💾 Archived View for library.inu.red › file › nicolas-walter-about-anarchism.gmi captured on 2023-01-29 at 13:06:26. Gemini links have been rewritten to link to archived content

View Raw

More Information

➡️ Next capture (2024-06-20)

-=-=-=-=-=-=-

Title: About Anarchism
Author: Nicolas Walter
Date: June 1969
Language: en
Topics: introductory
Source: 100th issue of Anarchy, (Vol 9 No 6) June 1969. Retrieved on 2020-09-30 from https://libcom.org/library/anarchy-100

Nicolas Walter

About Anarchism

The modern anarchist movement is now a hundred years old, counting from

when the Bakuninists entered the First International, and in this

country there has been a continuous anarchist movement for ninety years

(the Freedom Press has been going since 1886). Such a past is a source

of strength, but it is also a source of weakness—especially in the

printed word. The anarchist literature of the past weighs heavily on the

present, and makes it hard for us to produce a new literature for the

future. And yet, though the works of our predecessors are numerous, most

of them are out of print, and the rest are mostly out of date; moreover,

the great majority of anarchist works published in English have been

translations from other languages.

This means there is little that we can call our own. What follows is an

attempt to add to it by making a fresh statement of anarchism. It is

addressed in particular to readers in Britain at the end of the 1960s—a

place and a time in which there is a considerable revival of interest in

anarchism as a basis not for sectarian argument about the past but for

practical discussion about the future.

Such a statement is necessarily an individual view, for one of the

essential features of anarchism is that it relies on individual

judgement; but it is intended to take account of the general views

prevailing in the anarchist movement and to interpret them without

prejudice. It is expressed in simple language and without constant

reference to other writers or to past events, so that it can be

understood without difficulty and without any previous knowledge. But it

is derived from what other people have said in the past, and does not

purport to be original. Nor is it meant to be definitive; there is far

more to say about anarchism than can be fitted into thirty-two pages,

and this summary will no doubt soon be superseded like nearly all those

that have preceded it.

Above all, I make no claim to authority, for another essential feature

of anarchism is that it rejects the authority of any spokesman. If my

readers have no criticism to make, I have failed. What follows is simply

a personal account of anarchism drawn from the experience of fifteen

years’ reading anarchist literature and discussing anarchist ideas, and

of ten years’ taking part in anarchist activities and writing in the

anarchist press.

May 1969

What Anarchists Believe

The first anarchists were people in the English and French revolutions

of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries who were given the name as

an insult to suggest that they wanted anarchy in the sense of chaos or

confusion. But from the 1840s anarchists were people who accepted the

name as a sign to show that they wanted anarchy in the sense of absence

of government. The Greek word anarkhia, like the English word “anarchy”,

has both meanings; people who are not anarchists take them to come to

the same thing, but anarchists insist on keeping them apart. For more

than a century, anarchists have been people who believe not only that

absence of government need not mean chaos and confusion, but that a

society without government will actually be better than the sociey we

live in now.

Anarchism is the political elaboration of the psychological reaction

against authority which appears in all human groups. Everyone knows the

natural anarchists who will not believe or do something just because

someone tells them to. Throughout history the practical tendency towards

anarchy is seen among individuals and groups rebelling against those who

rule them. The theoretical idea of anarchy is also very old; thus the

description of a past golden age without government may be found in the

thought of ancient China and India, Egypt and Mesopotamia, and Greece

and Rome, and in the same way the wish for a future utopia without

government may be found in the thought of countless religious and

political writers and communities. But the application of anarchy to the

present situation is more recent, and it is only in the anarchist

movement of the past century that we find the demand for a society

without government here and now.

Other groups on both left and right want to get rid of government in

theory, either when the market is so free that it needs no more

supervision, or when the people are so equal that they need no more

restraint, but the measures they take seem to make government stronger

and stronger. It is the anarchists, and the anarchists alone, who want

to get rid of government in practice. This does not mean that anarchists

think ail men are naturally good, or identical, or perfectible, or any

romantic nonsense of that kind. It means that anarchists think almost

all men are sociable, and similar, and capable of living their own

lives. Many people say that government is necessary because some men

cannot be trusted to look after themselves, but anarchists say that

government is harmful because no men can be trusted to look after anyone

else. If all men are so bad that they need to be ruled by others,

anarchists ask, how can any men be good enough to rule others? Power

tends to corrupt, and absolute power corrupts absolutely. At the same

time, the wealth of the earth is the product of the labour of mankind as

a whole, and all men have an equal right to take part in continuing the

labour and enjoying the product. Anarchism is an ideal type which

demands at the same time total freedom and total equality.

Liberalism and socialism

Anarchism may be seen as a development from either liberalism or

socialism, or from both liberalism and socialism. Like liberals,

anarchists want freedom; like socialists, anarchists want equality. But

we are not satisfied by liberalism alone or by socialism alone. Freedom

without equality means that the poor and weak are less free than the

rich and strong, and equality without freedom means that we are all

slaves together. Freedom and equality are not contradictory, but

complementary; in place of the old polarisation of freedom versus

equality—according to which we are told that more freedom equals less

equality, and more equality equals less freedom—anarchists point out

that in practice you cannot have one without the other. Freedom is not

genuine if some people are too poor or too weak to enjoy it, and

equality is not genuine if some people arc ruled by others. The crucial

contribution to political theory made by anarchists is this realisation

that freedom and equality are in the end the same Ihing.....

Anarchism also departs from both liberalism and socialism in taking a

different view of progress. Liberals see history as a linear development

from savagery, superstition, intolerance and tyranny to civilisation,

enlightenment, tolerance and emancipation. There are advances and

retreats, but the true progress of mankind is from a bad past to a good

future. Socialists see history as a dialectical development from

savagery, through despotism, feudalism and capitalism, to the triumph of

the proletariat and the abolition of the class system. There are

revolutions and reactions, but the true progress of mankind is again

from a bad past to a good future.

Anarchists see progress quite differently; in fact they often do not see

progress at all. We see history not as a linear or a dialectical

development in one direction, but as a dualistic process. The history of

all human society is the story of a struggle between the rulers and the

ruled, between the haves and the have-nots, between the people who want

to govern and be governed and the people who want to free themselves and

their fellows; the principles of authority and liberty, of government

and rebellion, of state and society, are in perpetual opposition. This

tension is never resolved; the movement of mankind is now in one

direction, now in another. The rise of a new regime or the fall of an

old one is not a mysterious break in development or an even more

mysterious part of development, but is exactly what it seems to be.

Historical events are welcome only to the extent that they increase

freedom and equality for the whole people; there is no hidden reason for

calling a bad thing good because it is inevitable. We cannot make any

useful predictions of the future, and we cannot be sure that the world

is going to get better. Our only hope is that, as knowledge and

consciousness increase, people will become more aware that they can look

after themselves without any need for authority.

Nevertheless, anarchism does derive from liberalism and socialism both

historically and ideologically. Liberalism and socialism came before

anarchism, and anarchism arose from the contradiction between them; most

anarchists still begin as either liberals or socialists, or both. The

spirit of revolt is seldom born fully grown, and it generally grows into

rather than within anarchism. In a sense, anarchists always remain

liberals and socialists, and whenever they reject what is good in either

they betray anarchism itself. On one hand we depend on freedom of

speech, assembly, movement, behaviour, and especially on the freedom to

differ; on the other hand we depend on equality of possessions, on human

solidarity, and especially on the sharing of power. We are liberals but

more so, and socialists but more so.

Yet anarchism is not just a mixture of liberalism and socialism; that is

social democracy, or welfare capitalism, the system which prevails in

this country. Whatever we owe to and however close we are to liberals

and socialists, we differ fundamentally from them—and from social

democrats—in rejecting the institution of government. Both liberals and

socialists depend on government—liberals ostensibly to preserve freedom

but actually to prevent equality, socialists ostensibly to preserve

equality but actually to prevent freedom. Even the most extreme liberals

and socialists cannot do without government, the exercise of authority

by some people over other people. The essence of anarchism, the one

thing without which it is not anarchism, is the negation of authority

over anyone by anyone.

Democracy and representation

Many people oppose undemocratic government, but anarchists differ from

them in also opposing democratic government. Some people oppose

democratic government as well, but anarchists differ from them in doing

so not because they fear or hate the rule of the people but because they

believe that democracy is not the rule of the people—that democracy is

in fact a logical contradiction, a physical impossibility. Genuine

democracy is possible only in a small community where everyone can take

part in every decision; and then it is not necessary. What is called

democracy and is alleged to be the government of the people by

themselves is in fact the government of the people by elected rulers and

would be better called “consenting oligarchy”.

Government by rulers whom we have chosen is different from and generally

better than government by rulers who have chosen themselves, but it is

still government of some people by other people. Even the most

democratic government still depends on someone making someone else do

something or stopping someone else doing something. Even when we are

governed by our representatives we are still governed, and as soon as

they begin to govern us against our will they cease to be our

representatives. Most people now agree that we have no obligation to a

government in which we have no voice; anarchists go further and insist

that we have no obligation to a government we have chosen. We may obey

it because we agree with it or because we are too weak to disobey it,

but we have no obligation to obey it when we disagree with it and are

strong enough not to do so. Most people now agree that those who are

involved in any change should be consulted about it before any decision

is made; anarchists go further and insist that they should themselves

make the decision and go on to put it into effect.

So anarchists reject the idea of a social contract and the idea of

representation. In practice, no doubt, most things will always be done

by a few people—by those who are interested in a problem and are capable

of solving it—but there is no need for them to be selected or elected.

They will always emerge anyway, and it is better for them to do so

naturally. The point is that leaders and experts do not have to be

rulers, that leadership and expertise are not necessarily connected with

authority. And when representation is convenient, that is all it is; the

only true representative is the delegate or deputy who is mandated by

those who send him and who is subject to instant recall by them. In some

ways the ruler who claims to be a representative is worse than the ruler

who is obviously a usurper, because it is more difficult to grapple with

authority when it is wrapped up in fine words and abstract arguments.

The fact that we are able to vote for our rulers once every few years

does not mean that we have to obey them for the rest of the time. If we

do, it is for practical reasons, not on moral grounds. Anarchists are

against government, however it is built up.

State and class

Anarchists have traditionally concentrated their opposition to authority

on the state—that is, the institution which claims the monopoly of power

within a certain area. This is because the state is the supreme example

of authority in a society and also the source or confirmation of the use

of authority throughout it. Moreover, anarchists have traditionally

opposed all kinds of state—not just the obvious tyranny of a king,

dictator or conqueror, but also such variations as enlightened

despotism, progressive monarchy, feudal or commercial oligarchy,

parliamentary democracy, soviet communism, and so on. Anarchists have

even tended to say that all states are the same, and that there is

nothing to choose between them.

This is an oversimplification. All states are certainly authoritarian,

but some states are just as certainly more authoritarian than others,

and every normal person would prefer to live under a less authoritarian

rather than a more authoritarian one. To give a simple example, this

statement of anarchism could not have been published under most states

of the past, and it still could not be published under most states of

both left and right, in both East and West; I would rather live where it

can be published, and so would most of my readers.

Few anarchists still have such a simplistic attitude to an abstract

thing called “the state”, and anarchists concentrate on attacking the

central government and the institutions which derive from it not just

because they are part of the state but because they are the extreme

examples of the use of authority in society. We contrast the state with

society, but we no longer see it as alien to society, as an artificial

growth; instead we see it as part of society, as a natural growth.

Authority is a normal form of behaviour, just as aggression is; but it

is a form of behaviour which must be controlled and grown out of. This

will not be done by trying to find ways of institutionalising it, but

only by finding ways of doing without it.

Anarchists object to the obviously repressive institutions of

government—officials, laws, police, courts, prisons, armies, and so

on—and also to those which are apparently benevolent—subsidised bodies

and local councils, nationalised industries and public corporations,

banks and insurance companies, schools and universities, press and

broadcasting, and all the rest. Anyone can see that the former depend

not on consent but on compulsion and ultimately on force; anarchists

insist that the latter have the same iron hand, even if it does wear a

velvet glove.

Nevertheless, the institutions which derive directly or indirectly from

the state cannot be understood if they are thought of as being purely

bad. They can have a good side, in two ways. They have a useful negative

function when they challenge the use of authority by other institutions,

such as cruel parents, greedy landlords, brutal bosses, violent

criminals; and they have a useful positive function when they promote

desirable social activities, such as public works, disaster operations,

communication and transport systems, art and culture, medical services,

pension schemes, poor relief, education, broadcasting. Thus we have the

liberatory state and the welfare state, the state working for freedom

and the state working for equality.

The first anarchist answer to this is that we also have the oppressive

state—that the main function of the state is in fact to hold down the

people, to limit freedom—and that all the benevolent functions of the

state can be exercised and often have been exercised by voluntary

associations. Here the state resembles the medieval church. In the

Middle Ages the church was involved in all essential social activities,

and it was difficult to believe that the activities were possible

without it. Only the church could baptise, marry and bury people, and

they had to learn that it did not actually control birth, love and

death. Every public act needed an official religious blessing—many still

have one—and people had to learn that the act was just as effective

without the blessing. The church interfered in and often controlled

those aspects of communal life which are now dominated by the state.

People have learnt to realise that the participation of the church is

unnecessary and even harmful; what they now have to learn is that the

domination of the state is equally pernicious and superfluous. We need

the state just as long as we think we do, and everything it does can be

done just as well or even better without the sanction of authority.

The second anarchist answer is that the essential function of the state

is to maintain the existing inequality. Anarchists do not agree with

Marxists that the basic unit of society is the class, but most agree

that the state is the political expression of the economic structure,

that it is the representative of the people who own or control the

wealth of the community and the oppressor of the people who do the work

which creates that wealth. The state cannot redistribute wealth fairly

because it is the main agency of the unfair distribution. Anarchists

agree with Marxists that the present system must be destroyed, but they

do not agree that the future system can be established by a state in

different hands; the state is a cause as well as a result of the class

system, and a classless society which is established by a state will

soon become a class society again. The state will not wither away—it

must be deliberately abolished by people taking power away from the

rulers and wealth away from the rich; these two actions are linked, and

one without the other will always be futile. Anarchy in its truest sense

means a society without either rulers or rich men.

Organisation and bureaucracy

This does not mean that anarchists reject organisation, though here is

one of the strongest prejudices about anarchism. People can accept that

anarchy may not mean just chaos or confusion, and that anarchists want

not disorder but order without government, but they are sure that

anarchy means order which arises spontaneously and that anarchists do

not want organisation. This is the reverse of the truth. Anarchists

actually want much more organisation, though organisation without

authority. The prejudice about anarchism derives from a prejudice about

organisation; people cannot see that organisation does not depend on

authority, that it actually works best without authority.

A moment’s thought will show that when compulsion is replaced by consent

there will have to be more discussion and planning, not less. Everyone

who is involved in a decision will be able to take part in making it,

and no one will be able to leave the work to paid officials or elected

representatives. Without rules to observe or precedents to follow, every

decision will have to be made afresh. Without rulers to obey or leaders

to follow, everyone will be able to make up his own mind. To keep all

this going, the multiplicity and complexity of links between individuals

will be increased, not reduced. Such organisation may be untidy and

inefficient, but it will be much closer to the needs and feelings of the

people concerned. If something cannot be done without the old kind of

organisation, without authority and compulsion, it probably isn’t worth

doing and would be better left undone.

What anarchists do reject is the institutionalisation of organisation,

the establishment of a special group of people whose function is to

organise other people. Anarchist organisation would be fluid and open;

as soon as organisation becomes hardened and closed, it falls into the

hands of a bureaucracy, becomes the instrument of a particular class,

and reverts to the expression of authority instead of the coordination

of society. Every group tends towards oligarchy, the rule of the few,

and every organisation tends towards bureaucracy, the rule of the

professionals; anarchists must always struggle against these tendencies,

in the future as well as the present, and among themselves as well as

among others.

Property

Nor do anarchists reject property, though we have a peculiar view of it.

In one sense property is theft—that is, the exclusive appropriation of

anything by anyone is a deprivation of everyone else. This does not mean

that we are all communists; what it means it that any particular

person’s right to any particular thing depends not on whether he made it

or found it or bought it or was given it or is using it or wants il or

has a lega! right to it, but on whether he needs it—and, more to the

point, whether he needs it more than someone else. This is a matter not

of abstract justice or natural law, but of human solidarity and obvious

commonsense. If I have a loaf of bread and you are hungry, it is yours,

not mine, if I have a coat and you are cold, it belongs to you. If I

have a house and you have none, you have the right to use at least one

of my rooms. But in another sense property is liberty—that is, the

private enjoyment of goods and chattels in a sufficient quantity is an

essential condition of the good life for the individual.

Anarchists are in favour of the private property which cannot be used by

one person to exploit another—those personal possessions which we

accumulate from childhood and which become part of our lives. What we

are against is the public property which is no use in itself and can be

used only to exploit people—land and buildings, instruments of

production and distribution, raw materials and manufactured articles,

money and capital. The principle at issue is that a man may be said to

have a right to what he produces by his own labour, but not to what he

gets from the labour of others; he has a right to what he needs and

uses, but not to what he does not need and cannot use. As soon as a man

has more than enough, it either goes to waste or it stops another man

having enough.

This means that rich men have no right to their property, for they are

rich not because they work a lot but because a lot of people work for

them; and poor men have a right to rich men’s property, for they are

poor not because they work little but because they work for others.

Indeed, poor people almost always work longer hours at duller jobs in

worse conditions than rich people. No one ever became rich or remained

rich through his own labour, only by exploiting the labour of others. A

man may have a house and a piece of land, the tools of his trade and

good health all his life, and he may work as hard as he can as long as

he can—he will produce enough for his family, but little more; and even

then he will not be really self-sufficient, for he will depend on others

to provide some of his materials and to take some of his produce in

exchange.

Public property is not only a matter of ownership, but also one of

control. It is not necessary to possess property to be able to exploit

others. Rich men have always used other people to manage their property,

and, now that anonymous corporations and state enterprises are replacing

individual property owners, managers are becoming the leading exploiters

of other people’s labour. In both advanced and backward countries, both

capitalist and communist states, a tiny minority of the population still

owns or otherwise controls the overwhelming proportion of public

property.

Despite appearances, this is not an economic or legal problem. What

matters is not the distribution of money or the system of land tenure or

the organisation of taxation or the method of taxation or the law of

inheritance, but the basic fact that some people will work for other

people, just as some people will obey other people. If we refused to

work for the rich and powerful, property would disappear—in the same way

that, if we refused to obey rulers, authority would disappear. For

anarchists, property is based on authority, and not the other way round.

The point is not how peasants put food into the landlords’ mouths or how

workers put money into the bosses’ pockets, but why they do so, and this

is a political point.

Some people try to solve the problem of property by changing the law or

the government, whether by reform or by revolution. Anarchists have no

faith in such solutions, but they do not all agree on the right

solution. Some anarchists want the division of everything among

everyone, so that we all have an equal share in the world’s wealth, and

a laissez-faire commercial system with free credit to prevent excessive

accumulation. But most anarchists have no faith in this solution either,

and want the expropriation of all public property from those who have

more than they need, so that we all have equal access to the world’s

wealth, and the control is in the hands of the whole community. But at

least it is agreed that the present system of property must be destroyed

together with the present system of authority.

God and church

Anarchists have traditionally been anti-clerical, and also atheist. The

early anarchists were opposed to the church as much as to the state, and

most of them have been opposed to religion itself. The slogan, “Neither

God nor master”, has often been used to sum up the anarchist message.

Many people still take the first step towards anarchism by abandoning

their faith and becoming rationalists or humanists; the rejection of

divine authority encourages the rejection of human authority. Nearly all

anarchists today are probably atheists, or at least agnostics.

But there have been religious anarchists, though they are usually

outside the mainstream of the anarchist movement. Obvious examples are

the heretical sects which anticipated some anarchist ideas before the

nineteenth century, and groups of religious pacifists in Europe and

North America during the nineteenth and twentieth centuries, especially

Tolstoy and his followers at the beginning of the twentieth century and

the Catholic Worker movement in the United States since the 1930s.

The general anarchist hatred of religion has declined as the power of

the church has declined, and most anarchists now think of it as a

personal matter. They would oppose the discouragement of religion by

force, but they would also oppose the revival of religion by force. They

would let anyone believe and do what he wants, so long as it affects

only himself; but they would not let the church have any more power.

In the meantime, the history of religion is a model for the history of

government. Once it was thought impossible to have a society without

God; now God is dead. It is still thought impossible to have a society

without the state; now we must destroy the state.

War and violence

Anarchists have always opposed war, but not all have opposed violence.

They are anti-militarists, but not necessarily pacifists. For

anarchists, war is the supreme example of authority outside a society,

and at the same time a powerful reinforcement of authority within

society. The organised violence and destruction of war are an enormously

magnified version of the organised violence and destruction of the

state, and war is the health of the state. The anarchist movement has a

strong tradition of resistance to war and to preparations for war. A few

anarchists have supported some wars, but they have always been

recognised as renegades by their comrades, and this total opposition to

national wrars is one of the great unifying factors among anarchists.

But anarchists have distinguished between national wars between states

and civil wars between classes. The revolutionary anarchist movement

since the late nineteenth century has called for a violent insurrection

to destroy the state, and anarchists have taken an active part in many

armed risings and civil wars, especially those in Russia and Spain.

Though they were involved in such fighting, however, they were under no

illusions that it would itself bring about the revolution. Violence

might be necessary for the work of destroying the old system, but it was

useless and indeed dangerous for the work of building a new system. A

people’s army can defeat a ruling class and destroy a government, but it

cannot help the people to create a free society, and it is no good

winning a war if you cannot win the peace.

Many anarchists have in fact doubted whether violence plays any useful

part at all. Like the state, it is not a neutral force whose effects

depend on who uses it, and it will not do the right things just because

it is in the right hands. Of course the violence of the oppressed is not

the same as the violence of the oppressor, but even when it is the best

way out of an intolerable situation it is only a second best. It is one

of the most unpleasant features of present society, and it remains

unpleasant however good its purpose; moreover, it tends to destroy its

purpose, even in situations where it seems appropriate—such as

revolution. The experience of history suggests that revolutions are not

guaranteed by violence; on the contrary, the more violence, the less

revolution.

All this may seem absurd to people who are not anarchists. One of the

oldest and most persistent prejudices about anarchism is that anarchists

are above all men of violence. The stereotype of the anarchist with a

bomb under his cloak is eighty years old, but it is still going strong.

Many anarchists have indeed favoured violence, some have favoured the

assassination of public figures, and a few have even favoured terrorism

of the population, to help destroy the present system. There is a dark

side to anarchism, and there is no point denying it. But it is only one

side of anarchism, and a small one. Most anarchists have always opposed

any violence which is not really necessary—the inevitable violence occ

urs when the people shake off their rulers and exploiters.

The main perpetrators of violence have been those who maintain

authority, not those who attack it. The great bomb-throwers have not

been the tragic individuals driven to desperation in southern Europe

more than half a century ago, but the military machines of every state

in the world throughout history. No anarchist can rival the Blitz and

the Bomb, no Ravachol or Bonnot can stand beside Hitler or Stalin. We

would encourage workers to seize their factory or peasants to seize

their land, and we might break windows or build barricades; but we have

no soldiers, no aeroplanes, no police, no prisons, no camps, no firing

squads, no gas chambers, no hangmen. For anarchists, violence is the

extreme example of the use of power by one person against another, the

culmination of everything we are against.

Some anarchists have even been pacifists, though this is not usual. Many

pacifists have been (or become) anarchists, and anarchists have tended

to move towards pacifism as the world has moved towards destruction.

Some have been especially attracted by the militant type of pacifism

advocated by Tolstoy and Gandhi and by the use of nonviolence as a

technique of direct action, and many anarchists have taken part in

anti-war movements and have sometimes had a significant influence on

them. But most anarchists—even those who are closely involved—find

pacifism too wide in its rejection of all violence by ail people in all

circumstances, and too narrow in its belief that the elimination of

violence alone will make a fundamental difference to society. Where

pacifists see authority as a weaker version of violence, anarchists see

violence as a stronger version of authority. They are also repelled by

the moralistic side of pacifism, the asceticism and selfrighteousness,

and by its tender-minded view of the world. To repeat, they are

anti-militarists, but not necessarily pacifists.

The individual aud society

The basic unit of mankind is man, the individual human being. Nearly all

individuals live in society, but society is nothing more than a

collection of individuals, and its only purpose is to give them a full

life. Anarchists do not believe that people have natural rights, but

this applies to everyone; an individual has no right to do anything, but

no other individual has a right to stop him doing anything. There is no

general will, no social norm to which we should conform. We are equal,

but not identical. Competition and mutual aid, aggression and

tenderness, intolerance and tolerance, violence and gentleness,

authority and rebellion—all these are natural forms of social behaviour,

but some help and others hinder the full life of the individuals.

Anarchists believe that the best way to guarantee it is to secure equal

freedom for every member of society.

We therefore have no time for morality in the traditional sense, and we

are not interested in what people do in their own lives. Let every

individual do exactly what he wants’, within the limits of his natural

capacity, provided he lets every other individual do exactly what he

wants. Such things as dress, appearance, speech, manners, acquaintance,

and so on, are matters of personal preference. So is sex. We are in

favour of free love, but this does not mean that we advocate universal

promiscuity; it means that all love is free, except prostitution and

rape, and that people should be able to choose (or reject) forms of

sexual behaviour and sexual partners for themselves. Extreme indulgence

may suit one person, extreme chastity another—though most anarchists

feel that the world would be a better place if there had been a lot less

fussing and a lot more fucking. The same principle applies to such

things as drugs. People can intoxicate themselves with alcohol or

caffeine, cannabis or amphetamine, tobacco or opiates, and we have no

right to prevent them, let alone punish them, though we may try to help

them. Similarly, let every individual worship in his own way, so long as

he lets other individuals worship in their own way, or not worship at

all. It doesn’t matter if people are offended; what does matter is if

people are injured. There is no need to worry about differences in

personal behaviour; the thing to worry about is the gross injustice of

authoritarian society.

The main enemy of the free individual is the overwhelming power of the

state, but anarchists are also opposed to every other form of authority

which limits freedom—in the family, in the school, at work, in the

neighbourhood—and to every attempt to make the individual conform.

However, before considering how society may be organised to give the

greatest freedom to its members, it is necessary to describe the various

forms anarchism has taken according to the various views of the

relationship between the individual and society.

How Anarchists Differ

Anarchists are notorious for disagreeing with each other, and in the

absence of leaders and officials, hierarchies and orthodoxies,

punishments and rewards, policies and programmes, it is natural that

people whose fundamental principle is the rejection of authority should

tend to perpetual dissent. Nevertheless, there are several

well-established types of anarchism from which most anarchists have

chosen one to express their particular view.

Philosophic anarchism

The original type of anarchism was what is now called philosophic

anarchism. This is the view that the idea of a society without

government is beautiful but not really desirable, or desirable but not

really possible, at least not yet. Such an attitude dominates all

apparently anarchist writing before the 1840s, and it helped to prevent

anarchic popular movements from becoming a more serious threat to

governments. It is an attitude which is still found among people who

call themselves anarchists but remain outside any organised movement,

and also among some people inside the anarchist movement. Quite often it

seems to be an almost unconscious attitude that anarchism, like the

kingdom of God, is within you. It reveals itself sooner or later by some

such phrase as, “Of course, I’m an anarchist, but—.”

Active anarchists tend to despise philosophic anarchists, and this is

understandable, though unfortunate. So long as anarchism is a minority

movement, a general feeling in favour of anarchist ideas, however vague,

creates a climate in which anarchist propaganda is listened to and the

anarchist movement can grow. On the other hand an acceptance of

philosophic anarchism can inoculate people against an appreciation of

real anarchism; but it is at least better than complete indifference. As

well as philosophic anarchists, there are many people who are close to

us but refuse to call themselves anarchists, and some who refuse to call

themselves anything at all. These all have their part to play, if only

to provide a sympathetic audience and to work for freedom in their own

lives.

Individualism, egoism, libertarianism

The first type of anarchism which was more than merely philosophical was

individualism. This is the view that society is not an organism but a

collection of autonomous individuals, who have no obligation towards

society as a whole but only towards one another. This view existed long

before there was any such thing as anarchism, and it has continued to

exist quite separately from anarchism. But individualism always tends to

assume that the individuals who make up society should be free and

equal, and that they can become so only by their own efforts and not

through the action of outside institutions; and any development of this

attitude obviously brings mere individualism towards real anarchism.

The first person who elaborated a recognisable theory of

anarchism—William Godwin, in An Enquiry concerning Political Justice

(1793)—was an individualist. In reaction against the supporters and the

opponents of the French Revolution, he postulated a society without

government and with as little organisation as possible, in which the

sovereign individuals should beware of any form of permanent

association; despite many variations, this is still the basis of

individualist anarchism. This is an anarchism for intellectuals,

artists, and eccentrics, for people who work alone and like to keep

themselves to themselves. Ever since Godwin it has attracted such

people, especially in Britain and North America, and has included

figures such as Shelley and Wilde, Emerson and Thoreau, Augustus John

and Herbert Read. They may call themselves something else, but the

individualism always shows through.

It is perhaps misleading to call individualism a type of anarchism, for

it has had a profound influence on the whole anarchist movement, and any

experience or observation of anarchists shows that it is still an

essential part of their ideology, or at least of their motivation.

Individualist anarchists are, as it were, the basic anarchists, who

simply wish to destroy authority and see no need to put anything in its

place. This is a view of man which makes sense as far as it goes, but it

doesn’t go far enough to deal with the real problems of society, which

surely need social rather than personal action. Alone, we may save

ourselves, but others we cannot save.

A more extreme form of individualism is egoism, especially in the form

expressed by Max Stirner in Der Einzige und sein Eigentum (1845)—usually

translated as The Ego and His Own, though a better rendering would be

The Individual and His Property. Like Marx or Freud, Stirner is

difficult to interpret without offending all his followers; but it is

perhaps acceptable to say that his egoism differs from individualism in

general by rejecting such abstractions as morality, justice, obligation,

reason, and duty, in favour of an intuitive recognition of the

existential uniqueness of each individual. It naturally opposes the

state, but it also opposes society, and it tends towards nihilism (the

view that nothing matters) and solipsism (the view that only oneself

exists). It is clearly anarchist, but 111 a rather unproductive way,

since any form of organisation beyond a temporary “union of egoists” is

seen as the source of new oppression. This is an anarchism for poets and

tramps, for people who want an absolute answer and no compromise. It is

anarchy here and now, if not in the world, then in one’s own life.

A more moderate tendency which derives from individualism is

libertarianism. This is in its simplest sense the view that liberty is a

good thing; in a stricter sense it is the view that freedom is the most

important political goal. Thus libertarianism is not so much a specific

type of anarchism as a milder form of it, the first stage on the way to

complete anarchism. Sometimes it is actually used as a synonym or

euphemism for anarchism in general, when there is some reason to avoid

the more emotive word; but it is more generally used to mean the

acceptance of anarchist ideas in a particular field without the

acknowledgement of anarchism as a whole. Individualists are libertarian

by definition, but libertarian socialists or libertarian communists are

those who bring to socialism or communism a recognition of the essential

value of the individual.

Mutualism and federalism

The type of anarchism which appears when individualists begin to put

their ideas into practice is mutualism. This is the view that, instead

of relying on the state, society should be organised by individuals

entering into voluntary agreements with each other on a basis of

equality and reciprocity. Mutualism is a feature of any association

which is more than instinctive and less than official, and it is not

necessarily anarchist; but it was historically important in the

development of anarchism, and nearly all anarchist proposals for the

reorganisation of society have been essentially mutualist.

The first person who deliberately called himself an

anarchist—Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, in What is Property? (1840)—was a

mutualist. In reaction against the utopian and revolutionary socialists

of the early nineteenth century, he postulated a society which is made

up of cooperative groups of free individuals exchanging the necessities

of life on the basis of labour value, and exchanging free credit through

a people’s bank. This is an anarchism for craftsmen and artisans, for

smallholders and shopkeepers, for professional men and specialists, for

people who like to stand on their own feet. Despite his denials,

Proudhon had many followers, especially among the skilled working class

and the lower middle class, and his influence was considerable in France

during the second half of the nineteenth century; mutualism also had a

particular appeal in North America, and to a lesser extent in Britain.

It later tended to be taken up by the sort of cranks who favour currency

reform or self-sufficient communities—measures of a kind which promise

quick results but do not affect the basic structure of society. This is

a view of man which makes sense as far as it goes, but it doesn’t go far

enough to deal with such things as industry and capital, the class

system which dominates them, or—above all—the state.

Mutualism is of course the principle of the co-operative movement, but

co-operative societies are run on democratic rather than anarchist

lines. A society organised according to the principle of anarchist

mutualism would be one in which communal activities were in effect in

the hands of co-operative societies without permanent managers or

elected officials. Economic mutualism may thus be seen as co-operativism

minus bureaucracy, or as capitalism minus profit.

Mutualism expressed geographically rather than economically becomes

federalism. This is the view that society in a wider sense than the

local community should be co-ordinated by a network of councils which

are drawn from the various areas and which are themselves co-ordinated

by councils covering wider areas. The essential feature of anarchist

federalism is that the members of such councils would be delegates

without any executive authority, subject to instant recall, and that the

councils would have no central authority, only a simple secretariat.

Proudhon, who first elaborated mutualism, also first elaborated

federalism—in The Federal Principle (1863)—and his followers were called

federalists as well as mutualists, especially those who were active in

the labour movement; thus the figures in the early history of the First

International and in the Paris Commune who anticipated the ideas of the

modem anarchist movement mostly described themselves as federalists.

Federalism is not so much a type of anarchism as an inevitable part of

anarchism. Virtually all anarchists are federalists, but virtually none

would define themselves only as federalists. Federalism is after all a

common principle which is by no means confined to the anarchist

movement. There is nothing utopian about it. The international systems

for co-ordinating railways, shipping, air traffic, postal services,

telegraphs and telephones, scientific research, famine relief, disaster

operations, and many other world-wide activities are essentially

federalist in structure. Anarchists simply add that such systems would

work just as well within as they do between countries. After all, this

is already true of the overwhelming proportion of voluntary societies,

associations and organisations of all kinds which handle those social

activities which are not financially profitable or politically

sensitive.

Collectivism, communism, syndicalism

The type of anarchism which goes further than individualism or mutualism

and involves a direct threat to the class system and the state is what

used to be called collectivism. This is the view that society can be

reconstructed only when the working class seizes control of the economy

by a social revolution, destroys the state apparatus, and reorganises

production on the basis of common ownership and control by associations

of working people. The instruments of labour would be held in common,

but the products of labour would be distributed on the principle of the

slogan, “From each according to his ability, to each according to his

work.”

The first modern anarchists—the Bakuninists in the First

International—were collectivists. In reaction against the reformist

mutualists and federalists and also against the authoritarian Blanquists

and Marxists, they postulated a simple form of revolutionary

anarchism—the anarchism of the class struggle and the proletariat, of

the mass insurrection of the poor against the rich, and the immediate

transition to a free and classless society without any intermediate

period of dictatorship. This is an anarchism for class-conscious workers

and peasants, for militants and activists in the labour movement, for

socialists who want liberty as well as equality.

This anarchist or revolutionary collectivism must not be confused with

the better known authoritarian and reformist collectivism of the Social

Democrats and Fabians—the collectivism which is based on common

ownership of the economy but also on state control of production. Partly

because of the danger of this confusion, and partly because it is here

that anarchists and socialists come closest to each other, a better

description of this type of anarchism is libertarian socialism—which

includes not only anarchists who are socialists but also socialists who

lean towards anarchism but are not quite anarchists,

The type of anarchism which appears when collectivism is worked out in

more detail is communism. This is the view that it is not enough for the

instruments of labour to be held in common, but that the products of

labour should also be held in common and distributed on the principle of

the slogan, “From each according to his ability, to each according to

his needs.” The communist argument is that, while men are entitled to

the full value of their labour, it is impossible to calculate the value

of any one man’s labour, for the work of each is involved in the work of

all, and different kinds of work have different kinds of value. It is

therefore better for the entire economy to be in the hands of society as

a whole and for the wage and price system to be abolished.

The leading figures of the anarchist movement at the end of the

nineteenth century and the beginning of the twentieth century—such as

Kropotkin, Malatesta, Reclus, Grave, Faure, Goldman, Berkman, Rocker,

and so on—were communists. Going on from collectivism and reacting

against Marxism, they postulated a more sophisticated form of

revolutionary anarchism—the anarchism containing the most carefully

considered criticism of present society and proposals for future

society. This is an anarchism for those who accept the class struggle

but have a wider view of the world. If collectivism is revolutionary

anarchism concentrating on the problem of work and based on the workers’

collective, then communism is revolutionary anarchism concentrating on

the problem of life and based on the people’s commune.

Since the 1870s, the principle of communism has been accepted by most

anarchist organisations favouring revolution. The main exception was the

movement in Spain, which retained the principle of collectivism because

of strong Bakuninist influence; but in fact its aims were scarcely

different from those of other movements, and in practice the “comunismo

libertario” established during the Spanish Revolution in 1936 was the

most impressive example of anarchist communism in history.

This anarchist or libertarian communism must of course not be confused

with the much better known communism of the Marxists—the communism which

is based on common ownership of the economy and state control of both

production and distribution, and also on party dictatorship. The

historical origin of the modern anarchist movement in the dispute with

the Marxists in the First and Second Internationals is reflected in the

ideological obsession of anarchists with authoritarian communism, and

this has been reinforced since the Russian and Spanish revolutions. As a

result, many anarchists seem to have called themselves communists not so

much from definite conviction but more from a wish to challenge the

Marxists on their own ground and outdo them in the eyes of public

opinion. One may suspect that anarchists are seldom really communist,

partly because they are always too individualist, and partly because

they would not wish to lay down elaborate plans for a future which must

be free to make its own arrangements.

The type of anarchism which appears when collectivism or communism

concentrates exclusively on the problem of work is syndicalism. This is

the view that society should be based on trade unions, as the expression

of the working class, reorganised so as to cover both occupations and

areas, and reform so as to be in the hands of the rank and file, so that

the whole economy is managed according to the principle of workers’

control.

Most anarchist collectivists and many communists during the nineteenth

century were syndicalists by implication, and this was particularly true

of the anarchists in the First International. But anarcho-syndicalism

was not developed explicitly until the rise of the French syndicalist

movement at the end of the century. (The English word “syndicalism”

comes from the French word synclicalisme, which simply means

trade-unionism.) When the French trade-union movement divided into

revolutionary and reformist sections in the 1890s, the revolutionary

syndicalists became dominant, and many anarchists joined them. Some of

these, such as Fernand Pelloutier and Emile Pouget, became influential,

and the French syndicalist movement, though never rully anarchist, was a

powerful force for anarchism until the First World War and the Russian

Revolution. Anarcho- syndicalist organisations were also strong in the

labour movements of Itaiy and Russia just after the First World War, and

above all in Spain until the end of the Civil War in 1939.

This is an anarchism for the most class-conscious and militant elements

in a strong labour movement. But syndicalism is not necessarily

anarchist or even revolutionary; in practice anarcho-syndicalists have

tended to become authoritarian or reformist, or both, and it has proved

difficult to maintain a balance between libertarian principles and tne

pressures of the day-to-day struggle for better pay and conditions. This

is not so much an argument against anarcho-syndicalism as a constant

danger for anarcho-syndicalists. The real argument against

anarcho-syndicalism and against syndicalism in general is that it

overemphasises the importance of work and the function of the working

class. The class system is a central political problem but the class

struggle is not the only political activity for anarchists. Syndicalism

is acceptable when it is seen as one aspect of anarchism but not when it

obscures all other aspects. This is a view of man which makes sense as

far as it goes, but it doesn’t go far enough to deal with life outside

work.

Not so different

It ^ must be said that the differences between various types of

anarchism have become less important in recent years. Except for

dogmatists at each extreme, most anarchists tend to see the old

distinctions as more apparent than real—as artificial differences of

emphasis, even of vocabulary, rather than as serious differences of

principle. It might in fact be better to think of them as not so much

types as aspects of anarchism which depend on the direction of our

interests.

Thus in our private lives we are individualists, doing our own things

and choosing our companions and friends for personal reasons; in our

social lives we are mutualists, making free agreements with each other,

and giving what we have and getting what we need by equal exchanges with

each other; in our working lives we would mostly be collectivists,

joining our colleagues in producing for the common good—and in the

management of work we would mostly be syndicalists, joining our

colleagues in deciding how the job should be done; in our political

lives we would mostly be communists, joining our neighbours in deciding

how the community should be run. This is of course a simplification, but

it expresses a general truth about the way anarchists think nowadays.

What Anarchists Want

It is difficult to say what anarchists want, not just because they

differ so much, but because they hesitate to make detailed proposals

about a future which they are neither able nor willing to control. After

ail, anarchists want a society without government, and such a society

would obviously vary widely from time to time and from place to place.

The whole point of the society anarchists want is that it would be what

its members themselves want. Nevertheless, it is possible to say what

most anarchists would like to see in a free society, though it must

always be remembered that there is no official line, and also no way of

reconciling the extremes of individualism and communism.

The free individual

Most anarchists begin with a libertarian attitude towards private life,

and want a much wider choice for personal behaviour and for social

relationships between individuals. But if the individual is the atom of

society, the family is the molecule, and family iife would continue even

if all the coercion enforcing it were removed. Nevertheless, though the

family may be natural, it is no longer necessary; efficient

contraception and intelligent division of labour have released mankind

from the narrow choice between celibacy and monogamy. 1 here is no need

for a couple to have children, and children could be brought up by more

or less than two parents. People could live alone and still have sexual

partners and children, or live in communes with no permanent

partnerships or official parenthood at all.

No doubt most people will go on practising some form of marriage and

most children will be brought up in a family environment, whatever

happens to society, but there could be a great variety of personal

arrangements within a single community. The fundamental requirement is

that women should be freed from the oppression of men and that children

should be freed from that of parents. The exercise of authority is no

better in the microcosm of the family than in the macrocosm of society.

Personal relationships outside the family would be regulated not by

arbitrary laws or economic competition but by the natural solidarity of

the human species. Almost all of us know how to treat our fellow- men—as

we would like them to treat us—and self-respect and public opinion are

far better guides to action than fear or guilt. Some opponents of

anarchism have suggested that the moral oppression of society would be

worse than the physical oppression of the state, but a greater danger is

surely the unregulated authority of the vigilante group, the lynch mob,

the robber band, or the criminal gang—the rudimentary forms of the state

which come to the surface when the regulated authority of the real state

is for some reason absent.

But anarchists disagree little about private life, and there is not much

of a problem here. After all a great many people have already made their

own new arrangements, without waiting for a revolution or anything else.

All that is needed for the liberation of the individual is the

emancipation from old prejudices and the achievement of a certain

standard of living. The real problem is the liberation of society.

The free society

The first priority of a free society would be the abolition of authority

and the expropriation of property. In place of government by permanent

representatives who are subject to occasional election and by career

bureaucrats who are virtually unmovable, anarchists want co-ordination

by temporary delegates who are subject to instant recall and by

professional experts who are genuinely accountable. In such a system,

all those social activities which involve organisation would probably be

managed by free associations. These might be called councils or

co-operatives or collectives or communes or committees or unions or

syndicates or soviets, or anything else—their title would be irrelevant,

the important thing would be their function.

There would be work associations from the workshop or smallholding up to

the largest industrial or agricultural complex, to handle the production

and transport of goods, decide conditions of work, and run the economy.

There would be area associations from the neighbourhood or village up to

the largest residential unit, to handle the life of the

community—housing, streets, refuse, amenities. There would be

associations to handle the social aspects of such activities as

communications, culture, recreation, research, health and education.

One result of co-ordination by free association rather than

administration by established hierarchies would be extreme

decentralisation on federalist lines. This may seem an argument against

anarchism, but we would say that it is an argument for it. One of the

oddest things about modern political thought is that wars are often

blamed on the existence of many small nations when the worst wars in

history have been caused by a few large ones. In the same way,

governments are always trying to create larger and larger administrative

units when observation suggests that the best ones are small. The

breakdown of big political systems would be one of the greatest benefits

of anarchism, and countries could become cultural entities once more,

while nations would disappear.

The association concerned with any kind of wealth or property would have

the crucial responsibility of either making sure that it was fairly

divided among the people involved or else of holding it in common and

making sure that the use of it was fairly shared among the people

involved. Anarchists differ about which system is best, and no doubt the

members of a free society would also differ; it would be up to the

people in each association to adopt whichever method they preferred.

There might be equal pay for all, or pay according to need, or no pay at

all. Some associations might use money for all exchange, some just for

large or complex transactions, and some might not use it at all. Goods

might be bought, or hired, or rationed, or free. If this sort of

speculation seems absurdly unrealistic or utopian, it may be worth

remembering just how much we already hold in common, and how many things

may be used without payment.

In Britain, the community owns some heavy industries, air and rail

transport, ferries and buses, broadcasting systems, water, gas and

electricity, though we pay to use them; but roads, bridges, rivers,

beaches, parks, libraries, playgrounds, lavatories, schools,

universities, hospitals and emergency services are not only owned by the

community but may be used without payment. The distinction between what

is owned privately and what is owned communally, and between what may be

used for payment and what may be used freely, is quite arbitrary. It may

seem obvious that we should be able to use roads and beaches v/ithout

payment, but this was not always the case, and the free use of hospitals

and universities has come only during this century. In the same way, it

may seem obvious that we should pay for transport and fuel, but this may

not always be the case, and there is no reason why they should not be

free.

One result of the equal division or free distribution of wealth rather

than the accumulation of property would be the end of the class system

based on ownership. But anarchists also want to end the class system

based on control. This would mean constant vigilance to prevent the

growth of bureaucracy in every association, and above all it would mean

the reorganisation of work without a managerial class.

Work

The first need of man is for food, shelter and clothing which make life

livable; the second is for the further comforts which make life worth

living. The prime economic activity of any human group is the production

and distribution of the things which satisfy these needs; and the most

important aspect of a society—after the personal relations on which it

is based—is the organisation of the necessary work. Anarchists have two

characteristic ideas about work: the first is that most work is

unpleasant but could be organised to be more bearable and even

pleasurable; and the second is that all work should be organised by the

people who actually do it.

Anarchists agree v/ith Marxists that work in present society alienates

the worker. It is not his life, but what he does to be able to live; his

life is what he does outside work, and when he does something he enjoys

he does not call it work. This is true of most work for most people in

all places, and it is bound to be true of a lot of work for a lot of

people at all times. The tiring and repetitive labour which has to be

done to make plants grow and animals thrive, to run production lines and

transport systems, to get to people what they want and to take from them

what they do not want, could not be abolished without a drastic decline

in the material standard of living; and automation, which can make it

less tiring, makes it even more repetitive. But anarchists insist that

the solution is not to condition people into believing that the

situation is inevitable, but to reorganise essential labour so that, in

the first place, it is normal for everyone who is capable of it to take

a share in doing it, and for no one to spend more than a few hours a day

on it; and so that, in the second place, it is possible for everyone Jo

alternate between different kinds of boring labour, which would become

less boring through greater variety. It is a matter not just of fair

shares for all, but also of fair work for all.

Anarchists also agree with syndicalists that work should be run by the

workers. This does not mean that the working class—or the trade unions

or a working-class party (that is, a party claiming to represent the

working class)���runs the economy and has ultimate control of work. Nor

does it mean the same thing on a smaller scale, that the staff of a

factory can elect managers or see the accounts. It means quite simply

that the people doing a particular job are in direct and total control

of what they do, without any bosses or managers or inspectors at all.

Some people may be good co-ordinators, and they can concentrate on

co-ordination, but there is no need for them to have power over the

people who do the actual work. Some people may be lazy or inefficient,

but they are already. The point is to have the greatest possible control

over one’s own work, as well as one’s own life.

This principle applies to all kinds of work—in fields as well as

factories, in large concerns as well as small, in unskilled as well as

skilled occupations, and in dirty jobs as well as liberal

professions—and it is not just a useful gesture to make workers happy

but a fundamental principle of any kind of free economy. An obvious

objection is that complete workers’ control would lead to wasteful

competition between different workplaces and to production of unwanted

things; an obvious answer is that complete lack of workers’ control

leads to exactly the same things. What is needed is intelligent

planning, and despite what most people seem to think, this depends not

on more control from above but on more information below.

Most economists have been concerned with production rather than

consumption—with the manufacture of tilings rather than their use.

Right-wingers and left-wingers both want workers to produce more,

whether to make the rich richer or to make the state stronger, and the

result is “overproduction” alongside poverty, growing productivity

together with growing unemployment, higher blocks of offices at the same

time as increasing homelessness, greater yields of crops per acre when

more acres are left uncultivated. Anarchists are concerned with

consumption rather than production—with the use of things to satisfy the

needs of the whole people instead of to increase the profits and power

of the rich and strong.

Necessities and luxuries

A society with any pretension to decency cannot allow the exploitation

of basic needs. It may be acceptable for luxuries to be bought and sold,

since we have a choice whether we use them or not; but necessities are

not mere commodities, since we have no choice about using them. If

anything should be taken off the commercial market and out of the hands

of exclusive groups, it is surely the land we live on, the food which

grows on it, the homes which are built on it, and those essential things

which make up the material basis of human life—clothes, tools,

amenities, fuel, and so on. It is also surely obvious that when there is

plenty of any necessity everyone should be able to take what he needs;

but that when there is a scarcity, there should be a freely agreed

system of rationing so that everyone gets a fair share. It is clear that

there is something wrong with any system in which waste and want exist

side by side, in which some people have more than they need while other

people go without.

Above all it is clear that the first task of a healthy society is to

eliminate the scarcity of necessities—such as the lack of food in

undeveloped countries and the lack of housing in advanced countries—by

the proper use of technical knowledge and of social resources. If the

available skill and labour in Britain were used properly, for instance,

there is no reason why enough food could not be grown and enough homes

could not be built to feed and house the whole population. It does not

happen now because present society has other priorities, not because it

cannot happen. At one time it was assumed that it was impossible for

everyone to be clothed properly, and poor people always wore rags; now

there arc plenty of clothes, and there could be plenty of everything

else too.

Luxuries, by a strange paradox, are also necessities, though not basic

necessities. The second task of a healthy society is to make luxuries

freely available as well, though Ihis may be a place where money would

still have a useful function—provided it were not distributed according

to the ludicrous lack of system in capitalist countries, or the even

more ludicrous system in communist ones. The essential point is that

everyone should have free and equal access to luxury.

But man does not live by bread alone, or even by cake. Anarchists would

not like to see recreational, intellectual, cultural, and other such

activities in the hands of society—even the most libertarian society.

But there are other activities which cannot be left to individuals in

free associations but must be handled by society as a whole. These are

what may be called welfare activities—mutual aid beyond the reach of

family and friends and outside the place of residence or work. Let us

consider three of these.

The welfare society

Education is very important in human society, because we take so long to

grow and take so long learning facts and skills necessary for social

life, and anarchists have always been much concerned about the problems

of education. Many anarchist leaders have made valuable contributions to

educational theory and practice, and many educational reformers have had

libertarian tendencies—from Rousseau and Pesta- lozzi to Montessori and

Neill. Tdeas about education which were once thought of as utopian are

now a normal part of the curriculum both inside and outside the state

educational system in Britain, and education is perhaps the most

stimulating area of society for practical anarchists. When people say

that anarchy sounds nice but cannot work, we can point to a good primary

or comprehensive school, or a good adventure playground or youth club.

But even the best educational system is still “under the control of

people in authority—teachers, administrators, governors, officials,

inspectors, and so on. The adults concerned in any educational process

are bound to dominate it to some extent, but there is no need for

them—let alone people not directly concerned in it at all—to control it.

Anarchists want the current educational reforms to go much further. Not

only should strict discipline and corporal punishment be abolished—so

should all imposed discipline and all penal methods. Not only should

educational institutions be freed from the power of outside authorities,

but students should be freed from the power of teachers or

administrators. In a healthy education relationship the fact that one

person knows more than another is no reason for the teacher having

authority over the learner. The status of teachers in present society is

based on age, strength, experience, and law; the only status teachers

should have would be based on their knowledge of a subject and their

ability to teach it, and ultimately on their capacity to inspire

admiration and respect. What is needed is not so much student

power-—though that is a useful corrective to teachers’ power and

bureaucrats’ power—as workers’ control by all the people involved in an

educational institution. The essential point is to break the link

between teaching and governing and to make education free.

This break is actually nearer in health than in education. Doctors are

no longer magicians and nurses are no longer saints, and in many

countries—including Britain—the right of free medical treatment is

accepted. What is needed is the extension of the principle of freedom

from the economic to the political side of the health system. People

should be able to go to hospital without any payment, and people should

also be able to work in hospitals without any hierarchy. Once again,

what is needed is workers’ control by all the people involved in a

medical institution. And just as education is for students, so health is

for patients.

The treatment of delinquency has also progressed a long way, but it is

still far from satisfactory. Anarchists have two characteristic ideas

about delinquency: the first is that most so-called criminals are much

the same as other people, just poorer, weaker, sillier or unluckier; the

second is that people who persistently hurt other people should not be

hurt in turn but should be looked after. The biggest criminals are not

burglars but bosses, not gangsters but rulers, not murderers but mass-

murderers. A few minor injustices are exposed and punished by the state,

while the many major injustices of present society are disguised and

actually perpetrated by the state. In general punishment does more

damage to society than crime does; it is more extensive, better

organised, and much more effective. Nevertheless, even the most

libertarian society would have to protect itself against some people,

and this would inevitably involve some compulsion. But proper treatment

of delinquency would be part of the education and health system, and

would not become an institutionalised system of punishment. The last

resort would not be imprisonment or death, but boycott or expulsion.

Pluralism

This might work the other way. An individual or a group might refuse to

join or insist on leaving the best possible society; there would be

nothing to stop him. In theory it is possible for a man to support

himself by his own efforts, though in practice he would depend on the

community to provide some materials and to take some products in

exchange, so it is difficult to be literally self-sufficient. A

collectivist or communist society should tolerate and even encourage

such pockets of individualism. What would be unacceptable would be an

independent person trying to exploit other people’s labour by employing

them at unfair wages or exchanging goods at unfair prices. This should

not happen, because people would not normally work or buy for someone

else’s benefit rather than their own; and while no law would prevent

appropriation, no law would prevent expropriation either—you could take

something from someone, but he could take it back again. Authority and

property could hardly be restored by isolated individuals.

A greater danger would come from independent groups. A separate

community could easily exist within society, and this might cause severe

strains; if such a community reverted to authority and property, which

might raise the standard of living of the few, there would be a

temptation for people to join the secession, especially if society at

large were going through a bad time.

But a free society would have to be pluralist and put up with not only

differences of opinion about how freedom and equality should be put into

practice but also deviations from the theory of freedom and equality

altogether. The only condition would be that no one is forced to join

such tendencies against his will, and here some kind of authoritarian

pressure would have to be available to protect even the most libertarian

society. But anarchists want to replace mass society by a mass of

societies, all living together as freely as the individuals within them.

The greatest danger to the free societies that have been established has

been not internal regression but external aggression, and the real

problem is not so much how to keep a free society going as how to get it

going in the first place.

Revolution or reform

Anarchists have traditionally advocated a violent revolution to

establish a free society, but some have rejected violence or revolution

or both—violence is so often followed by counter-violence and revolution

by counter-revolution. On the other hand, few anarchists have advocated

mere reform, realising that while the system of authority and property

exists superficial changes will never threaten the basic structure of

society. The difficulty is that what anarchists want is revolutionary,

but a revolution will not necessarily—or even probably—lead to what

anarchists want. This is why anarchists have tended to resort to

desperate actions or to relapse into hopeless inactivity.

In practice most disputes between reformist and revolutionary anarchists

are meaningless, for only the wildest revolutionary refuses to welcome

reforms and only the mildest reformist refuses to welcome revolutions,

and all revolutionaries know that their work will generally lead to no

more than reform and all reformists know that their work is generally

leading to some kind of revolution. What most anarchists want is a

constant pressure of all kinds, bringing about the conversion of

individuals, the formation of groups, the reform of institutions, the

rising of the people, and the destruction of authority and property. If

this happened without trouble, we would be delighted; but it never has,

and it probably never will. In the end it is necessary to go out and

confront the forces of the state in the neighbourhood, at work, and in

the streets—and if the state is defeated it is even more necessary to go

on working to prevent the establishment of a new state and to begin the

construction of a free society instead. There is a place for everyone in

this process, and all anarchists find something to do in the struggle

for what they want.

What Anarchists Do

The first thing anarchists do is to think and talk. Few people begin as

anarchists, and becoming an anarchist tends to be a confusing experience

which involves a considerable emotional and intellectual upheaval. Being

a conscious anarchist is a continuously difficult situation (rather like

being, say, an atheist in medieval Europe); it is difficult to break

through the thought-barrier and persuade people that the necessity for

government (like the existence of God) is not self-evident but may be

discussed and even rejected. An anarchist has to work out a whole new

view of the world and a new way of dealing with it; this is usually done

in conversation with people who are anarchists or are near to anarchism,

especially within some left-wing group or activity.

Afterwards, even the most single-minded anarchist has contact with

non-anarchists, and such contact is inevitably an opportunity for

spreading anarchist ideas. Among family and friends, at home and at

work, any anarchist who is not entirely philosophical in his convictions

is bound to be influenced by them. It is not universal but it is usual

for anarchists to be less worried than other people about such things as

faithfulness in their spouses, obedience in their children, conformity

in their neighbours, or punctuality in their colleagues. Anarchist

employees and citizens are less likely to do what they are told, and

anarchist teachers and parents are less likely to make others do what

they are told. Anarchism which does not show in personal life is pretty

unreliable.

Some anarchists are content with making up their own minds and confining

their opinions to their own lives, but most want to go further and

influence other people. In conversation about social or political

matters they will put the libertarian point of view, and in struggles

over public issues they will support the libertarian solution. But’to

make a real impact it is necessary to work with other anarchists or in

some kind of political group on a more permanent basis than chance

encounter. This is the beginning of organisation, leading to propaganda,

and finally to action

Organisation and propaganda

The initial form of anarchist organisation is a discussion group. If

this proves viable, it will develop in two ways—it will establish links

with other groups, and it will begin wider activity. Links with other

groups may eventually lead to some sort of federation which can

co-ordinate activity and undertake more ambitious enterprises. Anarchist

activity normally begins with some form of propaganda to get across the

basic idea of anarchism itseli. There are two main ways of doing

this—propaganda by word and propaganda by deed.

The word may be written or spoken. Nowadays the spoken word is heard

less than it used to be, but public meetings—whether indoors or in the

open—are still a valuable method of reaching people directly. The final

stage in becoming an anarchist is normally precipitated by some kind of

personal contact, and a meeting is a good opportunity for this. As well

as holding specifically anarchist meetings, it is also worth attending

other meetings to put an anarchist point of view, whether by taking part

in the proceedings or by interrupting them.

The most sophisticated vehicle for the spoken word nowadays is of course

radio and television, and anarchists have occasionally managed to get a

hearing on some programmes. But broadcasting is in fact a rather

unsatisfactory medium for propaganda, because it is unsuitable for

conveying unfamiliar ideas, and anarchism is still an unfamiliar idea

for most listeners and viewers; it is also unsuitable for conveying

explicit political ideas, and anarchism is probably broadcast most

effectively in the form of implicit morals to stories. The same is true

of such media as the cinema and the theatre, which can be used for

extremely effective propaganda in skilful hands. In general, however,

anarchists have not been able to make as much of these channels of

communication as one might hope.

Anyway, however effective propaganda by speech may be, the written word

is necessary to fill out the message, and this has been and still is by

far the most common form of propaganda. The idea ot society without

government may have existed underground for centuries and occasionally

come to the surface in radical popular movements, but it was first

brought out into the open for thousands of people by the books of such

writers as Paine, Godwin, Proudhon, Stirner and so on. And when the idea

took root and was expressed by organised groups, there began that flood

of periodicals and pamphlets which is still the main method of

communication in the anarchist movement. Some of these publications have

been very good; most have been rather bad; but they have all been

essential in making sure that the movement has not turned in on itself

but has maintained a constant dialogue with the external world. Again,

as well as producing specifically anarchist works, it is also worth

contributing to non-anarchist periodicals and writing non-anarchist

books to put an anarchist point of view to non-anarchist readers.

But the spoken and written word, though necessary, are never sufficient.

We can talk and write in general terms as much we like, but by itself

that will get us nowhere. It is also necessary to move beyond mere

propaganda, in two ways—to discuss particular issues at such a time and

in such a manner as to have an immediate effect, or to win publicity by

something more dramatic than mere words. The first way is agitation, the

second is propaganda by deed.

Agitation is the point at which a political theory encounters political

reality. Anarchist agitation becomes suitable when people are made

especially receptive to anarchist ideas because of some kind of stress

in the state system—during national or civil wars, industrial or

agrarian struggles, campaigns against oppression or public scandals—and

it consists essentially of propaganda brought down to earth and made

practicable. In a situation of growing consciousness, people are not so

much interested in general speculation as in specific proposals. This is

the opportunity to show in detail what is wrong with the present system

and how it could be put right. Anarchist agitation has sometimes been

effective, especially in France, Spain and the United States before the

First World War, in Russia, Italy and China after it, and in Spain

during the 1930s; it has occasionally been effective in Britain, in the

1880s, in the early 1940s, and again in the 1960s.

The idea of propaganda by deed is often misunderstood, by anarchists as

well as their enemies. When the phrase was first used (during the 1870s)

it meant demonstrations, riots and risings which were thought of as

symbolic actions designed to win useful publicity rather than immediate

success. The point was that the propaganda would consist not just of

talk about what could be done but of news about what had been done. It

did not originally and does not necessarily mean violence, let alone

assassination; but after the wave of outrages by individual anarchists

during the 1890s, propaganda by deed became popularly identified with

personal acts of violence, and this image has not yet faded.

For most anarchists nowadays, however, propaganda by deed is more likely

to be non-violent, or at least un-violent, and to be against bombs

rather than with them. It has in fact reverted to its original meaning,

though it now tends to take rather different forms—sit-downs and

sit-ins, organised heckling and unorthodox demonstrations. Propaganda by

deed need not be illegal, though it often is. Civil disobedience is a

special type of propaganda by deed which involves the open and

deliberate breaking of a law to gain publicity. Many anarchists dislike

it, because it also involves the open and deliberate invitation of

punishment, which offends anarchist feelings about any kind of voluntary

contact with the authorities; but there have been times when some

anarchists have found it a useful form of propaganda.

Agitation, especially when it is successful, and propaganda by deed,

especially when it is illegal, both go further than mere propaganda.

Agitation incites action, and propaganda by deed involves action; it is

here that anarchists move into the field of action and that anarchism

begins to become serious.

Action

The change from theorising about anarchism to putting it into practice

means a change in organisation. The typical discussion or propaganda

group, which is open to easy participation by outsiders and easy

observation by the authorities, and which is based on each member doing

what he wants to do and not doing what we doesn’t want to do, will

become more exclusive and more formal. This is a moment of great danger,

since an attitude which is too rigid leads to authoritarianism and

sectarianism, while one which is too lax leads to confusion and

irresponsibility. It is a moment of even greater danger, since when

anarchism becomes a serious matter anarchists become a serious threat to

the authorities, and real persecution begins.

The most common form of anarchist action is for agitation over an issue

to become participation in a campaign. This may be reformist, for

something which would not change the whole system, or revolutionary, for

a change in (lie system itself; it may be legal or illegal or both,

violent or non-violent or just un-violent. It may have a chance of

success, or it may be hopeless from the start. The anarchists may be

influential or even dominant in the campaign, or they may be only one of

many groups taking part. It does not take long to think of a wide

variety of possible fields of action, and for a century anarchists have

tried them all. The form of action with which anarchists have been

happiest and which is most typical of anarchism is direct action.

The idea of direct action is also often misunderstood, by anarchists as

well as their enemies again. When the phrase was first used (during the

1890s) it meant no more than the opposite of “political”—that is,

parliamentary—action; and in the context of the labour movement it meant

“industrial” action, especially strikes, boycotts and sabotage, which

were thought of as preparations for and rehearsals of revolution. The

point was that the action is applied not indirectly through

representatives but directly by the people most closely involved in a

situation and directly on the situation, and it is intended to win some

measure of success rather than mere publicity.

This would seem clear enough, but direct action has in fact been

confused with propaganda by deed and especially with civil disobedience.

The technique of direct action was actually developed in the French

syndicalist movement in reaction against the more extreme techniques of

propaganda by deed; instead of getting side-tracked into dramatic but

ineffective gestures, the trade-unionists got on with the dull but

effective work—that at least was the theory. But as the syndicalist

movement grew and came into conflict with the system in France, Spain,

Italy, the United States and Russia, and even Britain, the high points

of direct action began to take on the same function as acts of

propaganda by deed. Then, when Gandhi began to describe as direct action

what was really a non-violent form of civil disobedience, all three

phases were confused and came to mean much the same—more or less any

form of political activity which is against the law or otherwise outside

the accepted rules of constitutional etiquette.

For most anarchists, however, direct action still has its original

meaning, though as well as its traditional forms it also takes new

ones—invading military bases or taking over universities, squatting in

houses or occupying factories. What makes it particularly attractive to

anarchists is that it is consistent with libertarian principles and also

with itself. Most forms of political action by opposition groups are

mainly designed to win power; some groups use the techniques of direct

action, but as soon as they win power they not only stop using such

techniques but prevent any other groups using them either. Anarchists

are in favour of direct action at all times; they see it as normal

action, as action whicli reinforces itself anti grows as it is used, as

action which can be used to create and also to sustain a free society.

But there are some anarchists who have no faith in the possibility of

creating a free society, and their action varies accordingly. One of the

strongest pessimistic tendencies in anarchism is nihilism. Nihilism was

the word which Turgenev coined (in his novel Father and Sons) to

describe the sceptical and scornful attitude of the young populists in

Russia a century ago, but it came to mean the view which denies the

value not only of the state or of prevailing morality, but of society

and of humanity itself; for the strict nihilist nothing is sacred, not

even himself—so nihilism is one step beyond the most thorough egoism.

An extreme form of action inspired by nihilism is terrorism for its own

sake rather than for revenge or propaganda. Anarchists have no monopoly

of terror, but it has sometimes been fashionable in some sections of the

movement. After the frustrating experience of preaching a minority

theory in a hostile or often indifferent society, it is tempting to

attack society physically. It may not do much about the hostility, but

it will certainly end the indifference; let them hate me, so long as

they fear me, is the terrorist’s line of thought. But if reasoned

assassination has been unproductive, random terror has been

counter-productive, and it is not too much to say that nothing has done

more damage to anarchism than the streak of psychopathic violence which

always ran and still runs through it.

A milder form of action inspired by nihilism is bohemianism, which is a

constant phenomenon though the name seems to change for each

manifestation. This too has been fashionable in some sections of the

anarchist movement, and of course far outside as well. Instead of

attacking society, the bohemian drops out of it—though, while living

without conforming to the values of society, he usually lives in and on

society. A lot of nonsense is talked about this tendency. Bohemians may

be parasites, but that is true of many other people. On the other hand

they don’t hurt anyone except themselves, which is not true of many

other people. The best thing that can be said about them is lhat they

can do some good by enjoying themselves and challenging received values

in an ostentatious but harmless way. The worst thing that can be said

about them is that they cannot really change society and may divert

energy from trying to do this, which for most anarchists is the whole

point of anarchism.

A more consistent and constructive way of dropping out of society is to

leave it and set up a new self-sufficient community. This has at times

been a widespread phenomenon, among religious enthusiasts during the

Middle Ages, for instance, and among many kinds of people more recently,

especially in North America and of course in Palestine. Anarchists have

been affected by (his tendency in the past, but not much nowadays; like

other left-wing groups, they are more likely to set up their own

informal community, based on a network of people living and working

together within society, than to secede from society. This may be

thought of as the nucleus of a new form of society growing inside the

old forms, or else as a viable form of refuge from the demands of

authority which is not too extreme for ordinary people.

Another form of action which is based on a pessimistic view of the

prospects for anarchism is permanent protest. According to this view,

there is no hope of changing society, of destroying the state system,

and of putting anarchism into practice. What is important is not the

future, the strict adherence (<> a fixed ideal and the careful

elaboration of a beautiful utopia, but the present, the belated

recognition of a bitter reality and the constant resistance to an ugly

situation. Permanent protest is the theory of many former anarchists who

have not given up their beliefs but no longer hope for success; it is

also the practice of many active anarchists who keep their beliefs

intact and carry on as if they still hoped for success but who

know—consciously or unconsciously—that they will never see it. What most

anarchists have been involved in during the last century may be

described as permanent protest when it is looked at with hindsight; but

it is just as dogmatic to say that things will never change as to say

that things are bound to change, and no one can tell when protest might

become effective and the present might suddenly turn into the future.

The real distinction is that permanent protest is thought of as a

rearguard action in a hopeless cause, while most anarchist activity is

thought of as the action of a vanguard or at least of scouts in a

struggle which we may not win and which may never end but which is still

worth fighting.

The best tactics in this struggle are all those which are consistent

with the general strategy of the war for freedom and equality, from

guerrilla skirmishes in one’s private life to set battles in major

social campaigns. Anarchists are almost always in a small minority, so

they have little choice of battlefield but have to fight wherever the

action is. In general the most successful occasions have been those when

anarchist agitation has led to anarchist participation in wider

left-wing movements—especially in the labour movement, but also in

anti-militarist or even pacifist movements in countries preparing for or

fighting in wars, anti-clerical and humanist movements in religious

countries, movements for national or colonial liberation, for racial or

sexual equality, for legal or penal reform, or for civil liberties in

general.

Such participation inevitably means alliance with non-anarchist groups

and some compromise of anarchist principles, and anarchists who become

deeply involved in such action are always in danger of abandoning

anarchism altogether. On the other hand, refusal to take such a risk

generally means sterility and sectarianism, and the anarchist movement

has tended to be influential only when it has accepted a full part. The

particular anarchist contribution to such occasions is twofold—to

emphasise the goal of a libertarian society, and to insist on

libertarian methods of achieving it. This is in fact a single

contribution, for the most important point we can make is not just that

the end does not justify the means, but that the means determines the

end—that means are ends in most cases. We can be sure of our own

actions, but not of the consequences.

A good opportunity for anarchists to give society a push towards

anarchism seems to be active participation on these lines in such

nonsectarian movements as the Committee of 100 in Britain, the March 22

Movement in France, the SDS in Germany, the Provos in Holland, the

Zengakuren in Japan, and the various civil rights, draft resistance, and

student power groups in the United States. In the old days the greatest

opportunity for really substantial movement towards anarchism was of

course in militant syndicalist episodes in France, Spain, Italy, the

United States and Russia, and above all in the revolutions of Russia and

Spain; nowadays it is not so much in the violent and authoritarian

revolutions of Asia, Africa and South America as in insurrectionary

upheavals such as those of Hungary in 1956 and France in 1968—and

Britain when?