other not. The later Stoics said

that in the golden age humans had actually lived in a society based on

natural law, led by wise men; but then avarice had made its appearance,

resulting in the development of private property, tyranny, slavery, war

and so forth; in short, social and political inequality, coercion and

strife had emerged. This view of human pre-history went into Cicero and

other Latin sources that passed to the medieval West, and above all it

went into the Latin Church Fathers, so that it became part and parcel of

Latin Christianity itself. In its Christianized version it said that

once upon a time, in Paradise or in some remote time on earth, humans

had lived social lives without private property and slavery (though not

without marriage), but that the Fall had so vitiated human beings that

this was no longer possible. Kings had been instituted as a punishment

for and remedy against sin; their authority derived from God Himself,

however oppressively they behaved, and one had to obey them, but they

did not form part of the original condition of innocence. The sinful,

yet God-given, nature of power enabled medieval churchmen to stress the

diabolical or celestial nature of government as they saw fit, and many

held political subordination to have existed even in Paradise, where the

existence of civil (as opposed to servile) subjection was to be

explicitly endorsed by Thomas Aquinas (d. 1274) with reference to

Aristotle's view of political organization as natural. But the view that

government was unknown to God's original plan and to nature alike was

too entrenched in Western thought to disappear, though it was often

attacked. As a result, Westerners have always found it possible to think

away the state. Some would think away society along with it, to

illustrate how nasty, brutish and short life would be in the state of

nature; but many would dream up societies from which the structures of

domination had been removed, with reference to the remote past, the

millenarian future, real or alleged primitive societies, or by way of

construing utopias based on natural law or its socio-economic successor.

In short, Western anarchism is in essence the belief that we can return

to the condition of innocence from which we have fallen, or to some

secularized version of it. Anarchist sentiments can thus be classified

as endemic to the Western tradition, though they have rarely been

epidemic. Differently put, if one thinks of an intellectual tradition as

a box of conceptual tools with which every generation tries to carve

some sense out of the world, the Western tradition has always had a tool

labelled 'does God/nature really want us to have rulers?'

III: THE MUSLIM PREMISSES

But the Muslims started with a very different set of conceptual tools.

As they saw it, structures of domination had always existed and always

would, for the universe itself was a kingdom, in the most literal sense

of the word. The king of the universe was God, who ruled by legislating.

At first sight, divine law as conceived by the Muslims looks much the

same as the natural law of the Stoics (who often called theirs divine as

well); but the conceptions are quite different. The natural law of the

Stoics was something built into nature, exemplified by nature, and

available to all humans by virtue of their possession of reason; it was

'written into their hearts', as St Paul put it, and thus wholly

independent of human government. But the divine law of the Muslims was

envisaged on the model of positive law as something that had to be

enacted, promulgated and enforced within a particular community: the

King had to send messengers in order for people to know it, and He had

to raise up deputies of one kind or another in order to have it

executed. Far from being independent of human government, divine law

engendered it. You acknowledged God as your king by accepting membership

of His polity, to live by His law as brought and executed by His agents.

God's government was coercive. He would not, of course, have to use

force if His subjects would obey Him of their own accord, but for some

reason or other they all tended to be rebellious. There was nothing

special about humans in this respect. God had sent armies against

disobedient creatures even before humans had been created, and the human

fall plays no role whatever in the Muslim view of why coercive

government exists. Government had always existed and always would; it

was an inescapable feature of the universe. Consequently, the Muslim

golden age myth is not about the absence of government, but rather about

its ideal form. The myth is set in Medina in the time of the Prophet and

the first caliphs, from 622 to 656 (or earlier), that is in a

well-remembered historical period rather than the hoary past, and what

it offers is an idealized version of that period rather than complete

fiction. Like the Stoic account, it describes a simple society which was

guided by wise men until things went wrong, as they did when the first

civil war broke out in 656, if not before. But unlike its Stoic what

counterpart, it starts with the foundation of a polity, and it

illustrates is not a contrast between divine law and human government,

but on the contrary their fusion. The Prophet and the first caliphs who

bring and execute God's law are unambigu- ously envisaged as rulers, not

just as wise men. They impose penalties, conduct campaigns, suppress

revolts and start the wars of conquest; in short, they use

institutionalized violence. But they always do so in accordance with

God's law. Nothing is wrong with coercive was institutions as long as

they are properly used: that the basic position. Ideal government was

government by an imam, a communal leader who modelled himself on God's

law and who thus set an example to be imitated. The first imam in human

history was Adam. The first imam in Islamic history was Muhammad; the

imams after him adopted the title of caliph, and their position was

thereafter known now as the imamate (which stressed its legitimate

nature) and now as the caliphate (which stressed its political reality).

But they were all rulers of the same kind. Everything else was a

corruption, in two opposite directions. On the one hand, some people

transgressed against God by arrogating His power to themselves, leading

to tyranny. This was the were condition under which the non-Arabs had

lived until they conquered by the Muslims. More precisely, they had

lived under kings, but all kings other than God Himself were tyrants,

for a king was somebody who wanted power at God's expense, like Pharaoh,

the paradigmatic example. On the other hand, there were people who

forgot about God and His law altogether and so had no government at all.

Statelessness was the condition in which the Arabs had lived before the

rise of Islam. The Greeks had rather admired them for their ability to

do without rulers, and they had certainly admired themselves for it:

they boast endlessly of their refusal to submit to kings or anyone else

in their poetry. But after the rise of Islam they realized that they had

lived in pagan ignorance and barbarism, Jahiliyya, a state of amorality

and disorder, not a condition of innocence, let alone one which

established a natural right to freedom from subordination. Obligation,

subordination and order all came with the revelation, for a religion was

first and foremost a set of legal and moral obligations whereby human

society was ordered. The Medinese caliphs steered a middle course

between tyranny and anarchy by adhering to God's law. To the vast

majority of Muslims they represented the political ideal, as indeed they

still do. In short, coercive government was not a mere human convention,

except in so far as it had been perverted by kings. In its authentic

form it was a sacred institution which reflected the absolute. You could

not have a moral order without a revealed law, and you could not have a

revealed law without an imam to enforce it. This was the premiss with

which the Muslims started. It is not easy to see how they could get to

anarchism from there.

IV: FROM IMAMATE TO KINGSHIP

Like everyone else, however, the Muslims soon discovered that divine law

and human government tended to be at loggerheads. By about 800 Medina

had long ceased to be the capital, the Muslim polity had long lost its

simplicity and the imams had long ceased to be wise men dispensing

friendly guidance, in so far as they ever were. The 'Abbasid caliphs

ruled a vast empire from Baghdad in a style all too reminiscent of

Pharaoh and his likes. The imamate had turned into kingship, as people

said; in other words, it had turned into tyranny. The question was what

one should do about it. Islam had originated as an activist religion,

and there were still people who said that wherever you saw people act

wrongly, you should take action against them, with the sword if

necessary: if the ruler misbehaved, one had to rebel and replace him

with another, provided that there was a reasonable chance of success.

Most ninth-century Mu'tazilites were of this opinion, as were all

Kharijites of the non-anarchist variety. But the religious scholars who

came to be the bearers of Sunni Islam were quietists, like the churchmen

of the medieval West. In their view, civil war was more destructive for

the community than such wrongs as tyrants could inflict on it, and

preserving the community was more important than setting its leadership

right; you had to obey the ruler, however sinful he was, unless he

ordered you to disobey God Himself, in which case you had to adopt

passive resistance. There were even some who argued in the Christian

style that tyrannical rulers were a punishment for sins. But the

anarchists proposed a third solution. We may start with the

Mu'tazilites, who will get the bulk of the attention.

V: THE MU'TAZILITE ARGUMENTS

The Mu'tazilites offered a variety of arguments in favour of anarchism,

but only one is quoted in full, that of the Mu'tazilite ascetics. It

went as follows. Islam is different from other religions, for other

religious communities have kings who enslave their subjects, but the

Prophet was not a king, nor were his successors, and if an imam tsere to

turn into a king, by ceasing to govern in accordance with the law, then

the Muslims would be legally obliged to fight him and depose him (as the

activists said). But civil war was indeed terrible; it split the

community and led to more violation of the law without guaranteeing a

better outcome (as the quietists said). Since imams kept turning into

kings, the best solution was not to set them up in the first place. The

Mu'tazilite ascetics did not deny that there might be a legitimate ruler

in the future: they seem to have thought that he would have to be an

'Alid, or in other words a descendant of the Prophet. But in the absence

of such a ruler it was better to have none. Al-Asamm's argument, which

has to be pieced together from diverse passages, was based on the

premiss that the imam was a ruler on whom all members of the community

agreed; without such consensus he would not be an imam at all. This was

widely accepted (and also the premiss of the Najdiyya). Originally, the

caliphs ruled with communal agreement and had thus been true imams

(according to al-Asamm, though not the Najdiyya), but nowadays they did

not: the community had grown too big. Like the ascetics, al-Asamm seems

to have kept open the possibility that there could be a true imam again

one day, though he cannot have regarded it as likely if he saw size as

the key problem; and he certainly did not think that the imam would have

to be an 'Alid, or even an Arab. In any case, one had to look for

alternatives while such a ruler was absent. Hisham al-Fuwatl subscribed

to a variant version of alAsamm's argument. According to him, the

community only needed an imam when it was unanimous and righteous, by

which he appears to have meant that it was only under such circumstances

that it was possible (and obligatory?) to elect one. In the past it had

been possible, but nowadays it was not: the community had grown

disunited and sinful. His pupil 'Abbad ibn Sulayman went so far as to

declare in categorical terms that there never could be an imam again.

Here too, it followed that one had to look for alternatives. The

Mu'tazilite anarchists were clearly regretful anarchists. They would not

have agreed with Emma Goldman (d. 1940) that 'all forms of government

rest on violence, and are therefore wrong and harmful, as well as

unnecessary'. In their view, this was only true of government in the

sense of kingship; the imamate had been an exception. But it was no

longer an exception. It had indeed come to rest on violence, and thus to

be wrong, harmful and unnecessary. This was the problem they were

grappling with. The Mu'tazilites (as also the Najdiyya) declared the

imamate unnecessary by denying that it was prescribed by the religious

law. A Muslim had to pray, fast and fulfil other duties laid down by the

law, but having an imam was not a duty of that kind, they said. They

demonstrated this in different ways. Al-Asamm, followed by al-Nazzam,

famously declared that people would not need an imam if they would obey

the law of their own accord. By this he does not seem to have meant that

such a situation could actually be brought about, but rather that since

one could envisage a situation in which the imamate was superfluous, one

could not identify the institution as obligatory on the basis of reason.

Nor was it prescribed in the Qur'an (as all or most nonShi' ites seem to

have agreed at the time); and according to al-Asamm's presumed followers

described by al-Jahiz, the behaviour of the Prophet's Companions after

his death also ruled out that it had been prescribed by him. In short,

no legal obligation to have the institution existed. 'Abbad ibn

Sulayman, perhaps echoing Hisham al-Fuwatl, used the very fact that

doubts about the possibility of having a legitimate imam had arisen to

demonstrate that none could appear any more, presumably inferring that

therefore no obligation to have the imamate could exist (any more?); it

was generally agreed that God did not impose impossible duties on the

believers. How the ascetics argued we do not know, but one way or the

other they all denied that the imamate was God-given. In other words,

they all desacralized it: it did not reflect the absolute; it was just a

fallible human institution like any other (min mu'amalat al-nas, as

al-Asamm put it). They did not say that it was a bad institution or that

God originally meant people to live without it; they merely denied that

God had any views on its desirability or otherwise. Given that the

imamate was simply a human convention, one could have it or not as one

saw fit: people had had it in the past, and it had worked very well, but

nowadays it was preferable, or even necessary, to do without it. In

short, they cut the link between the imamate and the law on which

Islamic society rested. That was how they made anarchism possible.

VI: DOING WITHOUT THE IMAM

But how would one manage without the would apply the law and imam? Above

all, who dispense the penalties of which it was so-called hudud, that is

generally agreed that they could only be applied by the imam or his

circumstances no private representatives? Under normal another believer.

The person was allowed to kill or maim law did, however, stipulate that

certain crimes (such as theft, adultery and wine-drinking) were punish-

able by death, amputation or flogging; these penalties were among 'God's

rights' (huquq allah), i.e. they were required for the greater good, and

a public figurehead was required for their This obviously suggested

execution. that having an imam zvas a legal duty, and itis presumably

for this reason that the hudud loom large in the military surviving

matters discussions. without an The question of how one might manage

imam attracts less attention, and there is no discussion at all of where

one would find religious guidance, for all that the ninth-century

Mu'tazilites generally saw the imam as religious guide or teacher. But

maybe this simply reflects the fragmentary state of the evidence. In any

case, the Mu'tazilites gramme of moral responded partly with a proAs

regards the former, rearmament and partly with practical proposals. they

harped on the theme of cooperation and taking duties seriously. degree

'People's welfare lies entirely in the to which they Everybody had to

cooperate', as some of them pointed out. participate, no people guilty

of crimes had shirking was allowed; even to do their bit, by giving

themselves up voluntarily. As regards the latter, the proposals ranged

from dissolution of public complete authority to drastic

decentralization.

Complete dissolution of public authority seems to be what Hisham

al-Fuwat. and 'Abbad ibn Sulayman had in mind. Since no legitimate

authority existed, people should take the law into their own hands

whenever they could to ensure that the law was applied: self-help was

encouraged even when it entailed killing, and even when the killing had

to be done on the sly. Better still, people should rebel and openly take

over the implementation of the law, including the amputation of thieving

hands, the execution of murderers and everything else that imams used to

do. This sounds like a prescription for anarchy in the normal sense of

chaos and disorder. In a slightly less anarchic vein, other Mu'tazilites

proposed that trustworthy and learned leaders of households, districts,

tribes and towns should apply the law within their jurisdiction, and

that they were qualified to carry out the hudud. In other words, power

should revert to patriarchs and local leaders domestic tyrants and local

thugs in modern parlance. But others were reluctant to do without public

authority altogether. In their view one could elect temporary imams.

This could be done whenever legal disputes arose or crimes were

committed, or when the enemy invaded; the imam would lose his position

as soon as he had finished the job, just as an imam in the sense of

prayer leader (another meaning of the word) loses his authority the

moment the prayer is over. One assumes that it was the above-mentioned

leaders of households, districts, tribes and towns that they had in mind

as candidates, but in any case these Mu'tazilites (apparently the

ascetics) clearly wanted government to be taken over by elected

officials. Al-Asamm played in sufficient numbers to minimize the danger

of bias and collu- sion, they could replace the imam for purposes of

maintaining the law and applying the hudud. In other words, one could

have government by executive committee. Al-Asamm also advanced a

proposal for extreme decentraliza- tion: one could have several,

semi-independent imams. One imam had been fine in the days of the first

caliphs, he said, but nowadays there could no longer be real unanimity

on just one man, and he could not know meritorious people in distant

provinces, meaning, as al-Asamm saw it, that he could not collaborate

with provincial elites; this, he said, was frustrating for those who

wished to participate in government. Hence it would be better to have

several imams, and this was perfectly lawful. He ought to have continued

that since the imamate is a human convention, we can do what we like

with it, but at this point he seems to have lost his nerve: he tried to

legitimate his proposal by invoking Prophetic precedent. He claimed that

the Prophet's governors in Arabia had in effect been independent imams.

Each one had collected taxes, maintained order, conducted defence and

taught people the law; and when the Prophet died, the inhabitants of

each provincial centre had inherited the right to appoint such governors

of their own. In short, all provinces were now entitled to elect their

own semi-independent rulers, who would, of course, have to cooperate.

Al-Jahiz scoffed at this proposal (as known to him from al-Asamm's

followers): who ever heard of neigh- bouring rulers who did not fight?

But what al-Asamm was grappling with was clearly the concept of

federation. No such concept existed, and he did not quite arrive at it

either, for he did not explain what would hold the governors together

now that the Prophet had died. But it is none the less a remarkable

piece of political thinking, and it is hardly surprising that he lost

his nerve, for to propose that the Muslim community should be divided up

among a number of imams was even more heretical than saying that it

could do without imams altogether. Al-Asamm never dared to publish this

proposal; he merely told his close friends and pupils (khazvass

ashabihi) about it.

VII: GREEK OR TRIBAL ROOTS?

Some eighty years ago Goldziher proposed that al-Asamm and Hisham

al-Fuwatl found their anarchism in a Greek letter supposedly written by

Aristotle to Alexander after the latter's conquest of Iran; but this is

unlikely and has rightly been rejected by van Ess. The letter makes two

points reflecting the Hellenistic debate for and against monarchy

(rather than government as such): first, 'many people think that a ruler

upholding the law is only necessary in times of war; when the war is

over and security and calm prevail, one can do without him'; and

secondly, 'some think that people should all be equal, without any ruler

or subject among them', while others go to the opposite extreme of

deeming it acceptable for the ruler to be 'coercive in disregard of the

law'. The letter was probably translated into Arabic in Syria in the

730s-740s, and a formulation reminiscent of the second point reappears

in a work by the Iraqi secretary Ibn al-Muqaffa' (d. c.757), suggesting

that it was read in Iraq well before the time of al-Asamm and Hisham.

But it is hard to see how it could have inspired them, for the concept

of the ruler as an emergency leader in war was alien to both of them,

and neither wished to dispense with the imam on the grounds that people

were, or ought to be, equal. The postulate of Greek influence is in any

case unnecessary. Al-Asamm and Hisham formulated their ideas in

interaction with their Kharijite neighbours (who were not given to

reading Greek works), and both the Mu'tazilite and the Najdite

anarchists were clearly drawing on tribal tradition which lies behind

all early Islamic political thought of the type which may be loosely

identified as libertarian. It should be stressed, however, that tribal

ideas were at work only in the sense that they formed part of the value

system of early Muslims, not as a model in their own right. There was no

tradition for crediting tribesmen with the preservation of political

virtues that the members of civilized societies had lost. Much later, in

a fourteenth-century school text from Iran, one does encounter the

argument that people do not need the imamate, for the bedouin manage

perfectly well without rulers; but there is no way of telling where this

argument comes from or how early it is. It could be of Najdite origin.

But the Mu'tazilites never invoke the bedouin in the surviving texts,

and the chances are that they envisaged tribal statelessness as every

bit as bad as tyranny in that neither was based on God's law. They do

not in fact invoke any concrete example of statelessness at all, and

this is what is so remarkable about them: they were not thinking in

terms of a return to some original condition; all were discussing new

forms of political organization for which they had no example in either

real or imagined history. In so far as one can tell, they simply

reasoned their way to the view that one could live by the law alone, in

conjunction with some local administration.

It could be argued that most of the Mu'tazilite proposals are not really

anarchist in that most of them replace one type of government with

another instead of abolishing it altogether. But this is true of most

anarchist proposals: the alternative to the state is more often than not

authoritarianism of another, and frequently more thoroughgoing, kind.

The main difference between Mu'tazilite and Western anarchism is that

the Mu'tazilites only proposed political alternatives to the imamate,

whereas Western anarchists have usually proposed social regimentation

and/or extreme simplicity of life in order to do without the state.

Western anarchism has always been as much about socio-economic

reorganization as political reform, almost always in an egalitarian

vein, and usually communist (thus already the Taborites). Neither

government nor private property had existed in the state of nature; the

former had come into existence for the protection of the latter, as

everyone knew from Cicero, so the two had to be abolished together. But

Mu'tazilite anarchism was not concerned with social reorganization at

all, nor was it egalitarian, let alone communist. The Mu'tazilite

ascetics did postulate a connection between government and property, but

what they said was not that both were intrinsically wrong, only that

both were wrong unless they were based on Islamic law. This they no

longer were. The abode of Islam had turned into an abode of unbelief, as

one of them declared, meaning that collective life no longer had any

legal or moral foundations. The illegitimacy of the ruler vitiated all

titles to property: all ownership was really usurpation until the

rightful imam appeared; making a living in any manner involving buying

and selling was forbidden; all income was sinful, apart from such scraps

as one received by begging in extreme need. (How they viewed living off

the land we are not told: all were clearly urbanites. ) Had the head of

state been legitimate, property and income therefrom would have been

lawful too. In so far as the Mu'tazilites postulated a relationship

between property and their political problems, their view was thus that

wrongful government made property immoral, not that property engendered

wrongful government. Far from construing their inegalitarian society as

a source of caliphal tyranny, they all saw it as an alternative to it:

society would be fine if only it were left alone; patriarchs and local

leaders would dispense the law. Their anarchism consisted in thinking

away the head of state and, implicitly, his army and bureaucracy too, in

order to replace the whole apparatus of central government with either

provincial imams in federation or local imams elected for a term, or

with executive committees, or simply with the leaders of households and

tribes as they were, or with straightforward self-help. But as regretful

anarchists, not one of them condemned the state on principle. What they

minded was not the existence of coercive power but rather its

distribution. The distribution of power in the ninth-century caliphate

was in fact extremely lopsided. The 'Abbasids tended to recruit their

soldiers and governors in one province, eastern Iran, and their

bureaucrats in another, lower Iraq; by and large, all others were

excluded from decision-making at a central level, however influential,

wealthy or meritorious they might be in local terms. This was to get

worse, for instead of broadening their power base the caliphs decided,

from the mid-ninth century onwards, to import Turkish tribesmen as

slaves and to train them as soldiers and government servants, so that

central government came to have even less anchorage in Muslim society

than before. This had not happened by the time al-Asamm wrote, but it

was where things were going, and his federation was undoubtedly meant to

counteract this trend. He wanted more local participation. The same

would appear to be true of the other Mu'tazilite anarchists.

IX: PUTTING ANARCHISM INTO PRACTICE

None of the Mu'tazilite anarchists explained how one was to do away with

the state. All seem to have made their proposals in what Dawson calls a

'low utopian' vein, meaning that their programme of radical reform was

destined for eventual implementation, if possible, but that meanwhile it

served the eminently useful function (shared by all utopias) of

providing a critique of existing institutions. Since all were scholars

devoid of political experience, they may have held the practicalities of

implementation to be for others to work out. We know next to nothing

about their social status or sources of income, but most of them seem to

have been happy to enjoy the comforts available under the protective

cover of the state, however despotic or illegitimate it might be. Hisham

al-Fuwat.l, possibly a wealthy trader, is even said to have frequented

the court. Only the Mu'tazilite ascetics of Baghdad appear to have kept

their distance from rulers and the normal comforts of life alike, but

their withdrawal gave them greater affinities with the mystics, with

whom the term sufiyyat al-mu'tazila brackets them, than with political

reformers. None of them displayed any interest in fomenting rebellion,

whether they considered it lawful or not; and al-Asamm positively ruled

it out. An opportunity did, none the less, arise. In 817 the government

collapsed of its own accord in Baghdad. There had been a civil war (the

fourth); the new caliph al-Ma'mun was still absent, and his governor

could not maintain order. The result was complete lawlessness, to which

a certain Sahl ibn Salama responded by founding a famous vigilante group

that proved quite effective. This man has turned out to be a Baghdad

Mu'tazilite, possibly of the anarchist variety. His brief career

certainly made a deep impression on the anarchists. 'At a time when

government disintegrated and the plebs and ruffians took over . . . we

saw a small number of people of integrity and standing get up in their

district, tribe, street and quarter to . . . subdue the ... ruffians so

that the weak could once more move freely . . . and so that merchants

could go around again', they boast in al-Jahiz's account of them. This

was devolution in action. The anarchists concluded that when people are

forced to rely on themselves, they discover talents they did not know

they had. People should wake up: the so-called shepherd would resume

oppression as soon as he recovered his strength. He did in fact recover

his strength, so that was the end of that.

X: THE NAJDIYYA

This brings us to the Najdiyya, who can be dealt with rather more

briefly.79 The Najdiyya were almost certainly the first to deny the

necessity of the imamate, and the reason why they did so, in so far as

one can tell, is that they wished to shed the obligation to rebel. By

origin they were activists: one had to fight to replace the illegitimate

caliph of today with a true imam. They had in fact started their history

by rebelling, in the late seventh century, but their revolt had been

suppressed, which left them with the choice between trying again or

modifying their doctrine. They chose the latter, we do not know exactly

when: their belief in the dispensability of the imamate is not attested

until the end of the ninth century. But the implications are clear

enough: if the law did not prescribe an imam, one did not have to rebel

to set one up; one could be a Kharijite without committing oneself to

establishing a true imamate; one could live under the illegitimate

'Abbasid caliphs without endangering one's chances of salvation. But the

Naidiyya soon developed a further reason to deny the necessity of the

imamate: they did not want an imam to lay down the law to them. It is

this second concern which is uppermost in their argument as we have it.

Unlike the Mu'tazilite anarchists, who merely held the imamate to have

become inoperable, the Najdiyya denied that it had ever existed. An imam

was someone on whom everyone agreed, they said, but perfect agreement

was inconceivable in theory and had never been seen in practice: even

the very first caliph, Abu Bakr, had encountered opposition, as everyone

knew. He had not been an imam, then, though he had certainly been a good

man. They classified him as a chief (ra>ts). From this they inferred

that the obligatory nature of the imamate was a myth. By denying that

the imamate had ever existed, they also denied that it was the only form

of government compatible with Islam, so they did not thereby declare

themselves to be anarchists: rightly guided chieftainship was still an

option. But the question of political government did not interest them

much, since they would have had to rebel in order to establish a ruler

of their own whether they classified him as an imam or not. They said

that if one were to establish a polity of one's own, then one could have

a chief, though one was not obliged to have one, adding that he would

have to be elected by the community, supervised by it and deposed by it

if he was found to stray: he would merely be the community's agent. But

this was the standard Kharijite view of the imam (a term the Najdiyya

sometimes fell into using of their rightly guided chief as well). As far

as religious guidance was concerned, however, their dismissal of the

imamate was certainly meant in an anarchist vein. Even if a ruler

existed, he would only be a chief, not an imam, meaning that he would

not be empowered over anybody else in religious terms. All believers

were entitled to their own opinions on law and doctrine on the basis of

iitihad, independent reasoning, for all of them were equally

authoritative. The believers were 'like the teeth of a comb', or 'like a

hundred male camels without a single female riding camel among them':

why should they defer to someone just like themselves? Just as there

could never be sufficient agreement to establish an imamate, so there

could never be enough to establish law: consensus (iima') was not a

source of law at all. Everybody was responsible for his own road to

salvation. Najdite Islam was a do-it-yourself religion. Politically and

intellectually a Najdite would have no master apart from God. This was

radical libertarianism, and it was achieved at a cost. The Naidiyya held

themselves to be the only Muslims. A11 others were infidels who could in

principle be enslaved, dispossessed and exterminated by the Najdiyya,

should the latter choose to rebel.83 In practice the Najdiyya seem to

have lived in perfect amity with their so-called infidel neighbours. But

they continued to regard the latter as outsiders, and this meant that

they did not have to consider them in their political thought. What they

were writing about was a tiny community in which people probably knew

each other face to face. They could allow a high degree of independent

reasoning because there was almost certainly a high degree of consensus

anyway, and they could dream of libertarian politics because they had no

polity of their own. As a solution to the problems of how one might keep

the Muslims from India to Spain together in a single political and/or

religious community, the Najdite vision was no use at all.

XI: CONCLUSION

Aristotle's Greeks and the very first Muslims were political animals in

much the same sense: both assumed the highest form of human life to

consist in participation in the public affairs of a politically

organized society, the polis (city-state) in the Greek case, the umma

(the community founded by Muhammad) in the Muslim case. As the

city-state was the only polity in which one could be free according to

the Greeks, so the community founded by the Prophet was the only polity

in which one could be a slave of God's, as the Muslims put it, meaning

free of subjection to mere humans in this world and saved in the next.

In both cases the conception was undermined by world conquest. What

Alexander did to the polis, the Muslim conquerors did to their own

community in Medina. People now had to come to terms with empires. The

original types of polity survived, of course: the polis continued

zuithin Alexander's empire, the umma continued as an empire. But they

ceased to be coterminous with the arena in which people found the

meaning of their lives. Real politics now meant kingship, which the

Greeks and Muslims alike equated with enslavement. Real freedom now

meant transcending politics, to find the meaning of one's life

elsewhere. This is the ultimate background to the anarchists, and it is

also what doomed them to extinction. The Mu'tazilites had not

transcended politics. Unlike the Cynics and the Stoics, they were not

saying that people should change their attitude to government and

understand how unimportant it was in terms of the ultimate order of the

universe. It was the Sufis who took that line. The Mu'tazilite

anarchists were saying that people should change government itself.

Al-Asamm and his pupils wanted their political participation back, even

if it meant sacrificing the imamate. The Najdiyya wanted to keep their

intellectual autonomy, even if it meant remaining a tiny minority. Both

were to that extent backward-looking. The Mu'tazilites were perfectly

realistic in their recognition that the imamate could no longer function

as it had done in Medina, and al-Asamm was also right that political

decentralization was on the cards. By the end of the ninth century the

caliphate had broken up under semi-independent governors, very much as

he said it should. But it did not break up in accordance with his

prescription. The semi-independent rulers were military leaders who

fought each other as much as al-Jahiz had said they would, and they were

simply miniature versions of the caliph the tyrant that al-Asamm had

wished to replace. By the tenth century these rulers had officially

taken to calling themselves kings in a flattering sense. By the twelfth

century the sources will routinely make statements such as that the king

must ensure that his subjects 'do not take out the ring of slavery from

their ears'. The anarchists must have turned in their graves. But

whether one tried to live with this development or sought to transcend

it, anarchism was dead. Of people contemplating life without mon- archs

on a permanent basis in the Islamic world I do not know a single

unambiguous example after the Mu'tazilite and Najdite anarchists had

disappeared.

Institute for Advanced Study,

Patricia Crone